A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    1/28

    Funded by European Research Council7th Framework Programme

    LECTURE

    A POLITICALTHEOLOGYFORACIVILRELIGION

    PAULW. KAHN

    JANUARY2012

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    2/28

    1

    A Political Theology for a Civil Religion

    Paul W. Kahn!

    Mention of political theology often triggers two sorts of worries. Some worry

    about the influence of religious groups on government policy in the United States,

    Christian fundamentalists; in Europe, Muslims. Others, particularly those who know

    the work of Carl Schmitt, worry about authoritarian forms of politics. These are

    certainly legitimate worries in the United States: consider the role of religious groups

    in the Republican primaries or the actions of the Bush administration in response to the

    exceptional circumstances of the war on terror. Both concerns arise out of a felt need

    to defend the liberal institutions of the secular state. Both imagine a point of tension

    between the secular idea of the rule of law and a theological approach to politics. My

    plan today is to question that tension. I want to explore the theological dimensions of

    that most secular of activities, the rule of law. My ambition is not to open up a space

    for sectarianism or authoritarianism, but rather to suggest that it is far too simple to

    address this problem in terms of a secular/theological divide.

    !

    Robert W. Winner Professor of Law and Humanities, and Director

    of the Orville H. Schell, Jr. Center forInternational Human rights at Yale Law School

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    3/28

    2

    For both Americans and Europeans, talk of political theology, instead of

    political theory, has a vaguely anachronistic feel to it. If political theology places a

    good deal of weight on the concept of sovereignty the point from which Schmitt

    began then it runs against the contemporary politics of globalization. Unsurprisingly,

    political theorists and political scientists tell us that sovereignty is a term that we should

    leave behind. Nations are now enmeshed in countless transnational relationships,

    ranging across commerce, policing, finance, communications, migration, climate

    change, humanitarian aid and virtually every other aspect of modern life. Problems in

    each of these domains are to be managed in ways that are transparent and justifiable

    under objective, reasonable norms. Sovereignty points in just the opposite direction: it

    is particular not universal; it is not a matter of justice and not accountable to reason.

    Sovereignty rests on contingent formations of power that are grounded in history, not

    reason. Political theology seems out of place in an era in which democratic politics is

    increasingly displaced by bureaucratic management, and national institutions by

    transnational.

    I will argue that it is too simple to think that the forces of faith, myth and

    irrationality are on one side, and those of the law and reason are on the other.

    Americans continue to live in a political world that rests upon a civil religion. The

    object of their faith is the popular sovereign, which is a transhistorical, collective

    subject. Political theology, as I pursue it, is the theology of this civil religion. At stake

    in the contest between political theology and political theory is not just the continuing

    role of sovereignty, but also the meaning of the rule of law and the nature of political

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    4/28

    3

    violence. Rather than occupying the margins, political theology studies an entire

    political imaginary.

    My plan is to present the nature of this modern political faith. Key

    elements of American legal practice, so puzzling to many Europeans, cannot be

    properly understood without seeing them as embedded in this imaginary. To lend

    concreteness to my interpretation of American practices and beliefs, I will use the

    example of our constitutional debate over the new health care law presently before

    the Supreme Court. In the conclusion, I will briefly consider two recent critiques of my

    work. This will give me an opportunity to say something about the normative

    implications of my pursuit of political theology.

    An American Civil Religion

    No one from abroad can study American constitutional law for long

    without sensing that something is out of place. Our practices of judicial review are

    difficult to reconcile with the dominant ideas of the nature of the modern regulatory

    state or even with contemporary ideas of human rights. Consider our constitutional

    debate over the recently enacted health care reform legislation. What might we want to

    know about this health care plan? Will it actually deliver quality care to everyone at a

    reasonable cost? Will it meet the expectations of patients concerning autonomy and

    choice? Will it be responsive to changes in health care technology? Does it deal fairly

    with those who already have substantial investments in the health care business? If we

    have religious and ethical concerns, we might want to know how the plan deals with

    issues such as end of life care and abortion. None of these issues will be before the

    Court, when it considers the case.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    5/28

    4

    Strikingly, the Court will begin from the commerce clause of the

    Constitution, which grants Congress the power to regulate commerce among the several

    states. Does that grant of regulatory authority include the power to compel an

    individual to purchase health insurance? That is the primary question for the Court.

    This question would not appear to anyone outside of our own practice of constitutional

    law. Indeed, they might question why anyone would locate a question of individual

    liberty in an insurance mechanism, given that every health care delivery system must

    rely upon some form of insurance.

    Notice the shift in the direction of my discourse as I take up the

    constitutional issue. I said that the constitutional issue arises under the commerce

    clause. But to describe the dispute, I have had to shift from the language of commerce

    to that of liberty. How did commerce come to do the work of liberty? Why are we not

    speaking directly of the scope of individual freedom under law, of a right to dignity or

    even of a positive right to health care?

