Giving Desert Its Due

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    1/33

    Giving Desert its Due1

    T. M. Scanlon

    Joel Feinberg wrote, In respect to modes of treatment which persons can be said

    to deserve, then, we can distinguish three kinds of conditions. There are those whose

    satisfaction confers eligibility (eligibility conditions), those whose satisfaction confers

    entitlement (qualification conditions), and those conditions not specified in any

    regulatory or procedural rules whose satisfaction confers worthiness or desert (desert

    bases) (Feinberg 1970, 58). Feinberg goes on to say that desert bases must be some

    possessed characteristic or prior activity of the person in question.

    Similarly, Derk Pereboom, describing the idea of basic desert that he takes to be

    presupposed by the variety of moral responsibility that has been at issue in debates about

    free will, writes, The desert at issue here is basic in the sense that the agent, to be

    morally responsible, would deserve to be the recipient of the expression of such an

    attitude just because she has performed the action, given sensitivity to its moral status;

    not, for example, by virtue of consequentialist or contractualist considerations

    (Pereboom 2012, 189; Sher 1987, 7).

    Following Feinberg and Pereboom, I will say that what is distinctive about a

    desert-based justification for treating a person in a certain way is that it claims that that

    treatment is made appropriate simplyby certain facts about that person, or what he or she

    has done. The simply in this formulation is intended to exclude justifications by appeal

    to the effects of treating the person in that way and justifications that appeal to the fact

    1I am grateful to Erin Kelly, Samuel Scheffler, and two anonymous readers for

    Philosophical Explorationsfor helpful comments on earlier drafts.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    2/33

    2

    that this treatment is called for by some institution (that is itself justified on some basis

    other than an appeal to desert.) So, for example, to discipline a child by depriving him of

    a treat because he deserves it is a different thing from doing this because this will

    improve his character or make him likely to behave better in future. Claiming that people

    who have worked hard all their lives deserve a good pension is also different from

    claiming that they are entitled to pension benefits according to the regulations of the

    Social Security System, or the pension scheme of their employer.

    My aims in this paper will be to examine this idea of desert-based justification

    and to consider the role of such justifications in answering questions about legal

    punishment, moral blame, and economic justice.

    In defending some desert-based justifications, I will be departing from positions I

    have taken in earlier work, in which I expressed skepticism about justifications of this

    kind (Scanlon 1988, 149-216; Scanlon 1998, chapter 6). There were two reasons for this

    skepticism. First, because I identified moral desert with the idea, which I regard as

    morally repugnant, that it is good that people who have done wrong should suffer, I was

    inclined to reject the idea of desert altogether. Second, interpreting and commenting on

    Rawls views on distributive justice, I endorsed the idea that the only sense of desert

    relevant to questions of distributive is what I called institutional desertthe sense in

    which a person deserves a form of treatment if a justified institution specifies that he or

    she should be treated in that way. I expressed skepticism about desert in a pre-

    institutional sense that is independent of what particular institutions require and can

    serve as a basis for assessing whether institutions are just. Each of these skeptical views

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    3/33

    3

    now seems to me to require some modification, which I will discuss in the course of this

    paper.

    Even though there is a difference, as Feinberg noted, between claims of desert and

    claims of institutional entitlement, institutions can have a role in determining desert bases.

    For example, a person who has achieved a certain score on a test is entitled to the grade

    that this makes appropriate. But, as Feinberg also recognizes, it makes sense to say that a

    person who did less well on the test deserved a higher grade than he received. This can be

    explained by the fact that the point of an institution of grading may be to make as

    accurate as possible an appraisal of the degree to which [the person or thing graded]

    possesses some skill or quality (Feinberg 1970, 65). And it may be, in a given case, that

    a persons performance on a test is not an accurate indication of the degree to which that

    person possesses the relevant skill. She may have just had a bad day. She therefore

    deserved a higher grade (the purposes of the system of grading would be better served if

    she had a higher grade) even though she is not entitled to this grade. This desert claim

    depends on the institution of grading (that is to say, on what the purposes of that

    institution are) even though it is not a claim of institutional entitlement. It is quite

    different from a claim that a person deserved to do better on the test because he tried so

    hard. Trying hard does not entail having a higher level of the skill that the test is intended

    to measure and that grades are intended to represent.

    The example of grading illustrates one way in which certain forms of treatment

    can be made appropriate simply by what a person is like or what he or she has done.

    Awarding a grade or a prize is an act of expression. As Feinberg says, it is intended to

    communicate that the subject has a particularly high level of some skill or other quality.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    4/33

    4

    Awarding such a grade or prize is therefore inappropriate if the subject does not possess

    this quality. So the possession of this quality is at least part of the justification for such an

    act of expression.

    It need not be a full justification, however.2There are many ways of expressing

    facts about a persons level of skill, and these modes of expression have costs. Awarding

    grades and prizes in certain ways, with certain kinds of fanfare or ceremony makes some

    people feel good but makes others feel sad and disappointed. Inflicting these costs on

    people is not justified simply by the fact that the message thereby conveyed is accurate. If

    the distinctions marked by the system of grading are pointless, then the costs of publicly

    awarding them with great fanfare may be unjustifiable. Similarly, expressing moral

    blame often involves psychological pain for those who are blamed, even if inflicting this

    pain is not thepurposeof that expression (as the infliction of pain is part of the purpose

    of acts of punishment) (Feinberg 1970, 67; compare Pereboom 2012, 193). So something

    needs to be said about when and why such costs are justified.

    Broadly speaking, these costs might be justified in two ways. The first is by

    appeal to the beneficial consequences of the policy that has these costs. The second is by

    arguing that, for one reason or another, the individuals who bear these costs cannot object

    to them. Desert may play a further role in arguments of the latter kind. These two forms

    of justification are not simply alternatives: they can be employed in tandem and in many

    cases an adequate justification will involve both in some form. This is illustrated by the

    case of legal punishment.

