24
Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices Aristotle and Our Contemporaries

Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

  • Upload
    elpida

  • View
    64

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices. Aristotle and Our Contemporaries. Introduction. Concern for character has flourished in the West since the time of Plato, whose early dialogues explored such virtues as courage and piety. Two Moral Questions. The Question of Action : - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Aristotle and Our Contemporaries

Page 2: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

IntroductionConcern for character has flourished in the West since the time of Plato, whose early dialogues explored such virtues as courage and piety

Page 3: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Two Moral Questions

• The Question of Action:- How ought I to act?

• The Question of Character:- What kind of person ought I to be?

• Our concern here is with the question of character.

Page 4: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

An Analogy from the Criminal Justice System

As a country, we place our trust for just decisions in the legal arena in two places:1. Laws, which provide the necessary rules2. People, who (as judge and jury) apply rules

judiciouslySimilarly, ethics places its tgrust in:3. Theories, which provide rules for conduct4. Virtue, which provides the wisdom necessary for

applying rules in particular instances.

Page 5: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Virtue• Strength of character (habit• Involving both feeling and action• Seeks the mean between excess and deficiency relative to us• Promotes human flourishing

- Aristotle

Page 6: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Sphere of Existence

Deficiency Mean Excess

Attitude toward self ServilitySelf-depreciation

Proper Self-LoveProper PrideSelf-Respect

ArroganceConceitEgoismNarcissimVanity

Attitude toward offenses of others

Ignoring themBeing a Doormat

AngerForgivenessUnderstanding

RevengeGrudgeResentment

Attitude toward good deeds of others

SuspicionEnvyIgnoring them

GratitudeAdmiration

Over-indebtedness

Attitude toward our own offenses

IndifferenceRemorselessnessDownplaying

Agent RegretRemorseMaking AmendsLearning from themSelf-Forgiveness

Toxic GuiltScrupulousityShame

Attitude toward our friends

Indifference Loyalty Obsequiousness

Page 7: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Spheres of Existence - 2Attitude toward our own good deeds

BelittlingDisappointcment

Sense of AccomplishmentHumility

Self-righteousness

Attitude toward suffering of others

Callousness Compassion Pity“Bleeding Heart”

Attitude toward the achievement of others

Self-satisfactionComplacencyCompetition

AdmirationEmulation

Envy

Attitude toward death and danger

Cowardice Courage Foolhardiness

Attitude toward our own desires

Anhedonia TemperanceModeration

LustGluttony

Attitude toward other people

Exploitation Respect Deferentiality

Page 8: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Two Conceptions of Morality

• We can contrast two approaches to the moral life.--The childhood conception of moral life• Comes from outside (usually parents)• Is negative (“don’t touch that stove burner)• Rules and habit formation are central.

---The adult conception of morality• Comes from within (self-directed_• Is positive (“this is the kind of person I want to be”)• Virtue centered, often modeled on ideals.

Page 9: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

The Purpose of Morality

• Both of these conceptions of morality are appropriate at different times in life.

• Adolescence and early adulthood is the time when some people make the transition from the adolescent conception of morality to the adult conception.

Page 10: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Rightly-ordered Desires

• Aristotle draws an interesting contrast between:• Continent people, who have unruly desires but

manage to control them.• Temperate people, whose desires are naturally—

or through habit, second-nature—directed toward that which is good for them.

• Weakness of will (akrasia) occurs when individuals cannot keep their desires under control.

Page 11: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Rightly-ordered Desires and the Goals of Moral Education

• Moral education may initially seek to control unruly desires through rules, the formation of habits, etc.

• Ultimately, moral education aims at forming rightly-ordered desires, that is, teaching people to desire what is genuinely good for them.

Page 12: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Character and Human Flourishing• Aristotle on Human Flourishing

- functional context: a good hammer nails well, a good guitar is capable of making good music.

- unique properties: for humans reasoning or thinking: for Aristotle, the contemplative life leads to happiness. Largely determined by leisure.