    To understand this peculiar conjunction of commerce and liberty, one has

    to know something about the work of the Supreme Court in the early part of the 20th

    century. That was a story of resistance to the rise of the modern regulatory state.

    Doctrinally, the Court deployed two constitutional provisions the commerce clause

    and the due process clause neither of which speaks directly to the substantive issue of

    liberty. That resistance was often pursued in the name of the individual actually, the

    worker providing for his family but the beneficiary was usually the corporation.

    Some see the same thing today: the beneficiaries of this argument for liberty will be the

    insurance companies, not the individuals left without insurance. No doubt there is

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    6/28

    5

    some of this, but this hardly explains why a majority of voters in Ohio symbolically

    rejected the federal health care law in the last election. For them, something important

    is at stake, and it is not insurance company profits.

    Where we locate an issue of liberty is a function of history, not theory.

    One hundred years ago, it was plausible to locate liberty in the right freely to enter a

    contract: free labor was a political aspiration, as well as a political movement that

    carried much of the nation through the Civil War. By the time of the Depression, it was

    difficult to imagine the labor contract as a site of liberty. At stake in the contract was

    not the power of the worker, but his powerlessness before economic forces that he

    could neither understand nor control. Government regulation was no longer seen in

    opposition to freedom, but as a condition of freedom. The Court, accordingly, changed

    its view: no longer would it strike down regulatory interventions in the market.

    By the early 60s, the site of constitutional liberty had shifted from contract

    to the body. The Court started taking up cases involving sexual autonomy, leading

    ultimately to its famous abortion and, then, gay rights decisions. The critics of these

    decisions often point out the similarity between the Courts early and since repudiated

    decisions in defense of contractual liberty and its defense of sexual liberty today. The

    parallel is indeed there. The point, however, cannot be that the Court should not defend

    liberty.

    The contemporary health care debate is yet another effort to shift the site of

    contested liberty. The new site arises at the intersection of contract and the body. This

    makes little sense apart from these earlier histories of liberty of the body and of

    contract. The doctrinal power of the current question draws from both: does a

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    7/28

    6

    mandatory health insurance policy renew a memory of contract as a site of liberty? does

    the health insurance law draw the subject into a regulatory regime that violates her

    liberty to control the disposition of her own body? To those who never quite accepted

    the New Deal Courts abandonment of contractual liberty, the case offers the ironic

    promise of harnessing the new doctrine of the liberty of the body to the old idea of

    liberty of contract.

    How will the Court go about answering this question of constitutional

    liberty? It will begin with the text itself: Congress has the power to regulate

    commerce . . . among the several states. Some lower courts have concluded that

    regulation of commerce does not include the power to force someone to enter into a

    contractual relationship. Before there can be regulation, there must be commerce.

    Someone who chooses not to purchase insurance is not yet engaged in commerce.

    Accordingly, Congress acted beyond the textual grant of authority. This argument

    repeats one of 100 years ago, when the Court lectured Congress on the distinction

    between commerce and production. Congresss commerce power did not allow it to

    regulate the means or conditions of production. The fact that production affects

    commerce was irrelevant because everything affects commerce. To accept this

    argument from effects would give Congress unlimited authority, and that is

    unacceptable because it would render the words of the Constitution meaningless.

    To this textual argument will be added historical arguments of two sorts.

    First, the court will inquire into the original understanding of the text. Justice Thomas

    will surely raise the issue, asking whether the federal government could force free

    citizens into a contract in 1787 probably not. Second, the Justices will surely

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    8/28

    7

    interrogate the Courts own precedents. The lower courts have been very focused on

    two recent cases in which the Supreme Court insisted on limits on commerce clause

    authority. Those decisions too were taken in the name of individual liberty. Indeed,

    the Court offered an explicit theory linking the clause to individual liberty: liberty is

    advanced by keeping clear the lines of regulatory authority. Not surprisingly, one

    decision involved guns and the other involved sex (actually sex and football): all

    historically contingent sites of liberty in the American imagination.

    A decision against the law would probably be on a 5 to 4 vote. If that

    happens, the Court will likely invoke the original foundation of judicial review, its

    1803 decision of Marbury v. Madison. There, the court claimed that in reading the

    Constitution, it speaks in the voice of the popular sovereign. Despite all that we know

    about the partisan, political backgrounds of the individual Justices, the nation will

    accept whatever the Court concludes. There will be no proposals to amend the

    Constitution, to act in disregard of the decision, or to dismantle the Court. Instead, we

    will see law review articles taking up the doctrinal issue of the meaning of the

    commerce clause and politicians recalibrating political possibilities in light of the

    decision.