    Legal Punishment

    2The limitations of veracity as a justification for responding to merit with good

    treatment are noted by (Sher 1987, 113-122).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    5/33

    5

    Legal punishment has two aspects: it condemns certain actions as wrongful and it

    involves some form of hard treatment, such as a fine or loss of liberty (von Hirsch 1992,

    55-98 & 73-74). Both elements figure in the positive case for having an institution of

    punishment. Governments owe it to their citizens is to affirm their rights by condemning

    serious rights violations (whether or not this makes those violations less likely to occur)

    and they also owe it to their citizens to discourage violations by condemnation and,

    insofar as this is necessary, by threatening wrongdoers with forms of hard treatment

    (Scanlon 2003, 219-233). But these two elements are separable: a public response to

    wrong doing could express condemnation without involving any form of hard

    treatment, so a justification for the former need not also justify any particular form of

    the latter.

    Both of these aspects of punishment have costs: individuals have good reasons to

    want not to be condemned as well as reasons to want not to be subjected to fines or

    imprisonment. These costs play different roles in the two arguments for punishment that I

    just mentioned. Threats of condemnation or of hard treatment deter because they are

    things most individuals want to avoid. But condemnation of wrong doers is owed to

    victims simply because of its expressive content, not because those who are condemned

    have reason to dislike it. The question we are concerned with, however, is how these

    costs can be justified.

    Fines, imprisonment and other forms of hard treatment are not justifiable unless

    they are necessary and effective means to protect citizens against serious wrongs. But an

    appeal to consequences alone is not sufficient justification. Policies of vicarious

    punishment of the members of criminals families, or exemplary punishment of innocent

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    6/33

    6

    people chosen at random and framed, might deter, but would not thereby be justified.

    This might be explained by appeal to the expressive content of punishment: those who

    would be subjected to hard treatment under such policies would not be properly

    condemned, since they have done no wrong. But this does not seem to me to be the whole

    story. There is also the important fact that these individuals would have no opportunity to

    avoid being treated in this way by choosing appropriately. Insofar as a policy of inflicting

    hard treatment on wrong doers is justified this must be not only because it is an effective

    way to protect others from being wronged but alsobecause this policy inflicts this

    treatment only on individuals who have had a fair opportunity to avoid being subject to it

    (Hart 1968, 1-27).

    This dual justification of the costs of punishment involves both of the forms of

    argument I mentioned above: an appeal to consequences and appeal to factors that

    undermine the objections of those who are punished. An idea of desert might, however,

    be invoked to play the latter role. It might be said that wrongdoers cannot complain of the

    hard treatment involved in punishment because these forms of treatment are deserved:

    given what a wrongdoer has done, these forms of treatment are appropriate, and even

    good things to occur, in part becausewrongdoers have reason to dislike them. And, it

    might be added, this is so only if only if these wrongdoers could have avoided doing what

    they did. Such a claim seem to me quite false. It is never a good thing, morally speaking,

    for anyone to suffer, no matter what they have done, and this is so quite independent of

    whether those who might be made to suffer have free will or not.

    I was earlier led to reject desert altogether because I identified desert with the

    thesis that it is a good thing for people who have done wrong to suffer, or at least that this

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    7/33

    7

    is less bad than the comparable suffering of people who have done no wrong.3It now

    seems to me a mistake to identify desert with these retributivist ideas. But even if

    retributivism is properly rejected, desert-based arguments still have a role in the

    justification of moral blame and the condemnatory aspect of punishment. It is reasonable

    to dislike having ones moral faults publicly acknowledged. But those who have done

    wrong cannot object to bearing this cost. They have no moral claim that their faults

    should be ignored in order to spare them this psychological discomfort, because this

    public acknowledgement is an appropriate response to what they have done. This does

    not mean that just any form of public condemnation is justified. Some practices of

    shaming may involve unjustifiable levels of humiliation. The point is just that official

    public acknowledgement of the faults of wrong doers is made appropriate by these faults

    themselves (it is deserved on this basis alone), and they therefore have no moral claim

    against it. (By the costs of the condemnatory aspect of punishment I will henceforth

    mean just the costs of such official acknowledgment.)

    Earlier, I distinguished between two kinds of arguments in support of punishment:

    arguments appealing the consequences of a policy of punishing wrong doers and

    arguments that undermine the objections that individuals may have to bearing the costs of

    being punished. The latter category includes both appeals to desert and appeals to the fact

    3George Sher defends this idea, on the ground that (1) those who seek value are therefore

    of greater value themselves; (2) the wicked are of lesser value than those who are morallygood; and (3) the value of the happiness of an individual varies with the value of that

    individual (Sher 1987, chapter 8). I have doubts about the idea of value in terms of whichthis argument is stated (On this see: Scanlon 1998, chapter 2). So I am somewhat unclear

    about claims (1) and (2). There might be a way of understanding value in terms of whichthese claims would be correct. Claim (1) might be, for example, that those who seek

    value are therefore more to be admired and emulated. But claim (3) would not follow.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    8/33

    8

    that individuals have a fair opportunity to avoid being punished, but these two forms of

    argument are distinct and independent.

    The fact that those who suffer a harm will have had a fair opportunity to avoid it,

    by choosing appropriately, may make a policy that allows such harms to occur more

    defensible.4But it does not presuppose, or do anything to show, that it is in any way good

    that people who have taken the risk of such harms should suffer them. By contrast,

    desert-based arguments of the kind I am considering maintain that certain kinds of

    response are made appropriate by what a wrong doer has done: that others are justified in

    responding in these ways simply by the faults displayed in the wrong doers conduct.

    It might, however, be said that the faults in questionthe features of the agent

    and what he or she has done that make blame appropriateintrinsically involve doing

    certain things, or having certain attitudes,freely; so a version of opportunity to avoid is

    built into the relevant desert bases. Whether this is so depends on the kind of freedom

    that is supposed to be in question. Here Hume seems to me to have been basically right

    (Hume, Book II, Part III, Sections I & II).5If someone did wrong only because he was

    4This is not true only of punishment but holds quite generally of policies that allow harm

    to occur. See (Hart 1968, 28-53; Scanlon 1988, Lecture 2; Scanlon 1998, chapter 6).5I say that Hume was only basically right because it seems to me that lack of liberty is

    a misleading way of describing the cases in which, as he puts it, an agent lacks theliberty of spontaneity. A lack of liberty may seem to be the crucial element in cases like

    that of a person who reveals a secret but does so only because she was threatened withserious harm. It may seem that such a person is not blameworthy for revealing the secret

    because she did so unwillingly. But this is misleading. The threat may undermineblameworthiness because it makes it the case that revealing the secret was justified, and

    therefore not blameworthy. And even if it does not justify revealing the secret, the threatchanges the meaning of the agents action, by altering the reasons she had, or believed

    herself to have. The general phenomenon at work in such cases is that blameworthinessdepends on a full picture of an agents reasons. Saying that an agent acted willingly or

    unwillingly is a way of referring to facts about these reasons, but it is misleading

