96
Book Reviews Political Theory The Dark Side of Modernity by Jeffrey C. Alexander. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2013. 187pp., £15.99, ISBN 978 0 7456 4822 4 This book is a collection of texts by Jeffrey C. Alexan- der, most of which have been previously published as book chapters or journal articles. Alexander sums up his ideas and criticisms of modern thought, which he divides into four elements: ‘philosophy, psychology, art and social engineering’ (p. 10). His focus is on the nega- tive effects side of modernity, whereof the gloomy title of the book. This intellectual exploration brings forth an argument that modernity is indeed two-dimensional – evil and good – and at the same time both backward- and forward-looking. Modernity, in other words, incites, encourages and produces the best and the worst kinds of social behaviour. This comprises technological and medical advances, the successful welfare systems and public education institutions, but it also includes the potential for violence of cataclysmic proportions, mass killings and limited freedoms (pp. 54–61). This guiding premise is critically engaged through- out the book. Alexander contrasts progress with debauchery in relation to the material and moral human condition. He analyses Weber’s understanding of rationality (pp. 45–9) and the process of rationali- sation as an example of modern intellectual struggle where reason and faith are constantly in conflict, and where faith will inevitably lose. Rationalisation came to be a process that ultimately objectified people in order to dominate them, replacing the old forms of domination with modern ones: isolation and cultural abandonment (p. 53). Throughout the chapters, along- side demonstrating the looming darkness within (post-)modernity, Alexander also suggests ways of overcoming the deep flaws embedded in it (pp. 76–7). By analysing various points of tension in modernity Alexander points to potential ways we, as a society, could amend and diffuse the tensions. He invokes Simmel’s notion of strangeness as one element of tension, wherein a variety of opposing groups in a society seek to dehumanise the other, thus rendering them the enemy to be destroyed (pp. 95–8). These tensions are seemingly inherent and essentially a neces- sary part of human imagination and subsequent sociali- sation rooted in our conceptions of good and evil (pp. 110–22). As a sociological theorist and functionalist, Alexander gives much attention to civil society and its ability to absorb, discuss and resolve much of the noted tensions. The healing process within which the darkness of modernity can be ameliorated involves individual self-repair and introspection, collective insistence on improving human rights, social mobilisation and social criticism, but also developing international institutions that would facilitate various locally produced capacities to assuage tensions. This book offers a highly engaging and insightful overview of modernity with one major flaw – it is too short. Emin Poljarevic (University of Edinburgh) Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction by Joshua Alexander. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2012. 154pp., £15.99, ISBN 978 0 7456 4918 4 It is often thought that the strength of a philosophical theory rests on the extent to which it accords with our philosophical intuitions. These include our intuitions about whether it is permissible to kill someone inten- tionally in order to save a number of lives, whether a person can be morally responsible if she could not have done otherwise, and whether justified true belief is sufficient for knowledge. Traditionally, philosophers have relied on their own intuitions as the basic data for philosophical inquiry. The problem with that strategy is that they often share the same educational back- ground as well as a similar way of thinking. Moreover, empirical evidence suggests that humans tend to over- estimate the extent to which others agree with them. POLITICAL STUDIES REVIEW: 2014 VOL 12, 248–343 © 2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review © 2014 Political Studies Association

Langlois - BSG Review

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • Book Reviews

    Political Theory

    The Dark Side of Modernity by Jeffrey C.

    Alexander. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2013. 187pp.,

    15.99, ISBN 978 0 7456 4822 4

    This book is a collection of texts by Jeffrey C. Alexan-

    der, most of which have been previously published as

    book chapters or journal articles. Alexander sums up his

    ideas and criticisms of modern thought, which he

    divides into four elements: philosophy, psychology, art

    and social engineering (p. 10). His focus is on the nega-

    tive effects side of modernity, whereof the gloomy title

    of the book. This intellectual exploration brings forth

    an argument that modernity is indeed two-dimensional

    evil and good and at the same time both backward-

    and forward-looking. Modernity, in other words,

    incites, encourages and produces the best and the worst

    kinds of social behaviour. This comprises technological

    and medical advances, the successful welfare systems and

    public education institutions, but it also includes the

    potential for violence of cataclysmic proportions, mass

    killings and limited freedoms (pp. 5461).

    This guiding premise is critically engaged through-

    out the book. Alexander contrasts progress with

    debauchery in relation to the material and moral

    human condition. He analyses Webers understanding

    of rationality (pp. 459) and the process of rationali-

    sation as an example of modern intellectual struggle

    where reason and faith are constantly in conflict, and

    where faith will inevitably lose. Rationalisation came

    to be a process that ultimately objectified people in

    order to dominate them, replacing the old forms of

    domination with modern ones: isolation and cultural

    abandonment (p. 53). Throughout the chapters, along-

    side demonstrating the looming darkness within

    (post-)modernity, Alexander also suggests ways of

    overcoming the deep flaws embedded in it (pp. 767).

    By analysing various points of tension in modernity

    Alexander points to potential ways we, as a society,

    could amend and diffuse the tensions. He invokes

    Simmels notion of strangeness as one element of

    tension, wherein a variety of opposing groups in a

    society seek to dehumanise the other, thus rendering

    them the enemy to be destroyed (pp. 958). These

    tensions are seemingly inherent and essentially a neces-

    sary part of human imagination and subsequent sociali-

    sation rooted in our conceptions of good and evil (pp.

    11022). As a sociological theorist and functionalist,

    Alexander gives much attention to civil society and its

    ability to absorb, discuss and resolve much of the noted

    tensions. The healing process within which the darkness

    of modernity can be ameliorated involves individual

    self-repair and introspection, collective insistence on

    improving human rights, social mobilisation and social

    criticism, but also developing international institutions

    that would facilitate various locally produced capacities

    to assuage tensions. This book offers a highly engaging

    and insightful overview of modernity with one major

    flaw it is too short.

    Emin Poljarevic(University of Edinburgh)

    Experimental Philosophy: An Introduction by

    Joshua Alexander. Cambridge: Polity Press, 2012.

    154pp., 15.99, ISBN 978 0 7456 4918 4

    It is often thought that the strength of a philosophical

    theory rests on the extent to which it accords with our

    philosophical intuitions. These include our intuitions

    about whether it is permissible to kill someone inten-

    tionally in order to save a number of lives, whether a

    person can be morally responsible if she could not

    have done otherwise, and whether justified true belief

    is sufficient for knowledge. Traditionally, philosophers

    have relied on their own intuitions as the basic data for

    philosophical inquiry. The problem with that strategy

    is that they often share the same educational back-

    ground as well as a similar way of thinking. Moreover,

    empirical evidence suggests that humans tend to over-

    estimate the extent to which others agree with them.

    POLITICAL STUDIES REVIEW: 2014 VOL 12, 248343

    bs_bs_banner

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies Association

    http://www.politicalstudies.org
  • Experimental philosophy promises to overcome this

    potential source of bias by using the tools of the

    cognitive and social sciences to uncover the philo-

    sophical intuitions of ordinary people. The literature in

    this burgeoning area of inquiry often reads like a

    detective novel where each researcher is engaged in a

    search not only for peoples intuitions, but also the

    factors that trigger those intuitions. Joshua Alexander

    provides us with an excellent introduction to the

    empirical detective work that has been undertaken

    since experimental philosophy was first conceived a

    little more than ten years ago. From his highly readable

    book we learn, for example, that normative considera-

    tions influence whether people assign intentionality to

    a persons actions. The side effects of a persons action

    are interpreted as intentional in those cases where the

    effect is morally bad and unintentional in those cases

    where the effect is morally good. In addition, experi-

    mental evidence suggests that emotional responses

    influence the attribution of moral responsibility. In a

    deterministic world, people assign responsibility to a

    person for causing a bad outcome, but not for causing

    a good outcome.

    Perhaps most surprising of all is that some of the

    standard philosophical intuitions that philosophers

    assume to be universally shared appear to vary between

    cultures and between genders. As Alexander concedes,

    this represents a potential problem for an approach to

    philosophical inquiry that takes intuitions as basic data

    points for constructing theory. The research findings

    described in this volume are genuinely fascinating, and

    Alexander does an admirable job of drawing out their

    implications for contemporary philosophy. This book

    should be of considerable interest to scholars and stu-

    dents who are curious about this intriguing approach

    to philosophy.

    Simon Wigley(Bilkent University, Ankara)

    The Dunayevskaya-Marcuse-Fromm Corre-

    spondence, 19541978: Dialogues on Hegel, Marx

    and Critical Theory by Kevin B. Anderson and

    Russell Rockwell (eds). Plymouth: Lexington Books,

    2012. 267pp., 21.95, ISBN 978 0 7391 6836 3

    In these letters, Anderson and Rockwell give their

    readers the opportunity to be the fly on the wall for

    the informal discussions between three of the most

    noteworthy leftist theorists of the twentieth century.

    The correspondence between Raya Dunayevskaya and

    Herbert Marcuse, and Dunayevskaya and Erich Fromm

    runs from 1954 to 1978. The most significant contri-

    bution this text makes, beyond the correspondence

    between these important thinkers to the historical

    record, is contained in the extensive introduction,

    which summarises and contextualises the letters to

    follow.