    Many elements of our civil religion are on display in my imaginative

    construction of a possible decision. We argue from a text: the Constitution. We have

    an idea of authorship: the popular sovereign. We have a hermeneutic issue: how do we

    interpret this text? We have an issue of authority: why is the Courts interpretation

    final? More deeply, we have the imaginative construction of a free citizen, who is both

    the author and subject of the law.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    9/28

    8

    Begin with the insistent focus on the text itself a text written according to

    18thcentury conventions. Our interpretive practices go so far as actually to consult 18th

    century dictionaries on the meaning of the words. No matter that the sense of a word

    for example, commerce may shift over time to reflect changing popular

    understandings. How can we map a 21stcentury practice of commerce in cyberspace

    on to an 18thcentury concept of commerce as a trade in goods transported by water or

    wagon? It is not even clear that medical care would have been conceived as commerce

    in 18th

    century America perhaps it was more like ministering to the soul.

    Doubts about the rationality of looking to the original meaning are hardly

    new. Yet, the reverence for the text continues. Reverence is exactly the word that

    Lincoln used to describe the relationship of Americans to their constitution. That

    reverence includes what Chief Justice Marshall described in Marbury as a no

    surplusage principle of interpretation: every word of the text must be given a meaning.

    There can be no infelicitous draftsmanship, no needless repetition, no failures to

    communicate. Such fastidious adherence to a text might be justified in statutory

    interpretation as a kind of default position. Congress can always respond when it

    disagrees with the judicial interpretation of a statute. But the constitution is

    extraordinarily difficult to amend. Why privilege archaic text over contemporary

    reasonableness?

    One cannot describe our practices of interpretation without quickly seeing

    the parallel to biblical hermeneutics. We begin with the same puzzle: how do we

    maneuver between a text that has a sacred warrant and the human voice that purports to

    speak for the text. One answer is to move toward a point at which the speaker displays

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    10/28

    9

    no subjectivity. We are not to hear the voice of the interpreter, but only of the text

    itself. The no surplusage rule is one devise for eliminating the subjectivity of the

    reader. In an odd rhetorical play, voice is suppressed and sight is emphasized. The

    reader is simply to look at the text. His will is determined by his sight. Reading

    becomes an act of seeing.

    Often, the argument is put forth that the reason for textualism is to limit the

    judges discretion, which is understood as opening a space for the expression of the

    judges own personality. Just last year, we had an example in the political controversy

    over President Obamas remark that he was looking to nominate Justices who had a

    quality of personal empathy. Empathy is a personality trait that operates where there

    is discretion. The threat seen in a manifest judicial personality is twofold. First, any

    appearance of the judge would pose an unrepresentative claim to power. Lacking a

    democratic warrant, the judge must always appear to subordinate himself to a law

    outside of himself. That much is easy, but it does not explain the horror that the figure

    of the uncontrolled judge evokes in the American imagination. Thus, there is a second

    point, which sounds not in democracy but in heresy. For a judge to appropriate the

    voice of the constitution in order to speak for himself is to speak as a false prophet.

    With reverence always comes a fear of heresy.

    Can we really make use of this prophetic idea to understand American

    constitutionalism? Absolutely. The biblical prophet is not a soothsayer; he is not

    someone who foresees the future. Rather, the prophets role is to call the nation back

    to its sacred origin. That founding carries the meaning of the whole. History is

    imagined as the working out of that original appearance of the sacred. The prophetic

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    11/28

    10

    role, accordingly, is to accuse the society of decline, of failing to remember the

    transcendent, original meaning embodied in the political order. The prophet offers a

    vision of a recovered Jerusalem in order to criticize the pathologies of history.

    The American Supreme Court aims to speak in a prophetic voice. The

    constitutional future is not an open field for construction of the polity. It is rather a

    field for holding forth that which we already are. To play the prophetic role, the Court

    must suppress the particular, contingent character of the Justices. The prophet does not

    have a personal opinion; he does not aim for a balanced or reasonable view of the

    totality of the circumstances. Rather, he claims to have a direct, unmediated

    relationship to the sacred.

    In American political life, the displacement of the subjectivity of the judge

    is the point of the ritual passage through the confirmation process. The nominee goes

    into this rite as a subject with a particular history. Indeed, he has been nominated for

    reasons both political and personal. In the course of the ritual, the nominee literally

    swears to give up that prior self and to speak now only in the voice of the

    Constitution. All that he had known is abandoned; everyone he knew before, in his

    professional and political life, is left behind. He brings with him no assistants, no

    professional colleagues, no political associates. This produces the odd character of the

    ritual inquiry in which the nominee is actually to say nothing at all, apart from

    proclaiming his faith in the constitution: to say something would be to express a point

    of view. From this point on, he begins again. His new beginning is the taking up into

    his own life of that collective beginning that is the Constitution.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    12/28

    11

    The rite of judicial passage offers a kind of metonym of the nation itself.