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    9/33

    9

    forced to do this by threats or by the lack of acceptable alternatives (if he lacked what

    Hume called the liberty of spontaneity), then this can change the kind of response that is

    appropriate because it changes facts about the attitudes reflected in the agents action. It

    is one thing to harm another person out of carelessness or spite and something different

    (even if perhaps still wrong) to do so only because one believed this was necessary in

    order to avoid a greater harm to oneself. But the fact that an agent lacked what Hume

    called the liberty of indifference, that is to say, the fact that his psychological make up

    was determined by conditions in the past, over which he has no control, and that, given

    this make up, it was inevitable that he would act the way he or did, does not change the

    attitudes he in fact has. Purely condemnatory responses (as distinct from hard

    treatment) are justified simply by what an agent is in fact like, psychologically, as

    revealed in his or her actions.6This justification does not require that the agent had

    control over (was responsible for) becomingsuch a person. If an agent does have some

    control over this, then he or she may be open to additional criticism for failing to exercise

    it properlyfailing to take due care in regard to his or her own moral development. But

    such control is not required in order for their present dispositions to be ones that are

    appropriately condemned. In Feinbergs terms, a desert basis need not itself be deserved.

    To sum up this discussion of legal punishment: the hard treatment aspect of

    punishment requires justification that appeals both to beneficial consequences and to fair

    opportunity to avoid, but the cost of the condemnatory aspect of legal punishment (at

    because it suggests that what is crucial is the agents will, or liberty, rather than thereasons the agent had and those he or she acted upon. For a similar point see Kelly, 2012.

    6For discussion of how this applies in the case of young children and the mentally ill, see

    (Scanlon 2008, chapter 4, esp. 156ff, 178-179, 197-198).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    10/33

    10

    least the costs of its basic content) does not require justification of either kind. The cost

    simply of being (properly) condemned can be justified simply on the ground that this

    condemnation is deserved.

    If, however, it is claimed that a certain form of treatment is appropriate simply

    because of what a person in question is like, or what he or she has done, then some

    explanation of the relevant idea of appropriateness is called for. Earlier, I offered one

    explanation of this kind in terms of the expressive content of the treatment in question. If

    the point or purpose of a system of grading, for example, is to represent the degree to

    which various people possess a certain skill, then what makes a certain grade appropriate

    is that is an accurate representation of this kind. As I noted, however, this falls short of a

    full justification for an act or policy of assigning grades, since these assignments have

    costs, such as embarrassment of those who get low grades. It is natural to find further

    justification for these costs in the beneficial consequences of a system of grading, as a

    source of information or a way of providing incentives. The condemnatory aspect of legal

    punishment might be justified in a similar way. But I have suggested that this is not the

    case, or at least not the whole story. The costs of the condemnatory aspect of legal

    punishment can be justified purely on the basis of desertthey are made appropriate by

    what a wrong doer has doneand this is even more obviously true of the costs of moral

    blame. So I need to provide an account of the idea of appropriateness that is being

    appealed to here that goes beyond the expressive account I sketched above, and to do

    this I will turn to the case of moral blame.

    Moral Reactive Attitudes

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    11/33

    11

    Suppose a person in your neighborhood has treated his wife very badlyabused

    her physically, treated her in humiliating ways, and gambled away her inheritance. What

    responses by his wife, or by you and other neighbors, does this make appropriate? To

    begin with, it is appropriate to conclude that he is a morally bad person. In addition,

    according to the most widely held accounts of blame and moral responsibility, it would

    be appropriate to suspend, at least temporarily, friendly feelings toward the person,

    replacing them by angry feelings of resentment and indignation.7I would not deny that

    these emotional responses are common and appropriate, but I believe that other responses

    are also called for, including such things as:

    1. Withdrawal of trust

    2. Decreased readiness to enter into special relations such as friendship with the

    person

    3.

    Decreased willingness to help the person with his projects

    4. Decreased tendency to take pleasure in things going well for the person and to

    feel sad or regretful when they do not

    I count all of these responses as forms of blame (Scanlon 2008, chapter 4). This

    thesis is controversial, but I need not argue for it here. The claim that is relevant for

    present purposes is that, whether or not they are forms of blame, they are all responses

    that are made appropriate simply by what the person is like and what he or she has done.

    The point of listing them here is to see whether, by focusing on this range of responses,

    we can understand more about the relevant idea of appropriateness.

    7(Strawson 2003) is the classical statement of this view, which has later been developed

    by many others. See, especially: (Wallace 1993).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    12/33

    12

    All of these responses are reactive attitudes in Strawsons sense: attitudes

    toward a person that are reactions to that persons attitudes toward others, including the

    modification or withdrawal of attitudes toward the person that one would normally have

    held. To say that these are reactions to the attitudes of this person is not merely to say

    that they are caused by his or her attitudes but also that they are seen by those who hold

    them as made appropriate by those attitudes. More specifically, they are seen as made

    appropriate by the fact that that persons attitudes are deficient as measured by to the

    standards of morality or some relevant interpersonal relationship.8Two aspects of this

    claim of appropriateness need to be explained: why the person toward whom they are

    directed cannot object to this modification or withdrawal of normal attitudes, and what

    positive reason others have for modifying or withdrawing their attitudes in these ways.

    Withdrawal of trust might be justified prudentially, since trusting such a person

    puts one at risk. Although this withdrawal has a cost to the person who is not trusted, the

    cost of continued trust is more than the rest of us can reasonably be asked to bear. We do

    not owe trust unconditionally, but only to the trustworthy. This explanation seems right

    as far as it goes, but does not seem to capture all that is going on. Its prudential character

    seems too limited.