    The editors argue that the publication of this book

    containing their original introduction, the correspond-

    ence and the appendices (which include several

    re-published prefaces, introductions and book reviews

    discussed extensively in the letters) represents a signifi-

    cant contribution to ongoing discussions within

    Marxism and Critical Theory and their connection to

    Hegelian thought. However, this seems to be some-

    what overstated. This contribution to the historical

    development and evolution of (post-)Marxist thinking

    re-emphasises the great contributions made by

    Dunayevskaya a seriously under-appreciated radical

    thinker in her own right and in these letters she often

    outshines the more widely read and appreciated

    counterparts to whom she was writing. This corre-

    spondence evinces her original thinking and scholar-

    ship in the fields of Hegelian Marxism, radical

    humanism and feminist socialism, as well as her influ-

    ence in these regards on the more widely recognised

    Fromm and Marcuse.

    Although the correspondence (as is often the case)

    contains a lot of personal discussions that are not

    especially relevant to the topics of Marx, Hegel or

    Critical Theory, some of the personal missives illu-

    minate the human relationships at play in academia,

    especially during such a tumultuous domestic and

    international political period. Alongside that, though,

    there is a great deal of discussion of the personal/

    professional roadblocks Dunayevskaya faced regardless

    of her obvious intellectual ingenuity, especially in

    getting her work published due to her lack of formal

    academic credentials.

    Although significant, I wonder if this work is a bit

    premature because of the inability to publish the

    actual texts of Fromms letters (due to posthumous

    restrictions put in place by his estate). Fromms cor-

    respondence is summarised by the editors and is

    therefore not a primary source. Overall, this book is

    an important piece of scholarship that is worth

    BOOK REVIEWS 249

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • reading for professional academics already interested in

    Critical Theory.

    Bryant William Sculos(Florida International University, Miami)

    Nonviolence in Political Theory by Iain Atack.

    Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press, 2012. 202pp.,

    19.99, ISBN 978 0 7486 3378 4

    While in recent decades international relations and

    democratic politics have been marked and inspired by

    practices of nonviolence including the end of com-

    munism in Eastern Europe, the Orange Revolution in

    Ukraine and the Rose Revolution in Georgia, the

    Arab Spring in Tunisia and Egypt, and the Occupy

    Wall Street movement the field of political theory

    has not included the category of nonviolence among

    its central preoccupations. In this regard, Iain Atacks

    Nonviolence in Political Theory marks a possible change ofdirection and suggests new research trajectories, as it

    examines the place of nonviolence and civil resistance

    in political theory. It applies the perspective of con-

    temporary theories of power and violence, as well as

    the role of the state and the nature of socio-political

    change. Reaching beyond the historical analysis of

    nonviolence as a political idea and event, Atack turns

    to the philosophies of Leo Tolstoy, Mahatma Gandhi,

    Martin Luther King, Hannah Arendt and Gene Sharp

    to examine the conceptual tapestry of two main

    streams in the tradition of nonviolence: principled

    nonviolence and pragmatic nonviolence.

    The question of the state, its legitimacy and role in

    the achievement of public liberty and security is the

    main reference point in the book. It is considered both

    from the perspective of social contract theory and the

    more radical traditions of Georges Sorel and Frantz

    Fanon. That particular conceptual and methodological

    approach allows Atack to highlight the complexity and

    diversity of the area of nonviolence insofar as it incor-

    porates diverse, and sometimes conflicting, positions,

    which include Tolstoys appeal to eliminate the coer-

    cive institution of the state inspired by his Christian

    anarchist ethics, and Gandhis belief in the possibility

    of the progressive substitution of the institutionalised

    violence of the state by practices of nonviolence for

    the goal of achieving a peaceful society (ramaraj). Thequestion of nonviolence in contemporary political

    theorising of power and state violence is subsequently

    taken up in Atacks reading of Michel Foucault and

    Antonio Gramsci. Finally, the book also includes dis-

    cussion of pacifism and nonviolence as related, but

    mutually irreducible political and philosophical posi-

    tions, thus situating nonviolence specifically in the

    context of armed conflict and internationalism.

    This book is a highly recommended text for under-

    graduate courses in critical political philosophy and in

    democratic theory, as well as for graduate students who

    are focusing on the topics of regime change, demo-

    cratic transition and consolidation, civil protest, paci-

    fism and war.

    Magdalena Zolkos(University of Western Sydney)

    The Philosophy of Race by Albert Atkin.

    Durham, NC: Acumen, 2012. 194pp., 15.99, ISBN

    978 1 84465 515 1

    This is a smartly written book that is a wonderful

    introduction to complex debates about the philosophy

    of race. Albert Atkin takes readers around the world

    from the United Kingdom to the United States, South

    America to Continental Europe, and in so doing gives

    them an international perspective on race. This alone is

    commendable. Despite its small size, this book contains

    a wealth of information. Yet readers hoping for par-

    ticularly in-depth case studies or thorough understand-

    ings of particular thinkers or philosophies will need to

    look beyond this text. The book will help those

    needing a quick refresher on the philosophy of race as

    well as those who want an introduction to the field.

    This work is divided into five short chapters,

    bookended by an introduction and conclusion. The

    chapters Is Race Real?, Is Race Social?, What

    Should We Do with Race?, Racism, The Everyday

    Impact of Race and Racism are judicially divided

    into subsections and each chapter ends with its own

    conclusion. This structure makes the book readable in

    short sittings, contributing to its utility as a study guide

    or quick reference. The book is accessible to readers of

    all experience levels.

    One cannot help but notice several omissions.

    Frantz Fanon, Cornel West, Eric Michael Dyson and

    Henry Louis Gates, Jr. are absent, as are the majority of

    critical race theorists and critical race feminists. Atkin,

    an expert in Charles Sanders Peirce, pragmatism and

    semiotics, leaves this expertise out of the book, which

    250 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • is unfortunate because such discussions might lend

    fruitfully to the text la Ruth Wodak and MichaelPounds, who have brought semiotics into conversation

    with the philosophy of race.

    These concerns are relatively minor. Atkin is adept

    at discussing the intersections of philosophy and

    biology as applied to race. Chapter 1 is particularly

    helpful for scholars interested in the ways biology has

    been used to promote notions of racial difference and

    inequality. Atkin discusses science with aplomb. He

    admits his discussion might be overwhelming to some,

    but here he is simply too modest. His ability to distil

    scientific arguments into readable prose is no small

    accomplishment.

    This text is strongly written and keenly priced. It

    should be a welcome read for anyone, of any educa-

    tional level, interested in the philosophy of race. While

    not flawless, Atkin has provided a solid contribution to

    this complex field, and has done so in an accessible and

    engaging way.

    Nick J. Sciullo(Georgia State University)

    In Our Name: The Ethics of Democracy by Eric

    Beerbohm. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University

    Press, 2012. 352pp., 30.95, ISBN 978 0 691 15461 9

    Work on the ethics of political conduct has tended to

    worry at politicians virtues, vices and dirty hands. Eric

    Beerbohms important new book zeroes in on the

    moral responsibilities and entanglements of the indi-

    vidual citizen in democratic societies. In particular, as

    its title suggests, it is concerned with complicity, thespecial horror that you experience when state-

    sponsored injustices are committed in your name (p.

    1). The agreeable moral it draws for those who value

    political participation is that the fuller our engagement

    in politics the more we inform ourselves and protest

    about the injustices carried out in our name the

    lighter our moral complicity in these injustices.

    Beerbohm works through three sets of ethical issues

    that the citizen confronts: the ethics of participation,

    belief and delegation. That each vote taken in isolation

    is a drop in the ocean, he argues, does not erase a

    defeasible moral reason to participate in elections

    where one can make a contribution against injustice.

    The cognitive bias and inattention of most of us when

    it comes to politics also does not wipe out the notion

    of responsibility (or, alternatively, demand that each

    citizen become what Walter Lippmann called

    omnicompetent). Instead, there is a place for an

    appropriate set of cognitive shortcuts in a democratic

    ethics of belief. Finally, citizens are viewed as

    co-principals in shaping the terms of their interaction,

    whose agents are an indispensable but fallible means for

    the implementation of these terms. While Beerbohms

    attention is largely on what it is like to be a citizen,

    as he puts it, there is some discussion of the implica-

    tions of this account of complicity, participation, belief

    and delegation for macro-democratic design. In par-

    ticular, he suggests a series of institutional paths

    (including opt-outs and petitions) that allow us to

    detach our agency from the states actions.

    This is a vigorously anti-Hobbesian book that in

    effect challenges those who vest less in the epistemic

    capacities and moral responsibilities of the individual

    citizen to work through the implications of their scep-

    ticism. Combining wide learning with a tenacious and

    undogmatic focus on the problems of democratic citi-

    zenship, Beerbohm has written a book that identifies

    fresh solutions to some important problems and

    should become a key reference point for democratic

    theorists.

    Matthew Festenstein(University of York)

    A Companion to Political Philosophy: Methods,

    Tools, Topics by Antonella Besussi (ed.).

    Farnham: Ashgate, 2012. 244pp., 75.00, ISBN 978 1

    409 41062 1

    Antonella Besussis edited volume has an ambitious

    goal a complete overview of political philosophy

    but it only delivers a fair overview of contemporary

    thought (p. ix). The difficulties such overview texts

    face are numerous two of which will be addressed

    here. Foremost is the question of audience, after which

    is the issue of what is included. By evaluating these

    issues, this review uncovers the strengths and weak-

    nesses of Besussis collaborative text.

