43
Generating a Scientific Hypothesis about Religion A Preliminary Attempt S.N. Balagangadhara Universiteit Gent Belgium [email protected] 1

A Scientific Hypothesis About Religion by SN Balagangadhara

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

A Scientific Hypothesis About Religion by SN Balagangadhara

Citation preview

  • Generating a Scientific Hypothesis about Religion

    A Preliminary Attempt

    S.N. Balagangadhara

    Universiteit Gent

    Belgium

    [email protected]

    1

  • Criticizing a Post-Colonial Saga

    Consider the claim that most would give their assent to: Hinduism, Buddhism, Jainism, etc.,

    are the religions of India. Postcolonial intellectuals would probably add two or three

    qualifications to this claim. They would probably say that it is not possible to speak of one

    Hinduism, one Buddhism, one Jainism; instead, one should speak about many Hinduisms,

    many Buddhisms, many Jainisms, etc. Secondly, they would also raise questions about

    who could speak about these religions. Thirdly, they are likely to add that the British created

    or constructed these religions in India during the colonial period. The first two qualifications

    are either misguided or cognitively uninteresting. For instance, it is both linguistically and

    logically impossible to speak about the plurality of any religion without referring to it in the

    singular: tigers are animals because tiger names a kind; trees makes no sense if there is

    no tree to speak of, etc. Such usage is misguided, unless, of course, one maintains that

    Hinduisms is not a plural of the singular noun Hinduism. No one has maintained this

    position. In any case, we could simply accept that Hinduism, Buddhism, Jainism etc., do

    not name a unitary phenomenon but that they pick out a superset that includes many different

    sets of practices and beliefs. One can after all assume that, in principle, it is possible to

    construct such a super set even if one is unable to practically do so at any given moment. The

    second qualification is uninteresting because we are not after canonical descriptions of these

    phenomena. In this sense, it matters very little who speaks about these religions. By far, the

    most interesting qualification is the third one. Let us look at it closely.

    During the colonial period, the British created many things: an education system, the

    legal system, a bureaucracy, roads and railways. None of these existed in these forms before

    the British colonized India. Were religions like Hinduism etc., also created in this way?

    Some postcolonial thinkers are inclined to answer this question in the positive: the British

    created Hinduism as a religion in India, the way they created the Indian Civil Service (ICS).

    2

  • In that case, it follows that there is nothing fundamentally wrong with the Orientalist writings

    on Hinduism. Some of them might have made false claims, but we can correct them as more

    accurate information accumulates. The contemporary writings on Hinduism, etc., whether

    from the field of Indology or of Religious Studies, would remain continuous with the

    Orientalist writings on the subject. That is to say, the facts that the Orientalists provide

    become the point of departure for the writings in social sciences. The latter either add to these

    facts or explain them. In fact, this is also the status of the field today: the writings in the

    humanities and social sciences maintain an unbroken line of continuity with the Orientalist

    writings on these religions in India.

    In such a case, one can hardly understand what the excitement is about either

    Orientalism or postcolonial studies. Of course, if one adds other items to this creation

    story, one can blame western culture as abig bad wolf: the British created Sati, the dowry

    system, the caste system, and anything else one feels like. This exercise in apportioning

    blame uninteresting because it transforms the Indians into a bunch of idiots bereft of all

    reason. The British could do what they wanted to with the Indian culture, introduce and create

    whatever took their fancy, while their subjects stood around without stopping sucking on their

    thumbs. To put it in the language of the postcolonial thinkers: such a story deprives the

    colonial subjects of their agency. The postcolonial writers who tell such stories indeed deprive

    the colonial subjects of their agency in the name of giving it back, or they discover an

    expression of resistance to colonialism in a vigorous sucking of thumbs. Homi Bhabha, for

    instance, has made a lucrative business of telling such stories.

    A Different Creation Story

    There is, however, another way of looking at the claim of creating these religions in India.

    Despite the limitations, drawing an analogy could make it more perspicuous. Imagine that an

    extraterrestrial came to earth and noticed the following phenomena: grass is green, milk turns

    3

  • sour, birds fly, and some flowers put out a fragrant smell. He is convinced that these

    phenomena are related to each other and sees hipkapi in them. The presence of hipkapi

    explains not only the above phenomena but also how they relate to each other. To those who

    doubt the existence of hipkapi, he draws their attention to its visible manifestations: the tigers

    eating the gazelle, dogs chasing the cats, and the massive size of the elephants. Each of these

    is a fact, as everyone can see it. However, they do not tell us anything about hipkapi. When

    more extraterrestrials come to earth and reiterate the presence of hipkapi, if other conditions

    permit, hipkapi not only becomes a synonym for these phenomena but also turns out to be

    their explanation. Thereafter, to ask what hipkapi is, or even how it explains, is an expression

    of ones idiocy: does not everyone see hipkapi, this self-explanatory thing? In this analogy,

    the extraterrestrial visitor has constructed the hipkapi. To him, it is an experiential entity. He

    talks, as his fellow-beings do, about this experiential entity in a systematic way.

    That is what the Europeans did. The puja in the temples, the sandhyavandanam of the

    Brahmins, the sahasranamams, etc., became organic parts of the Indian religion.

    Purushasukta was the cosmogony of the caste system, and untouchability its outward

    manifestation. Dharma and Adharma were the Sanskrit words for good and evil, and the

    Indian deities were much like their Greek counterparts. To the missionaries, Indians were

    idolaters; to the contemporary liberal, polytheism has to do with the conception of the

    deity. In terms of the analogy, these visitors construct a hipkapi. To them, it is an

    experiential entity. They talk about this experiential entity in a systematic way.

    This analogy entails suggesting that Europeans created Hinduism etc., as their

    experiential entities. Under this construal, the Orientalists did not describe what exists in the

    Indian culture. Instead, they created a hipkapi, constructed a pattern and structure that lent

    coherence to their cultural experience of India. In such a case, claims about Hinduism become

    somewhat akin to claims about having visions of Mother Mary in the Lourdes. Only

    4

  • somewhat, because such a vision might be a hallucination, whereas one cannot say that the

    West has been hallucinating about the Indian religions.

    When the Europeans came to India and wrote down their experiences, they were not

    hallucinating. They did not write about their dreams nor did they compose stories. Whether of

    a merchant, a missionary or a bureaucrat, the reports had some structure. Reflections about

    such reports at second remove, or reflections on experiences at a later stage or in a distant

    way, led to finding a pattern or structure in these experiences. That structure is the Orient and

    the discourse about it is the Orientalist discourse.

    The previous sentence is not a description of how the pattern or structure was found. It

    is not as though any one person pored over these reports (though many did), trying out one

    inductive hypothesis after another (even though a few were formulated), until a satisfactory

    pattern finally emerged. These reports lent structure to what the Europeans saw. At the same

    time, they filtered out phenomena that could not be structured in this fashion. Thus, these

    reports contributed to structuring a European way of seeing and describing phenomena in

    India. Such texts, which embodied an explanatory structuring of the European experiences,

    ended up becoming the ethnological data or the anthropological fieldwork that the social

    theories would later try to explain.

    Orientalism is how western culture came to terms with the reality that the East is.

    That is, Orientalism refers not only to the discourse about experience but also to the way of

    reflecting about and structuring this experience. In this sense, even though Orientalism is a

    discourse about western cultural experience, it is oblique. It is oblique because it appears to

    be about other cultures. It is also oblique because it is not direct and has not been an object of

    reflection. It is western in the sense that it refers to the experiences of the members from a

    particular culture. Orientalism is the western way of thinking about its experience of non-

    western cultures. However, it takes the form of an apparent discourse about the Orient.