    Reenacted in the rite is the enduring relationship between revolutionary sacrifice and

    constitutional construction, the giving up and taking on that is the constitutive act of

    national existence. Revolution in the American imaginary is both a historical event and

    an extraordinary way of being. It is the coming into being of the popular sovereign.

    Revolution is accomplished not when the British depart, but when the political

    imaginary is occupied by a new subject: We the people. The people do not first come

    into existence as a collective subject and then choose to revolt. Rather, revolution is

    the presence of the people. That presence is always characterized by a willingness to

    sacrifice. Conversely, every act of citizen sacrifice is a making present of the popular

    sovereign. Giving up his finite, particular self, he or she becomes the point through

    which we experience the whole.

    Sovereign presence is no longer carried in the body of a king, but in the

    body of the sacrificial citizen. Revolution has, accordingly, the quality of existential

    presence. It begins history by creating the subject of the national narrative. Absent

    revolutionary presence, there would be only an aggregation of individual members of

    the community; there would not be a trans-temporal, collective subject that is the

    popular sovereign.

    This popular sovereign has many of the qualities of the monotheistic God

    of the West. It fills the time and territory of the nation: it is present everywhere and

    always. It is whole and complete wherever or whenever it appears. It can do only one

    thing: exercise its will. This is the quality of the sacred, for its being is its meaning.

    The revolution, accordingly, does not represent some meaning apart from itself; it is not

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    13/28

    12

    measured by some universal, normative standard. To experience the popular sovereign

    is to experience an unlimited claim upon the self. We are enthralled to the sovereign,

    which always has the power of life and death. At the moment of sacrifice, there is no

    distance between the citizen and sovereign.

    To say that the American Revolution creates the nation by creating the

    subject the popular sovereign is not to state a historical fact. The meaning of the

    revolution does not actually stabilize until deep into the 19th

    century. Only then does

    the nations history appear as the working out in time of the limitless meaning of that

    appearance of the popular sovereign that is the Revolution. To use a metaphor from

    modern physics, the revolutionary appearance of the people is the big bang that already

    contains all that will ever be.

    Because Americans do not stabilize the meaning of Revolution until late,

    they do not imagine revolution unlinked to constitution. There is no place for

    permanent revolution in the national narrative. The permanence of the link to law is

    the enduring meaning of the Civil War. Defending that link makes the war essentially a

    conservative effort to preserve the Constitution despite its emancipatory result.

    From this point on, Americans see the revolution through the constitution. The author

    of this text is the sovereign people.

    The movement between revolution and constitution is reciprocal: we see

    constitution as the truth of revolution and revolution as the truth of constitution. A

    revolution that failed to produce a text would not be a revolution at all, but at best an

    act of rebellion. A constitution that could not claim a revolutionary foundation would

    lack legitimacy: it would not express the will of the popular sovereign. It would be, at

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    14/28

    13

    best, a contingent product of a collection of people acting at a particular time and place.

    It may express laws of which we approve. Its claim upon the citizen would rest, then,

    upon the justice that it promises, not on the identity of its author. The American

    constitution was demonstrably unjust in its protection of slavery. That injustice created

    a national problem, but it did not sever the constitution from its revolutionary

    foundation.

    The biblical dimensions of all of this are hardly hidden. The Bible is the

    trace of sovereign presence left behind after the exceptional moment of divine

    appearance. That text is the continuing point of access to the now withdrawn

    sovereign. We know the Bible is a sacred text because we see through it to Gods

    presence. We do not ask for some other proof some normative measure of this

    connection. If we fail to read the text as a representation of a sovereign presence, then

    it has no particular claim upon us. We might agree with its moral prescriptions, we

    might find it interesting, but we would have no reason to privilege its representations

    over others. Similarly, we cannot imagine Gods appearance absent the production of a

    text. Such an appearance would found nothing; it would be lost in time, which is to say

    it would be as if it never happened. This is what we are likely to think of claims of

    divine appearance that rely on personal witnessing, but leave no text. We are skeptical

    of the neighbor who tells us that God speaks directly to him; we dismiss the claims for

    divine presence made by those in other cultures.

    No God without a text, and no text without God. This is the same

    relationship of identity to representation that structures the American political

    imaginary. Law is always a representation: its source of authority is always outside of

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    15/28

    14

    itself. It points elsewhere, until that moment when we ask about the authority of the

    constitution itself. At that point, we acknowledge the revolutionary presence of the

    popular sovereign. If we ask why we are bound by that, we have asked one question

    too many. The popular sovereign does not bind us by virtue of some other

    representation; rather, its power is that of identity. We either find here the truth of the

    self or we find nothing at all. To understand this is to understand the power of

    textualism and originalism in American constitutionalism: we are not bound by the acts

    of long-dead, white men. We are bound only because, and as long as, we see their acts

    as our own.

