42
Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Econ 522Economics of Law

Dan Quint

Fall 2010

Lecture 3

Page 2: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

HW1 is online (due 5 p.m. Sept 24)Also lecture notes – try View Notes Page

Page 3: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Efficiency: “no available Kaldor-Hicks improvements” roughly, maximizing total value, or total surplus, or total payoffs, to

everyone in society but translating everything into dollars, so we can add/compare

across people

Means that… each scarce resource is owned by whoever values it most goods are produced whenever their value is greater than their cost and so on

Monday, we talked about efficiency

Page 4: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

20 fishermen Catch 260 – H fish per hour of fishing Get disutility of 8 fish per hour What would be the efficient amount to fish?

Each fisherman gets utility h(260 – H) – 8h Total fish caught = H(260 – H), total disutility cost = 8H Efficiency: maximize H(260 – H) – 8H = 252H – H2

Derivative = 252 – 2H = 0, so H = 126 So efficiency requires 126 total man-hours of fishing per week If everyone fishes same amount, that’s 126/20 = 6.3 hours/day H = 126, so people catch 260 – 126 = 134 fish/hour Each person’s utility is 6.3 (134) – 6.3 (8) = 844.2 – 50.4 =

793.8 fish/day

I completely mangled the example about fishing (externalities causing inefficiency)

Page 5: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

20 fishermen Catch 260 – H fish per hour of fishing Get disutility of 8 fish per hour What will people choose to do on their own?

Each fisherman gets utility h(260 – H) – 8h Maximize private gain = h(260 – H) – 8h = h(260 – H – h) – 8h

= 252h – Hh – h2

Derivative = 252 – H – 2h = 0, so h = 252 – H – h = 252 – H So everyone fishes the same amount, so H = 20h,

and h = 252 – 20h or 21h = 252 or h = 12 So everyone fishes 12 hours/day H = 240, so people catch 260 – 240 = 20 fish/hour Each person’s utility is 12 (20) – 12 (8) = 240 – 96 = 144 fish/day

I completely mangled the example about fishing (externalities causing inefficiency)

Page 6: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

20 fishermen Catch 260 – H fish per hour of fishing Get disutility of 8 fish per hour So…

Efficient level of fishing is 6.3 hours/day for each person,

giving everyone utility of 793.8 fish/day But acting in their own interest, everyone fishes 12 hours/day,

giving everyone utility of 144 fish/day

The point: since fishing imposes a negative externality, people naturally do it “too much” (more than the efficient amount)

I completely mangled the example about fishing (externalities causing inefficiency)

Page 7: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

I completely mangled the example about fishing (externalities causing inefficiency)

6 1290 3

Hours fishing, per day, per fisherman

Total fish

caught “Maximum sustainable

yield”

Efficientlevel offishing

“Equilibrium”fishinglevel

H (260 – H)

Page 8: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Posner: yes – ex-ante, we would all have agreed to efficient laws

Analogy to lottery ticket with highest expected value

We saw an example for asymmetric situations (landlords and tenants)

Next, we asked: Should efficiency be the normative goal of the law?

Page 9: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Ignores distribution of wealth

Doesn’t consider procedural fairness Auctioning off last seats for this class

Value is equated with willingness to pay I need a heart transplant, someone else is willing to pay more to

use heart as decoration

But there are problems with efficiency as a normative goal

Page 10: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

“The central question [in this book]… is a simple one: what set of rules and institutions maximize the size of the pie? What legal rules are economically efficient?

There are at least three reasons why that is the question we ask.

The first is that while economic efficiency… is not the only thing that matters to human beings, it is something that matters quite a lot to most human beings.

The second reason is that there is evidence that considerable parts of the legal system we live in can be explained as tools to generate efficient outcomes… It is a lot easier to make sense out of a tool if you know what it is designed to do.

A final reason is that figuring out what rules lead to… efficient outcomes is one of the things economists know how to do –

and when you have a hammer, everything looks like a nail.”

- Friedman, Law’s Order, p. 312

Friedman has his own take on why we should study efficiency

Page 11: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

Cooter and Ulen (textbook ch. 1)

Efficiency should not necessarily be the goal of society

But efficiency should be the goal of the legal system

If redistribution is desirable, it’s better to make the legal system efficient, and address distribution through taxes Cooter and Ulen offer four reasons why the tax system is a better

way to redistribute wealth than the legal system

Cooter and Ulen give a more pragmatic defense of efficiency as a goal for the law

Page 12: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

1. Taxes can target “rich” and “poor” more precisely than the legal system can

2. Distributional effects of legal changes are harder to predict

3. Lawyers are more expensive than accountants

4. More narrowly-targeted taxes cause greater distortion than broad-based taxes

Four reasons the tax system is a better way to redistribute wealth than the legal system

Page 13: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

13

Two goods: beer (x), pizza (y)

One consumer, with $60 and utility u(x,y) = x0.5 y0.5

a. Given prices p for beer and q for pizza, calculate demand.

(x,y) = (30/p, 30/q)

Beer and pizza are produced at $1 per unit, and perfectly competitive markets

So without any taxes, p = q = $1

b. Calculate demand, and utility, with no tax.