    Overall, the intended audience is unclear. The

    methods section contains six chapters. Chapters 1, 4

    and 6 are suitable for undergraduates, while chapters 2,

    3 and 5 are not. In particular, Besussis first chapter

    (explaining the tension between normative political

    philosophy and the descriptive science of politics

    BOOK REVIEWS 251

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • shaping political science today) is recommended for

    undergraduates as a short, accessible introduction to

    political thought and is more suitable than alternatives

    like Strausss What is Political Philosophy?.1 Also,Pasqualis summary of the pros and cons of theories

    emphasising feasibility versus desirability, and Zuolos

    similar evaluation of realistic versus idealistic thought,

    provide a good foundation for undergraduates.

    However, the essays on truth, objectivity and the

    debate over fact-grounded versus principle-grounded

    theories necessitate a pre-existing grounding in political

    philosophy more common to graduate students.

    Next, the six chapters in the tools section are pri-

    marily graduate level. Only Wijzes piece discussing

    the means versus ends or the Machiavellian dirty

    hands debate and possibly Reidys piece assessing

    theories driven by what is right versus what is good are

    appropriate for undergraduates. The four chapters on

    politics/metaphysics, counterfactuals, justification and

    trade-offs are denser, graduate readings.

    Following this, the eight chapters in the topics

    section are the most valuable in the book. Each piece

    takes a topic (ranging from the enduring themes of

    liberty, equality, justice and community to contempo-

    rary ones of pluralism, public discourse, (dis)agreement

    and identity/difference), identifies its key thinkers and

    summarises their arguments. One is hard pressed to

    find better concise summaries introducing contempo-

    rary debates.

    As for content, Besussis collaborative work should be

    called A Companion to Contemporary Political Philoso-phy as this is not an overview of the history of political

    thought. The methods section references some classics

    (Plato and Aristotle) and there is some use of modern

    thought (limited to Machiavelli, contractarianism and

    utilitarianism). Contemporary thought particularly

    Rawls is the focus. Habermas receives limited treat-

    ment, post-modern and post-structural scholarship is

    scarce (only Derridas deconstructionism receives much

    attention), and Marxist scholarship is absent. Given that

    most contributors are continental scholars, these choices

    are surprising.

    Note1 Strauss, L. (1959) What is Political Philosophy? Chicago, IL:

    University of Chicago Press.

    Michael T. Rogers(Arkansas Tech University)

    Hegels Political Philosophy: A Systematic

    Reading of the Philosophy of Right by Thom

    Brooks. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,

    second edition, 2013. 263pp., 22.99, ISBN 978 0

    7486 4509 1

    This book grew from a PhD thesis to a first edition in

    2007. In this second edition of Hegels Political Philoso-phy, Brooks includes additional chapters discussingHegels views on democracy and history. Also new is a

    reply to criticisms that followed the first edition. The

    author set out to argue for a systematic reading of

    Hegels work in particular Grundlinien der Philosophiedes Rechts (Elements of the Philosophy of Right). Part ofthe contemporary public shies away from Hegels

    metaphysical, even religious, conceptions. Such read-

    ings would focus on a single work or topic. Brooks

    successfully demonstrates the explanatory force of

    Hegels system while reading the Philosophy of Right.Over the years, Hegel described a dialectic, layered

    system of the world and its thought. Brooks references

    to conceptions Hegel introduced in other writings

    improve our understanding of the Philosophy of Right.Brooks uses his first chapter to situate the Philosophy

    of Right in the context of all Hegels writings. Ratherthan sketching the historical and philosophical context

    of Hegels works, Brooks discusses interpretations of

    those works and of the philosophers position. He does

    not side with any one school of interpretation Hegel

    seen as a conservative supporting the Prussian, reac-

    tionary regime versus Hegel promoting liberal ideas. In

    his moderation, Brooks turns our attention back to

    Hegels texts. Chapter 5, for instance, explains how

    Hegel thought about different forms of family life.

    Brooks neither dismisses nor excuses Hegel for his

    adherence to marriage with children, but rather shows

    why an unmarried couple or a same-sex marriage does

    not match the system of thought.

    This book is aimed at those who read Hegels works

    of political philosophy because it certainly helps to

    choose how to read and understand those works. Like-

    wise, some understanding of the Enlightenment,

    German idealism, the Napoleonic wars and German

    state-building can be deemed necessary to grasp

    Hegels philosophy. Brooks book is less suited as a

    stand-alone introduction to Hegels political philoso-

    phy, although the author discusses Hegels views on

    property, punishment, morality, family, law, monar-

    252 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • chy, democracy, war and history. While he relates

    those topics in the Philosophy of Right to other texts byHegel, he hardly contextualises them within history

    and political theory in general.

    Brooks writes clearly, does not confront readers with

    German and his book does not require advanced famili-

    arity with philosophy. However, there is a downside to

    his clarity in that the chapters are somewhat repetitive.

    Wouter-Jan Oosten(Sociotext Foundation, The Hague)

    Marx on Gender and the Family: A Critical

    Study by Heather A. Brown. Leiden: Brill, 2012.

    232pp., 94.84, ISBN 9789004214286

    In Marx on Gender and the Family, Heather Brown devel-ops a comprehensive analysis of Marxs entire oeuvre inrelation to the subjects of gender and the family. Based

    on a clearly written textual engagement with Marxs

    work, the book reveals the extent to which gender was

    an essential category for him, despite the fact that he did

    not formulate a systematic theory of gender (p. 3).

    The book follows a chiefly chronological order with

    which the impressive breadth of Marxs writings is

    unpacked and examined with particular reference to

    gender. Starting with the Economic and Philosophical

    Manuscripts of 1844, Brown retraces the development

    of Marxs thought on gender in his major and minor

    publications, including inter alia, The German Ideology,The Communist Manifesto, Capital and a selection of TheNew York Tribune articles. Despite the fact that Marxsometimes used the vocabulary of Victorian ideology

    in his writings, Brown maintains that the dialectical

    method developed in Marxs corpus is a potent anti-

    dote to the essentialist conceptualisations of gender

    and the family and that Marxs categories provide

    resources for feminist theory (p. 70). The conceptual

    discussion is reinforced with examples highlighting

    Marxs political activities and his direct engagement

    with the social and economic oppressions faced by

    women in bourgeois society.

    The final two chapters provide highly original exami-

    nations of the Ethnological Notebooks in which Marx

    studied and engaged with the anthropological works of

    Lewis Henry Morgan, Henry Sumner Maine, Ludwig

    Lange, John Budd Pear, John Lubbock and Maxim

    Kovalevsky. Focusing mainly on the sections related to

    Morgan, Maine and Lange, Brown offers a crucial

    reconsideration of the relationship between Marxs own

    analysis of Morgans Ancient Society and Engels TheOrigin of the Family, Private Property and the State. Theauthor convincingly draws a line between Marxs and

    Engels discussions of the position of women in histori-

    cal development and underlines that for Marx, unlike

    Engels, the introduction of private property and the

    naturalisation of monogamy did not entail the world-

    historic defeat of the female sex (pp. 117 and 158).

    Brown makes a compelling case for revisiting Marxs

    thought on gender since it is depicted as a productive

    starting point for conceptualising agency and subjectiv-

    ity compared to Engels relatively deterministic and

    unilinear framework (p. 175).

    Browns book is a laudable heir to Raya

    Dunayevskayas Rosa Luxemburg, Womens Liberationand Marxs Philosophy of Revolution.1 But beyond itsimmanent value as a powerful contribution to

    Marxism, the book further speaks to contemporary

    feminist debates by re-emphasising the significance of

    the dialectical method in overcoming binary dualisms

    (e.g. nature/culture, man/woman) and examining the

    non-static forms of social relations without overlook-

    ing local and macro power-structures (p. 209).

    Note1 Dunayevskaya, R. (1991) Rosa Luxemburg, Womens Lib-

    eration and Marxs Philosophy of Revolution. Urbana, IL:University of Illinois Press.

    Cemal Burak Tansel(University of Nottingham)

    Dialogues with Contemporary Political Theorists

    by Gary Browning, Raia Prokhovnik and Maria

    Dimova-Cookson (eds). Basingstoke: Palgrave Mac-

    millan, 2012. 248pp., 57.50, ISBN 978 0230303058

    In this volume, Gary Browning, Maria Dimova-

    Cookson, Raia Prokhovnik and others interview twelve

    prominent contemporary thinkers. Benjamin Barber,

    Jane Bennett, Dipesh Chakrabarty, Jerry Cohen,

    William E. Connolly, Rainer Forst, Bonnie Honig,

    Carole Pateman, Philip Pettit, Amartya Sen, Quentin

    Skinner and R. B. J. Walker provide fascinating insights

    into their work, discuss their intellectual trajectories,

    and reflect on politics, ethics and society.

    Barber stresses the limitations of representative

    democracy, and defends a theory of strong democracy

    BOOK REVIEWS 253

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • that cultivates the idea of an active and reflective citizen

    body. Bennett challenges traditional understandings of

    agency by introducing the notion of vibrant matter.