    Prudential considerations aside, the attitudes that are withdrawn in these

    responses are not owed unconditionally, but only given the presence of attitudes that this

    persons actions show him not to hold. So the cost to him of our changed attitudes

    consists only in the loss of something that we are not obligated to provide. It is thus a cost

    8The importance of such relationships was emphasized by (Strawson 2003). For fuller

    discussion see: (Scanlon 2008, chapter 4; Scanlon 2012, 84-99).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    13/33

    13

    to which he has no valid objection. Moreover, we have good non-prudential reasons to

    withdraw trust and the other normal attitudes that I have listed.

    Consider first the reasons that the victim of the subjects wrongdoing has. For her

    simply to ignore the indifference to her interests that his actions indicate would show a

    failure to take seriously her own moral status as someone entitled not to be treated in that

    way. This would be inappropriate, servile and demeaning. And for us, as third parties,

    simply to ignore the attitudes toward the victim (and perhaps others) that are indicated by

    the agents actions would show a lack of regard on our part for the moral standing of

    these people.

    9

    It might be said in response that not resenting those who have wronged one, and

    not reacting to them in any of the other ways I have listed, would not be inappropriate but

    in fact particularly saintly: it would be good to respond to wrongs in this way if we could

    manage it, even though most of us cannot. But reacting in this fashion seems saintly only

    because it is more than is owed to the agent, and involves overcoming strong contrary

    reasons. So on further examination the objection confirms, rather than undermines, the

    points I have been making about our reasons for reacting to wrongs in the ways I have

    described and about wrongdoers lack of standing to object to these reactions.

    Moreover, simply overlookingthe agents wrongs and faults would not be saintly.

    This is clearest in the case of third parties. A saintly person cannot simply ignorethe

    wrong done to victims and the objectionable attitudes toward them manifested in an

    agents actions. A saintly response must acknowledge these factors while somehow

    moving beyond them. This may be less obvious when the saintly person is the victim,

    9For fuller discussion of the impermissibility, and blameworthiness, of failures to blame

    wrongdoers see: (Scanlon 2008, 166-179).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    14/33

    14

    since she is in a position to forgive the wrong. But forgiving serious wrongs cannot be

    simply ignoring them, lest it be self-demeaning (Hieronymi 2001, 529-555).

    According to this account of appropriateness, what is appropriate is in the first

    instance some attitude.10In the examples I have listed, these attitudes are mainly

    described negatively, as the withdrawal or diminution of other attitudes. My claims thus

    have the following form: normally, a person would be open to moral criticism for failing

    to have certain attitudes, such as a disposition to trust others, to help them, and to be

    pleased when good things happen to them. But when others have themselves behaved in

    ways that evince certain kinds of morally faulty attitudes, this makes it no longer

    inappropriate to fail to have the attitudes just listed toward them, and one has good reason

    not to have these attitudes.

    These negative responses have positive analogs, for example in forms of gratitude.

    If a person has gone out of her way to help us (in ways not morally required) then we are

    open to moral criticism for not being more disposed to help her in return (in ways that we

    would not be morally required to help someone who had not helped us.)

    Many, although not all, of the responses I have been discussing involve intentions

    that are appropriate only if the actions that flow from them would be appropriate. So the

    ideas of appropriateness and desert that I am defending apply to these actions as well. We

    can say, for example, that people who have behaved in certain ways do not deserve to be

    trusted, or even that they deserve not to be trusted, where being trusted involves both

    intention and, under the relevant conditions, certain actions. It is worth noticing, since it

    10As Feinberg says, Responsive attitudes are the basic things persons deserve and

    modes of treatment are deserved only in a derivative way, insofar perhaps as they arethe natural or conventional means of expressing the morally fitting attitudes (Feinberg

    1970, 82).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    15/33

    15

    will be important is further discussion, that my fifth examplea reduced tendency to take

    pleasure in good things happening to a person, and to be sorry when they do notis an

    exception to the point just made. The response in this case is centrally a matter of attitude

    and affect, rather than action. I will return to this point in the next section.

    Earlier, I explained the appropriateness of grades in terms of their expressive

    content. Because grades are intended to represent the degree to which a person has some

    skill or quality, the appropriateness or inappropriateness of a grade depends on the

    presence or absence of this property. The explanation I have just been offering of the

    appropriateness of various reactive attitudes goes beyond this simple expressive model.

    Unlike grades, the reactive attitudes I listed are not primarily expressive in intent. But

    part of their contenttheir reactivecharacterinvolves the idea that they are responses

    to attitudes of others that are deficient, relative to the standards of relevant interpersonal

    relationships.11They would thus be inappropriate if the person toward whom they are

    directed did not have attitudes that were deficient in this way. But a judgment that a

    reactive attitude is not inappropriate in this way does not carry us all the way to the

    conclusion that that reaction is appropriate.For that to be the case it has to be positively

    justified, rather than merely not being based on faulty assumptions. It is therefore

    important that victims and others have reasons of the kind I have mentioned for reacting

    in these ways.

    As the frequent occurrence of the phrase subject to moral criticism in the

    preceding discussion indicates, the claims of appropriateness which underlie the idea of

    desert I am defending are first order moral claims, about the kinds of consideration and

    11As Feinberg points out, these responses have ostensible desert logically built into

    them (Feinberg 1970, 70-71).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    16/33

    16

    concern, and the degree of consideration and concern, that we owe to others. A

    divergence between my view and Strawsons similar view illustrates this point.

    The responses I listed above might all be described as instances of what Strawson

    called withdrawals of good will toward an agent in response to that agents attitudes

    toward oneself or others. This is particularly true of the fifth entry on my list, a decreased

    tendency to hope that things go well for a person and to be sad or regretful if they do not.

    Strawson says, however, that withdrawal of good will can involve modification of the

    general demand that another should, if possible, be spared suffering and a preparedness

    to acquiesce in that infliction of suffering on the offender which is an essential part of

    punishment (Strawson 2003, 90).

