468593 Stanley Fish

  • Upload
    vijeta1

  • View
    222

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    1/41

    Literature in the Reader: Affective Stylistics

    Author(s): Stanley FishReviewed work(s):Source: New Literary History, Vol. 2, No. 1, A Symposium on Literary History (Autumn,1970), pp. 123-162Published by: The Johns Hopkins University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/468593.

    Accessed: 15/11/2012 01:07

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    The Johns Hopkins University Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    New Literary History.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhuphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/468593?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/468593?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=jhup
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    2/41

    Literature

    n

    the Reader: Affective

    tylistics

    Stanley

    ish

    Meaning

    s

    Event

    I.

    F

    AT THIS

    moment

    omeone

    were

    to

    ask,

    what re

    youdoing? ,

    you might

    eply,

    I

    am

    reading,

    nd

    thereby

    cknowledge

    he fact

    that

    reading

    s

    an

    activity, omething

    ou

    do.

    No one would

    argue

    that

    the

    act

    of

    reading

    can take

    place

    in the

    absence

    of

    someone who

    reads-how

    can

    you

    tell the dance

    fromthe dancer?-but

    curiously

    enough

    when it comes

    time

    to

    make

    analytical

    statements

    bout

    the

    end product of reading (meaning or understanding), he reader is

    usually

    forgotten

    r

    ignored.

    Indeed in recent

    iterary istory

    e

    has

    been excluded

    by egislation.

    refer,

    f

    course,

    o

    the ex cathedra

    pro-

    nouncements

    f

    Wimsatt

    nd

    Beardsley

    n

    their

    normously

    nfluential

    article

    The Affective

    allacy :

    The Affective

    allacy

    is

    a confusion

    etween he

    poem

    and

    its

    results

    (what

    t is and what

    t

    does)

    ....

    It

    beginsby trying

    o derive

    he

    stan-

    dards

    of

    criticism

    rom he

    psychological

    ffects

    f the

    poem

    and ends

    n

    impressionism

    nd relativism.

    he outcome ..

    is

    that

    the

    poem tself,

    s

    an

    object

    of

    specifically

    ritical

    udgment,

    ends o

    disappear.

    In

    time,

    shall return

    o

    these

    arguments,

    ot so

    much to refute hem

    as

    to affirm

    nd embrace

    hem;

    but

    I

    would

    first

    ike

    to demonstrate

    he

    explanatory

    ower

    of a method

    of

    analysis

    which takes

    the

    reader,

    as

    an

    actively

    mediating

    resence,

    ully

    nto

    account,

    nd

    which,

    herefore,

    has

    as its

    focus the

    psychological

    ffects

    f the

    utterance.

    And

    I

    would

    like

    to

    begin

    with a

    sentence hat

    does not

    open

    itself

    p

    to

    the

    questions

    we

    usually

    sk.

    That

    Judas

    perished

    y

    hanging

    himself,

    here s no

    certainty

    n

    Scrip-

    ture:

    though

    n one

    place

    it seems

    o

    affirm

    t,

    and

    by

    a doubtful

    word

    I

    The Verbal

    Icon

    (Lexington,

    Ky.,

    1954),

    P.

    21.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    3/41

    124

    NEW

    LITERARY HISTORY

    hath

    given

    occasion to translate

    t;

    yet

    in

    another

    place,

    in

    a

    more

    punctual

    description,t

    maketh t improbable,nd seems o overthrow

    t.

    Ordinarily,

    one would

    begin

    by

    asking

    what

    does

    this

    sentence

    mean? or

    what is it about? or what is it

    saying? ,

    ll of which

    pre-

    serve the

    objectivity

    f the utterance. For

    my

    purposes,

    however,

    his

    particular

    entencehas

    the

    advantage

    of not

    saying

    nything.

    That

    is,

    you

    can't

    get

    a

    fact

    out of t whichcould serve s an answer

    o

    any

    one

    of

    these

    uestions.

    Of

    course,

    his

    difficulty

    s itself fact-of

    response;

    and it

    suggests,

    o

    me

    at

    least,

    hat

    what

    makes

    problematical

    ense

    as a

    statementmakes

    perfect

    ense as a

    strategy,

    s an action made

    upon

    a

    reader rather han as a container romwhich a reader extracts mes-

    sage.

    The

    strategy

    r action

    here

    s

    one of

    progressive

    ecertainizing.

    Simply

    by

    taking

    n the

    first lause of the

    sentence,

    he

    reader

    com-

    mits

    himself o

    its

    assertion,

    that

    Judas

    perishedby

    hanging

    himself

    (in

    constructions

    f

    this

    type

    that

    is

    understood

    o be

    shorthand

    or

    the

    fact

    that ).

    This

    is not so

    much a conscious

    decision,

    s

    it is an

    anticipatory

    djustment

    o his

    projection

    f

    the

    sentence's

    uture

    on-

    tours.

    He knows

    withoutgiving

    ognitive

    orm

    o

    his

    knowledge)

    that

    thisfirst

    lause

    s

    preliminary

    o some

    arger

    ssertion

    it

    is a

    ground )

    and he mustbe in control f it ifhe is to move easilyand confidently

    through

    what

    follows;

    and in the

    context

    of this

    knowledge,

    he

    is

    prepared,

    gain

    less

    than

    consciously,

    or

    any

    one

    of several

    construc-

    tions:

    That

    Judas

    perished

    y

    hanging

    himself,

    s

    (an example

    for

    us

    all).

    That

    Judas

    perished

    y

    hanging

    himself,

    hows

    how

    conscious e

    was

    ofthe

    normity

    f

    his

    sin).

    That

    Judas

    perished

    y

    hanging

    imself,

    hould

    give

    us

    pause).

    The

    range

    ofthese

    possibilities

    and

    there

    re,

    of

    course,

    morethan

    I have

    listed)

    narrows

    onsiderably

    s

    the

    next threewords

    are

    read,

    there s

    no.

    At this

    point,

    he

    reader s

    expecting,

    nd even

    predicting,

    a

    single

    word- doubt ;

    but instead

    he finds

    certainty ;

    nd

    at

    that

    moment

    he status

    of

    the fact that

    had served

    s his

    point

    of

    reference

    becomes

    uncertain.

    (It

    is

    nicely

    ronic hatthe

    appearance

    of

    certain-

    ty

    should

    be the

    occasion

    for

    doubt,

    whereas

    he word

    doubt

    would

    have contributed

    o

    the reader's

    certainty.)

    As a

    result,

    he

    terms

    of

    the

    reader's

    relationship

    o

    the sentence

    undergo

    a

    profound hange.He

    is

    suddenly

    nvolved n a differentind of

    activity.

    Ratherthan

    following

    n

    argument

    long

    a well

    lightedpath

    (a

    light,

    fter

    ll,

    has

    gone

    out),

    he

    is

    now

    looking

    for

    one. The natural

    mpulse

    n a

    situa-

    tion ike

    this,

    ither

    n

    lifeor in

    literature,

    s to

    go

    forward n the

    hope

    that what

    has been

    obscuredwill

    again

    become

    clear;

    but in

    this

    case

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    4/41

    LITERATURE IN

    THE READER: AFFECTIVE STYLISTICS

    125

    going

    forward

    nly

    ntensifies

    he

    readers

    ense

    of disorientation. he

    prose

    s

    continually

    pening,

    but then

    closing,

    n the

    possibility

    f

    veri-

    ficationn one direction r another.There are twovocabularies n the

    sentence;

    one

    holds out

    the

    promise

    of

    a

    clarification- place,

    af-

    firm,

    place,

    punctual,

    overthrow -while the other

    continually

    defaults n

    that

    promise- Though,

    doubtful,

    yet,

    improbable,

    seems ;

    and the

    reader s

    passed

    back

    and forth

    etween

    them and

    between

    the alternatives-that

    Judas

    did or did not

    perishby

    hanging

    himself-which are

    still

    suspended (actually

    it is

    the

    reader

    who is

    suspended)

    when the sentenceends

    (trails

    off?

    gives up?).

    The in-

    determinateness

    f

    this

    experience

    s

    compounded by

    a

    superfluity

    f

    pronouns. It becomes ncreasingly ifficulto tell what it refers o,

    and

    if the reader

    takes

    the trouble

    o

    retracehis

    steps,

    he

    is

    simply

    ed

    back to

    that

    Judas

    perished by

    hanging

    himself ;

    n

    short,

    he ex-

    changes

    an indefinite

    ronoun

    for n even ess definite

    that

    s,

    certain)

    assertion.