    5

  • It means to suggest that the West did two things: (a) created Hinduism and

    Buddhism, etc. as coherent and structured units and (b) did so as religions. The issue is not

    whether western culture created a monolithic religion instead of recognizing the multiplicity

    of theories and practices that go under the label Hinduism. It is not even whether they

    experienced Hinduism as a monolithic entity. Instead, it lies in the fact that Hinduism, as a

    concept and as an experiential entity, provided the Westerners with a coherent experience. To

    the extent it is a concept, like all other concepts, it is a human construct. It is also a construct

    because, as an experiential entity, it unifies the Western experience. However, this concept

    has no reference in the world, i.e., there is no Hinduism (whether as a religion, or as a

    multiplicity of religions) in the Indian culture. As a result, one could argue that the Saidian

    double qualification of makes sense: Hinduism is both a false description of the Indian

    reality and it is an imaginary. It is false not because the West gave a false description of the

    reality (Hinduism in this case) but because they falsely assumed that their experiential entity

    was also a real entity in the world. It is imaginary in the sense that it does not have an

    existence outside the experience of western culture. The same considerations apply to the

    caste system. The notion of such a system unified the British experience of India; they

    implemented certain political and economic policies based on their experience. However, this

    experience was not of the caste system. In fact, this experience was of no particular object but

    constituted the basis of their going-about with the Indians. By creating such a system the

    British lent stability, coherence and unity to their cultural experience. Both the caste system

    and the Indian religions are constructs in this specific sense.

    It is not as though colonialism brought Hinduism and the caste system into

    existence. The Europeans spoke about these entities as though they existed. They acted as

    though these entities were real. However, neither before nor after colonialism do such entities

    6

  • or phenomena exist. They are hipkapis. These entities merely lend structure and stability to

    the European experience.

    Here is the thesis I want to put across: except for Christianity, Islam and Judaism,

    there are no other religions in India. Entities like Buddhism, Hinduism, Jainism,

    Sikhism, etc which are called the religions of India, exist, it is true, but they do so only in

    the western universities. These religions are the imaginative creations of the western

    savants and of the culture to which they belong.

    In that case, all the books and articles, all the PhDs and all the commonsense talk

    about these religions tell you as much about India as other relevant books, articles and

    interviews tell you about the length of the Unicorns horn a creature which only virgins can

    see. Or about the relation between the upper and lower torso of a satyr or about the need for a

    curriculum reform at Harry Potters magical school, the Hogwarts.

    A Newtonian Anecdote

    As soon as such a thesis is put across, huge questions appear on the horizon. Here are some:

    are we to say that nearly four centuries of western intellectuals and nearly two centuries of

    English-speaking Indians (and others) were hallucinating? If they were not, what made them

    speak of Indian religions? If they were, why were they hallucinating, whereas I claim I am

    not?

    It is no part of my theory to suggest that the earlier generations were hallucinating. Of

    course, by the simple privilege of being born after them, from my vantage point and looking

    back, I do suggest that they were wrong. However, I do not merely record that they are wrong

    and claim that I have found the truth. What I do is something different altogether.

    What I argue is the following: thanks to their mistakes, we have the possibilities of

    correcting some of them today. To us, these mistakes take the form of cognitive problems that

    our theories have to solve. The very same theories should also explain (without adding any

    7

  • additional and ad hoc hypotheses) why thinkers from the earlier generations had to commit

    the mistakes they did commit. This cognitive requirement is important enough for us to think

    through a bit.

    Let me recount a charming anecdote that circulates in intellectual circles that makes

    the epistemological point I want to make. It appears that Sir Isaac Newton, one of the greatest

    geniuses we have known, was once congratulated as a genius who towered over both his

    predecessors and his contemporaries. The alleged reply of Newton goes as follows: Even

    the shortest of the pygmies sees farther than the tallest of men, when he stands on their

    shoulders. And I, Sir, am standing on the shoulders of giants.

    Quite apart from expressing the truly enviable intellectual humility, Newtons reply

    does something more: it tells us something about the growth of scientific knowledge itself.

    Amongst other things, it tells us that Newtons breakthrough was possible only because he

    built upon other, earlier theories. In exactly the same way, we can hope to create new theories

    today by building upon the theories of earlier generations. Thus, Orientalist description of

    India becomes the foundation for building theories about India. Today is possible only

    because of yesterday.

    Consequently, it is not sufficient to say, as the post-colonials do, that the Orientalist

    writings about India are wrong. In the process of providing alternate descriptions, we have to

    show why and how we would have committed the same mistakes were we to be placed in their

    situation. Here, the post-colonial writers fail abysmally: all they can say is that the Orientalist

    writers were misguided by their racist, imperialist, sexist and colonial motives.

    Obviously, only the post-colonial writers of today are the truly enlightened; all others before

    them were either bigots or unconscious servants of the exigencies of the colonial

    administration.

    8

  • Not only do I argue that the West imaginatively created Hinduism but also explain

    why it was compelled to do so. Its compulsion is rooted in the nature of religion, and I

    advance a hypothesis about religion that accounts for this compulsion (see further).

    Consequently, my story emerges as an alternative; it is a competitor theory to those in the

    marketplace about what religion is. This hypothesis breaks the structural unity that

    Orientalism has constructed. Hinduism, Buddhism, etc., become hipkapis. Consequently, it

    is possible to investigate which of the facts that went into constructing the hipkapi belong

    together, which do not, and how. One can start probing deeper into ones own culture,

    because ones experience is accessible for reflection. What is Hinduism? What is

    Buddhism? do not become definitional questions. Instead, they translate themselves as tasks,

    which require an alternative explanation of those facts that lend credibility to the existence of

    the hipkapi.

    Such an explanation also takes care of Lorenzens objection, which is quite fatal to

    those theories that speak of the colonial construction of Hinduism, when they have only the

    British colonialism in mind. Even though Lorenzen focuses upon the occurrence of the word

    Hinduism in India before the advent of British colonialism, there is a larger question to be

    raised. Why did Islam identify the presence of alternative and competing religions in India

    centuries before the British did? Even here, how do we understand the fact that both Islam and

    Christianity identified more or less same phenomenon as the native religion of India? My

    hypothesis answers these questions by arguing that those who come from a religious culture

    are forced to identify religions in other cultures as well and construct them, where they do not

    exist. There is logic to such constructions, the logic of the religions to which the observers

    belong. This explanation takes care of two issues: why both Islam and Christianity spoke of

    religions in India and why, this is more important, they identified (more or less) the same

    phenomenon as the native religion of India. Their construction followed analogous lines

    9

  • because of the shared heritage of the Semitic religions. In this sense, identification of

    Hinduism by the Muslims before the advent of the British does not testify to the existence of

    that religion in India; instead, it shows that there are deep lines of continuity between Islam

    and Christianity.

    In that case, what about generations of Indian intellectuals? Why do they see religions

    in their own culture? The answer has to be located in what colonialism is and what it does to a

    people: among other things, it generates what I call colonial consciousness in its subjects. It

    is generated through violence, reproduced through asymmetries in power and sustained by an

    ideology. Even though I cannot expand on this theme here, let me draw attention to one aspect

    of such a consciousness. Because the Indian culture does not have native religions, its

    intellectuals are blind to the existence of religions in their midst. Even where they look at the

    Semitic religions in India, they think that these are variants of what exist in India, namely,

    traditions. Consequently, either they simply mimic the western thinkers while talking about

    religions or, where they do not, try to re-describe Islam and Christianity as variants of Indian

    traditions. Hence the reason why many Indian intellectuals call the Muslims to reform the

    Koran or rewrite the Bible, so that they might become better suited to the Indian culture.

    In this sense, I cannot dream of suggesting that all our intellectual predecessors and all

    the contemporary English-speaking Indians were/are hallucinating. Instead, I suggest that the

    theoretical frameworks and the existing methodologies in the domain of religious studies are

    secularized variants of Christian theology. That is to say, what we call secular religious

    studies is embedded in a Christian theological framework. There is nothing secular or

    scientific about the domain of religious studies today.

    Some Additional Theses

    Immediately, the next questions force themselves upon us. Why are all the theories from the

    domain of religious studies, Christian-theological in nature? How can one make a claim as the

    10

  • one I am making, if we take the diversities in the theories and methods into consideration?

    After all, we know for a fact that not all those who study Indian religions are believers much

    less Christians. So, how could these people accept a theological framework to study the so-

    called Indian religions? I answer these questions and give more body to my earlier

    explanation by formulating the following hypothesis: I suggest that religion (in general) and

    Christianity (in particular) is characterized by a double dynamic of proselytization and

    secularization. I call this as the process of universalization of religion. Universalization wins

    converts in two ways: one through the process of conversion, where someone is inducted into

    a religious community; the other through the process of generating secular variants of its

    theology which also wins adherents. Let me explain.

