Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    1/18

    AMARTYA SEN

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE

    The subtitle of Isaac Levis book, Hard Choices, explains the nature of the

    problem that he addresses in that classic work: Decision Making under

    Unresolved Conflict.1 We have learned greatly from Levis analyses of

    why, despite our best efforts, the valuational conflicts that we face may

    not always be fully resolved when the point of decision making comes,

    and how we may nevertheless use systematic reasoning to decide what

    one should sensibly do despite the presence of unsettled conflicts. Indeed,

    through a variety of contributions stretching over several decades, Isaac

    Levi has powerfully illuminated the challenges of decision making in the

    presence of imperfect information, conflicting evidence, divergent values,

    discordant commitments, and other sources of internal dissension.2

    I seize the wonderful occasion of celebrating Isaac Levis work and ac-

    complishments by presenting a series of observations on rational decision

    making with incompletely resolved internal dissensions. In that context, I

    comment also on the nature and use of incomplete valuational orderings

    and the ways and means of extending their reach. I pursue these issues in

    the form of addressing a series of questions. Sometimes I draw on Levis

    work, and at other times, I comment on differences that we may still have.

    As will be obvious, even when we disagree, my understanding of theseissues is strongly influenced by Levis thinking.

    1. IS NONCOMMENSURABILITY THE PRIMARY REASON FOR

    UNRESOLVED CONFLICT?

    Noncommensurability of different types of values is often seen as a reason

    indeed the main reason for incompleteness of an overall (all things

    considered) ranking. Indeed, the belief that commensurability is neces-

    sary for arriving at a completely ordered ranking of different optionsseems to have considerable following in the literature. Since I have always

    had some problem in grasping the reasoning behind that belief, I should

    perhaps try to articulate where my difficulty lies.

    Synthese 140: 4359, 2004.

    2004 Kluwer Academic Publishers. Printed in the Netherlands.

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    2/18

    44 AMARTYA SEN

    Commensurability of two distinct objects stands for their being measur-

    able in terms of each other. Noncommensurability is present when several

    dimensions of value are irreducible to one another.3 In the context of

    evaluating a choice, commensurability requires that in assessing its results,we can see the values of all the relevant results in exactly one dimension

    measuring the significance of distinct outcomes in a common scale so

    that in deciding what would be best, we need not go beyond counting the

    overall value in one homogeneous metric. Since the results are all reduced

    to one dimension, we need do no more than checking which option will

    give us how much of the one good thing to which every value is reduced.

    We are, certainly, not likely to have much difficulty in choosing

    between two alternative options both of which offers just the same good

    thing, but one offers more than the other. This is an agreeably trivial case,

    but the belief that whenever the choice problem is not so trivial, we must

    have great difficulty in deciding what we should sensibly do seems pe-

    culiarly feeble (it is tempting to ask, how spoilt can one get!). Indeed, ifcounting one set of real numbers is all we could do, then there would not

    be many choices that we could sensibly and intelligently make. Whether

    we are deciding between buying different commodity baskets, or making

    choices about what to do on a holiday, or deciding whom to vote for in an

    election, we are inescapably involved in evaluating alternatives with non-

    commensurable results. Noncommensurability can hardly be a remarkable

    discovery in the world in which we live. And it need not, by itself, make it

    very hard to choose sensibly.

    For example, a fine mango may give us nutrition as well as some palatal

    or olfactory pleasure, whereas buying the record of a good song may offer

    a very different reward (not immediately reducible into the dimensions ofthe other), and given a budget constraint we could quite possibly face the

    choice of having one or the other. This involves choosing between non-

    commensurable results. And yet we may have no great difficulty in opting

    for the mango when immensely hungry or starved, and going for the song,

    when well endowed with tasty food but short of melodious entertainment.

    The choice need not be hard to make in many situations, despite the non-

    commensurability involved. The distinct dimensions of values may not be

    reducible into one another, and yet there may be no problem whatsoever in

    deciding what one should sensibly do when our priorities or weights over

    these values are clear enough.

    Making choices with noncommensurable rewards is like speaking in

    prose. It is, in general, not particularly hard to speak in prose (even if M.Jourdain in Molieres Le Bourgeois Gentilhomme may marvel at our ability

    to perform so exacting a feat). But this does not negate the recognition

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    3/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 45

    that speaking can sometimes be very difficult (for example, when one is

    overwhelmed by emotions), but that is not because expressing oneself in

    prose is in itself arduous. The presence of noncommensurable rewards only

    indicates that choice decisions will not be trivial (reducible just to countingwhat is more and what is less), but it does not at all indicate that it is

    impossible or even that it must be particularly difficult.