    Whatever

    s

    persuasive

    nd

    illuminating

    bout this

    analysis

    and

    it

    is

    by

    no

    means

    exhaustive)

    is the

    result of

    my

    substituting

    or

    one

    question-what

    does this

    sentence

    mean?-another,

    more

    operational

    question-what

    does this sentencedo?

    And

    what

    the

    sentence

    does

    is give the readersomething nd thentake it away, drawinghim on

    with the

    unredeemed

    promise

    of its return.

    An observation

    bout

    the

    sentence

    s

    an

    utterance-its refusal

    o

    yield

    a declarative

    tatement-

    has

    been transformednto an

    account of

    its

    experience

    not

    being

    able

    to

    get

    a

    fact out of

    it).

    It

    is no

    longer

    an

    object,

    a

    thing-in-itself,

    ut

    an

    event,

    omething

    hat

    happens

    to,

    and

    with the

    participation

    f,

    the

    reader. And it s this

    vent,

    his

    happening-all

    of t

    and not

    anything

    that could be said about it

    or

    any

    information

    ne

    might

    take

    away

    from

    t-that

    is,

    I

    would

    argue,

    the

    meaning

    of the

    sentence.

    (Of

    course, nthis ase there s no informationotakeaway.)

    This is

    a

    provocative

    hesis

    whose

    elaboration

    and

    defense

    will be

    the

    concern

    of

    the

    following

    pages,

    but

    before

    proceeding

    to

    it,

    I

    would

    like

    to

    examine another

    utterancewhich

    also

    (conveniently)

    saysnothing:

    Nor did

    they

    ot

    perceive

    he

    evil

    plight.

    The

    firstword of this line

    fromParadise Lost

    (I,

    335) generates

    rather

    precise if abstract) expectation

    f

    what

    will follow:

    a

    negativeassertionwhich will

    require

    for ts

    completion

    subject

    and a verb.

    There are then

    two

    dummy

    slots

    n the reader's

    mind

    waiting

    o

    be

    filled. This

    expectation

    s

    strengthened

    if

    only

    because

    it is not

    chal-

    lenged)

    by

    the

    auxiliary

    did

    and the

    pronoun they.

    Presumably,

    the verb

    is not far behind.

    But in its

    place

    the reader is

    presented

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    5/41

    S126

    NEW

    ITERARYISTORY

    with a

    second

    negative,

    ne

    that can not

    be accommodatedwithin

    his

    projection

    of the

    utterance'sform.

    His

    progress hrough

    he

    line

    is

    halted and he is forcedto come to termswiththe intrusive because

    unexpected)

    not.

    In

    effect hat the reader

    does,

    or

    is

    forced

    o

    do,

    at

    this

    point,

    s

    ask

    a

    question-did

    they

    or didn't

    they?-and

    in

    search

    of

    an

    answer he

    either

    rereads-in

    which case

    he

    simplyrepeats

    the

    sequence

    of

    mental

    operations-or goes

    forward-in which

    case he

    finds

    he

    anticipated

    erb,

    but

    in

    either ase

    the

    syntactical

    ncertainty

    remains

    nresolved.

    It

    could be

    objected

    that the solution

    to the

    difficulty

    s

    simply

    o

    invoke

    the

    rule

    of the double

    negative;

    one cancels

    the

    other

    and

    the

    correct reading s thereforetheydid perceive heevil plight. But

    however

    atisfactory

    his

    may

    be

    in

    terms

    f

    the nternal

    ogic

    of

    gram-

    matical

    utterances

    and

    even in those terms there are

    problems,2

    it

    has

    nothing

    o do with the

    logic

    of

    the

    reading

    experience

    or,

    I

    would

    insist,

    with ts

    meaning.

    That

    experience

    s a

    temporal

    ne,

    and

    in

    the

    courseof t the two

    negatives

    ombinenot

    to

    produce

    an affirma-

    tive,

    but to

    prevent

    he reader

    from

    making

    the

    simple

    (declarative)

    sense which would

    be the

    goal

    of a

    logical

    analysis.

    To clean the

    line

    up

    is to

    take from

    t

    its most

    prominent

    nd

    important

    ffect-the sus-

    pensionofthe readerbetween the alternativestssyntaxmomentarily

    offers.

    What is

    a

    problem

    f the

    line is

    considered

    as

    an

    object,

    a

    thing-in-itself,

    ecomes

    a

    fact

    when

    it is

    regarded

    as

    an occurrence.

    The reader's

    nability

    o tell

    whether

    r not

    they

    do

    perceive

    nd his

    involuntary

    uestion

    or

    its

    psychological

    quivalent)

    are

    events n

    his

    encounter

    with

    the

    ine,

    and as

    events

    hey

    re

    part

    of

    the

    ine's

    mean-

    ing,

    even

    though they

    take

    place

    in the

    mind,

    not

    on the

    page.

    Sub-

    sequently,

    we discoverthat

    the

    answer

    to the

    question

    did

    they

    or

    didn't

    they,

    s,

    they

    did and

    they

    didn't.

    Milton s

    exploiting

    and

    callingour attentiono) the twosensesof perceive : they the fallen

    angels)

    do

    perceive

    he

    fire,

    he

    pain,

    the

    gloom;

    physically

    hey

    ee

    it;

    however

    hey

    re

    blind

    to

    the

    moral

    significance

    f their

    ituation;

    nd

    in that

    sense

    they

    do not

    perceive

    the evil

    plight

    n which

    they

    are.

    But that s

    another

    tory.

    Underlying

    hese

    two

    analyses

    s

    a

    method,

    rather

    imple

    in

    con-

    cept,

    but

    complex

    (or

    at least

    complicated)

    in execution. The

    con-

    cept

    is

    simply

    the

    rigorous

    nd

    disinterested

    sking

    of

    the

    question,

    what

    does

    this

    word,

    phrase,

    entence,

    aragraph,chapter,

    novel,

    play

    poem, do?; and the execution nvolves n analysisof the developing

    responses

    f

    the

    reader

    in

    relation

    to the words as

    they

    ucceed

    one

    2

    Thus

    the line

    could read:

    They

    did not

    perceive,

    which

    is not the same

    as

    saying

    they

    did

    perceive.

    (The

    question

    is still

    open.)

    One could also

    argue

    that

    not

    is

    not

    really

    negative.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    6/41

    LITERATURE

    IN

    THE READER: AFFECTIVE

    STYLISTICS

    I27

    another n time.

    Every

    word n

    this

    tatement ears a

    special

    emphasis.

    The

    analysis

    mustbe of the

    developing esponses

    o

    distinguish

    t from

    theatomism f muchstylisticriticism.A reader'sresponse o thefifth

    word

    n

    a line

    or

    sentence

    s to a

    large

    extent he

    product

    f his

    responses

    to

    words

    one, two,

    three,

    nd

    four.

    And

    by

    response,

    intendmore

    than

    the

    range

    of

    feelings

    what

    Wimsatt

    nd

    Beardsley

    all the

    purely

    f-

    fective

    eports ).

    The

    category

    f

    response

    ncludes

    any

    and

    all

    of

    the

    activities

    rovoked

    by

    a

    string

    f words:

    the

    projection

    f

    syntactical

    and/or

    lexical

    probabilities;

    their

    subsequent

    occurrence

    or non-oc-

    currence;

    attitudes owards

    persons,

    r

    things,

    r ideas

    referred

    o;

    the

    reversal

    r

    questioning

    f those

    attitudes;

    nd much

    more.

    Obviously,

    this mposesa greatburdenon the analystwho in his observations n

    any

    one

    moment

    n

    the

    reading

    experience

    must take

    into account

    all

    that

    has

    happened

    (in

    the

    reader's

    mind)

    at

    previous

    moments,

    ach

    of which was in

    its turn

    subject

    to

    the

    accumulating

    pressures

    f

    its

    predecessors.

    He

    mustalso

    take

    nto account

    nfluences nd

    pressures

    pre-dating

    he actual

    reading

    experience-questions

    of

    genre,

    history,

    etc.-questions

    we shall

    consider

    ater.)

    All of this

    s

    included

    in

    the

    phrase

    in time.

    The basis of

    the method

    s a consideration

    f the

    temporal

    flow

    of

    the

    reading

    experience,

    nd

    it is assumed

    that

    the

    readerresponds n terms fthatflowand not to thewhole utterance.

    That

    is,

    in

    an utterance

    of

    any length,

    here s

    a

    point

    at which

    the

    reader

    has taken

    n

    only

    the first

    word,

    and then

    the

    second,

    and then

    the

    third,

    nd so

    on,

    and the

    report

    f

    what

    happens

    to the reader

    s

    always

    a

    report

    f what has

    happened

    to that

    point.