    Not many would challenge the claim that Christianity has been highly influential in

    the development of western culture. We need to take this statement utterly seriously. It means

    that many things we take for granted, whether in the West or in India, are influenced by

    Christianity. As I said, I claim that Christianity expands in two ways. Both of these have been

    present ever since the inception of Christianity and have mutually reinforced each other. The

    first is familiar to all of us: direct conversion. People from other religions convert to

    Christianity and this is how the community of Christian believers grows. This is the surface or

    explicit expansion of Christianity.

    In a manner of speaking, the second way in which Christianity expands is also familiar

    to us: the so-called process of secularization. I claim that Christianity secularizes itself, as it

    were, in the form of de-Christianized Christianity. Among other things, what this means is

    that typically Christian doctrines spread wide and deep beyond the confines of the community

    of Christian believers dressed up in secular (that is, not in recognizably Christian) clothes.

    The enlightenment period, which is identified as the Age of Reason, is alleged to be

    the apotheosis of the so-called process of secularization. What people normally mean by

    11

  • secularization here is the following: the enlightenment thinkers successfully fought against

    the dominance that religion (especially, Christianity) had exercised over social, political, and

    economic life. From then on, so goes the standard text book story, humankind began to look

    to reason instead of religion in matters social, civic, political etc. The spirit of scientific

    thinking, which dominated that age, has continued to gain ascendancy in our own day and

    time. As heirs to this period, which put an end to all forms of irrational subservience, we are

    proud citizens of the modern day world. We are against all forms of despotism and believers

    in democracy; we believe in the role of reason in social life; we recognize the value of human

    rights; and we should understand that religion is not a matter for state intervention, but a

    private and personal affair of the individual in question, etc. As I say, this is the standard

    textbook story. The problem with this story is this: the enlightenment thinkers have built their

    formidable reputation (as opponents of all organized religions or even religion tout court)

    by selling ideas from Protestant Christianity as though they are neutral and rational.

    As an example, consider the claim that religion is not a matter for state intervention

    and that it is a private affair of the individual in question. If we look historically, we

    discover that the contrast between the secular realm and the religious realm (often

    formulated also as a contrast between the temporal and the spiritual), and the debates about

    the relationship between these two realms (or spheres) characterise the history of

    Christianity for the last two thousand years. This debate was primarily a theological one. It

    revolved around the question of who the Vicar of Christ was. With the Gregorian revolution

    and the emergence of Canon Law (about a thousand years ago), the Catholic Church settled

    this issue in one particular way. This theological debate was an answer to the question of the

    relationship between the King (the emperor) and the Pope. The issue in the debate was about

    the relationship between the Church as a spiritual entity and its relationship to secular

    authorities: was the King subordinate to the Church or the other way round? Did they both

    12

  • have different spheres of influence, viz., the spiritual and the temporal? What was the

    relationship between these two spheres? Etc.

    With the Protestant reformation, this theological debate became more generalized,

    especially in Continental Europe. It now involved every single Christian: could the laws and

    institutions of men (the secular structures and their injunctions) in any way restrain the

    revelations of God? Could an institution like the Catholic Church, which was seen as a human

    institution by the Protestants, add anything to the word of God? Much like the earlier debate,

    this was also theological and political. Theologically at stake was the nature of Catholic

    Church and its theology; politically, it involved the relationship between religion and state.

    Protestant theologies make the following claim: nothing can come between an

    individual and God except Gods revelation. No human law or organization can dictate how a

    man worships or what he worships. Neither the Catholic Church nor the secular authorities

    could interfere in the affairs of religion, which involves the relationship between the

    individual and God. Any such incursion in the worship of God is the corrupting influence of

    the Devil. Being a Christian believer is a matter between the Maker (i.e. God) and the

    Individual. It was God (i.e. the Christian God), who judged man; and men could not judge

    each other in matters of faith.

    The theories of state neutrality we have (the so-called Liberal theories) secularize this

    Protestant theological claim. The separation of state from religion (to put it crudely) is a

    theological doctrine of Protestant Christianity. Over the centuries, intellectuals and political

    thinkers in Europe have been ceaselessly selling Protestant theology (albeit dressed in secular

    clothes) as the summum of human civilization. The triumph of Protestantism in Europe has led

    even the Catholic Christians to accept a watered-down version of this theological claim as a

    political doctrine.

    13

  • This claim makes sense only in relationship to what religion is (i.e. in what form is

    Christianity a religion?) and how religion draws a line between the secular and the sacred.

    The lines of distinction between the religious and the secular spheres are drawn within a

    religion. Historically speaking, this demarcation is the work of Christian theology and our

    political theories are Christian theologies in disguise. The enlightenment thinkers repeated

    this Protestant story and this has become our secularism.

    The so-called religious and secular divide is a distinction drawn within a religion and

    is internal to it. No possibility exists of conceptualizing such a distinction outside of some or

    another theological framework; no neutral or scientific description of such a divide will

    ever be forthcoming. Those who moan about the process of secularization as a

    disappearance of religion are ignorant of what they are talking about: secularization is one

    of the ways in which a religion spreads in society.

    To begin appreciating the plausibility (if not the truth) of my claim, ask yourselves the

    following question: why are the so-called social sciences different from the natural

    sciences? I mean to say, why have the social sciences not developed the way natural sciences

    have? There must have been many geniuses in the field of social sciences; the mathematical

    and logical sophistication in some of the social sciences is simply mind-bending; we have

    computers that can simulate almost anything. It is not even as though the social sciences are

    totally starved of funding or personnel. Despite these, the social sciences are not progressing.

    Why is this? There are many answers provided in the history of philosophy and many of you

    may have your own favourite explanation. Here is my answer: you cannot build a scientific

    theory based on theological assumptions. What you get then is not a scientific theory, but an

    embroidering of theology. I put to you that this is what has happened. Most of our so-called

    social sciences are not sciences in any sense of the term: they are merely secularized

    Christian theologies.

    14

  • These secular variants of Christian theology include our theories of human rights as

    natural rights, our theories about the state and politics, our theories about the growth and

    development of human psychologies, our theories about human ethics and moralities, our

    constitutions that erect the wall of separation between religion and politics... This list is both

    varied and huge. Theories in multiple domains about human beings and their endeavours

    build on secularized versions of Christian theological assumptions. As such, what they tell us

    about our nature and the nature of our interactions with fellow human beings is also what

    Christianity tells us.

    The secularized-theological framework is absorbed in multiple ways by the western

    intellectuals. To such people, there is only one mode of being-in-the-world: the western mode.

    Therefore, for example, I suggest that when people do research into the evolutionary and

    natural origins of religions in human communities, they are doing theology even though they

    proclaim to the world at large that they are doing science. Is there any wonder that they set

    out to naturalize this mode of being by chattering incessantly about the evolutionary and

    biological origins of religion?

    One might plausibly assent to what I have said so far and to one of its implications:

    The western intellectuals were mistaken and continue to be mistaken in seeing religions in

    India because they make use of theological frameworks to study other peoples and cultures.

    This theology is primarily Christian in its nature and Semitic in its origin. This framework

    compels them to discover religions in every culture; in fact, the belief that all cultures have

    some or another native religion is itself theological in nature. In this sense, western

    intellectuals mistakenly see religion in all cultures because of the compulsion exerted by the

    religious framework in which they are situated.

    Let me summarize what I have said so far very sharply. Christianity spreads in two

    ways: through conversion and secularization. The modern day social sciences embody the

    15

  • assumptions of Christian theology, albeit in a secularized form. It is an insidious process, the

    process of secularization of Christian ideas.

    Christianity, in my story, has also brought forth western culture. In this sense, a

    particular religion, namely Christianity, has brought forth a secular phenomenon, namely,

    western culture. This thesis is consistent with my claim that the secular is generated by the

    religious and that the secular remains within the boundaries of the religious. This western

    culture is, therefore, religiously secular: it is a secular world within the ambit of a religious

    world and is created by the latter.

