05--Matthewman

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

ANT and Foucault

Citation preview

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    1/19

    Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology ISSN: 1091-8264

    17:2 (Spring 2014): 274292 DOI: 10.5840/techne201311205

    Michel Foucault, Technology,

    and Actor-Network Theory

    Steve MatthewmanUniversity of Auckland, New Zealand

    Abstract:While Michel Foucaults significance as a social theorist is undisputed, his

    importance as a technological theorist is frequently overlooked. This article considers

    the richness and the range of Foucaults technological thinking by surveying his works

    and interviews, and by tracking his influence within Actor-Network Theory (ANT).

    The argument is made that we will not fully understand Foucault without understand-

    ing the central place of technology in his work, and that we will not understand ANT

    without understanding Foucault.

    Key words:actor-network theory; Foucault; technology; technique

    Introducon

    Michel Foucault is regarded as an important social theorist, yet rarely is he in-

    terpreted as an important technological theorist. Discussions of discipline and

    docility, for instance, tend to be abstracted from the very technologies that affordthem. As this article demonstrates, these are failures of exegesis, not emphasis, for

    the analyses of Foucault are intimately tied to technological artefacts, techniques,

    technical knowledges and forms of organization. Similar claims have already

    been made within this journals pages (Gerrie 2003). Jim Gerries article offered

    a reading of Foucault as a philosopher of technology. It considered connections

    between Foucault, Marshall McLuhan and Harold Innis. The present article draws

    on works that were then unavailable in English to examine Foucaults influence on

    one of the dominant paradigms in Science and Technology Studies (STS): Actor-Network Theory (ANT). Here the argument is made that we cannot understand

    ANT without understanding Foucault, although the broader argument is that we

    cannot fully understand Foucault without understanding the role of technology in

    his work. In order to make a case for Foucaults significance as a technological

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    2/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 275

    thinker we commence by looking at the deployment of technological terms in hiswork, his thoughts on technological innovation and his broadening of the concep-

    tual horizons of the technological to include the non-material realm.

    Foucaults Technological Terminology

    Surveys of Foucaults work show that most of his major concepts are couched in

    technological terms. In The Birth of the Clinic(2003a: 89) the medical gazethe

    eye that knows and decides, the eye that governsis discussed as the conflation

    of political ideology and medical technology, and knowledge and perception arepositioned as technological structures (2003a: 38, 48). Similarly, the hospital is

    interpreted as a therapeutic instrument in his lecture entitled The Incorporation

    of the Hospital in Modern Technology (Foucault 2007: 141). InDiscipline and

    Punish, Foucault (1979: 27, 215, 205, 257, 294) conceives of discipline, panopti-

    cism and power as technologies, imprisonment and the transformation of man

    as a technical project, and the judges of normality as technicians of behaviour.

    What is Enlightenment? discusses the rationalities that inform human action,

    what people do and how they do it, as the technological aspect of their exis-tence (Foucault 1984: 46). In Society Must Be Defended Foucault suggests that

    discipline is a micropolitical technology of the body based on drill and aimed at

    the individual, and biopower is a macropolitical technology of security whose

    target is the entire population. Biopower, then, is a regulatory technology of life

    (Foucault 2003b: 249). Volume one of The History of Sexuality (1990: 44, 90, 105)

    positions health and pathology, the regulation of sex and sexuality and processes

    of normalisation and correction as technologies. Governmentality is defined as

    contact between the technologies of domination of others and those of the self(Foucault 1988: 18). Security, Territory, Population sees government, police

    and security similarly interpreted as technologies (Foucault 2009: 8, 370, 382).

    The modern states art of governmentthe technology of state forcesfinds

    legitimacy through two great technological assemblages, the diplomatic-military

    system and the police (Foucault 2009: 296). In Technologies of the Self, Foucault

    (1988: 154) tells us that technologies like government manifest in three major

    forms: as utopian impulse, institutional practice and academic discipline. Indeed,

    even when he is not employing the t word, Jim Gerrie (2003) tells us that Fou-caults works are crammed with technological terms and metaphors, The Order of

    Things being a case in point.

    We might ask ourselves what work technology is doing in Foucaults writ-

    ings. Technology is a notoriously elastic category that can be made to stretch to

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    3/19

    276 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    the point of meaninglessness. To counter this, the STS literature defines it in fourways: as objects, activities, knowledge and modes of organisation (MacKenzie

    and Wajcman 1985: 3; Winner 1977: 12). Our discussion of Foucault will cover

    technology in all of these senses: as objects (in relation to stethoscopes and rifles),

    activities (such as disciplinary techniques and other exercises of power), knowl-

    edge (particularly medical and penological) and modes of organisation (hospitals

    and prisons). It will place particular emphasis, as Foucault does, on technology as

    activities, the techniques and practices through which ends are realised, for an on-

    going preoccupation of his was the manner in which subjects are transformed intoobjects of knowledge within organisational matrixes. Such is the message of The

    Birth of the Clinic, The Order of Things and The Archaeology of Knowledge.Dis-

    cipline and Punish and volume one of The History of Sexuality study the technolo-

    gies through which human beings are made subjects, while volumes one and two

    of The History of Sexuality consider the technologies through which human beings

    act upon themselves. Ultimately this is where Foucaults interests lay, not with his-

    tories of things, but of the terms, categories, and techniques through which certain

    things become at certain times the focus of a whole configuration of discussionand procedure. One might say he offers an historical answer to the philosophical

    question as to how such things are constituted (Rajchman 1984: 8).