    (The

    report

    n-

    cludes the

    reader's set

    toward future

    experiences,

    but

    not those ex-

    periences.)

    The

    importance

    f this

    principle

    s

    illustrated

    when

    we reverse he

    first

    wo

    clauses of the

    Judas

    sentence:

    There is no

    certainty

    hat

    Judasperished yhanginghimself. Here the statusof the assertions

    never

    n

    doubt

    because

    the reader

    knows

    from

    he

    beginning

    hat

    t

    is

    doubtful;

    he is

    given

    a

    perspective

    romwhich

    to

    view

    the

    statement

    and that

    perspective

    s

    confirmed ather han

    challenged

    by

    what

    fol-

    lows;

    even the confusion

    f

    pronouns

    n the

    second

    part

    of the

    sen-

    tencewill not be

    disturbing

    o

    him,

    because

    it can

    easily

    be

    placed

    in

    the

    context f

    his initial

    response.

    There

    is

    no

    difference

    n these

    two

    sen-

    tences

    n

    the nformation

    onveyed

    or

    not

    conveyed),

    or

    in

    the

    exical

    and

    syntactical

    omponents,3

    nly

    n

    the

    way

    these

    are

    received.

    But

    thatonedifference akes ll the difference-betweenn uncomfortable,

    unsettling

    xperience

    n which he

    gradual

    dimming

    f a fact s attended

    by

    a

    failure

    n

    perception,

    nd

    a

    wholly elf-satisfying

    ne in which

    an

    3

    Of

    course,

    That

    is no

    longer

    read

    as the fact

    that,

    but

    this is

    because the

    order

    of the clauses

    has resulted n

    the

    ruling

    out

    of that

    possibility.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    7/41

    128 NEW

    LITERARY

    HISTORY

    uncertainty

    s

    comfortably

    ertain,

    nd

    the

    reader's onfidence

    n

    his

    own

    powers

    emains

    nshaken,

    ecause

    he

    s

    always

    n

    control.

    t

    is,

    insist,differencenmeaning.

    The

    results

    I

    will

    ater

    all

    them

    dvantages)

    f

    this

    method re

    fairly,

    hough

    ot

    exhaustively,

    epresented

    n

    my

    two

    examples.

    Es-

    sentially

    hat

    the

    method

    oes

    s slow down

    the

    reading xperience

    so

    that events ne does

    not

    notice

    n

    normal

    ime,

    utwhich

    o oc-

    cur,

    are

    brought

    efore ur

    analytical

    ttentions.t is as if a slow

    motion amerawith n

    automatic

    top

    ction

    ffect ere

    ecording

    ur

    linguistic xperiences

    nd

    presenting

    hem to us

    for

    viewing.

    Of

    course he

    value

    of

    uch

    procedure

    s

    predicated

    n

    the

    dea of

    mean-

    ingas an event,omethinghat s happeningetween he words nd

    in the

    reader's

    mind,

    omething

    otvisible o

    the

    naked

    ye,

    ut

    which

    can

    be made visible

    or

    at

    least

    palpable)

    by

    the

    regular

    ntroduction

    of a

    searching

    uestion

    what

    does this

    do?).

    It is

    more

    usual

    to

    assume

    hat

    meaning

    s

    a functionf the

    utterance,

    nd

    to

    equate

    t

    with

    he nformation

    iven

    the message)

    or

    the

    attitude

    xpressed.

    That

    is,

    the

    components

    f

    an utterance

    re

    considered

    ither

    n

    rela-

    tion o each

    other

    r

    to a

    state

    f

    affairs

    n

    theoutside

    world,

    r

    to

    the

    state

    fmind

    fthe

    peaker-author.

    n

    any

    nd all

    of

    these

    ariations,

    meanings located presumedobe imbedded) n theutterance,nd

    the

    apprehension

    f

    meaning

    s

    an act

    of

    extraction.4

    n

    short,

    here

    is little

    ense f

    process

    nd even ess

    f

    the

    reader's

    ctualizing

    artici-

    pation

    n that

    rocess.

    This

    concentration

    n theverbal

    bject

    s

    a

    thing

    n

    tself,

    nd

    as

    a

    repository

    f

    meaning

    as

    many

    onsequences,

    heoretical

    nd

    practi-

    cal. First

    f

    all,

    t creates

    whole

    lass

    of

    utterances,

    hich

    because

    of

    their

    lleged

    ransparency,

    re

    declared

    o

    be

    uninteresting

    s

    ob-

    jects

    of

    analysis.

    entences

    r

    fragments

    f sentences

    hat

    mmediately

    makesense a deeply evealinghrase f onethinksbout t) are

    examples

    f

    ordinaryanguage;

    hey

    reneutralnd

    tyleless

    tatements,

    simply

    eferring,

    r

    simply

    eporting.

    ut the

    application

    o such

    utterances

    f

    the

    question

    what does it

    do?

    (which

    assumes

    hat

    something

    s

    always appening)

    eveals

    hat

    great

    eal s

    going

    n

    n

    their

    production

    nd

    comprehension

    every

    inguistic

    xperience

    s

    af-

    fecting

    nd

    pressuring)

    lthough

    most f t s

    going

    n so close

    up,

    at

    such

    basic,

    preconscious

    evelof

    experience,

    hatwe tend o

    over-

    look

    t. Thus

    the

    utterance

    written

    r

    spoken)

    theres

    a

    chair

    s

    at

    onceunderstoods thereportitherfan existingtate f affairsrof

    an

    act

    of

    perception

    I

    see a

    chair).

    In either

    rame f

    reference,

    t

    4

    This is

    not

    true

    of

    the Oxford

    school

    of

    ordinary

    language

    philosophers

    (Austin,

    Grice,

    Searle)

    who

    discuss

    meaning

    in terms

    f

    hearer-speaker

    elationships

    and

    intention-response

    onventions,

    .e.,

    situational

    meaning.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    8/41

    LITERATURE IN THE READER:

    AFFECTIVE STYLISTICS

    129

    makes

    mmediate

    ense. To

    my

    mind,

    however,

    hat s

    interesting

    about the

    utterance

    s

    the sub rosa

    message

    t

    puts

    out

    by

    virtue

    f

    itseasycomprehensibility.ecause t gives nformationirectlynd

    simply,

    t

    asserts

    silently,

    ut

    effectively)

    he

    givability ,irectly

    nd

    simply,

    f

    nformation;

    nd t

    s

    thus

    s

    extension

    f he

    rdering

    pera-

    tion

    we

    perform

    n

    experience

    hen

    ever

    t

    is

    filtered

    hrough

    ur

    temporal-spatial

    onsciousness.n

    short

    t makes

    ense,

    n

    exactly

    he

    way

    we make

    i.e.,

    manufacture)

    ense

    f

    whatever,

    f

    anything,

    xists

    outside

    s;

    and

    by

    making

    asy

    ense

    t tells

    s

    that ense an be

    easily

    made

    and thatwe

    are

    capable

    of

    easily

    making

    t.

    A

    whole

    document

    consisting

    f such

    utterances-a

    hemistry

    ext

    r a

    telephone

    ook-

    willbetellings that llthe ime; ndthat, ather han nyreportable

    content,

    ill

    be its

    meaning.

    uch

    anguage

    an be

    called

    ordinary

    only

    ecause t

    confirmsnd

    reflects

    ur

    ordinary

    nderstanding

    f

    the

    world nd our

    position

    n

    it;

    but for

    precisely

    hat

    reason t

    is

    extra-

    ordinary

    unless

    we

    accept

    naive

    epistemology

    hich

    grants

    s un-

    mediated ccess

    o

    reality)

    nd

    to

    eave

    t

    unanalyzed

    s to

    risk

    missing

    much

    f

    what

    happens-to

    us

    and

    through

    s-when we

    readand

    (or

    so we

    think)

    nderstand.

    In

    short,

    he

    problem

    s

    simply

    hat

    most

    methods

    f

    nalysis

    perate

    at sohigh level fabstractionhat hebasicdataofthemeaningx-

    perience

    s

    slighted

    nd/or

    bscured.

    n the rea of

    pecifically

    iterary

    studies,

    he

    effects

    f a naive

    theory

    f

    utterance

    meaning

    nd

    of

    its

    attendant

    ssumption

    f

    ordinary

    anguage

    can

    be

    seen

    in

    what

    is

    acknowledged

    o

    be

    the

    orry

    tate f

    thecriticism

    f

    the

    novel nd

    of

    prose

    n

    general.

    This

    s

    usually

    xplained

    with eference

    o

    a distinc-

    tion

    between

    rose

    nd

    poetry,

    hich

    s

    actually

    distinctionetween

    ordinary

    anguage

    nd

    poetic

    anguage.