    Why has this movement of secularizing the religious come about? I claim that we

    should seek the answers in what makes Christianity into a religion; that is to say, we should

    locate the causes in those properties that make something into a religion.

    Religion: A Characterization

    The presence of which properties transform some phenomenon into a religion? What makes

    the Semitic religions into religions at all? Why do I argue that Indian culture does not have

    native religions? Even though I cannot give detailed answers to these questions in the course

    of this paper, let me provide the outlines of my answer. My characterization of religion is that

    it is an explanatory intelligible account of both the Cosmos and itself. The reason why the

    Semitic religions are religions and not something else has to do with the fact that each

    possesses this property. Let me use an analogy to elucidate this point.

    Consider a non-smoker who objects to others smoking in the same room where he is

    present. Let us say that we need to account for this objecting behaviour: Why does he object if

    others smoke in his presence? Let us now consider the two kinds of accounts, an explanatory

    and an intelligible one, which answer the above question.

    One could make the objection of the non-smoker intelligible by appealing to the

    (reasonable and justifiable) beliefs held by him: he believes that smoking is injurious to

    16

  • health; and that passive smoking is also a form of smoking; and that he does not desire to

    injure his health... etc. Hence, we can understand his behaviour by appealing to his belief-

    states (or intentional states). That is to say, by looking at this behaviour as an intentional act.

    Why does this non-smoker object to the others smoking in his presence? Because, so the

    intelligibility account goes on, he believes that... The ellipsis would get filled-in by these

    above beliefs. It is important to note that his beliefs are connected to his actions by means of

    principle(s) of sound reasoning.

    Because I merely want to illustrate the difference between two kinds of account using

    the same example, let me introduce myself into this picture as a possessor of some piece of

    information. Let us suppose that I am his friend and that one day, in strict confidence, (which

    I am, alas, breaking for the good of science) he informed me that he cannot withstand smoke.

    (He has severe asthma and some other allergies that make him react physically to smoke.) He

    does not believe that the smell is injurious to health and that, in fact, he likes it. Smirking

    smugly, I now tell you that the cause of his objection has nothing to do with his `beliefs'.

    Because, I say grinning from ear to ear, he cannot withstand smoke...

    On the one hand, it appears impossible to speak of human actions without appealing to

    desires and beliefs, but doing so reduces the predictive power (or the problem solving

    capacity) of the accounts we may give. On the other hand, the search for the underlying

    (contingent) causal laws governing human behaviour has not yielded fruits either. In any case,

    we have two kinds of accounts, an explanatory account and an intelligibility one, each of

    which appears to focus on different questions.

    Consider now an account, which promises to give us both. It suggests or hints that

    some sets of actions are intelligible because they instantiate some sets of beliefs. And that the

    relationship between intending and acting is not only constant but that nothing else

    interferes between the former and the latter to such an extent that they virtually become

    17

  • identical. To those from the outside, knowledge of these actions is sufficient to draw

    inferences about the reasons for actions. There is only one proviso attached. Because the

    observers knowledge of these actions is always framed in some description or the other, one

    can only read-off the purposes of the actions exhaustively if the descriptions of these actions

    are themselves exhaustive. That is to say, a complete and totally accurate description of the

    actions is required before we can be said to have a complete knowledge of the reasons for the

    actions.

    Such an account, when it is forthcoming; of such sets of actions, if they are possible;

    of such a being, if it exists; these, together, will give us an explanatory intelligible account of

    that being and its actions. The reason for calling it thus must be obvious: the causes of the

    action are also its reasons. Further, because each type of action instantiates one and only one

    purpose, prediction becomes possible as well. The causal law will be general, its predictive

    power is not reduced, and the causes are the intentions of such a being.

    Suppose that we now have a doctrine which says the following: such a being exists,

    such actions exist too, but we could never provide a complete description of the actions of

    such a being nor possibly observe all the actions of that being. At best, we could have a very

    fragmented and partial description of such actions. It adds further that this being has

    communicated its purposes to us the understandability of this message is again restricted by

    the descriptive possibilities open to us. In such a case, we have two sources of knowledge:

    some sets of actions that we try to understand; the message, which we try to make sense of.

    Suppose further that this being is called God; His actions are the universe; His

    message is precisely the above doctrine. We now have on our hands what we call a religious

    doctrine. This doctrine makes the Cosmos into an explanatorily intelligible entity but not by

    providing us with a detailed explanation of all events, happenings, and phenomena. It claims

    that all there is, was, and shall be (the Cosmos, that is) are expressions of a will that

    18

  • constitutes the cementing bond of the Cosmos. However, this claim about the nature of the

    Cosmos is not a bare and simple statement but is itself couched in the form of an account.

    Which kind of an account? It is an account that not only says that the Cosmos is explanatorily

    intelligible but also one which makes the Cosmos into such an entity. Among other things, the

    latter involves that the religion itself exemplifies explanatory intelligibility.

    To get a better grasp on the issue, consider what religion does. First, it imparts

    knowledge by saying that the world is the expression of the purposes of God. Because this is

    what the world is, the knowledge of the world will be an explanatory intelligible account.

    Since the religion in question is making a claim about the world, it is a knowledge-claim. It is

    not just any knowledge-claim but one which brings reasons and causes together in an

    extraordinary way. In so far as it makes this particular claim about the Cosmos, it must also

    exemplify that property which makes the universe into a specific kind of a place. That is, a

    religious account must itself be explanatorily intelligible.

    Second, this knowledge of the world is also in the world. If the universe is

    explanatorily intelligible, so is this knowledge about the world. Consequently, it is not enough

    that the doctrine says that the world expresses the Will of God, but it must also exhibit or

    express the very same will of God as well. Religion makes both the Cosmos and itself

    explanatorily intelligible. That is, it must not only tell us why God created the world and us

    but also why He gave religion to humankind.

    This, then, is what makes an explanation religious: it is knowledge of the Cosmos

    which includes itself. It is the explanation of the universe which includes itself as an

    explanandum. There would have been a logical problem here, the threat of circularity perhaps,

    if this were to be the result of our (human) understanding or theory of the world. But this

    problem does not arise, because God has revealed His purposes by speaking to us about them.

    Revelation, then, is the crucial component that breaks the possible circularity. As religious

    19

  • figures would put it perhaps, religion need not prove the existence of God at all; the existence

    of religion is the proof for the existence of God. In this sense, as an explanatory intelligible

    account, religion is Gods gift to mankind and not a human invention.

    Religion and Meaning

    To accept this account is to accept that everything in the universe has a purpose. As human

    beings, we are born and die in the Cosmos. Consequently, both events have a purpose as well.

    To be part of a religion as a first approximation is to believe that human life and death

    have significance, a meaning, and a purpose. A religious doctrine need not specify the

    purposes of any individual life or death; it is enough that it merely says that there is one. Con-

    sequently to accept that life, including your life, has meaning and purpose is to accept this

    doctrine. As an individual, you do not know what the purpose or meaning of your birth or

    death is. But because you believe that your life itself is explanatorily intelligible, your actions

    appear to you as constituting (or exemplifying) the meaning of your life.

    One of the oft-heard claims about religion is that it helps human beings to find

    meaning and purpose in their lives. Equally often heard claims suggest that one of the

    problems in the secularized societies of ours is that individuals experience anomie or

    alienation by virtue of not finding such a meaning; finding that life is meaningless; or, used

    often as a synonym in this context, absurd.

    However, it is not always clear what this claim amounts to. Are the diverse religions

    so many different attempts to find solutions to the question of meaning of ones life and

    death? Some would say no. Yet others would say yes. However, it is not evident that reli-

    gion answers this question at all. What religions have done is to assert that life and death have

    a meaning and purpose. I know of no religion that has been able to answer a specific

    individuals existential question.

    20

  • In fact, if you talk to people who do believe that they have found their meaning and

    purpose in life, you get the following reply as an explication of the said meaning of their

    lives: they describe what they are doing, and inform you that this description is the meaning

    of their lives. That is, they merely reply that their lives have meaning and that the meaning of

    their lives is the lives they are leading. To understand this better, let us consider the following

    event and its account.