    A politics that rests on this formation of the social imaginary faces two

    sorts of challenges, which we can label Protestant and Jewish. The Protestant challenge

    arises from the unstable place of an authoritative voice. If the Constitution is the text

    produced by the popular sovereign, and every citizen has the same claim to

    membership in the popular sovereign, then with what authority can the Supreme Court

    claim finality for its interpretations. This is indeed a tremendous problem in American

    constitutionalism. Every branch of government, every interest group, and even every

    citizen can frame a political claim as a constitutional claim. No one willing gives up

    this rhetoric of constitutional truth. Each of these contending voices claims the

    prophetic role of returning the nation to its founding truth. This renders minorities

    relatively indifferent to their lack of standing among the population at large, for that

    larger population is in a state of political fallenness. When we couple this claim to

    truth with a violent, sacrificial tradition, we begin to grasp the threatening and

    dangerous character of American political contestation.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    16/28

    15

    The dominant form of this Protestant challenge is fundamentalist: the idea

    that the text need not be interpreted, but only read. The text is a trace, a remainder, of

    the presence of the popular sovereign. The text is a kind of gift that is not to be

    corrupted in its reception. Out of this idea comes the enduring appeal of an anti-

    interpretive approach to constitutional law. It is enough to hold the text in plain sight to

    know what is to be done. To this textualism is often coupled an appeal to original

    history: temporal proximity to sacred presence carries its own weight.

    The Courts response to the Protestant challenge, apart from relying on the

    power of its own rituals, is to appeal to what otherwise appears as the Jewish challenge.

    That challenge juxtaposes to the fundamentalist return to the text itself, the tradition of

    erudite commentary. Think of the Talmud as a model: it literally constructs a field of

    esoteric knowledge out of layers of interpretation. To be an expert requires mastery of

    this entire field of commentary. To think that one can simply read the original now

    appears as naive. Interpretation requires a lifetime of study precisely because we do

    not read with Gods mind. So too with the Justices. Their expertise is located in the

    body of commentary that is the collected opinions of the Court. The opinion they

    create weaves its argument out of this inherited legacy, adding yet another commentary

    to the continually growing body of interpretations. In this direction, the challenge

    comes from the law professors, who claim to know better than the Court the meaning of

    past, judicial decisions. They are the Talmudists of the law. Accordingly, American

    law professors unashamedly produce books with titles like We the People.

    American constitutional practice moves easily between the textualism of

    the fundamentalist and the erudition of the Talmudist. It is a matter of looking, on the

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    17/28

    16

    one hand, and reading, on the other. Each is always available as a critique of the other.

    There is no particular pressure to come to a consistent, interpretive position. We find

    ourselves open to persuasion in each form, but we cannot say in advance which will

    prove effective under any particular circumstances. In part, it depends upon what the

    opposition is saying. What has no place in this grand narrative is that form of judicial

    reasoning that characterizes much of the rest of the world: proportionality review. That

    is a model of reasoning stripped of any contact with the sacred.

    Because there is a diversity of interpretive forms, there is an indeterminate

    relationship between text and decision. The arguments purport to set forth of the truth

    of the text, but that truth does not exist until there is a decision. We dont apply the

    rule in a decision, but rather come to know what the rule is through the decision. The

    law is a product of the decision, and we come to a decision once we have been

    persuaded. Persuasion always contains an element of free decision, for persuasion is

    not deduction.

    Often in constitutional cases, the arguments appear quite literally in

    equipoise: we must decide. Once we decide, we know which are the right arguments.

    Until there is a decision, we have only interpretations. After the decision, we have the

    truth of the Constitution itself. When the Court is successful, we dont hear the Justices

    interpreting. Rather, we hear the Constitution through them, which is to say we hear

    the voice of the popular sovereign whose text this is. Achieving this identity in which

    the judicial opinion appears as the opinion of the people is the goal. At that point, the

    free decision of the judge re-presents the free decision of the sovereign whose trace is

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    18/28

    17

    the Constitution. From that point forward, we dont say the Court decided x, but

    only the constitution requires x.

    The decision reminds us that the state is neither natural nor logical. It must

    be willed into existence and it continues only as long as the will remains. Norms alone

    will not carry forward the political project. The decision requires an act of the will.

    The decision is, for that reason, always an act of violence: sometimes the violence is

    only the elimination of other interpretations; sometimes the violence is enforcement of

    the decision; sometimes the violence goes to the continuing existence of the state itself.

    In the end, each of these moments relies on the next: the constitutional project endures

    in the nations continuing to will its own existence.

    All of these imaginative structures are visible in our debate about the new

    health care law. The opposition, despite its minority status, claims to speak a

    constitutional truth. They claim to speak with the authority of the popular sovereign.

    They seek the symbolic high ground of defending the nation against a modernist

    pathology of legal regulation. The judges turn to the constitutional text, on the one

    hand, and the 20thcentury opinions elaborating the meaning of the commerce clause on

    the other. There is no expertise that can tell us in advance where the case will come

    out, because we do not know the law until the decision is made.