- for Aristotle happiness is related to practical wisdom. Deliberating well promotes flourishing and a recognition of political conception of happiness – that humans are happy in a social context.• Pluralistic approach recognizes humans have many goals,

contemplative and social. Some restraints on goals from our social and intellectual natures.

Page 13: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Assessing Aristotle’s Account of Flourishing

• Anti-reductionistic – not lowest common denominator.

• Holism – other extreme: highest common denominator. Overemphasis on role of thinking not totality of human functions.

• Ethics for nobility – ethics for privileged ruling class, free, adult Greek males.

Page 14: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Contemporary Accounts of Human Flourishing

• External impediments to human flourishing: - social factors: economics, architecture of living

and work environments• Internal Impediments:

- Freud’s or Jung’s balance of psychological factors

- Maslow’s peak experiences- we are our own worst enemies; flourishing is

primarily a state of mind rather than a state of matter.

Page 15: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Aristotle’s Definition of Virtue

• A habit or disposition of the soul• Involving both feeling and action• To seek the mean in all things relative to us• Where the mean is defined through reason as

the prudent man would define it (EN 2, p.6)

• Virtue leads to happiness or human flourishing.

Page 16: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Habits of Soul

• According to Aristotle virtue is a hexis, a dispostion or habit.

• We are not born with virtues. We acquire them through imitation of role models and practice.

• Moral education focusses on the development of character, or what Aristotle calls “soul.”

Page 17: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Feeling and Action

• For Aristotle virtue is not just acting in a particular way but feeling certain ways.

• Virtue includes emotion as well as action.• The compassionate person not only helps to alleviate

suffering but has feelings toward others’ suffering.• Exclusion of feeling from moral consideration led to

problems for Kantian theory, utilitarianism and egoistic theories. Aristotle’s inclusion of the emotive character of virtue overcomes this objection.

Page 18: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Virtue As the Golden Mean

• Strength of character (virtue), Aristotle suggests, involves finding the proper balance between two extremes.

--Excess: having too much of something--Deficiency: having too little of something• Not mediocrity, but harmony and balance.• See examples below.

Page 19: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Courage• The strength of character necessary to continue in the face

of our fears.-Deficiency: cowardice, the inability to do what is

necessary to have those things in life which we need in order to flourish.

• Too much fear• Too little confidence

-Excess: Rashness* Too little fear.* Too much confidence* Poor judgment about ends worth achieving.

Page 20: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Courage and Gender

• Women are not warriors: For Aristotle, women can’t be courageous in the fullest sense. They weren’t allowed to fight in wars. Only in 2011 have women been permitted active combat roles in America.

• Underrecognition of Women’s Courage: Native American and European pioneer women required courage. Childbirth requires courage. Courage in response to emotional and physical abuse. Developmental challenges of going from girlhood to womanhood.

Page 21: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Compassion

• Compassion begins in feeling.• Compassion needs action.• Moral imagination needed to translate feeling

into action.• Compassion is not pity – acknowledges a kind

of moral equality.

Page 22: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Self-Love

• Involves feeings as well as acting and knowing.• Loving Others – wants to see the other flourish.• Loving Ourselves – not unconditional self-

approval, involves self-examination and deep concern for welfare of the self.

• Self-love involves a self that is engaged in the world.

• Self-love demands self knowledge.

Page 23: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Practical Wisdom or Phronesis

• Application of specific excellence of character to a particular situation in light of an overall conception of the good life.

• Knowing how to achieve a particular end and which ends are worth striving to achieve.

• The virtues are interdependent.• Practical wisdom is difficult and elusive.

Page 24: Ch. 9 – the Ethics of Character: Virtues and Vices

Ethical Pluralism and Practical Wisdom

• Balance competing theories in particular situations.

• Admit all relevant moral considerations and seek best balance.

• Act-oriented traditions needed to balance character ethics. This is practical wisdom.