    Suppose that you have a friend who attends parties or goes to dancing clubs very

    regularly. Equally regularly, he chases after women on such occasions and, let us say, he

    succeeds in picking them up each time a different woman. Puzzled, you ask him one day

    why he does this. His answer goes like this: I always want a woman I cannot get that is

    why I go after women at the parties. As soon as I get them, I lose all interest, which is why I

    drop them. Even though what you have on your hands is a mere re-description of his action,

    which you have observed, this account makes it intelligible. As Davidson (1963) formulates

    it: (T)here is no denying that this is true: when we explain an action, by giving the reason,

    we do redescribe the action; redescribing the action gives the action a place in a pattern, and

    in this way the action is explained (in Davis, Ed., 1983: 64). That is, a reason makes an

    action intelligible by redescribing it (ibid.: 67).

    Those who have found meaning in their lives do precisely this: re-describe the lives

    they are leading. Where I can help people using my skills, said a doctor to me once, I do

    so; this is what makes my life meaningful to me. Neither you nor I are any the wiser for this

    piece of knowledge; but we can see that it has the structure of an intelligibility account. Your

    friend made his action of chasing after women intelligible not merely by describing the

    pattern in his actions; by re-describing the pattern he also appears to place it in a bigger

    pattern accessible to you. The description of a pattern in one's life also re-describes the pattern

    in one's life; it also places it in a bigger pattern. To those from the outside, the bigger pattern

    21

  • appears absent, which is why this account of life does not appear intelligible. From the inside

    though, i.e., to those to whom their own lives appear meaningful, a pattern appears to be pres-

    ent. They feel that their lives are placed in a pattern and not merely that their lives have a pat-

    tern.

    They cannot tell you what that pattern is, any more than your friend can tell you about

    the pattern where his women-chasing activity is placed. In this sense, it is not true to say that

    one cannot communicate the meaning one has found to ones life because it is some in-

    tensely personal thing or because such a deep personal thing is not communicable. No. In

    fact, these people are able to communicate the meaning of their individual lives; from the

    outside, to someone who listens to such accounts, the intelligibility appears missing because

    the pattern where it requires to be placed is not known.

    More generally, the answer to the question of the meaning of life is not to be sought in

    the answer. It is found in the belief that enables the formulation of such a question. Religion

    enables one to raise such questions because it is the only framework where such queries can

    arise. Religion was not invented to answer questions about the meaning and purpose of the

    life of some or another specific individual. Such questions come into being within the

    framework of religion. These problems do not antedate religion; instead, religion generates

    them. Having done so, the religious framework tantalizingly hints that the problem is

    solvable. Take religion away, you will also take these questions away.

    By saying this, I do not imply that life is either meaningless or that it is absurd. No,

    because, even this answer is given within a framework, which makes either meaning

    attribution or its denial sensible with respect to individual or collective life. Rather, what I am

    saying is that the questions about the meaning of life are internal to religion; they are religious

    questions no matter what the answer is. They are not questions that a primitive man raised

    10,000 years ago; nor are they the questions of the modern man but those of a religious man

    22

  • a homo religiosus. Religion makes the world intelligible to us, promises also to relate us

    intelligibly to the world.

    Clearly, the difference among religions will revolve around the specification of these

    purposes. What, then, makes them into rival religions is their characterization of this

    explanatory intelligibility of human life and death (at a minimum). Their affirmation that the

    Cosmos is an explanatorily intelligible entity makes them into religions. In a deep and

    fundamental sense, to grow up within a religious tradition is to grow up with this fundamental

    experience where the Cosmos has explanatory intelligibility. Equally, to have a religion is to

    have this experience.

    However, this does not imply that, in any particular religion, some or other statement

    need occur to the effect that the Cosmos is an explanatorily intelligible entity. It makes the

    world explanatorily intelligible by structuring experience accordingly. In doing so, it avoids a

    crippling circularity by placing the origin of this account outside those who accept it. In

    simple and simplified steps, both the problem and its solution can be described as follows:

    step 1: Created by God, the Cosmos exhibits His purpose;

    step 2: As human beings, we know this because God has revealed it;

    step 3: Gods revelation consists precisely of both the above steps, including this step.

    As an account, religion tells us what the Cosmos is like (step 1); makes itself into an

    object by telling us how we could know that such is the case (step 2); characterizes both itself

    as an account and the account of the Cosmos as true (step 3). What is paradoxical, perhaps

    even impossible, when viewed from the standpoint of finite individuals with finite knowledge

    and abilities, ceases being so when claimed to instantiate the infinite knowledge of some

    totally other kind of being. The problem that we could have with respect to such knowledge

    is not epistemic but hermeneutic in nature: our interpretative abilities are finite; therefore, the

    sense that we could make of this knowledge is fallible unless, of course, this Divine Being

    23

  • would also help us out in this case. Candour requires me to add: rumour has it that this Being

    is known to do precisely that, even if His criterion for selecting individuals remains rather

    vague and mysterious.

    Looked in terms of what human beings do and what they think, religion involves a

    peculiar kind of reflexivity. It is its own justification, its own truth, founded on nothing that is

    human. Given the nature of this object, we need not wonder anymore that we have to take re-

    course to religious/theological vocabulary in order to explicate the concept of religion.

    The creation of the world and all that is in it, the Bible tells us, is the Work of God. As

    a Being with goals and purposes, He brought forth everything for some purpose or another.

    The cosmic products and processes embody the Will of this God. What we human beings see

    are the phenomena; but underlying them, and expressed in them, is the Will of God. The same

    God, the Good Book further tells us, has manifested His Will to us in two ways: through

    revelation, as expressed in the scriptures; and in His product, viz., Nature. We can study His

    Works and through such a study learn inductively about His Will; and then, there is also the

    Biblical revelation. In a deep and fundamental sense, the world is governed by the Will of The

    Sovereign.

    How can we know the will of an actor by studying his actions? From our experience in

    the world, we do know that there is a hiatus between the actions we perform and our belief

    states. Even such a trivial action as my opening a door could not be said to instantiate some

    or other belief unambiguously: perhaps, I feel that the room is stuffy or that it is too cold;

    perhaps I want you to get out; or I sense an eavesdropper You cannot, in other words, read-off my intentions unambiguously by looking at my actions. You could also ask me the reasons

    for my action: but I could deceive you by telling a plausible lie; or I forgot my own reasons;

    or that I am not even sure that I have reasons... This being the case, how can we know (or

    even hypothesize about) Gods Will by studying His actions?

    24

  • The answer must be obvious. God is perfectly good, perfectly consistent and that His

    actions perfectly express His intentions... etc. The Sovereign's Will is not arbitrary but

    perfectly constant. Because he is a Being who is perfectly trustworthy, His works do not

    deceive us. The ascription of predicates of perfection to God, which many authors use as an

    argument for the impossibility of His existence, I suggest, was a necessary condition for the

    emergence of human knowledge about the natural world.

    Consider, by contrast, the gods of the so-called religions like those of the Greeks, the

    Romans, or the Hindus. What is constant about these gods is their capriciousness or unpre-

    dictability. They ceaselessly interfere with the affairs of mankind but in ways that are both

    unpredictable and mysterious. Thus, it is only right and proper that the universe is not

    governed by their will.

    Let me reformulate the earlier paragraphs in the following way: the Bible inculcates an

    experience of the Cosmos as a particular kind of order, and this order consists of the fact that

    phenomena express a deep, underlying constancy. This constancy is the Will of The Sover-

    eign. His Will governs the world.

    Religion and Truth

    In our daily activities in the world, we assume that many of our beliefs and theories are true.

    One such candidate, for example, is that the earth revolves around the sun or that we do not

    change shape while we sleep. Even though we do not know whether they are true, we have no

    reason (as yet) to presume their falsity. The assumption about the truth of these beliefs is

    strengthened by a whole number of other beliefs from sending satellites to circle the earth to

    biological theories and medical practices and we do not really despair about the tentative

    and hypothetical nature of our theories. Commendable and necessary though such attitudes

    are, our indifference does not affect the epistemological point: any and all of our theories

    could turn out to be false.

    25

  • Religion not only tells us the way the Cosmos is, but also makes itself explanatorily

    intelligible. Based on human knowledge and human cognitive abilities, both of which are

    finite, we could never arrive at an explanatory intelligible account, which includes itself as an

    explanandum.