    She argues that the real locus of agency is always a

    human non-human collective (p. 53). Chakrabarty

    reflects on the possibility of a genuinely democratic

    modernisation based on an open-ended dialogue

    between the subaltern classes and the elites (p. 67). For

    Cohen, the current economic crisis shows the problem-

    atic nature of the capitalist system, and creates more

    space for egalitarian and progressive theorisation.

    Connolly explores the dynamics of multidimensional

    pluralism, and speaks of the fragility and tensions that

    characterise the human condition today. Forst explains

    the key ideas of his philosophical project: normative

    justification in democratic politics, and a critical theory

    of justice. Honigs vision of agonistic humanism

    encompasses such issues as diagnostic political theory,

    agonistic cosmopolitanism, the confrontation with the

    other, and feminism as a democratic quest for equality

    and shared power. Pateman refers to her critique of the

    social contract tradition in The Sexual Contract and inContract and Domination (with Charles Mills). She thennotes the impact of globalisation and of the theories

    of deliberative democracy on contemporary political

    thought. Pettit argues that republicanism articulates

    ideals of democratic justice, public justification and

    civic freedom that seek to establish a relationship in

    which the governors do not dominate the governed (p.

    166). Sen extols the virtues of the social choice tradi-

    tion in theorising justice, and advocates a global public

    discourse on development and human well-being.

    Skinner talks about the corpus of his work, highlights

    his interest in the Renaissance, and defends the value

    and the emancipatory character of the republican theory

    of freedom. Walker shows that international relations

    theory can address a variety of innovative themes, such

    as spatiotemporality, the relation between subjectivity

    and sovereignty, boundaries, as well as issues of meaning

    and explanation.

    The interviews in this volume are not only accessible,

    but also skilfully executed and intellectually stimulating.

    The reader is invited on a journey of exploration and

    reflection in the rich landscape of political thought. The

    experience is both rewarding and empowering.

    Stamatoula Panagakou(University of Cyprus, Nicosia)

    The Poetic Character of Human Activity:

    Collected Essays on the Thought of Michael

    Oakeshott by Wendell John Coats Jr. and Chor-

    Yung Cheung. Plymouth: Lexington Books, 2012.

    140pp, 37.95, ISBN 978 0 7391 7161 5

    The British philosopher Michael Oakeshott is well-

    known for his critique of Rationalism (the assumption

    that social, economic and political problems can be

    anticipated and are readily amenable to solution through

    the application of human rationality), his preference for

    an approach sensitive to tradition and his view that the

    state should more closely approximate a civil association

    than an enterprise association. Oakeshott is also known

    for his preference for a morality of habit and affect over

    a morality of principle. The Poetic Character of HumanActivity is a collection of essays on the element inOakeshotts thought that, in its critique of what

    Oakeshott referred to as Rationalism, emphasises the

    notion of craft and art over science and reason. Also

    emphasised is the notion within his thought of a politics

    founded on the notion of conversation, and his discus-

    sion of the poetic or aesthetic as modes of experience.

    Each of the authors has considered such issues in

    previous works: Wendell Coats in Oakeshott and HisContemporaries and Chor-Yung Cheung in The Questfor Civil Order.1 They see this poetic or aesthetic aspectas fundamental to Oakeshotts understanding of how,

    while eschewing Rationalism (which he views as con-

    ducive to ideological politics), politics can keep a

    society together and maintain civil peace while at the

    same time permitting the flexibility that allows tradi-

    tions to achieve continuity as well as evolution. Of the

    nine essays included, six are by Coats and three are by

    Cheung. The latter include the additional focus of

    considering parallels between Oakeshotts thought and

    that of thinkers within the Chinese tradition.

    A number of other recent works on Oakeshott

    one thinks of Glenn Worthingtons Religious and PoeticExperience in the Thought of Michael Oakeshott and Eliza-beth Campbell Coreys Michael Oakeshott: On Religion,Aesthetics and Politics2 have moved in a similar direc-tion albeit with some differences of emphasis. Such

    an approach does shed light on some hitherto

    neglected aspects of Oakeshotts thought. The PoeticCharacter of Human Activity presumes some prior famili-arity with his thought, and students of Oakeshott

    should find this collection of interest.

    254 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Notes1 Coats, W. (2000) Oakeshott and His Contemporaries.

    Selinsgrove, PA: Susquehanna University Press; C.-Y.Cheung (2007) The Quest for Civil Order: Politics, Rules andIndividuality. Exeter: Imprint Academic.

    2 Worthington, G. (2005) Religious and Poetic Experience in theThought of Michael Oakeshott. Exeter: Imprint Academic; E.C. Corey (2006) Michael Oakeshott: On Religion, Aestheticsand Politics. Columbia, MO: University of Missouri Press.

    James G. Mellon(Independent scholar)

    Immunitas: The Protection and Negation of

    Life by Roberto Esposito. Cambridge: Polity Press,

    2011. 207pp., 16.99, ISBN 978 0 7456 4914 6

    A theoretically innovative book, useful for those inter-

    ested in the future of life and death in the biopolitical

    age, Immunitas is the concluding piece of the trilogythat includes Bios and Communitas. The book convinc-ingly positions immunity as the framework of moder-

    nity, employing law and religion to demonstrate the

    gravitas of the immunitary paradigm. Communities are

    rescued from violence through inoculation; the law

    mobilises legitimate violence through various apparat-uses to manage proscribed violence; religion is remedy

    to the cognizance of lifes bounds, assimilating uncer-

    tainty through a promise of immortality.

    The somatic mechanism of immunity is often

    described through a lexicon of war and turmoil. An

    etymological journey through the genesis of immun-

    ity before its adoption by cellular biology leads to a

    fascinating look at immunologists appropriation of

    politico-legal language of conflict and death. Although

    Roberto Esposito does not deny that a bodily

    immunitary mechanism pre-dated the immunitary

    model of law, the authors focus on the notions

    genealogy is effective in illustrating the use of immun-

    ity as a productive vehicle for the understanding of

    spheres beyond human biology.

    In the books final chapters, the discussion takes on

    especial energy. Esposito engages in a convincing cri-

    tique of Foucauldian biopolitics, arguing that its limi-

    tations are a product of Foucaults exhaustive, but

    temporally contingent, analysis of a specifically modern

    period in which sovereign power and then biopolitics

    came to articulate themselves. Esposito offers a clarifi-

    cation of the subject of biopolitics: the population.

    Rather than a confluence of people sharing rights or

    national consciousness, a population is many individ-

    uals each with a body. By anchoring biopolitics to thesoma and recognising developments in prosthesis,

    Esposito recognises that the ontology of corporeality is

    thrown into question. With the bodys bounds in

    crisis, what becomes of the biopolitical subject?

    We are asked whether or not there is a more effec-

    tive principle than immunity in understanding the

    semiotic gravity of the permeable bounds of the

    autonomous self in opposition to the other. The book

    argues convincingly that the paradigm of modernity

    can be conceived as one of immunity; Esposito high-

    lights the profound challenges to the bodys supposedly

    incontestable limits that are brought into being by

    advancements in contemporary biotechnology. With

    such an emphasis on modernitys challenge to accepted

    human selfhood, the book effectively prompts its

    readers to ask whether we must reconfigure the lens

    through which we understand autonomous human

    existence.

    Rosalind G. Williams(University of York)

    Nietzsches Enlightenment: The Free-Spirit

    Trilogy of the Middle Period by Paul Franco.

    Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press, 2011.

    262pp., 26.00, ISBN 9780226259819

    Paul Franco has written a very important book advanc-

    ing a compelling argument on Nietzsches thought,

    that contrary to the interpretation of various post-

    modern thinkers (Derrida, Kofman, Deleuze, Blondel

    et al.) Nietzsches middle period works (Human AllToo Human, Daybreak and The Gay Science) offer amore friendly critique of the Enlightenment and

    rationalism of the humanist tradition than is usually

    portrayed by the secondary literature that deals with

    this period (if at all). Franco also makes the point that

    these middle period works often lack the rhetorical

    character and tone that shape Nietzsches later works.

    In addressing the works of Nietzsches middle

    period, Franco suggests that they are hardly a minor

    respite or break from the early period of his work

    (with the influences of romanticism, Wagner and

    Schopenhauer), before Nietzsche turned to his later

    works (where his rhetorical character becomes that of a

    prophet, one who seeks to philosophize with the

    hammer). All too often Nietzsches middle period gets

    BOOK REVIEWS 255

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • overshadowed either by the early period or the later

    works, and is often seen as a transition point or a quiet

    interlude between the two storms that shape

    Nietzsches thought. Franco argues that this middle

    period, although it gave Nietzsche the means to break

    with the overly romantic influence of Wagner and

    Schopenhauer on his thinking, also reveals a Nietzsche

    who is more restrained in his critique of the Enlight-

    enment and various Enlightenment thinkers. One thus

    sees a different Nietzsche to the one usually presented

    in much of the secondary literature of the past thirty

    years; one who offers a much more friendly critique of

    the use of reason in various Enlightenment thinkers

    than he does in either the earlier or later works.