    It makes a big difference what kind of suffering is envisaged here. Decreased

    sympathetic concern of the kind I have just described, as well as other reactions such as

    withdrawal of trust, withdrawal of affection and concern, and refusal of some kinds of aid

    and association, all involve willingness to acquiesce in forms of lossfor the person

    toward whom they are directed, since they all involve withholding things that person has

    reason to want. In my view, as I have said, willingness to acquiesce in such losses is

    made appropriate simply by a persons deficient attitudes toward others. But readiness to

    inflict the kind of suffering typically involved in the hard treatment aspect of punishment

    is an entirely different matter. It can be justified only on some basis other than pure

    desert, such as the beneficial consequences of a policy of threatening and inflicting

    treatment of this kind. This divergence between my view and Strawsons is a first order

    moral disagreement about which kinds of concern are owed to others unconditionally and

    with are conditional upon their having the relevant moral attitudes toward others.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    17/33

    17

    It is also a first order moral question whether responses of the kind I have been

    discussing are appropriate responses to an agents attitude toward others only if that

    attitude is under the agents control. It seems to me clear that this is not the case. We do

    not owe it to others to trust them, to enter in to relations of friendship and cooperation

    with them, or to help them with their projects, no matter what their attitudes toward us

    and toward others may be. If they are prepared to manipulate and mistreat others

    whenever this is to their advantage, this fact alone about what they are like makes it

    appropriate for us to suspend or modify our normal attitudes toward them. How they

    came to be that way, and whether they had any control over this, is another matter.

    (Again: a desert basis need not itself be deserved.) We may owe them help in overcoming

    their deficiencies of character. But this is different from owing them the continuation of

    normal interpersonal relations.

    I realize that this claim is controversial. When I focus clearly on the particular

    responses that are in question, it seems to me an obvious moral truth. But its obviousness

    depends heavily on what these responses are. As I just indicated in discussing Strawson, I

    believe that desert-based justification alone can justify some responses, but only so much.

    Beyond that, an appeal to beneficial consequences and perhaps to fair opportunity to

    avoid is be required.12

    12When fair opportunity to avoid isrequired in order for a form of treatment to be

    justifiedas in the case of legal punishment and of some other forms of legal andeconomic treatmentit is a question whether this involves an ability to do otherwise that

    is incompatible with agents actions being caused by forces outside them over which theyhave no control. I argue that it does not, but that this answer is more difficult to defend

    than the corresponding negative answer about the preconditions for moral blame. Forfurther discussion, see: (Scanlon 1998, Chapter 6; Scanlon 2008, Chapter 4, esp. pp. 204-

    214).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    18/33

    18

    Whether such appeal is required is a moral question about what conditions must

    be satisfied in order for a particular form of moral response to be justified. In order to

    arrive at a considered judgment about such a question about the conditions of moral

    responsibility it is essential to first be clear exactly what response is in question. But

    discussions of moral responsibility are often not very clear about this. As the quote from

    Strawson illustrates, there is often a failure to distinguish clearly between responses of

    the kind I have been discussing, on the one hand, and punishment (involving forms of

    hard treatment) on the other. The term blame is often used, unhelpfully, to encompass

    both, or to cover a slide from the one to the other. So I conjecture that part of the

    disagreement between compatibilists and incompatibilists about moral responsibility may

    arise from unclarity of this kindfrom the fact that various participants in debates about

    moral responsibility may be thinking about the preconditions for different moral

    responses to wrong doing.

    Unclarity of this kind is particularly likely in regard to the fifth type of reaction I

    listed above: a decreased tendency to take pleasure in something good happening to a

    person, and a decreased tendency to feel sadness or regret when something bad happens

    to them. A person is generally open to moral criticism if he is not pleased, or is even

    displeased, when he hears of good things happening to others, and open to criticism if he

    does not react with regret at bad things happening to them. But when someone has treated

    others very badly it can cease to be morally criticizable to fail to be pleased when good

    things happen to him or to regret it when he suffers some misfortune. To change ones

    attitudes toward a person in these ways might be called, in Strawsons phrase, withdrawal

    of goodwill.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    19/33

    19

    But not being sad or regretful when something bad happens to a person is not the

    same thing as thinking it to be a good thing, or justified, that the person should suffer this

    fate, or even thinking that it is less bad that he should suffer in this way than that the

    same thing should happen to some innocent person. Attitudes such as hoping and being

    pleased, or regretting or being sad, need not involve or presuppose judgments about what

    is good or justified.

    The difference between these sets of attitudes is illustrated by our appropriate

    responses to what happens to our friends. It is entirely appropriate to hope that ones

    friend wins the lottery, and to regret it when she does not win. But it this need not involve

    believing that it would be a better thing if she wins rather than some other equally needy

    person. The latter attitude would reflect the implausible view that what happens to ones

    friends is, morally speaking, more important than what happens to others.

    Failing to draw this distinction can lead one to think that blaming a person

    involves not only feeling less sad when something bad happens to her but also holding

    the retributivist attitude that it is a good thing that she should suffer this loss, given what

    she has done. But the idea that it can be a good thing that something bad should happen

    to a person who has done wrong, even if she could not have avoided being the kind of

    person who would act in that way, is very implausible. Given the assumption that blame

    involves this retributivist attitude, this implausibility can then lead one to the conclusion

    that it can be appropriate to blame people for evil actions only if they have free will. The

    error in this line of thought lies at the beginning: in a failure to distinguish between not

    regretting it when bad things happen to a person who has done wrong and the retributivist

    attitude of taking this to be a good thing. The forms of blame that can be justified on a

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    20/33

    20

    pure desert basis involve only the former attitude. Forms of blame that involve the latter,

    retributivist, attitude are morally inappropriate, whether those who would be the subjects

    of these attitudes have free will or not.

    Desert and Distributive Justice

    In earlier writing, I distinguished between pre-institutional desert and institutional

    desert, by which I meant what Rawls calls legitimate expectations (Rawls 1971, section

    48). This is the idea that if justified institutions specify that those who do certain things,

    or have certain qualifications, should be given certain forms of treatment, then those who

    meet these conditions should have the specified forms of treatment.

    The term desert is often used to express claims of the latter kind, but I would

    now reserve that name for claims to certain treatment that are justified simply by what the

    person in question is like, or has done, without need for further justification. My reason

    for doing this is just to isolate a particular form of justification, which needs to be

    explained and distinguished from other forms. Claims of institutional entitlement need

    not be justified in this particular way. That is, they will not be justified in this way unless

    the justification for these features of the institution are in turn based on desert. When this

    is not so, these entitlements will not be desert-based in the sense in which I am now using

    the term.