    Having defined technology we now need to say what it actually does. Fou-

    cault (1988: 18) provides an answer. There are four types of technology, each with

    their own specific functions. They are used by people to comprehend and control

    themselves and others. All involve the training and manipulation of individuals,

    the generation of particular attitudes and competencies. He tells us that the first

    three types were identified by Jrgen Habermas: technologies of production con-cerned with the creation, conversion and control of things; technologies of sign

    systems devoted to symbolic communication; and technologies of power which

    dominate, objectify and ultimately determine individual behaviour. To these Fou-

    cault adds a fourth: technologies of the self, which permit individuals to effect by

    their own means or with the help of others a certain number of operations on their

    own bodies and souls, thought, conduct, and a way of being, so as to transform

    themselves in order to attain a certain state of happiness, purity, wisdom, perfec-

    tion, or immortality.Foucault (1988: 19) said that most of his work stressed technologies of

    power, but technologies of the self are a necessary complement if one is to com-

    prehend the development of the Western subject. For Foucault (1997b: 88), it is

    not possible to do a history of subjectivity without reckoning with technology,

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    4/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 277

    since this project involves histories of care and techniques of the self. In his latercareer Foucault became interested in those ways in which individuals act upon,

    and sometimes even dominate, themselves. This has led to standard interpretations

    of his work that reinforce the notion that he had an early archaeological period,

    a middle genealogical period and a later period detailing the history of subjec-

    tivity, involving a broad shift in focus from control to liberation (for example,

    see Han 2002). However, the posthumously published lectures at the Collge de

    France show a preoccupation with another controlling technology: that of security

    (Foucault 2008). Technologies of security are distinguished from technologies ofpower by their focus, which is the population not the individual, by its aims, which

    are risk-prevention rather than economic productivity or political compliance, by

    its location, which is at the level of the state (for example in demographic data)

    rather than within specific institutions like prisons, and by its techniques, which

    are regulation-based rather than disciplinary. Irrespective of the emphasis we can

    say that Foucault was always concerned with subjectivity and subjection under-

    stood through the optic of technology.

    Thus far we have built a weak case for Foucault to be considered a theoristof technology of any real import. This will be strengthened by considering his

    thoughts on technological innovation, technologies of domination, techniques and

    his profound influence upon ANT.

    Foucault on Technological Innovaon

    The claim for Foucault to be interpreted as a technological theorist has been based

    on a reading of his works and the self-assessment of his oeuvre; technology ap-

    pears as the conceptual and intellectual framework for his labours. In this sectionwe concretize Foucaults thoughts on the role of technology by considering his

    writing on technological innovation. This gives us the opportunity to see the ways

    in which technologies (understood as physical objects) transform interpersonal

    relations in the case of the stethoscope, and institutional relations in the case of

    the rifle. The former technical object can be interpreted as a technology of produc-

    tion. As a new diagnostic technology the stethoscope allowed for the creation of

    new medical knowledge (helping to transform medicine from a theoretical to a

    practical science). It also converted a potentially embarrassing situation into aprofessional medical encounter. The latter technical object, the rifle, is the driver

    for changes in the function and staffing of the technological mode of organisation

    that is the hospital. The hospital can be interpreted as a technology of power: here

    deviants from the norm of good health are categorized and corrected.

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    5/19

    278 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    When technological theorists explain the point of technology they routinelyfall back on the explanation of mediation (Verbeek 2005: 114). Technologies me-

    diate between the physical world and culture, between matter and meaning. This

    meshes with the notion of technologies as agents. We use technology to act on

    and in the world, and technologies reciprocate. In other words, we should not

    think of technologies as neutral intermediaries interposed between humans and

    the physical world, but as fully-blown mediators affecting what it is to be human

    in the world. Such a take on technology is typical of Foucault, as Gerrie (2003)

    notes: technology is not simply an ethically neutral set of artefacts by which weexercise power over nature, but also a set of structured action by which we also

    inevitably exercise power over ourselves. Bruno Latour (1999) argues that tech-

    nologies permit mediation in several senses. We will discuss three of relevance to

    the stethoscope. First, technologies create new programmes of action, new pos-

    sibilities. Second, they provide for new distributed practices, new compositions,

    and new associations. Third, technologies delegate. They do the work that humans

    would otherwise have to do.

    In The Birth of the Clinic, Foucault interprets the humble stethoscope as atonce a scientific, social, and ethical device. Manners and modesty forbade male

    doctors placing their ears to the chests of female patients. Moral screening was

    necessary. This came about via technical mediation. The stethoscope created per-

    sonal distance between doctor and patient. Significantly, it simultaneously per-

    mitted unprecedented intimacy. The stethoscope solidified distance, Foucault

    observed.

    [It] transmits profound and invisible events along a semi-tactile, semi-audi-

    tory axis. Instrumental mediation outside the body authorizes a withdrawalthat measures the moral distance involved; the prohibition of physical con-

    tact makes it possible to fix the virtual image of what is occurring below the

    visible area. For the hidden, the distance of shame is a projection screen.

    What one cannotsee is shown in the distance from what one must notsee.

    (Foucault 2003a: 164)

    Part of the medical gaze, the stethoscope augmented the diagnostic senses as one

    of a series of instruments and techniques that made the silent audible, the undetect-

    able discernable. The stethoscope tied setting (clinic) to procedure (mediate aus-

    cultation). Jonathan Sterne (2001: 116) suggests thinking about it as an artefact

    of technique, after all [i]t was designed to operate within the parameters of a set

    of social relationships, he writes, and it helped to cement and formalize those

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    6/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 279

    relations: the doctor-patient relationship, the structure of clinical research andpedagogy, and the industrialization, rationalization and standardization of medi-

    cine (along with the improvement of physicians social status). Alan Bleakley and

    John Bligh (2009: 371) come to a similar conclusion; such artefacts of technique

    were set within a wider architecture that was literal and cognitive: a discrete

    physical organization around treating patients that is the clinic (also the teaching

    hospital) and a structured way of thinking (in different ways for both doctors and

    patients) that is the clinical examination.