    Translating the debate over health care financing into a constitutional issue

    means constructing the regulatory claim on the individual as a site where the meaning

    of citizenship is at stake. That is never a matter of reason alone. Rather, political

    meaning begins with the individual who gives himself freely to the state. Not contract,

    but sacrifice; not a claim of right, but a gift of life. One reason human rights discourse

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    19/28

    18

    has so little purchase in the United States is because there is no space within our legal

    imaginary for a pre-political individual who has rights against the state. Rights arrive

    only after the revolution extends its claim upon everybody.

    The social contract is a way of thinking about the just content of law, while

    sacrifice is a matter of sovereign presence. The social contract answers the question

    what should the law be? Sacrifice answers the question who are we? A universal

    health insurance scheme sounds like exactly the sort of thing that we might find in a

    social contract negotiated behind a veil of ignorance. This suggests that the problem

    with the law lies not in the dimension of justice but in that of sacrifice.

    Serious problems of constitutional law often arise at the point at which law

    is forced to confront the conditions of sacrifice a point always resistant to

    considerations of justice. It is not an accident that the fundamental issue in the health

    care debate is a drama of possession of the citizens body. American have long

    struggled with the material conditions of the body politic. The most infamous of

    Supreme Court cases, Dred Scott, decided just before the Civil War, held that black

    people could not be citizens under the Constitution. They could not be citizens because

    their bodies could not be part of the body politic; their bodies could not bear the

    constitutional project. Put bluntly, white people could not imagine the death of a black

    person as a sacrifice for the nation. This remained a problem even after the Civil War,

    when the black soldiers contribution to the war effort was largely effaced from

    national memory.

    At issue in such controversies is participation in the mystical corpus of the

    state. This is entirely a matter of the social imaginary. There is no logic, no claim of

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    20/28

    19

    justice, that grounds these beliefs. As Dred Scott shows, however, this imaginative

    construction is subject to a kind of regulatory pressure: a desire to juridify. In one

    direction, we have laws of inclusion and exclusion raising issues of race, eugenics,

    and immigration. In another direction, we have legal attempts to commodify the citizen

    body, as if it were state property or a state resource.

    One form of this idea of commodification was rejected by the Court in the

    famous Lochnerdecision of 1904, in which state efforts to regulate the conditions of

    the workplace were held unconstitutional. One argument in defense of the law was that

    the state has an interest in maintaining the health of workers because they might be

    conscripted. Obviously, the nation needs strong and healthy soldiers. The Court rejects

    the argument, not because it is not true but because it has no limits: any regulatory

    intervention might be defended on this ground. To this male form of commodification,

    the female form was added 70 years later, when the Court rejected the claim that the

    state could deny a woman access to abortion because it has an interest in the production

    of new citizens.

    Both decisions stand in some tension with the acknowledged right of the

    state to conscript. Why doesnt the greater power to take possession of the citizen body

    include the lesser power to regulate? The liberty of the body protected against the idea

    of rational, bureaucratic management is misunderstood if seen only as a libertarian

    interest in freedom from government control. Self-possession as an aspect of the

    American political imaginary gains its symbolic weight from precisely the opposite

    direction: self-possession is a necessary condition of the sacrificial gift. If the citizen is

    to bear the body of the state, he must stand apart from the state. He must preserve the

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    21/28

    20

    capacity freely to give himself in an act of sacrifice. Claiming possession of the self

    against the regulatory/bureaucratic interests of the state is, oddly, an opting in, rather

    than an opting out. To be bound to the state is not to find oneself within its jurisdiction,

    but to decide for the state. We preserve the possibility of that decision by preserving a

    space between the state and the individual. The citizen owns himself not for himself,

    but for the sake of the nation.

    At stake is an interplay between the logic of conscription and that of

    sacrifice. Under the logic of conscription, the regulatory interests of the state are

    without limit for the state retains the right to dispose of every person and all of the

    material wealth of the nation. The final cause of the state is its own continued

    existence; the state is an end without limit. The constitution contains no sunset clause.

    Sacrifice rests upon an alternative biopolitics. Not that of discipline and regulation, but

    rather that of the decision. Sacrifice is always an act of will, not of reason. Its logic is

    that of the gift, which can never be demanded. Nevertheless, like every gift, sacrifice is

    dependent upon its reception. A sacrifice not received is not a sacrifice at all; it is a

    senseless act of violence. Precisely here, we see that the exception is dependent on the

    norm, but not determined by the norm.