    In earlier writings I also expressed skepticism (and interpreted Rawls as

    expressing skepticism) about the idea that there is a pre-institutional notion of desert

    relevant to questions of distributive justice. Samuel Scheffler has raised reasonable

    objections to this interpretation of Rawls, and he also interprets me as expressing

    skepticism about a pre-institutional notion of desert relevant to the justification of

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    21/33

    21

    punishment.13As I hope is clear from what I have said, I do believe that a pre-

    institutional idea of desert is relevant to the justification of an institution of punishment,

    even though it does not provide a full justification for such institutions. In this final

    section of my paper I want to re-examine the idea of pre-institutional desert and, consider

    drawing on the positive account of desert that I have outlined, whether such a notion is

    relevant to questions of distributive justice.

    First I need to say something about the sense in which the idea of desert that is

    relevant to the justification of punishment is pre-institutional. I have said that because

    punishment expresses a condemnation of certain actions, it is appropriate only when

    those on whom it is inflicted have done something condemnable. In many cases, such as

    murder, this idea of what is condemnable is pre-institutional in an obvious sense: the

    actions in question are wrong quite independent of any institution that forbids them. But

    this does not seem to be true of the condemnatory content of all instances of justified

    legal punishment. People are properly condemned for tax evasion, for example. But there

    is no such thing as taxes, or tax evasion, in the absence of institutions of a particular kind.

    This is even true of some cases of theft, since property is a purely institutional notion. (I

    say in some cases since some instances of theft interfere with the victims life in a way

    that is wrong quite apart from any institution of property.)

    Is there a pre-institutional wrong that is condemned by punishment for crimes of

    the latter kind? The natural candidate is a failure to abide by the requirements of just legal

    institutions. This general wrong is pre-institutional in one sense: it is not wrong because

    13(Scheffler 2001, 173-190). This is a fair criticism of what I said in my 1986 Tanner

    Lectures (Scanlon 1988). I corrected this error in later writing. See: (Scanlon 1998, 266-

    267; Scanlon 2003, 219-233).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    22/33

    22

    forbidden by such an institution. On the other hand, its content (which things are wrongs

    of this kind) depends on such institutions. Moreover, whether or not this wrong (and the

    appropriateness of condemning it) is pre-institutional, it is not pre-justicial, in Schefflers

    phrase (Scheffler 2001, 185). Refusing to obey the requirements of some institution is

    properly condemned for the reason I described only if that institution isjust(or

    sufficiently close to being just.) So the wrong that is said to deserve punishment depends

    on a prior conception of justice. The same is true in cases of what Rawls called

    institutional entitlement, where the property on the basis of which a person is said to

    deserve a certain form of treatment is the property of being entitled to this treatment

    according to a just institution. So desert is not is not a basic determinate of justice in these

    cases, not because it depends on some institution but because it depends on some

    independent conception of justice.

    If, then, desert is to have a fundamental role with regard to distributive justice this

    will be because, as a matter of justice, certain forms of economic advantage are made

    appropriate simply by facts about what individuals are like, or what they have done,

    where these facts (what Feinberg called the desert basis) do not themselves depend on a

    conception of justice. Such claims about justice would be individualistic in the sense

    distinguished by Scheffler: their desert basis is some characteristic of or fact about the

    deserving person (Scheffler 2001, 189).

    This is not yet enough to distinguish a desert-based view, however. It might be

    claimed that everyone who has a certain need should, as a matter of justice, be provided

    with certain kind of benefit (for example, that every child should have access to a certain

    level of education.) These claims seem individualistic, and they might be put in terms of

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    23/33

    23

    desert (that all citizens deserve to be treated equally and that all children deserve an

    education.) But they do not seem to me to be based on desert in any distinctive sense.

    So, narrowing this account, we might say that according to a desert-based view of

    distributive justice the appropriateness of some economic benefits depends on the degree

    to which individuals themselves, or their actions, meet certain standards of merit (in a

    broad sense of merit.)14The relevant standards could be moral or non-moral, specifying

    as desert bases such things as:

    1. Moral character

    2.

    Degree of effort expended in productive or other labor

    3. Special talents

    4. The contribution that a person has made to society, in the form of economic

    productivity or in some other form.

    This seems to fit better with the ordinary idea of desert. If we say, for example,

    that a child deserves a scholarship because of her distinctive academic talent this claim

    seems to use the notion of desert in a more substantial way than the general claim that all

    children deserve an education.

    How might one argue against the idea that distributive justice is, at least in part,

    based on desert in this sense? Scheffler suggests that what he calls Liberal Theorists

    reject claims of desert in distributive justice on the basis of the conviction that whereas

    desert is individualistic, distributive justice is holisticin the sense that the justice of any

    assignment of economic benefits to a particular individual always dependsdirectly or

    14These would be claims of what Michael Rosen calls desert as merit. See: (Rosen

    2003, 118-124).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    24/33

    24

    indirectlyon the justice of the larger distribution of benefits in society (Scheffler 2001,

    190).

    This seems to me correct as a description of theories of distributive justice of the

    kind that Scheffler, Rawls, and I myself hold. But as a reasonfor rejecting desert-based

    claims of justice the thesis that distributive justice is holistic may seem question begging,

    since it simply rules out desert-based views. Scheffler goes on, however, to offer three

    more specific reasons for taking distributive justice to be holistic.

    First, peoples productive contributions are mutually dependent in the sense that

    each persons capacity to contribute depends on the contributions of others.

    Second, the economic value of peoples talents is socially determined in the sense

    that it depends both on the number of people with similar talents and on the needs,

    preferences, and choices of others. Third, peoples expectations of material gain

    are linked in the sense that virtually any decision to assign economic benefits to

    one person or class has economic implications for other persons and classes

    (Scheffler 2001, 191).

    A satisfying argument against desert-based accounts of distributive justice needs

    to consider and respond to the reasons for thinking that justice depends on desert. The

    general idea that justice consists in giving people what they deserve may seem initially

    plausible. But this plausibility is undermined from two directions: first by the recognition

    that much of what people are due is determined by institutional entitlements, and second

    by the recognition that (as discussed above) there are many forms of desert that it is not

    the function of basic economic institutions to recognize (such as desert based on various

    forms of excellence in games and contests.)