    Poetry,

    t is

    asserted,

    s

    char-

    acterized

    y

    a

    high

    ncidence

    f

    deviance

    rom

    ormal

    yntactical

    nd

    lexical abits.tthereforeffershe nalyst-criticgreatmany ointsf

    departure.

    rose,

    n the ther and

    except

    or

    Baroque

    ccentrics

    ike

    Thomas

    Browne nd

    James

    Joyce)

    s, well,

    ust

    prose,

    nd

    just

    there.

    It

    is

    this

    helplessness

    efore

    ll

    but

    themost

    pectacular

    ffects

    hat

    would

    remedy;

    lthough

    n

    one

    way

    the

    two

    examples

    ithwhich

    his

    essay

    egan

    were

    badly

    hosen,

    ince

    hey

    were

    nalyses

    f utterances

    thatare

    obviously

    nd

    problematically

    eviant.

    This,

    of

    course,

    was

    a

    ploy

    o

    gain

    your

    ttention.

    ssuming

    hat now

    have

    t,

    et

    me

    n-

    sist

    that

    the

    method

    hows

    o

    best

    advantage

    when

    t is

    applied

    to

    unpromising aterial.Consider orexample his entenceactually

    part

    of a

    sentence)

    rom

    ater's

    Conclusion

    o The

    Renaissance,

    which,

    while t

    s

    hardly

    he tuff

    f

    everyday

    onversation,

    oes

    not,

    t

    first

    ight,

    fford

    much

    cope

    for

    he

    ritic's

    nalytical

    kill:

    That clear

    perpetual

    utline

    f face and limb

    s

    but an

    image

    of ours.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    9/41

    130

    NEW LITERARY

    HISTORY

    What can one

    say

    about a sentence ike this? The

    analyst

    of

    style

    would,

    I

    fear,

    find

    t

    distressingly

    traightforward

    nd

    non-deviant,

    simple declarativeof the form X is Y. And if he were by chance

    drawn

    to

    it,

    he

    would not be

    likely

    o

    pay

    very

    much attention

    o

    the

    firstword- That. It is

    simply

    here. But

    of

    course

    t is not

    simply

    there;

    t

    is

    actively

    here,

    oing something,

    nd

    what

    that

    something

    s

    can

    be discovered

    y asking

    he

    question

    what does t

    do? The answer

    is

    obvious,

    right

    here

    n

    front

    f

    our

    noses,

    lthough

    we

    may

    not

    see

    it

    untilwe ask the

    question.

    That

    is

    a

    demonstrative,

    word

    that

    points

    out,

    and

    as

    one takes t

    in,

    a sense

    of its

    referent

    yet

    unidentified)

    s

    established. Whatever that

    is,

    t s

    outside,

    t a distance

    from he

    ob-

    server-reader;t is pointable to (pointing s what theword that

    does),

    something

    f substance and

    solidity.

    In

    terms

    of

    the

    reader's

    response,

    that

    generates

    n

    expectation

    hat

    mpels

    him

    forward,

    he

    expectation

    f

    finding

    ut

    what

    that is. The word and its

    effect re

    the basic data of the

    meaning

    experience

    nd

    they

    will

    direct

    our

    de-

    scription

    f that

    experience

    ecause

    they

    direct

    he reader.

    The

    adjective

    clear

    works

    n

    two

    ways;

    it

    promises

    he reader

    that when

    that

    appears,

    he will

    be able

    to

    see

    it

    easily,

    nd,

    converse-

    ly,

    that

    it

    can be

    easily

    seen.

    Perpetual

    stabilizes

    he

    visibility

    f

    that evenbeforet s seen and outline gives tpotential orm,while

    at

    the ame

    time

    raising

    question.

    That

    question-outline

    of

    what?-

    is

    obligingly

    nswered

    by

    the

    phrase

    of

    face and

    limb,

    which,

    n

    ef-

    fect,

    ills he outline

    n.

    By

    the time

    the reader reaches

    the declarative

    verb is -which

    sets

    the

    seal

    on the

    objectivereality

    f what has

    pre-

    ceded

    it-he

    is

    fully

    nd

    securely

    riented

    n

    a world

    of

    perfectly

    is-

    cerned

    objects

    and

    perfectly

    iscerning

    bservers,

    f whom

    he is one.

    But then

    the sentence

    urns

    n

    the

    reader,

    nd takes

    away

    the world

    t

    has

    itself reated.

    With

    but

    the

    easy progress

    hrough

    he sentence

    is impeded (it is a splitsecondbeforeone realizes that but has the

    force of

    only )

    ;

    the

    declarative

    force of is

    is

    weakened

    and

    the

    status

    of the

    firmly

    rawn

    outline he

    reader has been

    pressured

    o ac-

    cept

    is

    suddenly

    uncertain;

    image

    resolves

    that

    uncertainty,

    ut

    in

    the direction

    f

    insubstantiality;

    nd the now blurredform

    disap-

    pears

    altogether

    when the

    phrase

    of

    ours

    collapses

    the

    distinction

    between

    he reader

    nd that

    which s

    (or

    was)

    without

    Pater's

    own

    word).

    Now

    you

    see

    it

    (that),

    now

    you

    don't. Pater

    giveth

    nd

    Pater

    taketh

    away.

    (Again

    this

    description

    f the reader's

    experience

    s

    an analysisof the sentence'smeaningand if you were to ask, but,

    what does

    it mean?

    I would

    simply epeat

    the

    description.)

    What is true

    of

    this entence

    s

    true,

    believe,

    of

    much

    of what

    we

    hold ourselves

    responsible

    for

    as

    criticsand teachers of literature.

    There is

    more to

    it,

    that

    s,

    to

    its

    experience,

    han

    meets

    he casual

    eye.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    10/41

    LITERATURE IN THE READER: AFFECTIVE

    STYLISTICS

    131

    What

    is

    required

    hen

    s

    a

    method,

    machine

    f

    you

    will,

    which

    n its

    operation

    makes

    observable,

    r

    at

    least

    accessible,

    what

    goes

    on below

    the level ofself-consciousesponse. Everyonewould admitthat some-

    thing

    funny happens

    n

    the

    Judas

    sentence

    from

    Browne's

    Religio

    Medici

    and that there

    s

    a

    difficulty

    uilt into the

    reading

    and under-

    standing

    of the

    ine

    from

    Paradise

    Lost;

    but

    there s a

    tendency

    o as-

    sume that the Pater sentence

    s

    a

    simple

    assertion

    whatever

    that

    s).

    It

    is of

    course,

    nothing

    f

    the

    kind.

    In fact t

    is

    not

    an assertion

    t

    all,

    although the

    promise

    f)

    an

    assertions one

    of

    ts

    components.

    t

    is

    an

    experience;

    t

    occurs;

    it does

    something;

    t makes us

    do

    something.

    Indeed,

    I

    would

    go

    so far as to

    say,

    n direct ontradiction

    f

    Wimsatt-

    Beardsley,hatwhat tdoes s what tmeans.

    The

    Logic

    and Structure of

    Response

    II.

    What

    I

    am

    suggesting

    s that

    there

    s no direct

    relationship

    etween

    the

    meaning

    of

    a sentence

    (paragraph,

    novel,

    poem)

    and what its

    words

    mean.

    Or,

    to

    put

    the matter ess

    provocatively,

    he nformation

    an

    utterance

    ives,

    ts

    message,

    s a

    constituent

    f,

    but

    certainly

    ot

    to

    be

    identified

    with,

    ts

    meaning.

    It is the

    experience

    f an utterance-

    all

    of

    it and

    not

    anything

    hat could be

    said about

    it,

    includingany-

    thing

    could

    say--that

    s

    ts

    meaning.

    It

    follows,

    hen,

    hat t is

    impossible

    o mean the same

    thing

    n two

    (or

    more)

    different

    ays,

    although

    we tend to

    think hat

    it

    happens

    all the

    time. We

    do this

    by

    substituting

    or our

    immediate

    inguistic

    experience

    n

    interpretation

    r abstraction f

    it,

    in which it is

    in-

    evitably ompromised.

    We contrive

    o

    forget

    what has

    happened

    to us

    in our ifewith anguage,removing urselves s faras possiblefrom he

    linguistic

    vent before

    making

    a statement

    bout

    it.