    Sacrifice is not a part of law, but it is the aether within which the

    constitutional decision works. This begins with the judge himself, who offers himself

    as a paradigm of sacrifice for law. He has given up his particular interests and become

    a point of revelation of the sovereign. That gift must be received or the Court will be

    viewed as an illegitimate, counter-majoritarian institution. The point was put

    remarkably well in one of the Courts most controversial abortion decisions.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    22/28

    21

    Some cost will be paid by anyone who approves or implements a constitutional

    decision where it is unpopular, or who refuses to work to undermine the decision or to

    force its reversal. The price may be criticism or ostracism, or it may be violence. An

    extra price will be paid by those who themselves disapprove of the decision's results

    when viewed outside of constitutional terms, but who nevertheless struggle to accept it,

    because they respect the rule of law. To all those who will be so tested by following,

    the Court implicitly undertakes to remain steadfast, lest in the end a price be paid for

    nothing. . . . From the obligation of this promise this Court cannot and should not

    assume any exemption when duty requires it to decide a case in conformance with the

    Constitution.

    Law, the Court says, is bound to sacrifice. The judicial decision is only as

    strong as the willingness to hold to it. This begins with the judges own giving up of

    him or herself. That is the free act that is beyond law, but is the condition of law.

    An analogy to the unique American position on gun control can help here.

    America is an armed body politic. Surely, regulating weapons is in the interest of most

    people, just as regulating health care is in the interests of all. Again, the opposition to

    gun control is misunderstood if seen only as a libertarian interest in occupying a

    position outside of politics. Doing so, we fail to see the imagination of politics as a

    calling forth of the body. The gun represents the condition of the possibility of

    sacrifice for the nation. This is never managed but always freely given.

    To understand the American political project, we have to think with the

    body: we have to plot an imaginative structure, rather than develop a theory of justice.

    Imagining the sovereign body, we begin not with the needful body of the welfare state,

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    23/28

    22

    but with the plentiful body of sacrifice. The giving of that body was the violent act of

    Revolution. It remains the imaginative structure that made it so easy for Americans to

    take up a war on terror. Always the point is the same: the law stands on an originary

    sacrificial act that is never fully past, but always an imagined possibility.

    Our popular debate over the constitutionality of health care stands squarely

    in this tradition. One enduring image offered by those in opposition has been that of

    the death panels: a regulatory regime of managing death. The point is not that

    Americans expect to live forever; rather, they object to the states commodification of

    the body. The rebellion against health care insurance is not about freedom as an escape

    from the obligations of citizenship, but freedom as a condition for the realization of the

    meaning of citizenship. Only understood in this way, can we understand how an

    insurance mechanism seems to so many people to put the very life of the nation at

    stake.

    The Stakes

    These symbolic skirmishes inform the imaginative structure behind our

    constitutional debates. Political theology explores this imaginary. Its ambition is

    phenomenological, not normative. I have, for example, not said anything about how

    the health care debate should be resolved. Political theology as an inquiry into the

    fundamental structures of the imagination simply cannot answer such a question.

    These structures make possible our controversies; they do not resolve them one way

    rather than another. My work pursues thick description by considering the various

    products of the political imaginary judicial decisions, political rhetoric, fiction, film,

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    24/28

    23

    and historical narrative. Recently, I have engaged two forms of critical response that

    have forced me to think again about the relationship between theory and practice.

    One set of responses comes from those with a broadly similar agenda of

    inquiry, but who generally work in humanities departments. They too are interested in

    studying power; they too reject the techniques of quantification and measurement that

    characterize much of the social sciences today. They too are interested in the nature of

    interpretation. We share an interest in popular culture as a site of serious inquiry,

    although they rarely share my interest in law.

    What separates us are contrasting views of the relationship between theory

    and practice. They insist that there is no neutral position from which to engage

    interpretation. For them, every act of speech is also an assertion of power. If so, every

    inquiry can be interrogated from the perspective of power. This puts immense pressure

    on theory. The classroom becomes a site of politics, and scholarship becomes a form

    of partisanship.

    The problem this poses for me is evident. For those who support national

    health care, the interpretation I offered cannot help but look like support for the

    opposition. I developed a sympathetic account of the imaginative construction of

    political meaning that is at stake. If I am persuasive, I may indeed have helped the

    opposition, for my point is that their fears are not met by pointing to the economics of

    health care. Even worse, I have undermined the claim that the opposition rests on self-

    interest. When I say that my own politics are liberal, and that I support health care

    reform, my interlocutors think that I am simply confused. For whatever my personal

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    25/28

    24

    views, my work is not contributing to the success of that project. But should it? Is

    theory to be judged as we would judge other forms of political practice?

    The second form of criticism comes not from the humanities, but from the

    divinity schools. The theologians see in my work an expression of idolatry, for it links

    a claim about the sacred to a fully human project. I speak of a politics of transcendent

    value, which supports a practice of sacrifice. The popular sovereign, however, is not a

    metaphysical entity, but a way of imagining the self and the community. To see in the

    products of mans imagination the expression of transcendent value is the very

    definition of idolatry. While the theologians appreciate my exploration of the

    continuing place of the sacred in the political imaginary, they insist that this be read as

    evidence of the continuing role of God in our common life.