    Physical technologies could also be the drivers for institutional change. Fou-cault makes what at first seems to be a highly unlikely claim: that the modern

    hospital owes its existence to the rifle. A key institution comes about in the form

    that we recognize it because of the technological transformation of European

    armies. Widespread uptake of rifles increased the training costs of military force.

    State budgeting increased accordingly. Long considered liable to be on the front

    line of disease, national governments looked to protect their fighting investments.

    Hospitals took on a new role. No longer a terminus for the poor the hospital be-

    came a place attempting a cure. Shirking, much less desertion should be denied.This necessitated new systems of surveillance and management. Experts required

    medical knowledge of both how to cure and when a patient was cured. A political

    technology of discipline developed in which doctors replaced priests as experts

    and administrators (Foucault 2007: 141). As an example of technological theoris-

    ing, this piece seems to fall short of Foucaults usual scholarly standard. Indeed,

    the idea that a single artefact on its own could transform an entire mode of organ-

    isation smacks of technological determinism. Ordinarily Foucault would position

    such technologies as part of a dispositif (see the Foucault/ANT section) includingknowledge, institutional discourses, professional practices and architectural struc-

    tures. A rather different reading of the development of hospital and modern medi-

    cine is to be found in other works by Foucault (2003a, 1994a). Elsewhere Foucault

    does write of the connections between technological invention and institutional

    change. InDiscipline and Punish, he argues that new weaponry precipitated new

    disciplinary arrangements, just as industrial inventions led to new regimes of order

    in the economic realm (Foucault 1979: 138).

    Foucault, then, was attuned to instrumental change in the most literal way.New devices could contribute to new practices, new observations, new organisa-

    tions and new knowledge, so too could new architectural forms. As with stetho-

    scopes, buildings could similarly act as scientific, social and even ethical devices.

    While palaces were built to be seen, and fortresses were built to see out, the

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    7/19

    280 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    panopticon prison was built to see in. Prisoners were arranged so as to be underconstant surveillance, and they behaved accordingly. He who is subjected to a

    field of visibility, and who knows it, assumes responsibility for the constraints of

    power; he makes them play spontaneously upon himself; he inscribes in himself

    the power relation in which he simultaneously plays both roles; he becomes the

    principle of his own subjection (Foucault 1979: 20203). Control was embedded

    in design. The material structure acted on the prisoners prompting Foucault (1979:

    172) to state: Stones can make people docile and knowable. The fundamental

    point stressed by Foucault is the intimate connection of technology, understoodin its broad sense as objects, activities, knowledge and modes of organisation, to

    power.

    Panopcism: A Technical Soluon to a Technical Problem

    InDiscipline and Punish, Foucault offers an extended analysis of a new technol-

    ogy of power made famous through the principle of panopticism. He identifies

    this as a technical mutation in power relations commencing at the onset of the

    nineteenth century (Foucault 1979: 257). The mutation concerns transformationsin social control from public punishment of the body to private punishment of the

    mind and soul. Prisons became the new penalty for transgression. Direct physi-

    cal force diminished. Training replaced torture. Instead, a regimen of rules and

    regulations covering every facet of existence, the development of detailed records,

    individual dossiers, new classificatory systems and timetables dictating activities

    to be undertaken. All conduct was to be underpinned by constant supervision.

    In the executioners place a whole army of technicians (Foucault 1979: 11):

    bureaucrats, chaplains, doctors, psychiatrists and warders. This new form of socialcontrol was defined by the twin processes of carceralization and medicalization.

    In his lecture on The Punitive Society, Foucault accounts for these trans-

    formations thus:

    What brought the great renewal of the epoch into play was a problem of

    bodies and materiality, a question of physics: a new form of materiality

    taken by the productive apparatus, a new type of contact between that appa-

    ratus and the individual who makes it function; new requirements imposed

    on individuals as productive forces. (Foucault 1997a: 34)

    This new physics of power developed simultaneously with modern state

    structures. It involved a new optics, mechanics and physiology. Foucault (1997a:

    35) tells us that the new optics refers to continual surveillance. Everything is seen,

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    8/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 281

    recorded and filed. He calls this panopticism. The mechanics concerns confine-ment. Closed systems can be interpreted as warehouses for surplus humanity, con-

    taining those considered useless or threatening to the social order. Individuals are

    isolated and regrouped to maximize bodily utility, in short, the putting into place

    of a whole discipline of life, time, and energies (Foucault 1997a: 35). Physiol-

    ogy refers to standards, their clinical enforcement, and measures of correction

    whether curative or punitive. In appearance, it is merely the technical solution of

    a technical problem; but, through it, a whole type of society emerges (Foucault

    1979: 216).Mark Kelly (2009: 4344) writes that [t]he key thing about technologies of

    power is that they are technologies, not merely structures or discourses of power,

    although structures and discourses play their part. That they are technologies

    means that they are, like other technologies, a body of technical knowledge and

    practices, a raft of techniques, which are transferable. Discipline and Punishis

    therefore about more than prisons. Foucault (1979: 205) made it clear that panop-

    ticism was a generalizable principle. Such is the architecture that would operate

    to transform individuals: to act on those it shelters, to provide a hold on their con-duct, to carry the effects of power right to them, to make it possible to know them,

    to alter them (Foucault 1979: 172). These disciplinary structures and practices

    occupy central positions in modern life.