    Francos examination of the middle period works

    shows a Nietzsche who preaches moderation and who

    sees the value of rationality instead of Dionysian

    Frenzy, and a philosopher whose philosophising is

    achieved through the will to power. Franco also

    argues that although the later works and their tone do

    break decisively with the moderation of the middle

    period, nonetheless key themes and concerns such as

    a commitment to reason and intellectual honesty

    remain in those later works as well. Francos work

    shows that the Nietzsche of the later period did not

    simply disregard all that was cultivated in the middle

    period, despite the radical break with regard to tone

    and style.

    Another important aspect of Francos book is its

    clear and relatively jargon-free style, which makes the

    reading experience enjoyable. Overall, this is a valuable

    addition to Nietzsche studies and will be a book that

    future scholars will be forced to address one way or

    another.

    Clifford Angell Bates Jr.(University of Warsaw)

    Rethinking Gramsci by Marcus E. Green (ed.).

    Abingdon: Routledge, 2013. 336pp., 28.00, ISBN

    978 0 415 82055 4

    The perspectives and interpretations of Antonio

    Gramsci in contemporary politics have become crucial

    to understanding the complex conjuncture of Interna-

    tional Relations over the decades. Under this lens,

    Rethinking Gramsci, which is a collection of 22 articlespreviously published in the journal Rethinking Marxism,edited by Marcus Green, provides a well-organised

    overview of Gramscis thought. Considering the com-

    plexity of Gramscis thought, this texts main goal is to

    investigate an interesting intersection between politics,

    economics and cultural processes analysed as being part

    of a continuum within the historical materialism of the

    past and the present (p. 7). This task is certainly

    accomplished.

    The book is organised into four sections that discuss

    the main approaches of Gramsci, from culture studies,

    hegemony and philosophy to translation problems of

    the Prison Notebooks. The first section is dedicated tothe main aspects of culture, literature and criticism

    according to Gramscis interpretation of those topics. It

    explores, for instance, Gramscis remarks on Dante,

    where Paul Bov analyses some reflections upon the

    problems of representation (p. 19), and Marcia Landy

    considers Gramscis work with regard to cultural and

    political approaches towards a socialist education in the

    modern day (p. 39).

    The second section presents several of Gramscis

    major political concepts and views, attempting to bring

    his theory into the contemporary world in several

    domains for instance, in South Asia, trade unions,

    feminism, political economy, ethics and capitalism.

    Regarding the concept of hegemony, Derek

    Boothman assesses its theoretical origins throughout

    the prison writings (p. 55).

    The third section advocates the co-relation between

    political philosophy and Marxism, presenting, among

    others, Carlos Coutinhos argument that Gramsci was

    in dialogue not only with Marx and Lenin, or

    Machiavelli (which is unequivocal), but also, if at times

    implicitly, with other great names of modern political

    philosophy Rousseau and Hegel in particular (p. 190).

    The final section explores the essential concerns

    regarding the translation and organisation of Joseph

    Buttigiegs English edition of Gramscis Prison Note-books. While on the one hand David Ruccio states thatthe Prison Notebooks represents for me ... the discoveryof a new Gramsci (p. 269), referring to the troubles of

    the English translation, Peter Ives chapter presents

    The Mammoth Task of Translating Gramsci. In a

    time where we can find a great deal of political and

    philosophical approaches, Rethinking Gramsci providesthe reader with distinctive approaches to interpreting

    Gramsci in several areas.

    Fernando J. Ludwig(University of Coimbra, Portugal)

    256 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Max Webers Comparative-Historical Sociology

    Today: Major Themes, Mode of Causal Analysis

    and Applications by Stephen Kalberg. Farnham:

    Ashgate, 2012. 338pp., 20.00, ISBN 978 1 4094

    3223 4

    The focus of this book is an attempt to re-evaluate

    Max Webers thought in light of the current interest in

    comparative-historical models of studying society.

    Stephen Kalbergs work reveals to the reader a Weber

    who is a much more complex and dynamic thinker.

    This is achieved by Kalbergs reconstruction of

    Webers thought from the various pieces of his work

    that were often incomplete and unfinished due to his

    premature death. It also reflects another current trend

    in Weber scholarship to overcome the understanding

    and view of Weber in English and the way his thought

    emerged from the translations and interpretation of his

    writings in the mid-twentieth century. This earlier

    presentation of Weber and his thought all too often

    ignored aspects in his writing, which reflected trends

    and concerns in German thinking at the beginning of

    the twentieth century and following on from the

    doubts that arose from the experience of the First

    World War. Over the past twenty years, Anglo-

    American scholars have started to re-evaluate Weber in

    light of their confrontation with the German scholar-

    ship on him that developed from the mid-1960s to

    1980s. Kalbergs volume arises in the middle of a series

    of new translation projects of Webers key works that

    have been started in the past fifteen years. The various

    themes that Kalberg presents in the pieces selected for

    this volume give us a fresh view of Weber and his

    thought.

    The essays in this volume are a collection of

    Kalbergs writings on Weber over the last thirty years,

    and consequently cohere rather well. Although this

    book is written more for those interested in sociology

    and social theory, it is also of interest to students of

    politics. I would suggest that Part III could be of great

    interest to students of comparative politics and espe-

    cially those interested in approaches to political culture.

    As for Part IV, this would very much interest students

    of political thought and the thought of Weber and its

    development. Kalbergs re-examination of Webers

    work on the role of religion (Jewish monotheism, the

    Hindu caste system and Confucianism in China) might

    also be of interest to students concerned with the

    impact religious actors have upon the structure of a

    society and its political culture. Overall, students of

    politics and political thought will find lots to mine

    from this volume, even if these contributions were

    directed more at students of sociology and social

    thought.

    Clifford Angell Bates Jr.(University of Warsaw)

    History of Political Theory: An Introduction,

    Volume I: Ancient and Medieval by George

    Klosko. Oxford: Oxford University Press, second

    edition, 2012. 373pp., 24.99, ISBN 978 0 19 969542 3

    History of Political Theory: An Introduction,

    Volume II: Modern by George Klosko. Oxford:

    Oxford University Press, second edition, 2013. 592pp.,

    24.99, ISBN 978 0 19 969545 4

    By now George Kloskos two-volume History of Politi-cal Theory is an established textbook that has proven tobe very useful both for students and teachers. There-

    fore, one should warmly welcome the fact that Oxford

    University Press has published a second, updated

    version.

    The first edition was published in 1994. Klosko has

    revised his magnum opus, taking into account hislongstanding experience of teaching undergraduate

    and graduate students and introducing them to the

    major authors and themes of the history of political

    thought. In doing so, he has rewritten several sections

    to clarify his presentation, replaced some older trans-

    lations with new ones, and updated the references and

    suggestions for further reading. The basic structure of

    the book, however, has been untouched. The core of

    it is reserved for detailed discussions of the political

    ideas of the great authors. So, in the first volume,

    Klosko narrates the history of Western political

    thought from its beginning in ancient Greece to the

    Middle Ages, culminating in the Reformation period.

    The major authors who receive lengthy treatments are

    Socrates, Plato, Aristotle, St Augustine, St Thomas

    Aquinas and Marsilius of Padua. There are also chap-

    ters on the origins, the Hellenistic period, the New

    Testament background and the Reformation period.

    In the second volume Klosko starts his exposition with

    Machiavelli and ends in the mid-nineteenth century

    with Marx. The other authors who figure prominently

    BOOK REVIEWS 257

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • in this volume are Hobbes, Locke, Hume,

    Montesquieu, Rousseau, Burke, Bentham, James and

    John Stuart Mill, and Hegel. The reason why Klosko

    has included these authors in his overview is for their

    continuing relevance (p. vii). What makes this text-

    book so useful is the large number of quotations from

    the primary texts. They give the reader the opportu-

    nity to delve directly into these authors political phi-

    losophy and become familiar with their concepts, ways

    of reasoning and political language.

    However praiseworthy and valuable Kloskos

    volumes may be, there are two points of criticism that

    should be noted. First, although it has been a deliberate

    choice to opt for depth rather than breadth (p. vii),

    the question remains why certain authors did not

    receive a (detailed) discussion. Just to give one

    example, why does Tacitus not figure in this textbook?

    His ideas have been very influential and have inspired

    dozens of authors during the Renaissance, while he

    might also have been an important key figure in the

    understanding of the transition from Machiavelli to

    Hobbes. On the other hand, one may question what

    has brought Klosko to devote two chapters to Plato

    (besides the fact that this Greek philosopher has

    attracted his attention for a long time and on whose

    political philosophy he has written several very valu-

    able contributions)?

    The second point of criticism concerns the title of

    this textbook with its reference to political theory

    (instead of political philosophy or political thought).

    The difference between these notions depends, as

    Klosko points out in a footnote, on the level of

    abstraction. Although it is true that he has paid careful

    attention to the context in which each of these phi-

    losophies took shape, it is also true that with his

    emphasis on depth rather than breadth as well as on

    continuing relevance he seems to have had a particular

    eye for a certain level of abstraction that has been

    appealing to other thinkers in the course of time.

    Therefore, doubts may be raised with regard to the

    choice of these volumes title. Part of these doubts

    could have been lifted by adding a section in which

    Klosko dwelled for a while on these matters. At the

    very least, it would have made clear his views on

    the use of these terms and what they implied for the

    narration of his overview. These are all, however,

    minor points of criticism, which in no way detract

    from the value this textbook has and will have for a

    new generation of students, teachers and others who

    are interested in the history of political theory.