    Both sets of criticism are skeptical of my claim to pursue a political

    theology that is descriptive, not normative. Both see theory through the lens of power:

    human or divine. One sees theory as an element in a political project of emancipation,

    the other sees it as part of a project of subordination to God. In each case, the larger

    project offers a normative perspective that gives direction to theoretical inquiry.

    My own work insists on the autonomy of theory. The proof of this

    possibility is not separate from the inquiry itself. Thus, my discussion of the health

    care controversy tries to show that we can indeed take the categories of our own

    experience as a subject of critical reflection.

    I try to imagine the debate from the inside, not as a matter of tactics but as the

    expression of an entire world of meaning. That exploration of the nature of the political

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    26/28

    25

    imaginary did not entail any answer to the question of what the law should be. It did

    not, because it cannot choose between the biopolitics of conscription and that of

    sacrifice. The autonomy of theory lies in this capacity to reveal the sense of our world

    from within, while simultaneously standing outside. After all, as an actual insider, I

    have a political position about health care. I dont think, however, that my work as a

    scholar should be marshaled to support that position. By suspending my own beliefs, I

    make myself an outsider.

    This double perspective is captured by the idea of the historical a priori.

    We find ourselves imagining the world one way rather than another, but we also

    recognize the historical contingency of our own imaginations. Here, we get to the

    deepest point, for this double perspective of being simultaneously bound and

    recognizing contingency describes our condition as free even as we find ourselves fully

    vested in a particular culture. Political theology is a practice of freedom precisely

    because it occupies these dual perspectives of commitment and contingency. In terms

    of this talk, I have pursued the deepest of all commitments sacrifice while arguing

    that the formations within which the issue arises are completely contingent.

    Both forms of criticism directed at my work miss this point. For those in

    the humanities, freedom is understood as self-invention under a rule one gives to

    oneself. Every speech act becomes a political act, because the agent is unbound.

    Contingency without commitment might be their motto. To the theologians, freedom

    remains fundamentally a metaphysical problem. There can be no such thing as self-

    invention for them. Commitment without contingency might be theirs.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    27/28

    26

    We are never so bound by culture, historical circumstance, or power that

    we cannot establish a critical distance from our selves. But still we must begin from

    where we are. We must say what we think, and we must think something. Similarly,

    we cannot help but believe that others have this same double capacity of affirmation

    and critique. Knowing what we do of ourselves, and of how we have come to be

    ourselves, we cannot help but believe that we might be moved by others, just as we

    believe we can move them. This proposition is the foundation of a belief in the

    possibility of a free discourse with every other subject.

    None of this will tell us what to do, but it may help us to understand who

    we are. At this point, methodological reflection on political theology crosses from

    positive to normative. It states the conditions of belief that ground free inquiry as a

    project of mutual dialogue. It describes a modern form of the Socratic idea that

    freedom is an end toward which we always have to work from within a cultural

    practice. I like to think that my claim that I have no normative position is not very

    different from Socrates claim that he knew nothing that is, nothing that could inform

    the citys laws.

    In sum, the normative implications of my work have nothing to do with

    resolving controversies within the law such as our health care debate. Rather, those

    implications have to do with the way in which the theory itself becomes a site of

    freedom, not power. We cannot think freely without being free. As free subjects, we

    must decide what to say, just as we must decide what to do, which is only to say we

    must take responsibility. We take responsibility, when we try to persuade others and

    open ourselves to persuasion in turn. On this, I suspect my critics agree with me.

  • 8/12/2019 A Political Theology for a Civil Religion_Paul Kahn

    28/28

    27

    ROBERT SCHUMAN CENTRE FOR ADVANCED STUDIES

    The Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies (RSCAS), created in 1992 and directed by

    Stefano Bartolini since September 2006, aims to develop interdisciplinary and comparative

    research and to promote work on the major issues facing the process of integration and

    European society. The Centre is home to a large postdoctoral programme and hosts major

    research programmes and projects, and a range of working groups and ad hoc initiatives. The

    research agenda is organised around a set of core themes and is continuously evolving,

    reflecting the changing agenda of European integration and the expanding membership of the

    European Union. The aim of the Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies is to

    contribute to the public debate by offering views and opinions on matters of general interest.

    The European University Institute and the Robert Schuman Centre for Advanced Studies are

    not responsible for the proposals and the opinions expressed by the author(s).

    RELIGIOWEST

    ReligioWest is a four year research project funded by the European Research Council and

    based at the European University Institute, Florence, Italy. It aims at studying how different

    western states in Europe and North America are redefining their relationship to religions,

    under the challenge of an increasing religious activism in the public sphere, associated with

    new religious movements and with Islam.