    Furthermore, religion, which claims to be the truth about the world, is radically

    independent of our prior theories about the world. Whether one believes in the existence of

    witches, ancestors, or quantum particles; whether one can understand Gdels theorem or the

    mechanism of gene-splicing; whether one can drive a car or not; ones access to the message

    of religion is not affected. Grasping the truth of the religious account does not depend on our

    finite knowledge of the world and this truth, note well, is about the Cosmos. On our own, as

    these religions have explained themselves, we could only arrive at a vague conception of

    God as the creator. But this notion does not make the world explanatorily intelligible. God has

    to reveal himself and aid us in seeing the truth because this truth does not depend upon human

    knowledge and what we, at any given moment, believe to be true.

    What we have on our hands, then, is an account that has no parallels in the domain of

    human knowledge. We know of partial explanatory accounts; we think that our folk-

    psychology makes use of intelligibility accounts. Religion alone is both an explanatory and an

    intelligibility account. Not of this or that individual phenomenon, but of the Cosmos and

    itself.

    Corresponding to this, the issue and the question of truth take a radical form. The

    problem is not whether religion is true in the same way my belief about Brussels being the

    capital city of Belgium is true. The latters truth depends on other beliefs being true as well.

    Such is not the case for religion at all. If we use the predicate true to describe religion, it

    looks as though we cannot use it for anything else: what makes religion true cannot make

    26

  • anything else true. Religion is the truth in the specific sense of not being dependent on the

    truth of any other belief we hold about the world.

    Religion Sui Generis?

    To the reader and to someone familiar with contemporary religious studies, two things must

    be clear by now: (a) my characterization of religion attempts to make sense of the experience

    of the believers. In contemporary jargon, I privilege the insider perspective as against the

    outsider perspective. (b) In doing so, I seem to talk as though religion cannot be studied

    using methods and theories from other sciences. In the words of McCutcheon, I seem to speak

    of religion as sui generis. Because I cannot fully answer these objections in the course of

    this article, let me make a few points in my defence, using a realist language.

    What we have in human cultures are specific phenomena like Christianity, Islam,

    Judaism and such like. If they are religions, then they are that by virtue of possessing some

    property that makes them into religions. In this sense, religion is a property of these specific

    phenomena. The insider and outsider problem makes sense only with respect to specific

    religions because they also have other properties than that of religion. However, with respect

    to that property which makes them into religion (the explanatory intelligibility that I talk

    about), there is no outsider perspective available to us human beings. Only that entity

    (God, in our case) whose will is the causal force of the Cosmos has an outsider perspective

    with respect to the explanatory intelligible account that religion is. Consequently, we cannot

    study religion as religion (or under the description of religion) from outside, ever.

    I am not speaking about what makes some phenomenon into Christianity but what

    makes Christianity into religion. From the outside, without having any such account, I cannot

    say what makes some account an explanatorily intelligible account of the Cosmos; why it

    does this to some and not to the others; what does the explanatory intelligibility consist of;

    etc. Maximally, one can do what I have done: take note of the fact that religion is an

    27

  • explanatory intelligible account. To be sure, we can ask the believers to explain themselves.

    In such a case, we will be studying what it means to believe for these people; if and where

    we can understand their answer to the meaning of the Cosmos and life, we will have some

    idea about what it means to be religious. But that is a different issue altogether.

    In fact, my characterization of religion says as much. Religion exhibits reflexivity:

    religion includes what it says about itself; religious language is both the object language and

    its own meta-language. Consequently, the possibility of a science of religion resides in our

    willingness to accept theology as science.

    However, this does not mean that one cannot study religion scientifically. If we study

    religion as religion, only then are we forced to do theology. But religion can be studied at

    different levels of description: (a) as religion; (b) as world view; (c) as a causal force in a

    culture; (d) as specific religions, etc. In this sense, yes, we can study religion scientifically but

    we must know the level at which we can provide a scientific description. In this sense, I am

    not in the least suggesting that we cannot study religion using theories and methods from the

    sciences.

    But, it does mean the following. My characterization of religion enables us to come to

    grips with authors like Schleiermacher and Otto, who have spoken of religious experience,

    without accusing them of bad faith or imputing apologetic motivations to them. Both argue

    that having a religious experience presupposes that one belongs to a religion, and that the non-

    rational elements are related to the rational. Indeed so. Religion is an account that involves

    concepts. To accept it is to feel a part of the purposes of that Being and depend on Him. With-

    out such an account, there is no question of experiencing the absolute dependency that

    Schleiermacher talks about; at best, all we can experience is a kind of relative dependency

    upon each other. In such a case, the other is not The Totally Other of Schleiermacher. To

    28

  • have the kind of experience that Schleiermacher talks about, we need to accept the

    explanatorily intelligible account of the Cosmos, i.e., accept religion.

    It is this property that makes not only Christianity but also Judaism and Islam into

    religions. But that which makes them into religion also divides, and this dispute is unsolvable

    because it has no solution. Each is a specific religion, that is, each is an explanatorily

    intelligible account and each makes the Cosmos into an explanatorily intelligible entity to

    those who accept this account. Some individual may, at any given moment of time, switch

    from one to the other on the ground that one does it better than the other. But his ground is

    that one succeeds better than the other in making the Cosmos explanatorily intelligible to him.

    He may even believe and, indeed, he has to that this superiority arises from the fact that

    one is better than the other. But he can only do so after the other account has made the

    Cosmos explanatorily intelligible to him but not before. He can judge that one religion is bet-

    ter than the other, only after trading places. A formal conversion may (and often does) come

    later, but the point is that there is no vantage point for the human being to judge the

    superiority of one religion against the other. The reason is, of course, simple: religion must

    make the Cosmos explanatorily intelligible to the individual in question.

    Very often, believers make the claim that one cannot investigate the nature of religion,

    unless one is a believer oneself. Brilliant and reputed thinkers have tried to argue for this point

    of view. Equally often, such people have been accused by their opponents of bad faith,

    dogmatism and suspected of harbouring apologetic motivations. Any phenomenon can be

    scientifically studied, the opponents have maintained, including both religion and science.

    Why should one believe in God in order to discuss His existence? One does not have to be a

    stone to describe its fall, any more than one has to be a neurotic to discuss the nature of

    neurosis. Therefore, why should one be religious to scientifically investigate religion?

    29

  • Consider what I just said above regarding how anyone could judge the superiority of

    one religion against the other. One can only do so from within the framework of some specific

    religion or another. The reason, as I have said, lies in the fact that they are all explanatorily

    intelligible accounts. Only from within the framework of one religion can we judge the

    adequacy of the other. In the starkest possible terms: to investigate religion as an

    explanatorily intelligible account of the Cosmos we need to accept some or another

    explanatorily intelligible account of the Cosmos. That is, religion can be investigated only by

    being religious yourself; religion is an object of investigation from within some or another

    religion. This position stands to reason because, as I have said, religion makes itself

    explanatorily intelligible too. The believers are not, I submit, dogmatic when they say, as

    Sderblom did, that the only science of religion could be theology.

    Again, it is important to note what I am saying and what I am not. Any specific

    doctrine within a specific religion say, for example, the doctrine of trinity is not immune

    from criticism or beyond discussion. After all, those who do not accept it do criticize and

    discuss this doctrine. In this sense, in all probability, every single doctrine of every religion

    has been discussed and criticized either at one time or another. So, if a Jew can criticize the

    doctrine of Trinity, why not someone else, who denies the existence of God? Belonging to a

    religion is not equivalent to holding a party card.

    Some Contemporary Criticisms

    Quite apart from the above remarks, my attempt has also met with criticisms either directly or

    indirectly. I should like to answer a few of them, beginning with those of Sweetman and

    Pennigton. Both believe that my definition of religion is flawed because I take Christianity

    (especially, according to them, Protestant Christianity) as an exemplary instance of the

    category of religion. Failing to appreciate what I do or even understand the difference

    between a definition and a hypothesis, they come up with totally muddleheaded criticisms. In

    30

  • what follows, I shall not try to set right the manifold confusions in Sweetmans thinking but,

    instead, address myself to his central criticism.