(x,y) = (30, 30) u(x,y) = 300.5 300.5 = 30

c. Calculate demand and utility with $0.50 tax on beer.

(x,y) = (20, 30) u(x,y) = 200.5 300.5 = 6000.5 24.49

d. How much revenue does $0.50 tax on beer raise?

20 X $0.50 = $10

e. Calculate demand and utility with $0.20 tax on both goods.

(x,y) = (25, 25) u(x,y) = 250.5 250.5 = 25

f. How much revenue does $0.20 tax on both goods raise?

25 X $0.20 + 25 X $0.20 = $10

g. Which is the better way to raise revenue?

To make this last point, an example(The question I distributed Monday)

Page 14: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

We’ve seen two arguments in favor Posner: it’s what we all would have agreed on ex-ante C&U: if you want to redistribute, it’s better to do it through taxes

But there are definitely some problems with efficiency Distribution matters; not everything is monetizable; people might care

about procedural fairness

My take In this class, we’ll mostly focus on the positive questions But in the background, I think of efficiency as a “pretty good”, but

definitely imperfect, measure of “goodness”

So, summing up… is efficiency a good goal for the law?

Page 15: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

15

I don’t have many “absolute beliefs” about economics Some people do

I hope that doesn’t make things too confusing

Before we move on, a quick digression…

Page 16: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

16

I don’t have many “absolute beliefs” about economics Some people do

I hope that doesn’t make things too confusing

Relatedly, if I don’t see economics as a set of rules to memorize, how do I know what I know?

I need to see a model, or an example, that demonstrates it

Before we move on, a quick digression…

Page 17: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

17

introduce some basic game theory

begin property law

Rest of today:

Page 18: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

18

Some basicgame theory

Page 19: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

19

Today, we focus on static games Also known as simultaneous-move games

A static game is completely described by three things: Who the players are What actions are available to each player What payoff each player will get, as a function of

his own action, and the actions of the other players

Any complete description of these three things fully characterizes a static game

A brief introduction to game theory

Page 20: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

20

(Story)

Players: player 1 and player 2

Two actions available to each player: rat on the other, or keep mum

Payoffs: u1(mum, mum) = -1

u1(rat, mum) = 0

u1(mum, rat) = -10

u1(rat,rat) = -5

Same for player 2

A classic example: the Prisoner’s Dilemma

Page 21: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

21

In two-player games with finite actions, one way to present game is payoff matrix

-1, -1 -10, 0

0, -10 -5, -5

Mum Rat

Mum

Rat

Player 2’s Action

Player 1’s Action

Player 1’s Payoff Player 2’s Payoff

Always Player 1

Page 22: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

22

In the Prisoner’s Dilemma, one player’s best action is the same, regardless of what his opponent does

This is called a dominant strategy Regardless of what he thinks 2 will do, 1 would rather play Rat

Dominant Strategies (skipped this in lecture)

-1, -1 -10, 0

0, -10 -5, -5

Mum Rat

Mum

Rat

Player 2’s ActionP

laye

r 1’

s A

ctio

n

Page 23: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

23

In most games, players won’t have a single move that’s always best

We solve a game by looking for a Nash equilibrium

Nash equilibrium is a strategy profile (an action for each player) such that: No player can improve his payoff by switching to a different action… …given what his opponent/opponents are doing

Nash Equilibrium

Page 24: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

24

If any player can improvehis payoff by changing hisaction, given his opponents’actions, then it is not a Nashequilibrium

Is (Mum, Mum) an equilibrium? No, if player 2 is playing Mum

player 1 gains by deviating

A strategy profile is a Nash Equilibrium if no player can gain by deviating

-1, -1 -10, 0

0, -10 -5, -5

Mum Rat

Mum

Rat

Player 2’s Action

Pla

yer

1’s

Act

ion

Page 25: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

25

My best response to a particular play by the other player is whichever action(s) give me the highest payoff

To find Nash Equilibria… Circle payoff from player 1’s

best response to each action by his opponent

Circle payoff from player 2’sbest response to each action

Any box with both payoffscircled is an equilibrium

Because each player is playinga best-response to his opponent’s action…

…so neither one can improve by changing his strategy

In two-player games, we find Nash equilibria by highlighting best responses

-1, -1 -10, 0

0, -10 -5, -5

Mum Rat

Mum

Rat

Player 2’s Action

Pla

yer

1’s

Act

ion

Page 26: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

26

Another classic: Battle of the Sexes

(Story)

Circle player 1’sbest responses

Circle player 2’sbest responses

We find two equilibria: (ballgame, ballgame) and (opera, opera) Game theory usually doesn’t have that much to say about which

equilibrium will get played when there are more than one

Some games will have more than one equilibrium

6, 3 0, 0

0, 0 3, 6

Baseball Game Opera

BaseballGame

Opera

Player 2’s Action

Pla

yer

1’s

Act

ion

Page 27: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

27

Growth model

(Story)