    Thus

    we

    say,

    for

    example,

    that

    the book

    of the

    father and

    the

    father's

    book

    mean

    the same

    thing, forgetting

    hat

    father and book

    occupy

    different

    ositions

    of

    emphasis

    in

    our

    different

    xperiences;

    and as

    we

    progress

    n

    this

    forgetting,

    e become

    capable

    of

    believing

    hat

    sen-

    tences

    s

    differents these

    re

    equivalent

    n

    meaning:

    This fact

    s

    concealed

    by

    the

    nfluence

    f

    anguage,

    moulded

    by

    science,

    which oistsn usexactconcepts

    s

    though hey epresented

    he

    mmediate

    deliverances

    f

    experience.

    A. N. Whitehead

    And

    ifwe continue o

    dwell

    n

    thought

    n this

    world,

    not of

    objects

    n

    the

    olidity

    ithwhich

    anguage

    nvests

    hem,

    ut of

    mpressions,

    nstable,

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    11/41

    132

    NEW

    LITERARY

    HISTORY

    flickering,

    nconsistent,

    hich

    burn

    and are

    extinguished

    ith our

    con-

    sciousness

    f

    them,

    t

    contractstill

    urther.

    Walter

    Pater

    It

    is

    (literally)

    tempting

    o

    say

    that these

    sentences

    make the same

    point:

    that

    anguage

    which

    pretends

    o

    precision perates

    to

    obscure

    the

    flux

    and

    disorder f

    actual

    experience.

    And of

    course

    they

    do,

    if

    one

    considers hem

    t

    a

    high

    enough

    evel

    of

    generality.

    But

    as individ-

    ual

    experiences

    hrough

    which

    a

    reader

    ives,

    they

    re not

    alike

    at

    all,

    and

    neither, herefore,

    re

    their

    meanings.

    To

    take the

    Whitehead

    entence

    irst,

    t

    simply

    oesn'tmean what

    it

    says; for s thereadermovesthrought,he experiences hestability f

    the world

    whose existence

    t

    supposedly

    enies.

    The

    word

    fact itself

    makes

    an

    exact

    concept

    out

    of

    the dea of

    nexactness;

    nd

    by

    referring

    backward to find ts

    referent- the

    radically

    untidy

    ll-adjusted

    har-

    acter

    of...

    experience -the

    reader

    performs

    he characteristic

    ction

    required

    of him

    by

    this

    entence,

    he

    fixing

    f

    things

    n

    their

    place.

    There is

    nothing ntidy

    ither

    n the

    sentence

    r

    in

    our

    experience

    f

    it.

    Each clause is

    logically

    relatedto its

    predecessors

    nd

    prepares

    he

    way

    for what

    follows;

    and

    since

    our active

    attention

    s

    required

    only

    at thepoints frelation, hesentence sdividedbyusintoa succession f

    discrete

    reas,

    each of which s dominated

    by

    the

    anguage

    of

    certainty.

    Even the

    phrase

    as

    though

    they

    represented

    alls

    nto

    this

    category,

    since its

    stress

    falls on

    they

    represented

    which

    then thrusts s

    for-

    ward to the

    waiting

    deliverances f

    experience.

    In

    short,

    he sen-

    tence,

    n

    its action

    upon

    us,

    declares

    the

    tidy

    well-ordered haracter

    f

    actual

    experience,

    nd that

    s ts

    meaning.

    At

    first

    he Pater sentence s

    self-subverting

    n the

    same

    way.

    The

    least

    forcefulword

    in

    its first

    wo

    clauses is

    not,

    which is

    literally

    overwhelmed ythewordsthat urroundt- world, objects, solid-

    ity, language ;

    and

    by

    the timethe readerreaches he

    but

    in

    but

    of

    mpressions,

    e findshimself

    nhabiting

    dwelling n)

    a

    world

    of

    fixed and

    solid

    objects.

    It is of course a world

    made

    up

    of

    words,

    constructed

    n

    large

    part by

    the reader himself

    s he

    performs ram-

    matical

    actions

    which

    reinforce he

    stability

    f its

    phenomena. By

    re-

    ferring

    ackwards from

    them

    to

    objects,

    the reader accords

    ob-

    jects

    a

    place

    in the

    sentence

    whatever

    can

    be referred ack

    to

    must

    be

    somewhere)

    and in his

    mind.

    In the second half of the

    sentence,

    however, his ame world s unbuilt. There is stilla backward

    depen-

    dence to the

    readingexperience,

    ut

    the

    point

    of

    reference

    s

    the word

    impressions ;

    nd the eries

    which

    follows

    t- unstable,

    flickering,

    'inconsistent -serves

    nly

    o accentuate ts

    nstability.

    ike

    Whitehead,

    Pater

    perpetrates

    he

    verydeception

    he is

    warning against;

    but

    this s

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    12/41

    LITERATURE

    IN

    THE

    READER:

    AFFECTIVE

    STYLISTICS

    133

    only

    one

    part

    of

    his

    strategy.

    The other s to break down

    (extinguish)

    the

    coherenceof

    the

    illusion

    he has

    created.

    Each successive

    tage

    of

    thesentence s less exact (in Whitehead'sterms)than itspredecessors,

    because

    at

    each successive

    tage

    the reader

    s

    given

    ess

    and

    less to

    hold

    on

    to;

    and when

    the

    corporeality

    f this

    world

    has

    wasted

    away

    to

    an it

    ( it

    contracts

    till

    further ),

    he is

    left

    with

    nothing

    t

    all.

    One could

    say,

    suppose,

    hatat

    the east

    these wo

    sentences

    esture

    toward

    the same

    insight;

    but even this

    minimal statement

    makes

    me

    uneasy,

    because

    insight

    s

    anotherword that

    mplies

    there

    t

    is,

    I've

    got

    it. And this s

    exactly

    he difference etween the

    two

    sentences:

    Whitehead

    lets

    you

    get

    it

    ( the

    neat, trim,

    tidy,

    exact

    world ),

    while Pater gives you the experienceof having it meltunder your

    feet.

    It

    is

    only

    when one

    steps

    back

    from

    the sentences

    hat

    they

    are

    in

    any

    way

    equivalent;

    and

    stepping

    ack

    is what

    an

    analysis

    n

    terms

    of

    doing

    and

    happenings

    does

    not allow.

    The

    analysis

    of

    the Pater sentence llustrates

    notherfeatureof the

    method,

    ts

    independence

    of

    linguistic

    ogic.

    If

    a casual reader

    were

    asked

    to

    point

    out the

    most

    important

    word

    in

    the second clause-

    not of

    objects

    n

    the

    solidity

    with which

    anguage

    invests

    hem -he

    would

    probably

    answer

    not,

    because as a

    logical

    marker not

    controls verythinghat follows t. But as one component n an ex-

    perience,

    t is

    hardly ontrolling

    t

    all;

    for

    as the

    clause

    unfolds,

    not

    has less

    and

    less

    a claim on our attention nd

    memories;

    working gainst

    it,

    and

    finally

    verwhelming

    t,

    as we

    saw,

    is

    an

    unbroken uccession

    f

    more

    forcefulwords.

    My

    point

    of course

    s

    that

    n an

    analysis

    of the

    sentence

    s a

    thing

    n

    itself,

    onsisting

    f

    words

    arranged

    n

    syntacto-

    logical relationships,

    not would

    figure

    rominently,

    hile in

    an

    ex-

    periential

    nalysis

    t is noted

    chiefly

    or ts weakness.

    The

    case

    is

    even clearer

    and

    perhaps

    more

    interesting

    n this sen-

    tencefrom neofDonne's sermons:

    And

    therefore,

    s

    the

    mysteries

    f our

    religions

    re

    not

    the

    objects

    of

    our

    reason,

    ut

    by

    faithwe

    rest

    n

    God's

    decree

    nd

    purpose it

    is

    so,

    O

    God,

    because

    t

    s

    thy

    will

    t

    should

    be

    so)

    So

    God's

    decrees

    re ever

    to

    be

    considered

    n

    the

    manifestation

    hereof.

    Here the

    not -again logically

    ontrolling-is

    subverted

    y

    the

    very

    construction

    n

    which

    t s

    mbedded;

    for

    hat

    construction,

    nobtrusive-

    ly,

    but nonethless

    ffectively,ressures

    he reader to

    perform xactlythose mental

    operations

    whose

    propriety

    hestatement f the sentence

    -what it is

    saying-is challenging.

    That

    is,

    a

    paraphrase

    of the

    ma-

    terialbefore he

    parenthesismight

    ead- Matters of faith

    nd

    religion

    are not

    the

    objects

    of

    our

    reason ;

    but the

    simple

    act of

    taking

    n the

    words And therefore

    nvolves

    s

    unavoidably

    n

    reasoning

    bout mat-

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    13/41

    134

    NEW ITERARY

    ISTORY

    ters

    f

    faith nd

    religion;

    n fact

    o

    strong

    s

    the

    pull

    of

    thesewords

    hat

    our

    primary esponse

    o this

    part

    of the

    sentence s

    one of

    anticipation;

    we are waitingfora so clause to completethe logicallybased se-

    quence

    begun by

    And

    therefore

    s.