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    25/33

    25

    This leads me to conclude that the appeal of desert-based ideas of justice is more

    piecemeal. It derives from the plausibility of claims that economic distribution should be

    sensitive to particular forms of merit such as the four I have listed, rather than on the

    general idea that justice depends on desert. If this is correct, then a satisfying argument

    against desert-based views will also be piecemeal, consisting of arguments that

    undermine claims of desert of these particular forms. So in the remainder of this section I

    will examine why these properties of individuals and their actions might be thought to

    make differences in economic benefits appropriate. Drawing on the account of desert

    presented earlier in this paper and on the three points highlighted by Scheffler, I will

    argue that the appeal of these claims of desert is largely illusory. I will be concerned only

    with claims that desert has a fundamental role in the justification of significant

    differences in economic benefit (leaving aside the role it may have, for example, in

    making small monetary prizes appropriate.)

    Consider first the idea that economic advantages should be distributed in

    accordance with moral merit. Rawls argued that such a distributive norm was

    impracticable, because there is no way to determine whether what seems to be

    meritorious conduct really reflects greater moral merit or is due to other factors (Rawls

    1971, 312). The difficulty might be that the moral merit of a persons action depends on

    the motives with which he or she acted, which are often difficult to discern. But Rawls

    goes beyond this, and appeals also to the fact that a persons superior character may

    depend in large part on fortunate family and social circumstances for which he can claim

    no credit. (Rawls 1971, 103-104)

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    26/33

    26

    This objection may seem to depend on the idea, which I have rejected above in

    discussing moral blame, that a desert basis must itself be deserved. But there is another

    way of understanding Rawls point. Suppose that one persons good character is indeed

    due to her fortunate family and social circumstances and that another persons bad

    character is similarly due to the unfortunate circumstances in which he grew up. Each of

    these individuals would have had a different character, I am supposing, if they had been

    placed in different circumstances as children. I believe, as I have said, that this does not

    mean that they cannot be blamed (or praised) for actions expressing the character that

    they in fact have. Leaving the question of blame aside, however, there is a further

    question whether this difference in their character is an appropriate basis for assigning

    them different levels of economic benefits. If the unfortunate circumstances in which one

    of these people grew up were in fact unjust, this would undermine the degree to which

    the effects of this injustice on the persons character can then be taken to justify the

    states denying him benefits that he otherwise would have been entitled to. 15So the case

    for economic rewards based on individuals moral character, if there is such a case,

    would not be independent of the justice of the background institutions that lead people to

    develop such characters.

    A more direct argument against distributing economic reward in accord with

    moral merit even in a fully just society is that rewarding moral merit is not the function of

    economic institutions. But this claim about function needs to be backed up in some

    way. One argument in support of this idea begins from the third way in which Scheffler

    15For a fuller discussion of the parallel case of how wrongful treatment of a person can

    undermine someones standing to blame that person for what he does, see: (Scanlon

    2008,175-179).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    27/33

    27

    says that distributive justice is holistic. A justification for a claim that it is just for some

    to have more than others needs to provide some reason why those who have less should

    accept this distribution. But there is no reason for other individuals to accept less than

    others simply because these others are morally more meritorious. Moral merit calls for

    respect, admiration, and other responses, but not obviously for economic sacrifice.

    This connects with a point I made earlier in discussing moral blame and legal

    punishment. According to the idea of appropriateness discussed there, what is made

    appropriate by a desert base, and hence deserved, is always in the first instance some

    attitude. So we need to distinguish between the attitude (of respect, admiration, or

    whatever) that is made appropriate by a given form of merit and the justification for a

    specific means by which this attitude is expressed. In the case of blame and punishment

    the need for further justification was raised by the further costs for those who are blamed

    or punished. In the case of distributive justice what requires justification is the cost to

    those who would have less as a result of a distribution accord with merit. The moral merit

    of those who are given more does not, by itself, provide such a justification for

    significant differences in economic reward.

    Consider next the idea of effortas a ground for special economic reward. There

    are a number of ways in which the reasons for rewarding effort might be understood. One

    rationale might be that willingness to exert oneself (for the public good) is morally

    meritorious, and therefore should be rewarded. This rationale for rewarding effort is open

    to the objections I have just discussed. In addition, it is limited to cases in which effort is

    exerted for non-self-interested reasons, and so would not apply to many cases of

    economic interaction.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    28/33

    28

    Another possible rationale is that exerting effort involves a sacrifice for which

    someone should be compensated. This presupposes some background just distribution

    (egalitarian or not), which is disrupted by the welfare lost due to exertion and therefore

    needs to be restored by compensating for this loss. So it is this background standard that

    is doing the justificatory work rather than an idea that effort intrinsically deserves

    reward.16

    A third rationale is that a person who has exerted greater effort has done this for

    some reason, presumably in the expectation of some gain. It is therefore appropriate that

    the person be rewarded with this gain, for the sake of which he or she has sacrificed. But

    this is just the idea that it is wrong to disappoint legitimate expectations, rather than an

    idea that effort, in itself, deserves special reward. So none of these reasons for holding

    that effort deserves special economic reward supports a compelling desert-based claim.

    Consider now the idea that those who have special talent deserve economic

    reward for these talents, or for using them. I will assume, for purposes of this discussion,

    that a persons talents belong to that person, in the sense that it is up to him or her to

    decide whether to develop these talents and whether or not to use them in a particular

    way. There may be cases in which a person is obligated to develop a talent or to use it for

    some particular purpose. But I will set this question aside since it does not seem to

    involve claims of desert. Given that a person is free to decide not to develop or use his or

    her talent, if a person is willing to use a talents only if offered a certain reward for doing

    so, and if such a reward is offered, then the person is entitled to keep the results of this

    transaction to whatever degree this is allowed by the applicable (just) laws governing

    16As Feinberg pointed out in the appendix to Justice and Personal Desert (Feinberg

    1970).

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    29/33

    29

    employment, contract, taxes and so on. This argument depends, however, on the justice

    of those laws. The question presently at issue is what role the idea that a talent deserves

    special reward should play in determining what a legal framework of this kind would

    have to be like in order to be just.