    What we have to ask is: why are some choices hard? This must be

    the case when the diverse values involved are both in conflict and difficult

    to weigh relative to each other, that is, when (as Isaac Levi discusses with

    such care) it is hard to resolve their conflicting pulls. The exercise of

    overall evaluation may not only involve more than counting, the process

    of non-trivial aggregation may be complex and challenging in some cases

    in a way it may not be in others. To say that noncommensurability is the

    primary cause of incompleteness amounts to missing the specific causes

    of incompleteness in favour of an ever-present precondition that has little

    discriminating relevance. To use an analogy, it would be like saying that wefeel hungry primarily because we have a stomach. Certainly, it is hard to

    explain hunger without presuming something about the stomach, but it is

    not particularly useful to concentrate on the existence of the stomach in the

    human body in trying to explain hunger in the world. While the stomach is

    generically involved, we are likely to get more help in explaining hunger if

    we try to examine instead how difficult it may be for a person particularly

    a poor person to fill his or her belly. Similarly, even though the presence

    of noncommensurable results is generically involved in incompleteness,

    we have to investigate whether it is difficult or easy to weigh the

    different types of values involved and to resolve their conflicts.

    2. IS THERE ULTIMATELY ONLY ONE SOURCE OF IMPORTANCE?

    Noncommensurability does not in itself take us very far in understanding

    the nature of the decisional problem to be addressed. It is, therefore, in

    many ways a pity that so much attention has been heaped in the literature

    on the existence of noncommensurability as such, which is an omnipresent

    and ordinary feature of the world, compared with the distinct reasons

    that make value conflicts so serious in some cases and not at all in oth-

    ers. But perhaps there is a different, more dialectical, explanation of why

    several perspicacious thinkers have chosen to emphasize the importance of

    noncommensurability. The attention paid to noncommensurability is partlya critique of the belief often implicit that there must ultimately be

    only one source of significance. By focusing on noncommensurability, the

    critics of such reductionism assert something of importance regarding the

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    4/18

    46 AMARTYA SEN

    absence of a single standard of value.4 Indeed, the hold of the tradition

    of reducing everything to one homogeneous virtue may explain why the

    mundane recognition that there are different values that are not reducible to

    each other has been seen as worth asserting. Even a humdrum cognizancemay have a positive and indeed a constructive role in the dialectics of

    conceptual diagnosis.

    Adam Smith complained more than two hundred years ago about the

    tendency of some philosophers (he had separated out Epicurus, but clearly

    had others in mind as well, including circumstantial evidence indicates

    his friend, David Hume) to look for a single homogenous virtue in terms

    of which all values could be explained:

    By running up all the different virtues to this one species of propriety, Epicurus indulged

    a propensity, which is natural to all men, but which philosophers in particular are apt to

    cultivate with a peculiar fondness, as the great means of displaying their ingenuity, the

    propensity to account for all appearances from as few principles as possible. And he, no

    doubt, indulged this propensity still further, when he referred all the primary objects of

    natural desire and aversion to the pleasures and pains of the body.5

    There are indeed schools of thought which insist, explicitly or by implic-

    ation, that all the appearances of value must be reduced ultimately to a

    single source of importance. This claim about the nature of value is of-

    ten supplemented by the further thought, in which commensurability does

    come in, that in order to be able to choose rationally, all values must be

    reduced to one. Evidently, the protagonists of this view believe that human

    beings can count but cannot evaluate.

    The counting freaks (if I may call them that, without intending any

    disrespect) include some but not all utilitarians. There is indeed a

    version of utilitarian reasoning that takes the form of arguing that there

    is no noncommensurability at all in what ultimately matters, to wit utility.

    In the example considered earlier, if we contingently have no difficulty

    in choosing between the mango and the song, it is because (the argument

    runs) both can be judged by their respective ability to generate utility. In

    the last analysis (the argument insists), we count, not judge.