    For Foucault the industrial take-off of the West required the accumulation of

    people as well as capital. The development of industrial capitalism could not be

    realised without the proper control of people within the political apparatus. The

    Industrial Revolution was therefore also a political revolution, resting on a cal-

    culated technology of subjection (Foucault 1979: 221). This Foucault ascribedto a commingling of technological innovations, an enhanced division of labour

    and new techniques of discipline, with discipline being those techniques by which

    bodies are transformed into productive entities. His discussion makes it plain that

    power is neither property nor capacity. Power is a relation, an accomplishment

    actualized by techniques.

    Foucault and the Mechanisms of Power: The Mediang Role of Techniques

    Latour (1988: 199) registers his objection to dominant conceptions of technol-ogy thus: The word technology is unsatisfactory because it has been limited

    for too long to the study of those lines of force that take the form of nuts and

    bolts. This aligns with Foucault (2000: 364): A very narrow meaning is given to

    technology: one thinks of hard technology, the technology of wood, of fire, of

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    9/19

    282 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    electricity. Even within the field of Latours labours, STS, there is an obsessionwith physical things from Michel Callons (1986a) electric car, to Latours (1996)

    automated commuter system, to John Laws (2000) aircraft, Donald MacKenzies

    (1990) missile guidance system, Wiebe Bijkers (1995) bikes and Bakelite, and

    Trevor Pinch and Frank Troccos (2002) synthesiser. With the growing salience of

    material culture across increasing disciplinary domains this trend has intensified.

    Once we wrote of the linguistic turn. Jonathan Sterne (2003: 367) believes that

    we may now be undergoing an even larger technological turn in the human

    sciences, while Steven Connor (2008) has identified a thingly turn in philoso-phy and cultural studies and Judy Wajcman (2002: 361) has noted the increasing

    salience of material culture in social anthropology. This gives nuts and bolts

    technology more importance, but leaves techniques untouched.

    Things enjoy prestige value, but techniques have pariah status. They have

    received especially poor treatment at the hands of scholars (Lemonnier 1993: 2).

    Yet for Pierre Lemonnier it is precisely these techniques which beg our analysis

    for they are unambiguously social productions. Other theorists are wont to go

    much further; these are the social productions that produce us (Serres 1982: 91).Foucault would doubtless assent. It is to techniques that he is routinely drawn;

    alerting us to this vitally important yet customarily overlooked subject (Discipline

    and Punish mentions techniques on ninety-six separate occasions, and Security,

    Territory, Populationeighty). Indeed, Latour (2005: 76) accords Foucault now

    classical status for his work in materialising non-material technologies, intellec-

    tual technologies included. In a scholarly universe now fixated on things, Foucault

    returns us to one of technologys forgotten domains; the scholarly blind spot of

    technique (see also Gerrie 2003).Can techniques be as significant as things? Can we compare disciplinary

    techniques with technological marvels like the steam train and the microscope?

    On this issue Foucault (1979: 225) wavers: They are much less, and yet, in a way,

    they are much more. The disciplinary techniques of panopticism have garnered

    far less attention than physical objects like blast furnaces and steam engines (Fou-

    cault 1979: 224). This is regrettable as they represent a veritable technological

    take-off in the productivity of power (Foucault 1980: 119):

    We frequently speak of the technical inventions of the seventeenth cen-

    turychemical, metallurgical technologyyet we do not mention the

    technical invention of this new form of governing man, controlling his mul-

    tiplicity, utilizing him to the maximum, and improving the products of his

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    10/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 283

    labour, of his activities thanks to a system of power which permits control-ling them. (Foucault 2007: 146)

    Herein lays the crucial point. In Foucaults telling, prior academic accounts of

    power fixated on those who were said to hold it, an endless procession of mon-

    archs and generals. Scholars either studied great individuals or great institutions;

    the exercise of power was seldom discussed, much less the mutual imbrications

    of knowledge and power (Foucault 1980: 51). It is to these very mechanisms and

    techniques that Foucault (2003b; 2009: 150) routinely turned. As he put it: The

    case of the penal system convinced me that the question of power needed to be

    formulated not so much in terms of justice as in those of technology (Foucault

    1980: 184).

    Discipline and Punish identifies the methods through which subjects are ren-

    dered docile by the exercise of disciplinary power (Foucault 1979: 138). Enmeshed

    in a mechanism of domination people could be known, controlled, transformed

    and used. As we saw, this rested on a new technology of design in which bodies

    were placed (the panopticon), these bodies were then regulated through new tech-

    nologies of coding (timetables, routines) and body-object training (rifle drills),

    supplemented by various techniques (surveillance, documentation, examination).

    Through these technologies and techniques bodies are made visible, politically

    compliant and economically productive. Techniques come to the fore. Through

    them power is operationalized (Foucault 1990: 11). Accordingly, Foucault made

    the question of techniques an ongoing concern of his work, by which he meant

    the specific practices which concretize political rationalities and tie individuals to

    social collectives in particular ways.

    Latour (2005: 86) has suggested that this aspect of Foucaults scholarship, the

    analysis of the very stuff of power, has been forgotten in the Anglophone world,

    but his message has not been lost on actor-network theorists. The only way to

    understand how power is locally exerted is thus to take into account everything

    that has been put to one side, that is, essentially, techniques (Latour 1986: 277).