    Some forms of talent, such as artistic and intellectual abilities, are distinctive

    forms of valuable human excellence. This makes certain attitudessuch as admiration

    appropriate responses to their exercise. But it does not follow that these attitudes are

    appropriately expressed by making those who have them significantly better off

    economically, or that those who do not have these talents should accept this excellence as

    a justification for their having less. This, again, is just the distinction between the

    appropriateness of an attitude and the justifiability of a particular mode of expressing it.

    In any event, the talents that receive special reward in a market economy are not

    necessarily excellences but rather those abilities that are in demand and in short supply.

    So insofar as a claim that talents deserve special reward is thought to justify rewards of

    this kind, the relevant desert base is scarcity, which determines which abilities, among

    those that are in some demand, will receive greater reward. As Scheffler put it, the

    economic value of peoples talents is socially determined in the sense that it depends both

    on the number of people with similar talents and on the needs, preferences, and choices

    of others (Scheffler 2001, 191).

    Here the relevant critical point was made by Rawls, in his remark that no one

    deserves hisplacein the distribution ofnative endowments (Rawls 1971, 104, emphasis

    added). This remark is often read as presupposing the idea that a desert basis must itself

    be deserved. But this is not the correct interpretation. Rawls point is not that no one

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    30/33

    30

    deserves to have endowments that are scarce (although that may be true), but rather that

    no one deserves any special reward simply because his abilities are scarcethat mere

    scarcity is not a desert basis at all. This is not to deny that institutions that assign

    premium prices to scarce talents and resources may not be justifiable, perhaps on grounds

    of greater efficiency. If such an institution is justified in this way, and isjust, then

    individuals with scarce talents are entitled to the rewards that this institution provides.

    This, however, is not a desert-based argument but rather an argument for institutional

    entitlement, based on a prior conception of justice.

    The last claim of desert that I will consider is the claim that individuals deserve to

    be rewarded in proportion to their contributions to society. Contributions to the public

    good can deserve gratitude. But this is so only if those contributions are made for the

    right kind of reasonsroughly, reasons that are not self-interested. Moreover, the

    appropriateness of gratitude does not entail the appropriateness of significant economic

    reward, or justify the cost of such reward to those who would as a consequence have less.

    It may be claimed that, quite apart from gratitude, individuals are entitled to a

    reward proportional to their marginal contribution. But as Rawls and Scheffler point out,

    an individuals marginal productivity depends on the demand for what he or she can do

    and on the contributions others are making, or could make, to the process of production

    (Rawls 1971, 271; Scheffler 2001, 191). It depends on the overall productive system and,

    I would add, on the justifiability of the form of cooperation that this system involves.

    Contribution in this sense is therefore not a distinct property of the individual that is a

    basis for a claim of desert.

    Conclusion

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    31/33

    31

    I have identified desert with a particular form of justification: a claim that treating

    a person in a certain way is made appropriate simply by what that person is like or has

    done, without reference to the good consequences of this treatment, or to the fact that this

    treatment is licensed or required by justifiable institutions. After examining some ways in

    which the idea of appropriateness can be understood, I have maintained that a certain

    (limited) range of attitudes in response to moral wrongdoing can be deserved in the sense

    I describe. This idea of desert also plays a role, although not a conclusive role, in the

    justification of legal punishment. But, I have argued, a pre-justicial concept of desert has

    no role to play in the justification of significant differences in economic benefits.

    My claim here is not just that the particular conception of desert that I have

    examined earlier in the paper, based on the ideas of appropriateness that I have

    explored, plays no role in distributive justice. It is rather that initially plausible claims

    that individuals deserve certain economic benefits turn out, on closer examination, either

    to be invalid or to reduce to claims of justice of some other identifiable sort.

    Literature

    Feinberg, J. 1970. Justice and Personal Desert. InDoing and Deserving.Princeton:Princeton University Press.

    Hart, H.L.A. 1968. Legal Responsibility and Excuses. In Punishment and

    Responsibility, 28-53. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Hart, H.L.A. 1968. Prolegomenon to the Principles of Punishment. In Punishment andResponsibility, 1-27. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Hieronymi. P. 2001. Articulating an Uncompromising Forgiveness. Philosophy and

    Phenomenological Research62: 529-555.

    Hirsch von, A. 1992. Proportionality in the Philosophy of Punishment. Crime andJustice16: 55-98.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    32/33

    32

    Hirsch von, A. 1993. Censure and Sanctions. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Hume. A Treatise of Human Nature. Gutenberg Project.

    http://www.gutenberg.org/files/4705/4705-h/4705-h.htm .

    Kelly, E. 2012 What Is an Excuse? InBlame: Its Nature and Norms, eds.N.Tognazzini, & J. Coates. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Pereboom, D. 2012. Free Will Skepticism, Blame, and Obligation. InBlame: Its Nature

    and Norms, eds.N. Tognazzini, & J. Coates. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Rawls, J. 1971.A Theory of Justice.Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

    Rosen, M. 2003. Liberalism, Desert and Responsibility: A Response to Samuel

    Scheffler. Philosophical Books44: 118-124.

    Scanlon, T. 1988. The Significance of Choice. In Tanner Lectures on Human Values,

    Volume VIII, ed. Sterling & McMurrin. Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press.

    Scanlon, T. 1998. What We Owe to Each Other. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University

    Press.

    Scanlon, T. 2003. Punishment and the Rule of Law. In The Difficulty of Tolerance,219-233. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Scanlon, T. 2008.Moral Dimensions. Harvard: Harvard University Press.

    Scanlon, T. 2012. Interpreting Blame. InBlame: Its Nature and Norms, eds.N.Tognazzini, & J. Coates, 84-99. New York: Oxford University Press.

    Scheffler. 2001. Justice and Desert in Liberal Theory. InBoundaries and Allegiances.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Sher, G. 1987.Desert. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Strawson, P.F. 2003. Freedom and Resentment. In Free Will, ed. G. Watson. Oxford:

    Oxford University Press.

    Wallace, J.R. 1993.Responsibility and the Moral Sentiments. Cambridge MA: HarvardUniversity Press.

  • 7/25/2019 Giving Desert Its Due

    33/33

    33