    I shall not scrutinize here this particular argumental loop, but only note

    that utility may be far from a homogenous magnitude (a recognition that

    had not escaped that great utilitarian, John Stuart Mill), and also that there

    can be other reasons for choice (other than the pursuit of utility), no mat-

    ter how utility is substantively defined. If, however, utility is not defined

    independently, but only as the real-valued representation of the binary re-lation underlying choice behaviour (as is common in modern economics),

    then utility is not only not one good thing, it is not a thing at all, but a

    mere phantom of representation. Furthermore, even a consistent phantom

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    5/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 47

    may not exist when choice behaviour is non-binary. I have discussed these

    issues elsewhere, and will desist from pursuing them further here.6

    3. HOW USEFUL IS LEVIS GENERAL CONCEPT OF

    V-ADMISSIBILITY IN UNDERSTANDING THE DEMANDS OF

    RATIONAL DECISION MAKING WITH UNRESOLVED CONFLICTS?

    V-admissibility, which is a central concept in Levis investigation, is in-

    deed very useful. Even though I shall presently argue (in Section 5) that

    particular questions can be raised about some applications of the idea of

    V-admissibility that Levi endorses, let me first discuss why the concept is,

    I think, important and helpful.

    In a set of options (let me call it the menu), the V-admissible options

    are those that have not been prohibited by the agents value commitments

    from being chosen by the agent.7 They are, thus, admissible relative tothe agents valuations of the feasible options as better or worse, all things

    considered. The concept of V-admissibility introduces, in two distinct

    ways, a useful gradualism in the process of systematic choice. First, if

    an option is not V-admissible, then it would not be sensible to choose it,

    but if it is V-admissible, there may still be further questions to be asked

    as to whether it is optimal or not. In being definitive in exclusion but only

    permissive in terms of inclusion, it makes the choice process capture an

    important asymmetry. Weeding out the clearly unchoosable options can

    be a good way to begin, but even when the rotten ones have been weeded

    out, the remainder may call for further and closer attention.

    Second, V-admissibility itself is a parametric concept: the criteria of

    admissibility are not already ingrained in the very idea of V-admissibility

    and they have to be additionally defined, and can be varied. As the criteria

    are more and more specified, the constraints imposed by V-admissibility

    can be gradually tightened. Sequential tightening can be helpful in coming

    to grips with hard choices.

    Let me illustrate by recharactering Levis investigation in the form of

    four distinct steps associated with the idea of V-admissibility (drawing on

    different parts of Levis work).

    (1) Single-dimensional valuation. It is, as discussed already, trivial to

    decide what to do when the different results are all fully commensurable.

    We can, in this very special case, simply count our way to checking

    which option or options are the best (that is, have most of the onegood thing to which everything else is reduced). With single-dimensional

    valuation, V-admissibility is both trivial and decisionally definitive: in one

    step we can reject all the rejectable alternatives and go straight to what we

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    6/18

    48 AMARTYA SEN

    should choose.8 If this does not work and mostly it will not then we

    must get into non-trivial exercises.

    (2) Congruent multi-dimensionality. When distinct and disparate values

    all move together, in the same direction with each other, the ranking ofoptions can simply follow the shared ordering of all the distinct value com-

    mitments. As Levi notes, when the agents value commitments generate

    no conflict but constrain the agent to evaluate his feasible options in an un-

    equivocal manner, the agent is obligated by those commitments to restrict

    his choice to one of the feasible options which is optimal according to the

    mandated ranking.9 The V-admissible alternatives are those that could not

    be eliminated on the ground of their being inferior to some feasible option

    in terms ofeach of the value commitments involved. This is also a simple

    enough case, but it does not presuppose any commensurability at all.

    (3) The Weighted Average Principle: So far nothing more than ordinal

    ranking of each value commitment has been invoked, but we must now go

    beyond that. Let v1, . . . , vn be the n numerical valuational functions thatgive the value of each option according to each of the n value commitments

    respectively. It is assumed that each of these vi is cardinally measurable

    unique up to a positive affine transformation.10 Levi confines attention now

    to the weighted sum of all the vi as reflecting the aggregate value v of the

    respective options, for a set of non-negative weights (w1, . . . , wn).11 So we

    have: v = wi vi, and depending on the weights we choose for the respect-

    ive value commitments, we get a corresponding set of aggregate values of

    each option. If we had a uniquely specified set of such weights (w1, . . . ,

    wn), then of course the valuational exercise would be over. But so long as

    the conflict is unresolved, this could not be presumed. So, at this stage,

    Levi concentrates attention on the entire class of non-negative weights.However, some options may end up having a lower aggregate value than

    another under every permissible set of non-negative weights, and in that

    case, the uniformly lower valued alternative can be eliminated as being

    non-admissible. This way the afforced criterion of V-admissibility elim-

    inates some non-admissible options in the menu.12 This is a critically

    important and innovative step in Levis reasoning, and I shall examine the

    pros and cons of going this way in Section 5, when I specifically scrutinize

    the weighted average principle.