    Power is simply their effect (Latour 1986; Foucault 1979: 27). We should, how-

    ever, note differences of emphasis. Foucault was interested in the ways in which

    techniques resocialize human subjects; ANT is more interested in the ways in

    which techniques socialize non-human objects (Latour 1999: 197). Still, the influ-

    ence of Foucault is clear. Laws article on the long-distance control of Portuguese

    colonies (Law 1986b) is a case in point. This required ship construction that could

    protect sailors from enemies and from the elements. Ships needed to be capable of

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    11/19

    284 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    covering vast distances with commercially viable amounts of cargo. This neces-sitated navigational instrumentation that was durable, portable and reliable. Law

    (1986a: 17) extends Foucaults comments about drilled people to technologies,

    discussing the development of docile devices like astrolabes (see also Callon

    (1991: 151) on docile agents.)

    Foucaults Inuence on ANT

    While Foucault enjoys canonical status in Surveillance Studies, his profile in STS

    is considerably lower. This is particularly strange given his profound influence onANT, which has been in ascendency within STS for two decades. We will consider

    ANTs intellectual debt to Foucault with reference to its leading figures: Latour,

    Law, and Callon. We will do so by examining the topics of power, materiality, the

    nature of the social, non-human agency and technological neutrality. These topics

    have been selected as they form the core of what leading protagonists take ANTs

    concerns to be. Law (1992), for example, sums up the core principles of ANT

    thus: it is centrally interested in the operations of power, and it conceives of the

    social as a heterogeneous network. Knowledge, action and power are explained asmaterially embodied network effects (Law 1992: 381). As we shall see, these ideas

    all resonate with Foucault.

    ANT shares Foucaults (1982) definition of power as the ability to affect the

    actions of others (Latour 1986: 265). Success is therefore measured in the same

    way. Disciplinary power results in the docility of opponents. Like Foucault (1979:

    27) ANT treats power as effect rather than cause, and as strategy not property (Law

    1986a). The notion of power operating through a network is also already present

    in Foucaults (1980: 98) thought: Power must be analysed as something whichcirculates, or rather as something which only functions in the form of a chain. It

    is never localized here or there, never in anybodys hands, never appropriated as a

    commodity or piece of wealth. Power is employed and exercised through a net-like

    organisation. Compare Latour (1991: 110): Power is not a property of any one

    of those elements but of a chain of human and non-human actors. For Foucault

    (1994b: 345) as for ANT this network is heterogeneously composed: [p]ower

    relations are rooted in the whole network of the social, a multiple network of

    diverse elements (Foucault 1979: 307). People and things do not populate a void;rather they occupy heterogeneous space, with various sites defined by their re-

    lations (Foucault 1986: 23). The network is invoked by Foucault (1990: 46) to

    describe social formations such as the family, as well as to describe our social

    situation more broadly, [t]he present epoch will perhaps be above all the epoch

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    12/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 285

    of space. . . . We are at a moment, I believe, when our experience of the world isless that of a long life developing through time than that of a network that connects

    points and intersects with its own skein (Foucault 1986: 22).

    In Discipline and Punish (1979), Power/Knowledge (1980) and The Pu-

    nitive Society (1997a), Foucault discusses the materiality of power, and in the

    opening volume of The History of Sexuality(1990: 140), he reminds us that power

    is made possible only through agencement concrets (concrete arrangements). That

    is to say, power is not a network of forces, but a multiple network of diverse

    elementswalls, space, institution, rules, discourse . . . a strategic distribution ofelements of different natures and levels (Foucault 1979: 307). This is precisely

    what ANT theorists take the social to be, nothing other than patterned networks

    of heterogeneous materials (Law 1992: 381, emphasis in original). ANT also

    fully subscribes to Foucaults notion of the materiality of power. Writes Latour:

    Left to its own devices, a social tie made only of social ties would be limited

    to very short-lived, local, face-to-face, unequipped interactions. . . . When

    power is exerted, it is because it is not made of social ties. . . . It is when

    power is exercised through things that dont sleep and associations thatdont break down that it can last longer and expand furtherand for this,

    of course, links made of another stuff than social contracts are required.

    (Latour 2004: 225)

    Foucaults work is sensitive to the ways in which subjects become objects and the

    ways in which objects act upon subjects. Colin Gordon (1980: 23839) draws at-

    tention to the significance of this. Foucault does not affirm the radical autonomy

    of human from physical technologies; moreover, he jettisons the ethical

    polarisation of the subject-object relationship. Domination, after all, is simul-

    taneously subjectification and objectification. Gordon directs us to Foucaults

    discussion of Man-the-Machine, although his later observations on body-object

    articulation are more apposite. Foucault argues that the early modern idea of

    man as machine had two sources of influence, an anatomico-metaphysical register

    inaugurated by Descartes and elaborated by subsequent philosophers and phy-

    sicians, and a technico-political register beginning in the military but spreading

    to schools and hospitals. The former aimed at making the body intelligible, the

    latter useful. One was aimed at comprehension, the other control. Man could be

    treated as a machine, with bodily movements made to operate as if clockwork:

    The human body was entering a machinery of power that explores it, breaks it

    down and rearranges it (Foucault 1979: 138). Foucault continues in this vein

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    13/19

    286 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    citing Ordonnance du 1er janvier 1766, pour rgler lexercise de linfanterie, aweapons drill for the correct holding, aiming, firing, and reloading of rifles. Here

    the body relates to manipulated object in a precisely codified manner. Another

    example concerns the Prussian military regulations of 1743 which stipulated six

    stages for bringing the weapon to foot, four to extend it and thirteen to raise it to

    the shoulder. In the process soldier and rifle are fused, the two become one, bonded

    by a power that operates over all surfaces. Together they become a body-weapon,

    body-tool, body-machine complex (Foucault 1979: 153). Latour (1994: 32) also

    wrote of person and firearm in combination as more than the sum of their parts,describing the result as a gun-citizen. Like Foucault, Latours analysis eschews

    moralist accounts which focus exclusively on users of technology (people kill

    people) and materialist accounts focusing only upon the technology being used

    (guns kill people). Neither of their analyses proceeds with essences, subjects or

    objects, but with a hybrid composite. What is fore-grounded is the mediating role

    of techniques. They argue for what we might call a distributed agency (people

    with guns kill people).