    Erik De Bom(University of Leuven)

    Mill: A Guide for the Perplexed by Sujith

    Kumar. London: Bloomsbury, 2013. 179pp., 14.99,

    ISBN 978 1 84706 403 5

    This book is, as the author tells us, an introduction to

    the topics in J. S. Mills thought that are particularly

    challenging to access on their own (pp. 1112). As

    such, it is not an overview of Mills thought and is

    written in the context of the liberal-utilitarian debate

    that has been the focus of much scholarship on Mill.

    The book is a contribution to the revisionary school,

    which suggests Mills liberalism and utilitarianism are

    part of a coherent project of reform.

    Those with a philosophical background will be espe-

    cially interested in the second chapter that discusses

    Mills method and his views on character. These

    themes are developed by an analysis of Mills utilitari-

    anism, such as the role of associationism in sanctions

    that enforce utilitarian morality. This is followed by

    an examination of Mills Principle of Liberty which

    includes an assessment of applications of the Principle

    to the free market, indecency and the liberty of

    parents. Kumar then addresses Mills view of history,

    including his views on democracy, before returning to

    the liberal-utilitarian debate by assessing some of Isaiah

    Berlin and John Grays arguments. Although this book

    will be of primary benefit to students, Mill scholars

    will also gain from reading it.

    This is a well-written, accessible and engaging book,

    which succeeds in providing an introduction to some

    of the most important aspects of Mills thought as well

    as being a worthy contribution to the liberal-utilitarian

    debate. Kumar does not allow this debate to dominate

    all chapters, resulting in a larger number of topics

    being addressed than is often the case with such con-

    tributions. Although other important topics that have

    been the focus of much recent research, such as Mills

    international political thought, are not discussed, this is

    understandable given the aims and parameters of the

    book.

    Kumars references to other thinkers and groups

    who influenced Mill, such as Jeremy Bentham and

    Auguste Comte, and lesser known influences such as

    258 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Thomas Hare and Malthusian ideas, help us to under-

    stand the intellectual context in which Mill developed

    his ideas. Although there is overall a good balance

    between description and evaluation, further analysis

    on certain topics, such as the strength of Grays argu-

    ment concerning the fallacy of progress and the

    implications of this for Mills project, would have

    been beneficial given its potentially devastating con-

    sequences for Mill.

    Daniel Duggan(Durham University)

    Democratic Futures: Re-visioning Democracy

    Promotion by Milja Kurki. Abingdon: Routledge,

    2012. 296pp., 26.99, ISBN 978 0 415 69034 8

    The ubiquity of democracy promotion on Western

    policy agendas provides the context for Milja Kurkis

    timely and compelling new book. From Afghanistan

    and Iraq to Libya and Mali, military interventions are

    increasingly justified in terms of democracy promo-

    tion, restoration or support, rendering this one of

    the most powerful international policy dynamics in the

    post-Cold War era (p. 1). Democratic Futures aims togo behind the appearances of democracy support,

    problematising the models of democracy that underpin

    policy practice in a way the positivist literature, with its

    normatively pre-given concepts, cannot (p. 3).

    With an analytic terrain stretching from John Locke

    to the Occupy movement, Kurki situates democracy

    promotion policies within a continuum of Western

    democratic discourse, practice and contestation. A con-

    ceptual matrix of ideal-typical politico-economic

    visions of democracy, ranging from classical liberal

    and neoliberal to radical and global, informs

    empirical analyses of democracy promotion models in

    practice. Discourse analysis of the policies and practices

    of key international actors reveals that, despite impor-

    tant tensions, liberal democratic understandings of

    democracy still seem to dominate (p. 215). Crucially,

    it is argued that the triumphalist, explicit, big L

    Liberalism of the 1990s has been replaced by implicit

    (and often fuzzy or internally contested) liberalisms in

    democracy promotion discourse.

    Kurkis critical explanation for the dominance of

    implicit liberalism among democracy promoters draws

    productively upon Gramscis concept of hegemony

    and Foucaults concept of governmentality. In an

    important sense, the book provides a useful corollary to

    the end of ideology debates of the 1990s. If ideol-

    ogy disappeared from view with the Berlin Wall,

    perhaps it found clandestine refuge in democracy pro-

    motion discourses. It is therefore somewhat disap-

    pointing that Kurki largely eschews direct engagement

    with the concept of ideology here.

    A cardinal achievement of Democratic Futures is there-politicisation of democracy. While many have

    pointed to the essentially contested nature of the

    concept, there has seldom been so thoroughgoing an

    account of opposing (and overlapping) visions of

    democracy. Democratic Futures constitutes an innovativeand necessary intervention in the field of democracy

    promotion, denaturalising and re-politicising the terms

    of debate, and pointing to some interesting alternative

    directions. The book concludes with a series of policy

    provocations. A refreshing antidote to the insipid

    policy recommendations found at the end of many

    works of political science, this set of normative injunc-

    tions directed at key actors, from non-governmental

    organisations to international financial institutions, cul-

    minates in a general, and laudable, demand for a

    radical democratic pluralism.

    Ben Whitham(University of Reading)

    Bergson, Politics and Religion by Alexandre

    Lefebvre and Melanie White (eds). Durham, NC:

    Duke University Press, 2012. 338 pp., $17.99, ISBN

    978 0 8223 5275 4

    Tremendous tension is tearing consumer society apart.

    But any separation of societys intellectual and in-

    stinctual, or of individual-mechanistic and species-

    preservationist tendencies would be dreadful. Henri

    Bergson teaches that these dually opposed tendencies

    can neither be separated nor assimilated. They remain

    the two differing manifestations of one ascetic life-

    process (p. 293), for how species instinct coincides

    with individual intellect so should society cohere with

    its temporal freedoms. The fifteen essays in this bundle

    consider Bergsons assurances that such coherence

    exists and assurances may give confidence, Keck

    finds, which then befalls us in one simple action

    (p. 277).

    All essayists in this volume respond to the why-war-

    question, so finely posed throughout Bergsons The

    BOOK REVIEWS 259

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Two Sources of Morality and Religion, yet almost noneresponds to wars against biodiversity. Worms especially

    could have added that the great mystics made truce

    with extinction by taking pleasure in not wanting

    pleasure: in freedom from want. Janklvitch suggests

    that their mysteriously inexhaustible freedom might

    turn into a static ritual. Keck understands that the

    mystics were as free as they were bound by fear.

    [Their] intelligence frightens itself before it cohered

    with their actions (p. 276). Fujita compares this to

    Sorels myth of the general strike, which frightened

    before it would cohere with the free workshops (p.

    137). Not an image of awful force, but the force of an

    awe-inspiring image (the strike) now becomes fre-

    edoms foundation.

    Free and democratic societies cannot be founded

    undemocratically, although they are. Societal inclusion

    and forceful exclusion cannot coexist, although they

    do. Ochoa-Espejo dissolves this paradox of democratic

    foundation in her wonderful interpretation. Inclusive

    and exclusive tendencies are the mutually opposing and

    yet also qualitatively different dimensions of one

    image, of the people. Ochoa-Espejo never speaks of

    the myth/mystery of the democratic people and this

    appears regrettable because, as concept, mystery

    conveys more Bergsonism than paradox. Bergson

    attended a few sances and might even have known

    the 1914 Christmas truce a mysterious event that

    could complement Barnards reading of him as a para-

    psychologist well. Soulez instead reads Bergson as the

    first to have called for a decision on the species, and

    thus sounds much more urgent than either Barnard or

    Ochoa-Espejo (p. 110). Still, these essayists are all very

    earnest about us risking a separation between intellec-

    tual and instinctual tendencies. Their work will be

    warmly welcomed by students of early twentieth-

    century polemological, political psychological and

    perhaps political ecological action as well.

    Paul Timmermans(Portland State University)

    Foucault, Governmentality and Critique by

    Thomas Lemke. Boulder, CO: Paradigm, 2012.

    131pp., 19.99, ISBN 978 159451 638 2

    Michel Foucault has been one of the most significant

    influences on critical and interpretive social science in

    Britain over the last two decades. Yet his influence

    during this time has not been static. Since 2003, the

    steady trickle of translations into English of his 197884

    lectures at the Collge de France has allowed Foucaults

    mature reflections about governmentality, neoliberalism

    and security to provide new conceptual tools for

    empirical research. In this concise yet rich introduction,

    Thomas Lemke presents this new Foucault to an unfa-

    miliar audience. Here, Foucault is no longer the theorist

    of discourse, discipline and sexuality who was known in

    the 1980s and early 1990s, but founder of the field of

    Governmentality Studies. No undergraduate guide, this

    tightly argued and scholarly discussion explains how

    governmentality not only refines Foucaults earlier,

    influential theory of power, but also re-engages with

    the study of the state and other phenomena of central

    concern to political science.

    Lemkes first chapter deftly sketches Foucaults cri-

    tique of concepts of repressive sovereign power and

    explains his alternative model of power as structural,

    relational and productive. While most introductory

    accounts might stop there, Lemke argues that, in such

    works as Discipline and Punish, this model confined Fou-caults attention to the micropolitics of singular institu-

    tions and eschewed any consideration of more complex

    and more heterogeneous structures of power. Lemke

    explains that Foucaults lectures on governmentality

    transcend these limitations and offer the means to

    study the broader processes of state formation and

    subjectification that Foucault is sometimes accused of

    overlooking.