    He detects the following form in my argument:

    First premise: Christianity is prototypically what religion is.

    Second premise: Hinduism does not share all (or perhaps any) of the relevant properties of

    Christianity.

    Conclusion: Hinduism is not a religion. (p.337)

    To begin with, let me make three logical points about his reconstruction of my argument. In

    the first place, the conclusion that Sweetman attributes to me is not derivable on the basis of

    these two premises alone: we need more. No one can derive the conclusion (without adding

    additional premises) that Sweetman attributes to me: Hinduism is not a religion. As a result,

    second, as it stands now, the conclusion is invalid: the only possible conclusion that one can

    draw from the above is the following: Hinduism is not prototypically what a religion is. (Of

    course, this could imply that Hinduism is a religion, even if it is not prototypically what a

    religion is.) Third, he wants to take issue with the truth of the conclusion but he does so by

    throwing doubts upon the truth of the premises. A freshman introduction to logic course

    would have told him that he cannot do this. In deductive logics, truth is transmitted from the

    premises to the conclusion but not their falsity. Falsity travels, again in deductive logics, the

    other way round: falsity is transmitted from the conclusion to the premises. In other words,

    there is an asymmetry in the transmission of truth and falsity in deductive logics. Thus, he

    cannot contest the truth of the conclusion (that he attributes to me) on logical grounds by

    challenging the truth-value of the premises. Yet, he does exactly that.

    Let me take up the more substantive issues. My statement about the exemplary nature

    of Christianity must, above everything else, be situated in the context of providing an

    ostensive definition of the term religion. Such an ostensive gesture though given in

    31

  • language instead of in physical gestures does not make any claims about the nature of

    religion except to point out that, in our language-use (in western languages), the word

    religion refers at least to Christianity. Such an ostensive definition does not mean that

    Christianity is the best religion or the most perfect one or the only one. In fact, it is easily

    conceivable that Christianity is not even a religion and that our language-use is wrong.

    However, it is sensible to say this only when we have a theory of religion and not before. In

    other words, ones view of Christianity whether it is a true religion or merely a false

    consciousness does not affect the definition I am putting forward. My definition registers a

    fact about a language-use but makes no further assertions either about Christianity or about

    religion.

    I am not providing an explicit definition of the word religion; I am simply identifying

    an example, a prototypical example, of the category religion. I am not making any

    assumptions about what religion is, or what makes Christianity into one. My only argument

    is: if Christianity is not an exemplary instance of religion, then we have no other examples

    of religion. Therefore, I make no assumptions about the nature of religion or of Christianity in

    beginning a study of religion. In fact, I do not even assume the existence of religion. Rather, I

    merely point out the fact that unless we can show that our language-use refers to an entity that

    does not exist in our world in which case we need not study religion at all we may not

    reject our linguistic practice. If religion refers to something at all, the history of our natural

    language-use with respect to this word does suggest that it does, it must at least refer to

    Christianity. Otherwise, it picks out a fictitious entity and this is a theoretical claim that

    one cannot make at the preliminary stage of defining a word in a theory.

    Suppose that we extend this argument further. The very same linguistic practice that I

    talk about also refers to following entities: Leprechauns, Cyclops, Satyrs and Unicorns.

    Our linguistic practice not only assures us that these words refer to creatures in the world but

    32

  • also provides us with entertaining tales about the behaviour of such creatures. We can take

    issue with the claims about the existence of such creatures (and, thus, whether these words

    have any reference in the real word) only by accepting the theories in evolutionary biology

    and not by talking about some or another philosophical claim about meaning and

    reference. In this sense, if one wants to challenge the linguistic-use with respect to the word

    religion, it is advisable that one arms oneself adequately, i.e., one should have some or

    another substantial theory about the relevant part of the world. A bare claim about meaning

    and reference will not do.

    On the reference of the word religion

    When we use the category religion, we minimally refer to Christianity. Why minimally?

    What if someone refuses to recognize that Christianity is a prototypical instance of the

    category religion? My answer is that this is the only option open to us, unless we make

    epistemic assumptions about the object before having studied it.

    Suppose that someone denies the prototypicality of Christianity as a religion. Then, he

    has to (a) either deny that the concept religion has any reference to any entity in the world;

    (b) or claim that it has some other reference. If he argues the first position, he is running

    counter to our linguistic practice where the word does have a reference. Of course, one is at

    perfect liberty to counter the linguistic practice; but, then, he must also have some kind of a

    theory about what religion is and what it is not. Such a theory also has to explain why, for

    more than two-thousand years, the word found a home in Christian theory and practice.

    Let me linger on this point a bit longer because quite a few scholars argue today

    (Jonathan Smith, Russell McCutcheon to name a few) that the word religion has no

    reference to anything in the world and that it is merely a part of scholars talk. In fact

    Jonathan Smith even claims that there is no data for religion. How much is this argument

    33

  • worth? By building an analogical argument, let me identify the conditions under which such

    an argument becomes admissible.

    Let us suppose that I make the following claim: the words gravity and gravitational

    force are mere words in the scholarly talk. They are parts of scholarly discourse. In the

    absence of theories about gravity and gravitational force, what could we possibly conclude

    about the reference of these words? Epistemically speaking, one cannot conclude anything

    because we cannot know what the data sets for these words are. It is only a theory about these

    phenomena that tells us that the free fall of objects, the ebb and tide in the sea and the

    presence of atmosphere on earth, etc. have all to do with gravity and gravitational force. Such

    a theory also postulates relations between these phenomena and gravitational force. Thus, it is

    the theory of gravitation that tells us what its facts are. Without such a theory, we might

    notice some facts: that objects in free fall downwards or that there are ebbs and tides in the

    sea etc. But our problem is: which theory should explain these facts? Should a theory in

    geography or a theory from physics or a theory about the fairies and angels tell us about the

    why? Should one particular theory explain all the above facts, or are they discrete facts for

    different theories? There is no way we can answer such questions in the absence of a theory

    that effectively solves these problems. In the absence of such theories, it is meaningless to

    make the claim that there is no data for gravity. Because none of the authors named above

    have anything that remotely resembles a theory of religion or a theory of scholarly discourse

    in the domain of religious studies, or a theory of theologies, their claim is unfounded. Worse,

    it is meaningless.

    However, it is meaningless only if treated as a philosophical objection. Actually,

    though disguised as an objective criticism, it is actually ad hominem: they are directed

    against certain authors (Scheleirmacher, Otto, Eliade and others), who are characterized as

    harbouring apologetic motivations. Basically, the accusation is that some scholars attempt to

    34

  • prevent a naturalistic study of religion by cordoning off religion from any such approach.

    Apparently, they do this by suggesting that religious experience, religiosity, etc. are

    unique to religion.

    The problem with ad hominem attacks is that they embody fallacious reasoning. One

    cannot either criticize or explain Schleirmachers theory about religion by suggesting that he

    had apologetic motivations. Though meaningful in so far as speculations about motives are

    concerned, such fallacious arguments have no place in an intellectual discussion. If taken as

    philosophical criticisms, as I have said, they are meaningless.

    On the other hand, one could meaningfully suggest that gravity and gravitational

    force do not refer to anything in the real world, when there is a theory of gravity and

    gravitational force. This is a philosophical stance that some assume with respect to scientific

    theories: one could consider such concepts as fictions, or as theoretical terms, or as

    pragmatically useful concepts that help us predict etc. In other words, it is a sensible meta-

    scientific standpoint that tries to account for scientific theories by denying reference to

    theoretical terms. However, today, we are not in such a situation.

    Regarding the second point, I can be briefer. Indeed, the concept could have other

    references, but it minimally picks out Christianity. To argue that it refers to some other entity

    without referring also to Christianity is to take an epistemic decision: after all, Christianity has

    described itself as a religion, and the word has its home in the European languages. To go

    against either of these two facts is to have a theory about both.