    But

    when that

    so

    appears,

    t

    is

    not at all what we had

    expected,

    or t s

    the so of divinefiat-it is so

    O

    God because it is

    thy

    will

    it should be so-of

    a

    causality

    more real

    than

    any

    that can be

    observed

    n

    nature or described

    n a natural

    (human)

    language.

    The

    speaker,

    however,

    ompletes

    is

    explaining

    and

    organizing

    statement

    s

    if its silent

    claim

    to be

    a

    window

    on

    reality

    were still

    unquestioned.

    As

    a

    result he reader

    s

    alerted

    o

    the

    inadequacy

    of

    the

    very

    process

    n

    which he

    is

    (through

    the

    syntax)

    involved,and at the same time he accepts the necessity, or limited

    human

    beings,

    of

    proceeding

    within

    he now discredited

    ssumptions

    ofthat

    process.

    Of

    course,

    formalist

    nalysis

    f

    this

    entencewould

    certainly

    ave

    discovered

    the tension

    between the two

    so's,

    one a

    synonym

    or

    therefore,

    he other horthand

    or so be

    it,

    and

    might

    ven have

    gone

    on

    to

    suggest

    hat the

    relationship

    etween

    them

    s

    a mirror f the

    re-

    lationship

    between

    the

    mysteries

    f faith nd

    the

    operations

    f reason.

    I

    doubt, however,

    hat a formalist

    nalysis

    would

    have

    brought

    us

    to

    thepointwherewe could see thesentence, nd themode ofdiscourse

    it

    represents,

    s

    a

    self-deflating

    oke ( thereof

    mocks

    therefore ),

    to

    which the

    reader

    responds

    nd

    of

    whichhe

    is

    a

    victim.

    In

    short,

    nd

    to

    repeat

    myself,

    o consider

    he

    utterances

    part

    from he

    consciousness

    receiving

    t is

    to

    risk

    missing great

    deal of

    what

    is

    going

    on.

    It is a

    risk

    which

    analysis

    n

    terms of

    doings

    and

    happenings

    works

    to

    minimize.

    Another

    dvantage

    of the method s its

    ability

    o deal

    with

    entences

    (and works)

    that

    don't

    mean

    anything,

    n

    the sense of not

    makingsense.

    Literature,

    t is oftenremarked

    either

    n

    praise

    or with con-

    tempt)

    is

    largely

    made

    up

    of

    such utterances.

    It

    is an

    interesting

    om-

    mentboth

    on

    Dylan

    Thomas

    and the

    proponents

    f

    a

    deviation

    heory

    of

    poetic

    language

    that

    their

    examples

    so

    often

    are taken from

    his

    work.)

    In

    an

    experiential

    analysis,

    the

    sharp

    distinction

    etween

    sense and

    nonsense,

    with the attendant value

    judgments

    and

    the

    talk

    about truth

    ontent,

    s

    blurred,

    because the

    place

    where sense

    is

    made

    or

    not

    made

    is

    the reader's mind rather han the

    printedpage

    or the space betweenthe covers of a book. For an example,I turn

    once

    again,

    and forthe last

    time,

    to Pater.

    This

    at

    leastof

    flame-like,

    ur life

    has,

    that t is but the

    concurrence,

    5

    I borrow this

    phrase

    from

    P.

    W.

    Bridgman,

    The

    Way Things

    Are.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    14/41

    LITERATURE IN

    THE

    READER: AFFECTIVE STYLISTICS

    135

    renewed

    from

    moment

    o

    moment,

    f

    forces

    arting

    ooner

    or

    later

    on

    theirways.

    This

    sentence

    deliberately

    rustrates he reader's natural desire

    to

    organize

    the

    particulars

    t offers.

    One

    can

    see

    for

    nstance

    how

    dif-

    ferent ts

    experience

    would be if

    concurrences f forces were sub-

    stituted or

    concurrence,

    enewed rom

    moment o

    moment,

    f forces.

    The

    one

    allows and

    encourages

    he formation f

    a

    physical

    mage

    which

    has a

    spatial

    reality;

    the mind

    imagines

    (pictures)

    separate

    and

    dis-

    tinctforces

    onverging,

    n an

    orderly

    ashion,

    n

    a

    centerwhere

    they

    form

    new,

    but

    still

    recognizable

    nd

    managable

    (in

    a

    mental

    sense),

    force;the otherdeterminedlyrevents hat image fromforming. e-

    fore the

    reader

    can

    respond fully

    o

    concurrence,

    renewed

    stops

    him

    by making

    the

    temporal

    status

    of

    the

    motion unclear. Has the

    concurrence

    lready

    taken

    place?

    Is

    it

    taking place

    now?

    Although

    frommoment

    o moment answersthese

    questions,

    t does

    so at the

    expense

    of the

    assumptions

    ehind

    them;

    the

    phrase

    eaves no

    time for

    anything

    o

    formal

    nd chartable s a

    process.

    For

    a

    moment,

    t

    of

    forces,

    here s a

    coming together;

    but

    in

    the

    next

    moment,

    he

    moment when

    the

    reader takes

    in

    parting,

    they

    separate.

    Or

    do

    they? sooner or later upsetsthis new attempt o findpatternand

    direction

    n

    our

    life

    and

    the

    reader s

    once more

    disoriented,

    patial-

    ly

    and

    temporally.

    The final deterrent o order s the

    plural

    ways,

    which

    prevents

    he

    mind's

    eye

    from

    ravelling

    own a

    singlepath

    and

    insistson the

    haphazardness

    and randomness

    of

    whatever

    t is that

    happens

    ooner r

    ater.

    Of

    coursethis

    reading

    of

    the

    sentence

    that

    is,

    of its

    effects)

    gnores

    its status

    s

    a

    logical

    utterance.

    Concurrence,

    enewed

    frommoment

    to

    moment,

    f

    forces s

    meaningless

    s a statement

    orresponding

    o

    a

    state of affairs n the real world; but its refusalto mean in that

    discursive

    way

    creates

    he

    experience

    hat s

    its

    meaning;

    and an

    analy-

    sis

    of

    that

    experience

    rather

    than of

    logical

    content s able

    to

    make

    sense

    of one

    kind-experiential

    ense-out

    of nonsense.

    A

    similar

    and

    saving) operation

    can

    be

    performed

    n units

    arger

    than

    the sentence.

    One

    of

    Plato's

    more

    problematical

    ialogues

    s

    the

    Phaedrus,

    n

    part

    because

    its

    final assertion- no

    work

    .

    .

    . has

    ever

    been

    written

    r

    recited hat

    s

    worthy

    f serious attention -seems

    to

    be

    contradicted

    y

    its

    very

    existence.

    This embarrasment has

    been

    the cause of a

    great

    many

    articles,

    ftenentitled The

    Unity

    of the

    Phaedrus,

    in

    which the

    offending

    ection s somehow

    accounted

    for,

    usually

    by explaining

    t

    away.

    What

    these tudies

    ttempt

    o discover

    s

    the nternal

    nity

    f the

    Phaedrus,

    ts coherence

    s a self-contained

    rti-

    fact;

    but

    if we look

    for the coherenceof

    the

    dialogue

    in the reader's

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    15/41

    136

    NEW LITERARY

    HISTORY

    experience

    f

    it rather

    han n

    its

    formal

    tructure,

    he

    inconsistency

    is

    less a

    problem

    to be

    solved

    than

    something

    hat

    happens,

    a fact of

    response;and as a fact of response t is thekeyto theway thework

    works.

    Rather than a

    single

    sustained

    argument,

    he Phaedrus

    is

    a

    series

    of

    discrete

    onversations

    r

    seminars,

    ach

    with

    ts

    own

    carefully

    posed

    question,

    nsuing

    discussion

    nd

    firmly

    rawn

    conclusion;

    but so

    arranged

    that to enter nto

    the

    spirit

    and

    assumptions

    f

    any

    one

    of

    these

    self-enclosed nits

    s

    implicitly

    o

    reject

    the

    spirit

    and

    assump-

    tions

    of

    the unit

    mmediately

    receding.

    This is a

    pattern

    which can be

    clearly

    llustrated

    y

    the

    relationship

    etween he

    speech

    of

    Lysias

    and

    the first

    peech

    delivered

    by

    Socrates.