    The second chapter explains how governmentality

    can usefully inform study of the genealogy and histori-

    cal ontology of the state, with an instructive aside on

    the distinction between governmentality and govern-

    ance. Chapter 3 redefines biopolitics in the context of

    security and neoliberalism, while Chapter 4 touches on

    the ethical imperatives of critique. The final chapter

    introduces contemporary Governmentality Studies,

    which, inspired yet not confined by Foucaults prelimi-

    nary remarks in the lectures, has been applied to sub-

    jects as diverse as the welfare state, economic regulation

    and counter-terrorism. While highlighting common

    blind spots (teleology, historicism, Eurocentrism),

    Lemkes concern for concision unfortunately precludes

    detailed consideration of the rich interdisciplinary

    scholarship on governmentality in colonial and post-

    colonial contexts, which directly addresses many of

    these difficulties.

    260 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Political scientists whose last contact with Foucault

    occurred in the 1990s would be well advised to

    re-acquaint themselves with the re-born Foucault

    through Lemkes masterful introduction. Foucault is

    dead; long live Foucault!

    Daniel Neep(Georgetown University)

    The Bloomsbury Companion to Hobbes by S. A.

    Lloyd (ed.). London: Bloomsbury, 2013. 334pp.,

    100.00, ISBN 978 1 4411 9045 1

    The Bloomsbury Companion to Hobbes aims to provide anaccessible guide to the major themes and ideas of

    Hobbesian thought (p. x). Sharon Lloyd keeps the

    remainder of her editorial introduction brief. The Com-panion is divided into seven thematic chapters, rangingfrom Hobbes life and times through different aspects of

    his philosophy, finishing with enduring debates and

    remaining questions. Each chapter contains entries on

    many of Hobbes most important ideas, and each entry

    can be read independently of the others. The entries are

    authored by a range of different scholars; some are

    responsible for all or most of a single chapter, while

    others contribute just one or two entries.

    In general, the entries are informative and reliable,

    providing a solid reference point for both students and

    scholars of Hobbes alike. However, there are notable

    exceptions and those relatively unfamiliar with Hobbes

    should treat the Companion with caution. For example,after having read the very short entry on duty and

    obligation (pp. 1245), a newcomer to Hobbes could

    remain completely unaware that there has ever been

    any controversy concerning the nature of obligation in

    his philosophy. That the further reading points to

    nothing more than three chapters from Leviathan andone section of De Corpore is unlikely to remedy this.By contrast, other articles are far more thorough and

    are accompanied by extensive and helpful guides to the

    secondary literature.

    This reflects a more general problem concerning

    the balance and consistency of the Companion. Someentries are simply reference points, providing an over-

    view of Hobbes ideas on the topic, while others adopt

    a more critical and evaluative approach. For example,

    in a concise entry on instrumental reasoning we learn

    that Hobbes goal of a fully deductive science of poli-

    tics was bound to fail (p. 76). Of more concern is the

    extent to which different entries vary in length, some-

    times with seemingly no correspondence to their rela-

    tive importance. In the chapter on Hobbes method

    we thus find more space dedicated solely to game

    theoretic interpretations than to the following four

    entries on geometry, logic, materialism and motion

    combined. Some stylistic differences are unavoidable

    given that the entries are authored by different schol-

    ars, but at times there seems to be a lack of common

    purpose regarding the desired contribution of the

    entries. Nonetheless, the Companion does address acomprehensive range of topics and could prove a

    useful, albeit somewhat flawed, reference point for

    anyone studying Hobbes.

    Robin Douglass(Kings College, London)

    Shaping the Normative Landscape by David

    Owens. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.

    260pp., 30.00, ISBN 978 0 19 969 150 0

    In David Owens interesting and challenging new

    book, he aims to explore how human beings create

    norms for themselves and how they shape those norms.

    Human beings, he says, have a need to mould our

    normative niche (p. 172). The types of cases used to

    support his argument include friendships, promises and

    consent to sexual contact. The interesting departure in

    his project is that he makes little effort to attempt to

    ground these normative obligations in the typical

    framework of morality (autonomy, moral reason,

    equality, rights), but instead tries to build the frame-

    work of the normative landscape from the ground up,

    in a constructivist fashion, although Owens himself

    never refers to his own view as constructivist in the

    typical, meta-ethical sense.

    Owens primary targets are those, like David Hume

    and T. M. Scanlon, who hold the view he calls

    Rationalism about Obligation the belief that you

    are bound to perform your obligations only in the

    sense that they serve some interest (p. 124). The

    primary counter-example to this view, according to

    Owens, is cases of bare wrongings, where a violation

    (usually of a promise) constitutes no harm or action

    against a human interest (p. 15). A broken promise, for

    instance, not to photograph someone while they sleep

    could be a bare wronging even if the promisee neverlearns of the existence of said photo, and even if the

    BOOK REVIEWS 261

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • photo is never developed or downloaded anywhere.

    These bare wrongings are harms despite the fact that

    Rationalism can make no sense of them being harmful

    without someones interest being affected by them. In

    Owens view, much of the social function of activities

    like promising and the value of friendship is deter-

    mined by our need to shape the world we live in to fit

    our (non-Rationalistic) phenomenology of intentional

    agency. Crucial concepts in moral psychology and

    moral agency like consent, forgiveness and obliga-

    tion are examined in varying degrees of detail

    although, at times, some views are more skeletal than

    others. The discussion of sexual consent and rape in

    Chapter 7, for example, lays out only the barest of

    theories about the nature of what consent to sex

    might really be. This is a mere quibble, however. This

    is an original and challenging attempt to ground the

    nature of normativity, placed in the welcome contexts

    of (as Scanlon would say) what we owe to each other.

    Eric M. Rovie(Georgia Perimeter College, Atlanta)

    Reading Hayek in the 21st Century: A Critical

    Inquiry Into His Political Thought by Theo

    Papaioannou. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2012.

    221pp., 57.50, ISBN 978 0 230 30162 7

    Friedrich von Hayek has been recognised as one of the

    greatest economists of the twentieth century. This

    book is written with the explicit aim of proving his

    theory inadequate for the problems of the twenty-first

    century. The author claims that not only does Hayeks

    theory offer no remedy to the current global economic

    crises, but it is their cause (p. 193). Yet interestingly,

    this book is not about contemporary politics or eco-

    nomic theory. Rather, Theo Papaioannous goal is to

    provide an immanent critique of the moral dimension

    of Hayeks political theory and its epistemological and

    methodological foundations (p. 2). In a long and

    complex intellectual excursus which demonstrates

    the authors wide-ranging philosophical knowledge

    and demands no less dexterity from the reader the

    internal paradox of Hayeks political theory is revealed.

    The book explores the development of the founda-

    tions of Hayeks economic theory: biological sponta-

    neity, anti-rational epistemology and the order of

    catallaxy the concept of social spontaneity and cul-

    tural evolution that sets the term of his moral and

    political thought (p. 131). Papaioannous main claim is

    that there is a fundamental problem with Hayeks

    catallaxy: although the spontaneous order does not

    morally justify substantive politics, it requires powerful

    political institutions to be preserved in terms of liber-

    alism. The biologically inspired system of spontaneous

    social order is not per se a guarantee against anti-socialbehaviour, totalitarianism and strife (p. 144).

    The book is well-written, albeit at times the sub-

    stance is obfuscated by repetitions or excessive use of

    jargon. Clearly, the author takes very seriously his com-

    mitment to purge Hayek from contemporary economic

    thought, and he makes a strong point about the internal

    incoherence in Hayeks thought. Yet at times it seems

    the authors own political goal to prove that Hayek

    cannot be reconciled with political liberalism cuts

    short the intellectual breadth of his otherwise worthy

    book.

    Or Rosenboim( University of Cambridge)

    The Cambridge Companion to Oakeshott by

    Efraim Podoksik (ed.). Cambridge: Cambridge

    University Press, 2011. 386pp., 19.99, ISBN 978 0

    521 14792 7

    Following publication of a similar work by Penn State

    Press, Cambridge University Press (CUP) has pub-

    lished a companion of considerable quality on the

    British philosopher Michael Oakeshott. Having

    reviewed the first volume with reference to the second

    in the previous issue of PSR, I now briefly review thesecond, with reference to the first.1

    Edited by Efraim Podoksik, CUPs volume focuses

    on Oakeshotts philosophical work, leaving his life

    largely out of the picture. Biographical information is

    provided only through a brief chronology of short

    notes. In lieu of shedding light on his thought by

    considering the philosophers extra-academic activity,

    substantial space is reserved in the book for contextual

    analyses of Oakeshotts interventions in historical dis-

    courses. Thus, one part (Part III) of CUPs Companion isdedicated to comparative perspectives on Oakeshott

    and others. Otherwise, the organisation of the book

    very much parallels Franco and Marshs volume in that

    first articles are collected on Oakeshotts understanding

    of philosophy, history, science, aesthetics and education

    (Part I), and second on his political philosophy (Part II).

