18
1 1 I I Euthanasia Euthanasia

1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

11

IIEuthanasiaEuthanasia

Page 2: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

22

Some Background:

Voluntary Involuntary

Pas

sive

Act

ive

VoluntaryPassive

Euthanasia

InvoluntaryPassive

Euthanasia

VoluntaryActive

Euthanasia

InvoluntaryActive

Euthanasia

Involve withholding or taking the patient off live-preserving treatments.

Involve giving the patient a life-ending “treatment”.

Patient consent. No patient consent.

What is euthanasia?

Page 3: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

33

Some Background:

Why might someone request or perform euthanasia?

What ethical positions might one take on euthanasia?

Page 4: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

44

Rachels’ Project• Rachels argues that the American Medical Association’s

distinction between active and passive killing is ethically unfounded.

• Note that Rachels’ paper was published in a medical journal, not a philosophical journal.

James Rachels: “Active and Passive Killing”

Page 5: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

55

The intentional termination of the life of one human being by another—mercy killing—is contrary to that for which the medical profession stands and is contrary to the policy of the American Medical Association. The cessation of the employment of extraordinary means to prolong the life of the body when there is irrefutable evidence that biological death is imminent is the decision of the patient and/or his immediate family. The advice and judgment of the physician should be freely available to the patient and/or his immediate family.

American Medical Association Doctrine (244):

Page 6: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

66

American Medical Association Doctrine:• “extraordinary means”: ‘any procedure or intervention which

in the judgment of the attending physician would serve only to postpone artificially the moment of death.’ (North Carolina legal definition)

• “imminent”: within a week? within six months?

According to Rachels:• The AMA doctrine forbids “active euthanasia”.• The AMA doctrine permits “passive euthanasia”.

Page 7: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

77

Case 1: Throat Cancer PatientA patient is dying of incurable throat cancer, and is in terrible pain, which can no longer be alleviated.• He is certain to die within a few days, even if present

treatment is continued.• But he does not want to go on living for those few days

since the pain is unbearable.• As such, the patient asks the doctor to put and end to it,

and his family joins in the request.

Page 8: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

88

• Suppose the doctor agrees to withhold treatment, as the AMA doctrine says he may.

• The justification for his doing so is that the patient is in terrible agony, and since he is going to die anyway, it would be wrong to prolong his suffering needlessly.

• But if one simply withholds treatment, it may take longer for the patient to die, and he is sure to suffer more than he would if direct action were taken in the form of a lethal injection.

• In this case, endorsing passive euthanasia over active euthanasia leads to more suffering, and this is in direct opposition to the humanitarian impulse that fuels the original decision not to prolong his life.

• The AMA doctrine is essentially cruel!

Case 1: Throat Cancer Patient

Page 9: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

99

Case 2: Down’s Syndrome BabySome Down’s syndrome babies are born with congenital defects, such as intestinal obstructions, which require surgery if they are to live.• Intestinal surgery is relatively routine, but sometimes the

parents and the doctor will decide not to operate, and to let the child die.

• Ultimately, the child will die of dehydration and infection over the course of hours or days.

• The AMA doctrine says that this is allowable, where giving the baby a lethal injection to end its life without suffering is not.

Page 10: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1010

Case 2: Down’s Syndrome BabyThe AMA doctrine leads to life-and-death decisions made on irrelevant grounds.• The reason that the relatively simple intestinal operations

are not performed is clearly that the child has Down’s syndrome, and the parents and doctor judge that because of that, it is better to let the child die.

• But it is the intestinal obstruction and not the Down’s syndrome that risks killing the child. The issue of the intestinal blockage is essentially irrelevant to the issue of why the parents are letting the child die.

• According to this way of thinking, if there is an intestinal blockage, it is permissible to let the child die, but if there were no such blockage, one must not “kill” it.

• Surely that it leads to such life-and-death decisions made on irrelevant grounds is a strike against the AMA doctrine!

Page 11: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1111

Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:

Smith stands to gain a large inheritance should anything happen to his six-year-old cousin.• One evening, while the child is taking a

bath, Smith sneaks into the bathroom and drowns the child.

• Then Smith arranges things so it will look like an accident.

Is there a moral difference between killing and letting die?

Page 12: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1212

Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:Jones also stands to gain a large inheritance should anything happen to his six-year-old cousin.• Jones sneaks into the bathroom,

planning to drown the child in the bath.• However, when he enters, he sees the

child slip and hit his head, fallingface-down in the water.

• Jones is delighted! He stands by, readyto push the child’s head back underif necessary, but it isn’tnecessary.

• With only a little thrashing about,the child drowns all by himself,“accidentally,” while Jones doesnothing.

Page 13: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1313

Smith & Jones Thought Experiment:The only difference in the cases is that Smith killed the child, whereas Jones “merely” let the child die.• Did either man behave better, from a moral point of view?• If the difference between killing and letting die were a

morally important matter, we should say that Jones’ behavior was less morally reprehensible than Smith’s.

• But both men acted from the same motive (personal gain), and had the same end in view.

• And the consequence of each situation was the same.• If Jones pleaded, “But I didn’t kill him; I just let him die,”

we wouldn’t give this any weight.• But if there was some moral difference, we should.

Page 14: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1414

Killing vs. Letting DieThe fact that most cases of euthanasia are not motivated by greed, nor do they involve the deaths of normal healthy children, does not change the fact that there is no moral difference between killing and letting die.• The AMA policy focuses on the crucial issue of “the

intentional termination of the life of one human being by another.”

• But the AMA policy denies that the cessation of treatment is the intentional termination of a life.

• But what is the cessation of treatment but the intentional termination of a life?

• If it weren’t the intentional termination of a life, what would be the point of it?

Page 15: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1515

Killing vs. Letting DieOne reason why so many people think there is an important moral difference between killing and letting die is that most actual cases of killing are clearly terrible, and most actual cases of letting die seem motivated by humanitarian reasons.• We learn to associate killing with people with morally

reprehensible motives, and letting die with doctors trying to alleviate their patients’ suffering.

• But the difference between these cases is one of motivation, not one about the acts themselves.

Page 16: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1616

Killing vs. Letting DieStandard claim distinguishing killing from letting die:

• It is inaccurate to say that, in passive euthanasia, the doctor does nothing. He does something very important: he lets the patient die.

“The important difference between active and passive euthanasia is that, in passive euthanasia the doctor does not do anything to bring about the patient’s death […] In active euthanasia, however, the doctor does something to bring about the patient’s death: he kills him.” (246)

Page 17: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1717

Killing vs. Letting Die• In moral terms, inaction is a kind of action.• You might insult someone by not shaking their hand.• You might make someone believe you are dead by not

moving.• You might starve your pet to death by not feeding it.• If a doctor knowingly lets a patient die who was suffering

needlessly from an easily-curable illness, the doctor would be blameworthy, just as he would be if he had needlessly killed the patient.

• Just like Jones, it wouldn’t do him any good to stand by the defense that he “didn’t do anything.” For not doing anything is precisely what killed the patient.

Page 18: 1 I I Euthanasia. 2 Some Background: Voluntary Involuntary Passive Active Voluntary Passive Euthanasia Involuntary Passive Euthanasia Voluntary Active

1818

Morality and the Law• Whether a patient died as a direct result of his disease, or

as a result of a life-ending treatment can make an important legal difference.

• But this should not make an important moral difference.• Ultimately, the law forces upon medical professionals a

moral doctrine than may be indefensible, and which will have considerable effect on their practices.