    Lysias'

    speech

    is

    criticized or

    notconformingo the definition fa good discourse: everydiscourse,

    like

    a

    living

    creature,

    hould be so

    put together

    hat

    it

    has

    its

    own

    body

    and

    lacks

    neither

    ead

    nor

    feet,

    middle nor

    extremities,

    ll com-

    posed

    in

    such a

    way

    that

    they

    uit

    both

    each

    other

    and the

    whole. 6

    Socrates,

    n

    fact,

    s

    quite

    careful

    to rule out

    any

    other

    standard

    of

    judgment:

    it is the

    arrangement

    rather

    than the invention

    or

    relevance that concerns

    him

    as

    a critic.

    Subsequently,

    ocrates

    own effort

    n the

    same theme s criticized or

    ts

    mpiety,

    n

    impiety,

    moreover,

    hat

    is

    compounded by

    its

    effectiveness

    s

    a

    piece

    of rhe-

    toric. In otherwords,Lysias' speech s bad because itis not well put

    together

    nd

    Socrates'

    speech

    s bad because it

    is

    well

    put

    together.

    Although

    neither

    Socrates nor

    Phaedrus

    acknowledges

    the

    con-

    tradiction,

    he

    reader,

    who

    has fallen

    n

    (perhaps

    involuntarily)

    with

    thestandards f

    udgment

    stablished

    y

    the

    philosopher

    imself,

    s

    cer-

    tainly

    onfronted ith

    t,

    and asked

    implicitly

    o

    do

    something

    with t.

    What he

    does

    (or

    should

    do)

    is

    realize that

    in

    the condemnation f

    Socrates'

    speech

    a new standard

    (of

    impiety)

    has been

    introduced,

    one

    that invalidatesthe

    very

    basis on

    which

    the

    discussion

    and

    his

    reading experience) had hitherto een preceding. At that moment,

    this

    early

    section

    of the

    dialogue

    will

    have

    achieved

    its true

    purpose,

    which

    is,

    paradoxically,

    o

    bring

    the reader to

    the

    point

    where

    he

    is

    no

    longer

    nterested

    n

    the issues t

    treats;

    no

    longer

    nterested

    ecause

    he has come

    to

    see

    thatthe real ssues

    xist t a

    higher

    evel of

    generality.

    Thus,

    in

    a

    way peculiar

    to

    dialectical form

    nd

    experience,

    his

    pace

    of

    prose

    and

    argument

    will have been the

    vehicle of

    its own

    abandon-

    ment.

    Nor is

    that

    by any

    means the end of

    the

    matter. This

    pattern,

    n

    whichthe reader s first

    ncouraged

    to entertain

    ssumptions

    e

    prob-

    ably

    already

    holds

    and

    then is later

    forced to

    re-examine

    nd

    dis-

    credit

    hose ame

    assumptions,

    s

    repeated

    gain

    and

    again.

    In

    the

    mid-

    6 Ed.

    W.

    C.

    Helmbold

    and

    W.

    G.

    Rabinowitz

    (New

    York,

    1956), p.

    53.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    16/41

    LITERATURE IN

    THE

    READER: AFFECTIVE STYLISTICS

    137

    dle

    section

    of

    the

    dialogue,

    the two friends

    gree

    to

    explore

    the

    sub-

    ject

    of

    good

    and bad

    writing;

    and Socrates

    argues against

    the

    sophistposition hat an orator may neglectwhat is really good . . .

    for t is from

    what seems to be true that

    persuasion

    comes,

    not

    from

    the

    real

    truth

    p.

    46).

    It

    is

    essential,

    ounters

    ocrates,

    for

    a

    com-

    petent

    speaker

    to know the truth

    bout all

    things

    nd

    subjects,

    for

    unless he

    does,

    and

    here the

    reader

    anticipates

    ome

    kind of

    equation

    between

    good

    writing

    nd a

    concernfor he truth-he will

    be

    unable

    to

    deceive

    ( When

    a man sets out

    to

    deceive someone

    else without

    being

    taken in

    himself,

    e

    must

    accurately

    grasp

    the

    similarity

    nd

    dissimi-

    larity

    of the

    facts ).

    While art

    and truth

    have

    been

    joined

    in one

    context-the ruthlessly ractical contextof manipulativerhetoric-a

    wedge

    has been drivenbetween them

    in

    another-the

    moral context

    assumed at

    the

    beginning

    f

    the

    discussion.

    To

    the earlier

    nsight

    hat

    a well-made

    speech

    is not

    necessarily

    true

    speech

    (in

    the moral

    sense),

    the reader must now add the further

    and extending)

    nsight

    that well-madeness s

    likely

    o

    be a

    weapon

    in

    the arsenal

    of Truth's

    enemies.

    So

    that

    what was at

    first tandardof

    udgment

    o

    which

    Soc-

    rates,

    Phaedrus

    and the

    reader

    repaired,

    s

    now seen

    to be

    positively

    deleterious o the

    higher

    tandard now

    only graduallyemerging

    rom

    thedialogue.

    The

    important

    word in

    my

    last sentence s

    seen ;

    for

    it

    suggests

    that what

    is

    being

    processed

    by

    the Phaedrus

    is not an

    argument

    r a

    proposition,

    ut

    a vision. As

    an

    argument,

    n

    fact,

    he

    dialogue

    makes

    no

    sense,

    since Socrates

    is

    continually

    eaching

    conclusionswhich

    he

    subsequently,

    nd

    without

    omment,

    bandons.

    But

    as an

    attempt

    o

    refine

    ts

    reader's

    vision

    t

    makes a

    great

    deal

    of

    sense;

    for then the

    contradictions,

    he moments

    of

    blurring,

    become

    invitations

    o ex-

    amine

    closely

    remises

    oo

    easily

    cquiesced

    n. The readerwho

    accepts

    this invitationwill find,on retracinghis steps,that statements nd

    phrases

    which had

    seemed

    unexceptionable

    re

    now

    suspect

    and

    du-

    bious;

    and

    that ines of

    reasoning

    which

    had seemed

    proper

    nd

    to

    the

    point

    are

    now

    disastrously

    arrow.

    Of course

    they-phrases,

    state-

    ments,

    premises

    and conclusions-haven't

    changed

    (as

    Socrates

    re-

    marks

    ater,

    written

    words

    .

    go

    on

    telling

    you

    the same

    thing

    over

    and

    over ),

    the reader

    has,

    and with

    each

    change

    he is able

    to

    dis-

    pense

    with whatever ection

    of

    the

    dialogue

    he has been

    reading,

    be-

    cause

    he has

    passed

    beyond

    the level

    of

    perception

    t

    respresents.

    To read the

    Phaedrus,

    then,

    s to use it

    up;

    for the value of

    any

    point

    n

    it is that

    t

    gets

    you

    (not

    any

    sustained

    rgument)

    to the next

    point,

    which s

    not so

    much

    a

    point

    (in logical-demonstrative

    erms)

    as

    a

    level

    of

    insight.

    t is thusa

    self-consuming

    rtifact,

    mimetic

    nact-

    ment n the reader's

    experience

    of the Platonic ladder in which each

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    17/41

    138

    NEW LITERARY

    HISTORY

    rung,

    s

    it

    is

    negotiated,

    s

    kicked

    away.

    The final

    rung,

    he

    intuition

    which

    stands

    (or,

    more

    properly,

    n

    which the reader

    stands),

    be-

    cause it is thelast, s of course the rejectionof written rtifacts, re-

    jection

    that far

    from

    ontradicting

    hat has

    preceded,

    s

    an

    exact de-

    scription

    f

    what the

    reader,

    n

    his

    repeated

    abandoning

    of

    successive

    stages

    n

    the

    argument,

    as

    been

    doing.

    What

    was

    problematical

    ense

    in

    the structure

    f

    a self-enclosed

    rgument,

    makes

    perfect

    ense

    n the

    structure

    f

    the

    reader's

    xperience.

    The Phaedrus s a radical criticism f the dea of internal oherence

    from

    a

    moral

    point

    of

    view;

    by

    identifying

    he

    appeal

    of

    well-put-

    together

    rtifacts iththe

    sense

    of

    order

    n the

    perceiving

    i.e.,

    receiv-

    ing) mind, tprovides strong rgument or hebanishing f thegood

    poet

    who is

    potentially

    he

    good

    deceiver.

    We can

    put

    aside the

    moral

    issue and still

    profit

    rom

    he

    dialogue;

    for

    f

    the

    laws

    of

    beginning,

    middle,

    and end

    are laws of

    psychology

    ather

    han form

    or

    truth),

    a

    criticism

    hich has as its

    focus

    the

    structural

    ntegrity

    f the artifact s

    obviously

    misdirected.