    (4) Categorical preference and optimality. It is possible to go beyond

    valuational conflicts when aggregate valuations are in conformity with

    each other, at least in part. For example, ifx is strictly preferred in value to

    y according to all permissible valuation rankings, then x is categoricallypreferred to y.13 The notion of categorical preference is useful in checking

    admissibility, but it can also in some cases with luck help to identity an

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    7/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 49

    optimal choice. When it turns out that there exists an option x in the menu

    such that for every permissible valuational ranking, x is at least as good as

    every other alternative in the menu, then x is declared to be V-optimal.

    If, furthermore, the rankings are such that any option y in the menu thatis regarded as indifferent to an optimal option x is also optimal (but y is

    definitely not optimal when x is ranked above y), then we get to the more

    regular idea of full optimality rather than only V-optimality.14

    The possible existence of optimal or V-optimal options can make de-

    cisions easier to take despite unresolved conflicts, but the broader idea

    of V-admissibility gets us, in general, part of the way, even when we do

    not arrive at a categorically justified optimal decision. In the gradualist

    approach investigated by Isaac Levi, the role of each of the finely defined

    concepts is explored and explained.15

    4. IS THERE AN ALTERNATIVE SYSTEMATIC APPROACH TO RATIONALDECISION MAKING UNDER UNRESOLVED CONFLICTS?

    There is, and indeed, to a great extent, Levis strategy can be seen as a

    reasoned departure from an older approach that focuses on maximization

    based on a possibly incomplete ordering derived from the intersection of

    different value commitments. That approach can be seen in terms of its two

    constitutive components, viz. maximization and intersection.16 I shall call

    it (not terribly imaginatively) intersection maximization.17

    The idea of maximization as choosing an option that is no worse than

    any other feasible option can work with incomplete orderings. To qualify

    as maximal an option need not be shown to be at least as good as all the

    other feasible options only that it is not strict worse than any. The idea

    of maximality in this broad sense has been well formalized by Bourbaki,

    Debreu and others.18 If decision making is based on maximization (rather

    than optimization choosing an option that is at least as good as every

    other option), it is not a requirement that all value conflicts be resolved

    before a reasoned choice can occur. The incomplete ordering to be used for

    maximization can be derived on the basis of the intersection of the different

    valuational rankings. Even when unresolved conflicts exist, an incomplete

    ordering can be identified that ranks two options in the overall ranking in a

    certain way if and only if those options are ranked in the same way by all

    the different values involved. So, if x is ranked above y according to each

    of these values, then x is ranked overall above y. Similarly, if x and y tiein terms of each of these values, then x and y are taken to be indifferent

    overall. The intersection partial ordering generated in this way can then

    be used, along with the approach of maximization, for systematic choice

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    8/18

    50 AMARTYA SEN

    despite the presence of unresolved conflicts (which can make the overall

    ranking incomplete).

    The combined use of maximization and intersection is basically iso-

    morphic with Levis identification of a mandated ranking related toV-admissibility before we get to his weighted average principle.19 Since

    the older approach does not invoke the weighted average principle, we

    can perhaps ask what alternative principle does it use? The answer is noth-

    ing: it stops right there with maximization based on the intersection partial

    ordering. In this sense, intersection maximization is an ineloquent theory (I

    shall presently comment on the strategic use of this lack of eloquence). The

    maximal set is the set of all options that are undominated by the inter-

    section partial ordering. It can be shown that maximization, in this broader

    sense (broader than optimization, and also as it happens, broader than

    V-admissibility with Levis weighted average principle) yields many im-

    portant and rather far-reaching properties in the discipline of choice,

    and it can be defended both on analytical and substantive grounds. 20 Thegeneral approach of maximization can also incorporate various additional

    features that were not part of the old structure of maximality identified by

    Bourbaki and Debreu: such as incorporating actions of agents as a part of

    the comprehensive outcome of choice, which allows us to re- examine

    the dividing line between consequentialist and deontological reasoning.