    Nonetheless, as Latour (2002) would do much later, Foucault identified amoral dimension to technology. Tellingly, Foucault (1979: 223) refers to moral-

    ity as a set of physico-political techniques. Here he adds his voice to all of the

    others that have opposed the nave view of technological neutrality: technology

    as mere tool, as mere means to an end. Instead, technologies are positioned as

    political actors. Means and ends are enmeshed. Technologies like stethoscopes are

    designed to do specific things, to allow certain actions. That is, there is a morality

    to artefacts that affect decisive transformations. As noted, institutional formations

    are included in this. Foucault (2007: 149) writes that [t]he architecture of thehospital must be the agent and the instrument of cure. Prison is discussed as

    an instrument and vector of power (Foucault 1979: 30). The cell acts as moral

    agent, disciplines fundamental structure, necessary for isolation, reflection and

    transformation. It is the instrument by which one may reconstitute both homo

    oeconomicus and the religious conscience, the means by which the body and

    soul are worked upon to reconstitute deviant subject as model citizen (Foucault

    1979: 123). Warders do not need to exert force, this is assured by the materiality

    of things (Foucault 1979: 239). Walls do the punishing. Stones can make peopledocile and knowable.

    ANT scholars have noted their affinities with Foucault. Callon (1986a: 196)

    introduced the sociology translation as a new sociology of power. It would later be

    known as ANT. His programmatic article hinted at ANTs progenitor. In his con-

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    14/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 287

    cluding comments about translationhow power is realized and how the conductof others is controlledhe directed his readers to a final footnote: this point links

    with the notion of the political economy of power proposed by Michel Foucault

    (Callon 1986b: 230). Latours (1986: 279) discussion of power draws the same

    conclusion, the result of ANT analysis is in effect the same result as that obtained

    by Michel Foucault . . . when he dissolves the notion of a power held by the power-

    ful in favor of micro-powers diffused through the many technologies to discipline

    and keep in line. ANT, then, is simply an expansion of Foucaults notion to the

    many techniques employed in machines and the hard sciences. Law (1992: 388)offers a further point of connection when he notes that processes of translation

    like Foucauldian discourses, ramify through and reproduce themselves in a range

    of network instances or locations.

    What might be original to ANT? Law (1992: 387) suggests that because it

    makes no sharp ontological distinction between subject and object it is analyti-

    cally radical. As demonstrated,Discipline and Punish had already taken this posi-

    tion. Law (1992: 389) further suggests that ANTs relational materialism might be

    novel, by which he means its insistence on viewing both people and things as partof the social scientists story. But recalling Foucaults writings on heterogeneity,

    materiality and networks this claim is also contestable. Indeed, Law (1994: 11)

    would later write that relational materialism is not unique to ANT, rather it is a

    sensibility it shares with Foucault and various stars of STS like Donna Haraway

    and Madeleine Akrich. In more recent writings still ANT is offered as a scaled

    down version of Foucaults discussions of discourse and epistemes (Law 2007: 6).

    The real point of departure is methodological not conceptual. Foucault excavates

    points in the past, ANT tells empirical stories about processes of translation inthe present (Law 1992: 387). For the most partand this only seems to hold if

    we ignore Foucaults interviews and shorter works and Latour (1988) and Laws

    (1986b) historic piecesFoucault was in the archive whereas ANT theorists are

    in the field. In an interview Latour (2003: 16) brought some clarification to his

    lifes work. He described his enduring project as an analysis of contemporary civi-

    lizations truth-generation sites: science, religion, law, technology and techniques.

    Again, this is rather close to Foucaults core concerns. Perhaps the methodological

    differences, such as they are, are less significant than the political reasons thatseem to drive them. Foucaults excavations show us that our social arrangements

    can be different because they have been different, while ANT shows us how power

    is achieved and how worlds are built. Both, in their own ways, offer the possibility

    of alternatives.

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    15/19

    288 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    Before STS and ANT came into being Foucault had already made the pointthat neither agency nor morality are the exclusive preserve of humanity. Similarly,

    prior to Latour (1991) writing Technology Is Society Made Durable, Foucault

    had already shown us the the decisive role of technological procedures and ap-

    paratuses in the organization of a society (De Certau 2000: 187, emphasis in

    original). Humans can not be abstracted from the very technologies that help

    constitute them. Matter matters. Hence the proliferation of words like apparatus,

    instrumentations, machineries, mechanisms, techniques, technologies and techno-

    politics throughout Discipline and Punish to capture the silent agents of hisstory (De Certau 2000: 185). By showing, in a single case, the heterogeneous

    and equivocal relations between apparatuses and ideologies, Michel De Certau

    (2000: 189) writes, Foucault has constituted a new object of historical study:

    that zone in which technological procedures have specific effects of power, obey

    logical dynamisms which are specific to them, and produce fundamental turnings

    aside in the juridical and scientific institutions. Foucaults notion of apparatus

    (dispositif) assumes central significance here. His fullest definition of the term is

    to be found in The Confession of the Flesh:

    What Im trying to pick out with this term is, firstly, a thoroughly heteroge-

    neous ensemble consisting of discourses, institutions, architectural forms,

    regulatory decisions, laws, administrative measures, scientific statements,

    philosophical, moral and philanthropic propositionsin short, the said as

    much as the unsaid. Such are the elements of the apparatus. The apparatus

    itself is the system of relations that can be established between these ele-

    ments. (Foucault 1980: 194)

    Compare, once more, ANT theorists on the nature of the social: Agents, texts,

    devices, architectures are all generated in, form part of, and are essential to, the

    networks of the social (Law 1992: 379).