Circle player 1’sbest responses

Circle player 2’sbest responses

Two equilibria: (invest, invest)and (consume, consume) Some papers explain differences in growth across countries by

saying some are in “good” equilibrium and some are in “bad” one

Sometimes, there will be a “good” and a “bad” equilibrium

2, 2 0, 1

1, 0 1, 1

Invest Consume

Invest

Consume

Player 2’s Action

Pla

yer

1’s

Act

ion

Page 28: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

28

Scissors, Paper, Rock for $1 Look for Nash

Equilibria by circling best responses

No square with both payoffs circled

No equilibrium where each player plays a single action

In this class, we’ll focus on games with a pure-strategyNash equilibrium

Some games don’t have any equilibrium where players only play one action

0, 0 1, -1

-1, 1 0, 0

Scissors Paper

Scissors

Paper

Player 2’s Action

Pla

yer

1’s

Act

ion -1, 1

1, -1

Rock

1, -1 -1, 1Rock 0, 0

Page 29: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

29

Now on to…

That’s a very quick introduction to static games

Page 30: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

30

Property Law

Page 31: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

31

In a sense, same question as,

why do we prefer organized society of any sort to anarchy?

Suppose there are two neighboring farmers

Each can either farm his own land, or steal crops from his neighbor Stealing is less efficient than planting my own crops

Have to carry the crops from your land to mine Might drop some along the way Have to steal at night move slower

If I steal your crops, I avoid the effort of planting and watering

Why do we need property law at all?

Page 32: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

32

Suppose that planting and watering costs 5, the crops either farmer could grow are worth 15, and stealing costs 3

With no legal system,the game has the following payoffs:

We look for equilibrium

Like Prisoner’s Dilemma both farmers stealing is the only equilibrium but that outcome is Pareto-dominated by both farmers farming

Why do we need property law?

10, 10 -5, 12

12, -5 0, 0

Farm Steal

Farm

Steal

Player 2

Pla

yer

1

Page 33: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

33

Suppose there were lots of farmers facing this same problem

They come up with an idea: Institute some property rights And some type of government that would punish people who steal

Setting up the system would cost something Suppose it imposes a cost c on everyone who plays by the rules

So how do we fix the problem?

Page 34: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

34

So how do we fix the problem?

10 – c, 10 – c -5 – c, 12 – P

12 – P, -5 – c -P, -P

Farm Steal

Farm

Steal

Player 2

Pla

yer

110, 10 -5, 12

12, -5 0, 0

Farm Steal

Farm

Steal

Player 2

Pla

yer

1

MODIFIED GAMEORIGINAL GAME

If P is big, and c is not too big, then 12 – P < 10 – c In that case, (Farm, Farm) is an equilibrium

Payoffs are (10 – c, 10 – c), instead of (0, 0) from before

Page 35: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

35

Anarchy is inefficient I spend time and effort stealing from you You spend time and effort defending your property from thieves Instead of doing productive work

Establishing property rights, and a legal process for when they’re violated, is one way around the problem

So the idea here…

Page 36: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

36

Cooter and Ulen: property is

“A bundle of legal rights over resources that the owner is free to exercise and whose exercise is protected from interference by others”

Property rights are not absolute Appendix to ch. 4 discusses different conceptions of property rights

Any system has to answer four fundamental questions: What things can be privately owned? What can (and can’t) an owner do with his property? How are property rights established? What remedies are given when property rights are violated?

Overview of Property Law

Page 37: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

37

BUT…

http://www.msnbc.msn.com/id/21088150/

Answers to many of these seem obvious

Page 38: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

38

Please see me if you’re not yet registered

Take a look at Coase, “The Problem of Social Cost”

Have a good weekend

Monday: Coase

Page 39: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

39

(I doubt we’ll get to…)

Page 40: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

40

Pierson v. Post (NY Supreme Court, 1805) Post organized a fox hunt, was chasing a fox Pierson appeared “out of nowhere,” killed the fox, took it Post sued to get the fox back Lower court sided with Post; Pierson appealed to NY Sup Ct

Both were wealthy, pursued the case on principle or out of spite

Question: when do you own an animal?

One early, “classic” property law case

Page 41: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

41

Court ruled for Pierson (the one who killed the fox) “If the first seeing, starting, or pursuing such animals… should

afford the basis of actions against others for intercepting and killing them, it would prove a fertile source of quarrels and litigation”

(Also: just because an action is “uncourteous or unkind” does not make it illegal)

Dissenting opinion: a fox is a “wild and noxious beast,” and killing foxes is “meritorious and of public benefit” Post should own the fox, in order to encourage fox hunting

Pierson v. Post

Page 42: Econ 522 Economics of Law Dan Quint Fall 2010 Lecture 3

42

Pierson gets the fox

simpler rule (finders keepers)

easier to implement

fewer disputes

Same tradeoff we saw earlier:

Post gets the fox

more efficient incentives

(stronger incentive to pursue animals that may be hard to catch)

Just like Fast Fish/Loose Fish vs Iron Holds The Whale Fast Fish/Loose Fish is the simpler rule, leads to fewer disputes Iron Holds the Whale is more complicated, but is necessary with

whales where hunting them the old-fashioned way is too dangerous