    It

    is

    the

    experience

    f

    works,

    not

    worksthat

    have

    beginnings,

    middles,

    nd

    ends.)

    A new look

    at

    the

    question

    may

    result

    n

    the rehabilitation f

    works

    ike

    The

    Faerie

    Queene

    which

    have

    been

    criticized

    because their

    poetic

    worlds lack

    unity

    and

    consis-

    tency. And a new look at thequestionmayresult lso in a more ac-

    curate account

    of

    workswhose formal

    features re so

    prominent

    hat

    the critic

    proceedsdirectly

    rom

    hemto

    a

    statement f

    meaning

    with-

    out

    bothering

    o

    ask whether

    heir

    high

    visibility

    as

    any

    direct rela-

    tionship

    o

    their

    operation

    n the

    reader's

    experience.

    This

    analysis

    f

    the Phaedrus

    lllustrates,

    ot

    incidentally,

    he

    ability

    of the method

    to handle units

    arger

    than the

    sentence.

    Whatever

    he

    size of

    the

    unit,

    he focus

    of

    the method

    remains he

    reader's

    xperience

    of

    it,

    and the mechanism f the method

    s

    the

    magic question,

    what

    does this do?

    Answering

    t of course s more difficulthan it

    would

    be for a

    single

    entence. More

    variables

    creep

    n,

    more

    respon-

    ses

    and

    more

    different inds of

    responses

    have to

    be

    kept

    track

    of;

    there re

    more contextswhich

    regulate

    nd

    modulate he

    temporal

    low

    of the

    reading

    experience.

    Some of

    these

    problems

    will

    be considered

    below.

    For the

    present

    et

    me

    say

    that

    have

    usually

    foundthat

    what

    might

    e

    called the basic

    experience

    f

    a work

    do

    not

    read basic

    mean-

    ing)

    occurs

    at

    every

    evel. As an

    example,

    we

    might

    onsider,

    riefly,

    The

    Pilgrim'srogress.

    At one

    point

    n

    Bunyan's prose

    epic,

    Christian

    sks

    a

    question

    and

    receives

    n

    answer:

    7

    See

    Paul

    Alpers,

    The

    Poetry of

    The Faerie

    Queene (Princeton,

    1967),

    where

    exactly

    this

    point

    is

    made.

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    18/41

    LITERATURE IN

    THE

    READER: AFFECTIVE

    STYLISTICS

    139

    Chr. Is this he

    way

    to

    the

    Celestial

    City?

    Shep. You are ust n yourway.

    The

    question

    s asked in

    the

    contextof certain

    ssumptions

    bout

    the

    world,

    the

    stability

    f

    objects

    n

    it,

    the

    possibility

    f

    knowing,

    n

    terms

    of

    measurable

    distances nd

    locatable

    places,

    where

    you

    are;

    but the

    answer while it

    is

    perfectly

    atisfactory

    ithin

    that assumed

    context,

    also

    challenges

    t, or,

    to

    be more

    precise,

    forces he reader to

    challenge

    it

    by

    forcing

    im to

    respond

    to the

    pun

    on the word

    just.

    The

    in-

    escapability

    f the

    pun

    reflects

    ackward on

    the

    question

    nd the

    world

    view

    it

    supports;

    and it

    gestures

    oward another

    world

    view

    in

    which

    spatial configurationsave moral and innermeanings, nd being n the

    way

    is

    independent

    f

    the

    way

    you happen

    to

    be in. That

    is,

    if

    Chris-

    tian

    s

    to

    be

    truly

    n

    the

    way,

    the

    way

    must

    first e

    in

    him,

    and thenhe

    will

    be

    in

    it,

    no matter

    where-in

    what

    merely hysical

    way-he

    is.

    All

    of

    this

    s

    meant,

    hat

    s

    experienced,

    n the reader's

    ncounterwith

    just

    which s

    a comment ot

    only

    n

    Christian

    or

    sking

    he

    question,

    but on

    the reader for

    aking

    t

    seriously,

    hat

    s,

    simply.

    What has

    hap-

    pened

    to the

    reader

    n

    this

    brief

    pace

    is the

    basic

    experience

    f The

    Pilgrim's

    Progress. Again

    and

    again

    he

    settles

    nto

    temporal-spatial

    forms fthought nly obe brought p shortwhentheyproveunable to

    contain

    the

    insights

    f

    Christian aith. The

    many

    evels

    on

    which

    this

    basic

    experience

    occurs

    would be the

    substance

    of

    a

    full

    reading

    of

    The

    Pilgrim'sProgress,

    omething

    he

    world

    will soon

    have,

    whether

    it

    wants t or

    not.

    The

    method, hen,

    s

    applicable

    to

    larger

    units

    and

    its chiefcharac-

    teristics

    emain

    he

    same:

    (I)

    it refuses

    o

    answer

    or

    even ask

    the

    ques-

    tion,

    what is

    this

    work

    about;

    (2)

    it

    yields

    an

    analysis

    not

    of

    formal

    features,

    ut

    of

    the

    developing responses

    f the reader

    in

    relationto

    the wordsas they ucceedone another n time; (3) the resultwill be a

    description

    f

    the structure

    f

    response

    which

    may

    have

    an

    oblique

    or

    even

    (as

    in

    the

    case

    of The

    Pilgrim's

    Progress),

    a

    contrasting

    elation-

    ship

    to

    the

    structure f

    the

    work as

    a

    thing

    n itself.

    The Affective

    allacy Fallacy

    III.

    In the

    precedingages

    have

    argued

    hecase

    for method

    f

    analysis

    whichfocuseson the readerrather han on the

    artifact,

    nd in what

    remains

    f this

    ssay

    would

    like

    to consider ome

    of

    the

    more obvious

    objections

    to that

    method. The

    chief

    objection,

    of

    course,

    s that

    af-

    fective riticism

    eads

    one

    away

    from

    he

    thing

    tself n all its

    solidity

    to

    the

    nchoate

    mpressions

    f

    a

    variable

    and variousreader.

    This

    argu-

    This content downloaded by the authorized user from 192.168.82.206 on Thu, 15 Nov 2012 01:07:47 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 8/21/2019 468593 Stanley Fish

    19/41

    140

    NEW LITERARY HISTORY

    ment

    has

    several

    imensions

    o

    it,

    and

    will

    require

    multi-directional

    answer.

    First, hecharge fimpressionismas beenanswered, hope,by

    someof

    my ample nalyses.

    f

    anything,

    he

    discriminations

    equired

    and

    yielded

    y

    the

    method

    re

    too fine or

    ven hemost

    nalytical

    f

    tastes.This

    s

    in

    large

    part

    because

    n

    the

    category

    f

    response

    in-

    clude

    not

    only

    tears,

    rickles,

    nd

    other

    sychologicalymptoms, 8

    but

    all the

    precise

    mental

    perations

    nvolved

    n

    reading, ncluding

    theformulationf

    complete

    houghts,

    he

    performing

    and

    regretting)

    of

    acts

    of

    udgment,

    he

    following

    nd

    making

    f

    logical

    equences;

    and also because

    my

    nsistencen

    the cumulative

    ressures

    f

    the

    reading xperienceuts estrictionsnthepossible esponsesoa word

    or a

    phrase.

    The

    larger

    bjection

    emains. ven

    fthe

    reader's

    esponses

    an be

    described ith

    ome

    precision, hy

    bother

    with

    hem,

    ince

    he more

    palpable objectivity

    f

    the

    text

    s

    immediately

    vailable

    the

    poem

    itself,

    s an

    object

    f

    pecifically

    ritical

    ulgment,

    ends

    o

    disappear ).

    My

    reply

    o this s

    simple.

    The

    objectivity

    f he

    ext

    s

    an

    illusion,

    nd

    moreover,

    dangerous

    llusion,

    ecause t is so

    physically

    onvincing.

    The

    illusions

    one

    of

    elf-sufficiency

    nd

    completeness.

    line

    of

    print

    or a pageora book s so obviouslyhere-itcan be handled, hoto-

    graphed,

    r

    put

    away-that

    t seems

    o be

    the

    ole

    repository

    f

    what-

    ever

    alue nd

    meaning

    e

    associate

    ith

    t.

    (I

    wish

    he

    pronoun

    ould

    be

    avoided,

    ut n

    a

    way

    t

    makes

    my

    point.)

    This s of

    course heun-

    spoken

    ssumption

    ehind

    he

    word content.

    The line

    or

    page

    or

    book

    contains-everything.

    The

    great

    merit

    from

    his

    oint

    f

    view)

    of

    kinetic

    rt s t