    Conclusion

    This article has advanced a case for taking Foucault seriously as a theorist of tech-

    nology. Only rarely is he acknowledged as such. The oversight is strange given

    the fact that Foucault anchored much of his conceptual terminology in technol-

    ogy. This vocabulary was necessary as technology was the lens through which he

    made sense of the world. Technologies channel action. Through them and their

    allied techniques we understand, and transform, ourselves and others. They play

    a crucial role in the constitution of the subject and in the construction of soci-

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    16/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 289

    ety. Recognising this, Foucault (1997a) located his intellectual output within atechnological framework. We therefore need to understand technology if we are

    to understand his work. This point is particularly pertinent to his core concern:

    power. For Foucault power is not a capacity residing within particular individuals

    but an interactive effect, disseminated through heterogeneous networks of people

    and things in combination. Technologies and techniques come to the fore as the

    creators, carriers, and conveyors of power relations (Foucault 1979: 201; Foucault

    1984). They are the means by which power is exercised and its very substance.

    This has been recognised by ANT scholars who have profitably applied Foucaultsinsights to illuminate the production of scientific knowledge and the construction

    of technological artefacts in a range of empirical case studies. In the process they

    have become one of the leading schools within STS.

    References

    Bijker, W. E. 1995. Of Bicycles, Bakelites and Bulbs: Toward a Theory of Socio-

    Technical Change. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    Bleakley, A. and J. Bligh. 2009. Who can Resist Foucault?,Journal of Medicine andPhilosophy34(4): 36883. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jmp/jhp028

    Callon, M. 1986a. The Sociology of an Actor-network: The Case of the Electric

    Vehicle inMapping the Dynamics of Science and Technology: Sociology of Sci-

    ence in the Real World, ed. M. Callon, J. Law, and A. Rip. London: Macmillan,

    1934.

    . 1986b. Some Elements of a Sociology of Translation: Domestication of the

    Scallops and the Fishermen of St Brieuc Bay, in Power, Action and Belief, ed. J.

    Law. London: Routledge, 196233.

    . 1991. Techno-economic Networks and Irreversibility, in A Sociology ofMonsters: Essays on Power, Technology and Domination, ed. J. Law. London:

    Routledge, 13261.

    Connor, S. 2008. Thinking Things, Plenary lecture, 9th annual conference of the Eu-

    ropean Society for the Study of English (ESSE), Aarhus, Denmark, 25 August.

    Available at http://www.stevenconnor.com/thinkingthings/ (accessed 17 August

    2011).

    De Certau, M. 2000, Micro-techniques and Panoptic Discourse: A Quid Pro Quo, in

    Heterologies: Discourse on the Other, trans. B. Massumi. Minneapolis: Univer-

    sity of Minnesota Press, 18592.

    Foucault, M. 1979.Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison, trans. Alan Sheri-

    dan. New York: Vintage Books.

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    17/19

    290 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    . 1980. Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings 19721977, trans. C. Gordon. New York: Pantheon.

    . 1982. How is Power Exercised?, inMichel Foucault: Beyond Structural-

    ism and Hermeneutics, ed. H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow. Chicago: University of

    Chicago Press, 21626.

    . 1984. What is Enlightenment?, in The Foucault Reader, ed. P. Rabinow.

    New York, Pantheon Books, 3250.

    . 1986. Of Other Spaces,Diacritics16(1): 2227.

    http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/464648

    . 1988. Technologies of the Self, in Technologies of the Self, ed. L. Martin, H.Gutman, and P. Hutton. Amherst: The University of Massachusetts Press, 1649.

    . 1990. The History of Sexuality, vol. 1. New York: Penguin.

    . 1994a. The Birth of Social Medicine, in Power: Essential Works of Fou-

    cault 19541984, vol. 3, ed. J. D. Faubion. New York: The New Press, 13456.

    . 1994b. The Subject and Power, in Power: Essential Works of Foucault

    19541984, vol. 3, ed. J. D. Faubion. New York: The New Press, 32648.

    . 1994c. Truth and Power, in Power: Essential Works of Foucault 19541984,

    vol. 3, ed. J. D. Faubion. New York: The New Press, 11133.

    . 1997a. The Punitive Society, in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth: Michel

    Foucault on Truth, Beauty, & Power 19541984, ed. P. Rabinow, trans. R. Hurley.

    London: Penguin, 2339.

    . 1997b. Subjectivity and Truth, in Ethics: Subjectivity and Truth: Michel

    Foucault on Truth, Beauty, & Power 19541984, ed. P. Rabinow, trans. R. Hurley.

    London: Penguin, 8792.

    . 2000. Space, Knowledge, Power, in Power: Essential Works of Foucault

    19541984, ed. J. Faubion. New York: The New Press, 34964.

    . 2002a. The Archaeology of Knowledge. London: Routledge.

    . 2002b. The Order of Things. London: Routledge.

    . 2003a. The Birth of the Clinic. London: Routledge.

    . 2003b. Society Must Be Defended,trans. D. Macey. London: Penguin.

    . 2006.History of Madness, trans. J. Murphy and J. Khalfa. London: Routledge.

    . 2007. The Incorporation of the Hospital in Modern Technology, in Space,

    Knowledge and Power: Foucault and Geography, ed. J. W. Crampton and S.