    262 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • Whereas Franco and Marsh include pieces of scholar-

    ship that will be of greater interest for advanced scholars,

    the strength of CUPs Companion is its clear conspectus ofOakeshotts philosophy. Unfortunately, the editor pro-

    vides little guidance to the reader in his introduction,

    which will be regretted by students unfamiliar with the

    content and significance of Oakeshotts thought.

    Podoksik affirms that the book has a plan and direction

    (p. 3) without explaining exactly what this plan and

    direction are supposed to be. Thus, the organisation of

    the book in particular, the fact that the articles dealing

    with the intellectual influences on Oakeshott are placed

    at the end will not strike everyone as self-explanatory.

    Also, one may have wished to know more about why the

    editor and some contributors hold Oakeshotts philoso-

    phy in particularly high esteem, while others are abra-

    sively critical. In the essay meant to provide a general

    overview of Oakeshotts political theory (p. 5), for

    instance, William A. Galston concludes that Oakeshott

    ultimately cross[ed] the line separating philosophical

    radicalism from outright implausibility (p. 242). In the

    face of such dissenting voices, the editor only recalls the

    truism that the recognition of the value of a philosophy

    is a matter of subjective judgement (p. 1), which is

    unsatisfying if only because it tends to imply that readers

    sympathetic to Oakeshott need not take seriously the

    objections raised by critics.

    However, despite the deficits of the introduction,

    Podoksik has certainly done a good job with assem-

    bling the contributions to CUPs Companion. It servesas a very good starting point for familiarising oneself

    with Oakeshotts thought. By portraying Oakeshott as

    a particularly controversial thinker, it is also likely to

    motivate further research.

    Note1 Franco, P. and Marsh, L. (eds) (2012) A Companion to

    Michael Oakeshott. University Park, PA: Pennsylvania StateUniversity Press. For the mentioned review, see PSR(2014) 12 (1), 967.

    Martin Beckstein(University of Zurich)

    On Global Justice by Mathias Risse. Princeton, NJ:

    Princeton University Press, 2012. 480pp., 27.95,

    ISBN 978 0691142692

    As Mathias Risse explains in the opening chapter of

    On Global Justice, traditionally, debates over justice in

    political philosophy have been concerned with

    domestic justice: justice within states. However, inrecent decades, due to globalisation, the issue of

    justice between states has become increasingly salient.This is the area of global justice. Discussion in this

    area has been framed by two different approaches:

    statist and cosmopolitan. For statists, the relevant

    grounds of justice are relational: membership withinstates. For cosmopolitans, on the other hand, states are

    viewed as morally arbitrary and, as such, the relevant

    grounds of justice are non-relational: our common

    humanity.

    In this book Risse develops an intermediate

    approach to global justice, which he terms pluralistinternationalism. This novel approach generates differ-ent principles of justice for each of the various

    grounds. At the domestic level, Risse employs a

    Rawlsian approach to justice. At the global level,

    however, he recognises non-relational grounds of

    justice that must also work alongside domestic princi-

    ples of justice. In short, pluralist internationalism rec-

    ognises the normative peculiarity of states, while, at

    the same time, recognising various other grounds of

    justice such as our common humanity and collective

    ownership of the earth. Building on the work of the

    seventeenth-century philosopher Hugo Grotius, Risse

    develops a secularised account of our common own-

    ership of the earth. As a relevant ground of justice,common ownership implies that each person, through

    having common ownership of the earth, has a right to

    satisfy their basic needs independently of the accom-

    plishments of others. Common ownership has impli-

    cations for immigration, intergenerational justice and

    climate change, and entails a minimally demanding set

    of rights. The grounds of justice approach also hasimplications for global trade, intellectual property

    rights and labour rights.

    This book will appeal to those engaged in normative

    theorising about justice at the global level. It displays a

    scholarly rigour and philosophical depth that renders

    much of the existing literature in this area obsolete. As

    a unique approach to global justice, it helps us under-

    stand the way in which justice applies in nuanced ways

    depending on the particular context we are examining.

    Risses attempted rapprochement between statists andcosmopolitans is persuasive and should provide a para-

    digm shift for many working in the area of interna-

    tional justice. I have no doubt that this book will come

    BOOK REVIEWS 263

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • to play a central role in normative theorising about

    global justice for some time to come.

    Daniel Savery(National University of Ireland, Galway)

    Perpetual War: Cosmopolitanism from the

    Viewpoint of Violence by Bruce Robbins.

    Durham, NC: Duke University Press, 2012. 247pp.,

    15.99, ISBN 978 0 8223 5209 9

    When you purchase a shirt in Wal-Mart, wonders

    Bruce Robbins in Perpetual War, do you ever imagineyoung women in Bangladesh forced to work from 7:30

    a.m. to 8 p.m., seven days a week, paid just 9 cents to

    20 cents an hour? (p. 97). At the root of the intellectual

    exercise in which Robbins invites his readers to indulge

    lies a profound disenchantment with the old elitist

    formulations of cosmopolitan thought, informed by

    existential detachment from the core practices of

    national belonging and normative impulses ingrained

    with patriotic fervour, and an embrace of more

    immediate, everyday (p. 34) and, therefore, more cen-

    sorious new modes of being in the world rife with

    economic injustices and exploitation, pathologies of

    global inequality, cultural and religious intolerance, mili-

    tarism and asymmetries of power, and the unredeemable

    ghosts of imperial zeal all of which are searchingly

    appraised in the books eight incisive chapters.

    In the face of gratuitous acts of violence, the author

    argues, cosmopolitanism can no longer afford to remain

    disaffected and narcissistically self-absorbed with its

    highly individualised emotional philanthropy toward

    abstract notions of humanity. Its bland, pious, or pow-

    erless (p. 30) propensities, Robbins contends, must be

    abandoned in the name of probing critiques of nation-

    alism, interventionism and the socio-economic conse-

    quences of unrestrained capitalism. Cosmopolitanism

    must seek to become a moral equivalent of war (p. 30)

    that is audaciously committed to the defence of human

    dignity, humanitarian principles and translocal justice.

    The key challenge of the book for the author is to

    articulate a viable global ethic, able to express an inter-

    national sense of right and wrong that is powerful

    enough to have an enduring grip on our hearts (p. 36).

    Scholars of cosmopolitan thought who expect

    Robbins to furnish a nuanced expos of juridical reper-

    cussions of war from a cosmopolitan point of view will

    be disappointed. For one thing, the books title is, at

    face value, misleading. Robbins thematically discon-

    nected chapters survey instead contributions of the

    mainstream academic left (Noam Chomsky, Edward

    Said and Slavoj iek, among others) to a conception

    of cosmopolitanism qua exile, secularism and anti-imperialism in order to elucidate its often paradoxical

    nature and alert the reader to the cosmopolitan duty of

    waging perpetual war with the lingering echoes of

    national self-righteousness. The author falls short,

    however, of imbuing the peculiarities of cosmopolitan

    normativity with the overpromised and under-delivered

    weighty, positive, and socially grounded (p. 34) ori-

    entation. Nevertheless, a forgiving and open-minded

    audience will appreciate the determination with which

    Robbins dissects the vicissitudes of political action in

    the world of profound socio-cultural complexities and

    ever-shifting allegiances.

    Joanna Rozpedowski(University of South Florida, Tampa)

    Hegels Rabble: An Investigation into Hegels

    Philosophy of Right by Frank Ruda. London:

    Continuum, 2011. 218pp., 21.99, ISBN 978 1 4725

    1016 7

    Frank Ruda is not the first to take an interest in what

    Hegel has to say about the existence of the rabble in

    the Philosophy of Right. Others have seen in this accountevidence of Hegels sociological sensibility about the

    underside of an emergent market economy and have

    borne witness to the great thinkers uncertainty about

    what if anything can be done about the challenge

    this creates. This book takes Hegels remarks on the

    rabble and spins out from them a critique of the entire

    structure of the mature Hegels politics. In his recogni-

    tion of the existence and the attitude of the rabble,

    Hegel reveals an entity that his account of civil society

    (and family and state) cannot comprehend. The rabble

    is not just another name for the poor. In fact, Hegel

    speaks of both a poor rabble and a rich rabble, with

    the latter characterised above all by the figure of the

    gambler the one who has taken a punt in the lottery

    of the market and won. Both rich and poor are

    excluded (or exclude themselves) from the life (and

    norms) of civil society. Upon Rudas account, the poor

    rabble (the only authentically radical rabble) rebels

    against the morality of civil society and its rights. It is

    indignant and, in some sense Hegel feels, it is right to

    264 POLITICAL THEORY

    2014 The Authors. Political Studies Review 2014 Political Studies AssociationPolitical Studies Review: 2014, 12(2)

  • be indignant. It is required to share the norms of a civil

    society from which it is systematically excluded. It

    demands subsistence from society because it cannot playby the rules. In the book, Ruda tracks the various ways

    in which Hegel tries (and fails) to resolve this challenge

    from within the framework of his philosophy of right.

    But, in the end, it is a problem he cannot solve. It is only

    really resolved when, in the work of Marx, rabble

    morphs into proletariat.

    Hegels Rabble is not an easy read. In a dense argu-ment, paradox piles upon paradox in an accumulation

    of un-everything (the un-estate, the un-organ, theun-right and so on). And the difficulty of the text isnot made any easier by some infelicitous translation

    and some careless proofreading. Noneth