    This linguistic practice itself is not neutral. After all, it is the practice of a community

    that speaks this way and not that or another way. I do not deny this. This fact about the

    linguistic practices of a community having a cultural history reflects a general point, viz., that

    as socio-cultural entities, we function in a context. To be sure, it also underlines the fact that

    scientific enquiries have a context too. But then, these are the general presuppositions of any

    35

  • human enquiry not merely of this one. Needless to say, that I am a human being and, conse-

    quently, I am situated in a cultural and intellectual milieu is not quite the same as accepting

    presuppositions either about religion or the relation of Christianity to religion.

    Let us say that in some phenomenon this or that property, or even a group of them, is

    absent; let us assume that these very same properties are present in Christianity. This situation

    does not tell us a great deal: it could be that the former is merely less prototypical than

    Christianity; or that the former is a truer religion than Christianity; it could be that both have

    all the properties of religion; etc.

    Could we answer the question about the existence or nonexistence of religion by

    simply looking at the properties of Christianity? That is, can we argue that because some

    properties characteristic of Christianity are absent from traditions elsewhere, (say, in

    Hinduism or Buddhism) the latter cannot possibly be religions? Such an argument is

    possible only if one is able to show that the properties of Christianity which one has identified

    are also the properties of religion. In the absence of such proof, all that one can do is to notice

    that Christianity and some other tradition differ from each other. However, one cannot argue

    that, because of these differences, some other tradition is not a religion.

    This is so obvious a point that one wonders how Sweetman could possibly see me

    arguing the opposite. Consider the distinction between Christianity as a historical movement

    and Christianity as a religion. Today, the former owns buildings, land, telephones, television

    studios, aircrafts, etc. These are the properties in both the senses of possessions and

    predicates of Christianity. Is it any more or less of a religion because of that? The only way

    we can answer this question either way is by postulating (or having a theory about) the

    relation between Christianity and religion. One may want to argue that Christianity has

    progressively become less of a religion because it is now more interested in earthly

    possessions. Or the other way round. Notice, however, that this argument can work only if we

    36

  • know what religion is. By looking at Christianity alone as the exemplar of the concept of

    religion we can make no such claim.

    One can think of many such examples. One such is the obverse of this argument.

    Because some or another tradition appears to share some of the properties of Christianity,

    people have argued, the former is also a religion. This is how the anthropologist Martin

    Southwold, for instance, argues: because Buddhism shares many properties of Christianity,

    the former is also a religion even if it does not believe in God. This argument is flawed for

    exactly the same reason as well: the properties that Christianity has by virtue of being a

    religion may or may not be identical to the properties that it has by virtue of being a historical

    movement. If Southwold can argue anything at all on grounds of his polythetic attributes, he

    would have to say: because Buddhism shares many properties of Christianity, the former is

    also like Christianity minus its belief in God. But he does not say this, does he?

    In more mundane terms: we are studying, let us say, a brown cat that limps, has one

    eye, a tail, one ear, a few teeth, and eats rats. Question: Is limping, having one eye, a tail, one

    ear, being brown, having a few teeth, eating rats, the properties of all cats or merely of this

    specific cat? Answer: that depends on the knowledge we have of cats. Precisely.

    The Argument Explained

    Instead of focussing further on Sweetman and Pennigton, let me outline the way I formulate

    the problem of studying religion.

    As I have argued, if the word religion picks out something, it refers at least to Chris-

    tianity because the latter refers to itself as a religion (i.e., it uses the word with respect to

    itself). This self-reference is not a few centuries old: it has been so used ever since the

    inception of Christianity. If Christianity refers to itself as a religion and recognizes itself as

    one, then the terms in which it does so gives us its concept of religion. This concept not only

    enabled Christianity to describe itself as a religion, but also helped it to recognize some of the

    37

  • rivals it encountered as religious rivals. Therefore to study Christianity as a religion is to

    study those properties by virtue of which not only did Christianity think of itself as a religion

    but also confronted rival or competing religions. This is the first step of the argument. This

    step merely allows us to establish the terms of description. These very same terms, however,

    allow us to take the second step.

    Christianity is a historical movement. So are Judaism and Islam. The former has

    construed the latter as rival religions. Whatever goals they were/are competing for, they

    did/do so as religions. Judaism and Islam were not merely baptized as rival religions by

    Christianity. These two also saw Christianity as a rival religion under the same description.

    The second step establishes that the terms under which Christianity recognized itself

    as religion are also the terms under which Islam and Judaism recognize themselves as

    religions as well (using whatever word they use). That is to say, the concept used by Chris-

    tianity to call itself a religion is also the one which makes some (Judaism and Islam) who do

    not call themselves as religions into religions (because it is also their self-description).

    Therefore, the Christian concept is not just Christian. It cuts across the three Semitic

    religions. This is not my concept or your concept, but self-descriptions of these religions. At

    the same time, it suggests that the concept of religion is itself part of a religious framework

    and vocabulary. This lends a greater probability to the claim that whether or not Judaism and

    Islam use the word religion, they too are religions. That is, if Christianity is a religion, so are

    Judaism and Christianity.

    The third step picks out two salient facts. One: the terms under which Christianity

    transformed Islam and Judaism are also those that make Judaism and Christianity rivals to

    Islam, and Islam and Christianity rivals to Judaism. The possibility that Judaism and Islam

    were merely reacting to the attacks of Christianity and were, therefore, forced to accept the

    terms of Christianitys self-description is ruled out by the second salient fact: all three

    38

  • singled out exactly the same rivals under the same description elsewhere unerringly. Judaism

    had singled out the Roman religio as its rival before Christianity was even born; Islam had

    picked out precisely those Indian traditions as its rivals, which Christianity was also to

    identify, centuries before the European Christians launched their major and massive

    evangelizing activities.

    The fourth step completes this argument by looking at the reaction of the rivals

    identified by Christianity, Judaism, and Islam. These rivals, the Roman religio and the Indian

    traditions, did not recognize themselves in the description provided by Christianity, Judaism

    and Islam. Nor did they see the relationship between themselves and the latter as religious

    rivalry. Incomprehension of the terms of description and indifference to the alleged rivalry

    characterize the reactions of those belonging to the Roman religiones and the Indian

    traditions. There are different roads to heaven, said the one shrugging its shoulders; How

    could only your religion be true and ours false? asked the other uncomprehendingly. Even

    under persecution, this tone did not change. The persecution of the Christians in the early

    Roman Empire did not take place using those terms which Christianity would use to persecute

    the pagans centuries later.

    The third and the fourth step, together, establish the following case: the terms under

    which Christianity recognized itself and identified rival religions were also those that

    provided self-identity and rivals to Judaism and Islam. Precisely this description was incom-

    prehensible to those in whose language the word religion existed (the Roman religio) and

    to those who had no such word (the Indians). Neither recognized itself in this description;

    neither fought the others as rivals under this description.

    These four steps constitute the historical constraints under which we must generate

    our hypothesis about religion. On the one hand, our hypothesis must capture the self-

    description of the Semitic religions; further, it must also explain why Hinduism,

    39

  • Shintoism, etc., also appear as religions (even if they are false religions) to them. On the

    other hand, the very same hypothesis must also explain why neither the Hindus nor the

    Romans were able to recognize themselves as religions, whether true or false. Why this

    double constraint and what does it do?

    Quite apart from the issue that these are historical facts that any hypothesis on religion

    has to explain, there is something more intriguing here. If one merely generates a

    naturalistic hypothesis about religion that tells us why both the Semitic religions and the

    Indian traditions (and the Roman religiones) are religions, then there is no reason to choose a

    so-called naturalistic hypothesis above a theological explanation: both explain the same

    phenomenon in the same way, viz., they are all religions. Actually, the situation is far worse:

    theological theories tell us more about the differences between, say, Hinduism on the one

    hand and the Semitic religions on the other. That is, apart from noticing all kinds of detailed

    differences between these two groups (which a naturalistic hypothesis can also do),

    theologies provide additional explanations of these differences: Hinduism is a false religion

    because it practices idolatry (for example). In other words, if one intends to be scientific, then

    one has to choose a theological explanation above a naturalistic hypothesis because the

    former explains more facts than the latter can possibly do. This is one side of the coin.

    The second side of the coin is this. If, on the other hand, we develop a naturalistic

    hypothesis about religion that merely shows that Hinduism etc are not religions (because

    there is no religion), then we merely side with the pagans and dis