    Elden. Aldershot: Ashgate, 14152.

    . 2008. The Birth of Biopolitics: Lectures at the Collge de France 19781979,

    trans. G. Burchell. Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan.. 2009. Security, Territory, Population: Lectures at the Collge de France

    19771978, trans. Graham Burchell. New York: Picador.

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    18/19

    The Relationship between Thought Structures and Media Structures 291

    Gerrie, J. 2003. Was Foucault a Philosopher of Technology?, Techn: Research inPhilosophy and Technology7(2), available at http://scholar.lib.vt.edu/ejournals/

    SPT/v7n2/gerrie.html.

    Gordon, C. 1980. Afterword, in Michel Foucault, Power/Knowledge: Selected In-

    terviews and Other Writings 19721977, trans. C. Gordon. New York: Pantheon,

    22959.

    Han, B. 2002. Foucaults Critical Project: Between the Transcendental and the His-

    torical. Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press.

    Kelly, M. 2009. The Political Philosophy of Michel Foucault. New York: Routledge.

    Latour, B. 1986. The Powers of Association, in Power, Action and Belief, ed. J. Law.London: Routledge, 26480.

    . 1988. The Pasteurization of France, trans. A. Sheridan and J. Law. Cam-

    bridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    . 1991. Technology Is Society Made Durable, inA Sociology of Monsters: Es-

    says on Power, Technology and Domination, ed. J. Law. London: Routledge, 10331.

    . 1994. On Technical Mediation: Philosophy, Sociology, Genealogy, Com-

    mon Knowledge3(2): 2964.

    . 1996. Aramis, or, The Love of Technology, trans. C. Porter. Cambridge,

    Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    . 1999. Pandoras Hope: Essays on the Reality of Science Studies. Cambridge,

    Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    . 2002. Technology and Morality: The Ends of Means, Theory, Culture &

    Society19(5/6): 24760. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/026327602761899246

    . 2003. Interview with Bruno Latour, in Chasing Technoscience: Matrix for

    Materiality, ed. D. Ihde and E. Selinger. Bloomington: Indiana University Press,

    1526.

    . 2004. Nonhumans, in Patterned Ground: Entanglements of Nature andCulture, ed. S. Harris, S. Pile, and N. Thrift. London: Reaktion, 22427.

    . 2005.Reassembling the Social: An Introduction to Actor-Network Theory.

    Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Law, J. 1986a. Editors Introduction: Power/knowledge and the Dissolution of the

    Sociology of Knowledge, in Power, Action and Belief. London: Routledge,

    119.

    . 1986b. On the Methods of Long-distance Control: Vessels, Navigation and

    the Portuguese Route to India, in Power, Action and Belief. London: Routledge,

    23463.. 1991. Power, Discretion and Strategy, inA Sociology of Monsters: Essays

    on Power, Technology and Domination. London: Routledge, 16591.

  • 5/21/2018 05--Matthewman

    19/19

    292 Techn: Research in Philosophy and Technology

    . 1992. Notes on the Theory of the Actor Network: Ordering, Strategy, andHeterogeneity, Systems Practice5(4): 37993.

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/BF01059830

    . 1994. Organizing Modernity. Oxford: Blackwell.

    . 1999. After ANT: Complexity, Naming and Topology, inActor Network

    Theory and After, ed. J. Law and J. Hassard. Oxford: Blackwell, 114.

    . 2000.Aircraft Stories: Decentering the Object in Technoscience. Durham,

    N.C.: Duke University Press.

    . 2007. Actor Network Theory and Material Semiotics, Available at http://

    www.heterogeneities.net/publications/Law-ANTandMaterialSemiotics.pdf (ac-cessed 23 July 2012).

    Lemonnier, P. 1993. Introduction, in Technological Choices: Transformation in

    Material Cultures Since the Neolithic. London: Routledge, 135.

    MacKenzie, D. 1990.Inventing Accuracy: An Historical Sociology of Nuclear Missile

    Guidance. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.

    MacKenzie, D., and J. Wajcman, eds. 1985. The Social Shaping of Technology. Milton

    Keynes: The Open University Press.

    Olsen, B. 2006. Scenes from a Troubled Engagement: Post-structuralism and Mate-

    rial Culture Studies, inHandbook of Material Culture, ed. C. Tilley, W. Keane,

    S. Kuechler, M. Rowlands, and P. Spyer. London: Sage, 85103.

    Pinch, T., and F. Trocco. 2002.Analog Days: The Invention and Impact of the Moog

    Synthesiser. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.

    Rajchman, J. 1984. The Story of Foucaults History, Social Text8: 324.

    Rooney, D. 1997. A Contextualising, Socio-technical Definition of Technology:

    Learning from Ancient Greece and Foucault, Prometheus 15(3): 399407.

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08109029708632084

    Serres, M. 1982.Hermes: Literature, Science, Philosophy. Baltimore: Johns HopkinsUniversity Press.

    Sterne, J. 2001. Mediate Auscultation, the Stethoscope, and the Autopsy of the

    Living: Medicines Acoustic Culture, Journal of Medical Humanities 22(2):

    11536. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/A:1009067628620

    . 2003. Bourdieu, Technique and Technology, Cultural Studies 17(3/4):

    36789. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/0950238032000083863a

    Verbeek, P. 2005. What Things Do: Philosophical Reflections on Technology. Univer-

    sity Park: Pennsylvania University Press.

    Wajcman, J. 2002. Addressing Technological Change: The Challenge to SocialTheory, Current Sociology50(3): 34763.

    http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0011392102050003004

    Winner, L. 1977. Autonomous Technology: Technics-out-of-Control as a Theme in

    Political Thought. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press.