    Various other properties can also be optionally imposed by utilizing the

    capacious format of maximization, and making use of the room for further

    articulation left open by the ineloquent form of that approach.21

    We have to examine whether Levis addition of weighted average prin-

    ciple and its implications for categorical preference can also be sensibly

    added on to the basic structure of intersection maximization. I take up thatissue next.

    5. IS THE CRITERION OF WEIGHTED AVERAGE PRINCIPLE FO R

    V-ADMISSIBILITY PERSUASIVE AND ACCEPTABLE?

    There are certainly good arguments in favour of using some additional

    structure, like Levis weighted average principle, to extend the reach of

    intersection maximization. There is, first, a manifest need here, and second,

    Levis particular constructive proposal has some conspicuous merit.

    I begin with the issue of need and the motivation for Levis departure.

    The maximal set based on intersection can be quite large. Consider Levisexample of a hapless office manager, called Jones: I shall call her Ms.

    Jones. She wants to hire a secretary who is a good typist and a good

    stenographer as well (and thus has two value commitments), and con-

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    9/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 51

    siders three candidates: Jane, Dolly and Lilly. Jones finds that in terms of

    typing skill, Jane is better than Dolly and Dolly superior to Lilly, but in

    stenographic competence, Lilly is better than Dolly, who is better than

    Jane. The intersection of these two rankings is empty, and intersectionmaximization based on these two orderings would suggest that all three

    are maximal.

    Levi, not surprisingly, sees this as hopelessly inarticulate. He wants to

    ask such questions as whether Dolly, the middle skilled in each, is the

    second best typist and second best stenographer, or merely the second

    worst typist and second worst stenographer. Dolly is, of course, all

    these, in ordinal terms, but Levi wants to be able to get and use more

    information about where Dolly figures vis-a- vis Jane and Lilly. This takes

    Levi to cardinal valuational functions vi and then to the weighted aver-

    age principle. With this motivation for wanting a more informed and

    through that a more articulate choice, I am in total sympathy.22 The issue

    to be examined is whether the particular procedure developed by Levi isadequate.

    The weighted average principle is a way of cutting down the

    intersection-based maximal set by eliminating some options that would

    have a lower value than an alternative option in terms of all non-negative

    weights that can be placed on the cardinal valuational functions associated

    with the respective value commitments. The Levi approach goes beyond

    the older maximization approach both (i) by introducing cardinal meas-

    urement associated with each value commitment, and (ii) by using the

    strategy of weeding out any option as V-inadmissible if it gets dominated

    by all possible weighted aggregate values by some other feasible option (in

    terms of the cardinal representation chosen). This is where the departurecomes, and we have to ask whether it is convincing.

    The second argument, which takes us beyond motivation, is that

    Levis reasoning certainly has considerable plausibility (which as I shall

    presently discuss is not the same thing as its being, all things considered,

    convincing). The plausibility can be illustrated by giving valuational num-

    bers to the two skills of the three candidates each. Consider the following

    valuations:

    Candidates Typing skill Stenographic skill

    Jane 10 1

    Dolly 2 2

    Lilly 1 10

    Given the cardinal characteristics of this measurement, any positive affine

    transformation of these numbers will serve as well.

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    10/18

    52 AMARTYA SEN

    We can add up the two numbers of each with any set of non- negative

    weights. But it is clear that no matter what these chosen weights are, Dolly

    will get trumped by either Jane or Lilly, since Dolly is nearly as bad a typist

    as Lilly and nearly as bad a stenographer as Jane. To see this consider thepossibility that Dolly gets a higher total score than Jane. In that case the

    weights must be such that the one- point advantage in stenography that

    Dolly has over Jane (with her mark of 2 against Janes 1) outweighs the

    8-point advantage that Jane has over Dolly in typing (with their respective

    figures of 10 and 2). So the weight on stenographic skill must be at least

    8 times as great as on typing skill. But, then, clearly Lilly will beat Dolly

    hollow with her 8-point advantage over Dolly in stenography, despite her

    one-point deficit vis-a-vis Dolly in typing. If Dolly beats Jane, then Lilly

    beats Dolly, and it can also be readily checked that if Dolly beats Lilly,

    then Jane will beat Dolly. Dolly is, thus, not V-admissible, given Levis

    weighed average principle. The reasoning not only takes us beyond the

    purely ordinal comparisons of intersection maximization, it also has someevident appeal.

    Though I have not been retained by luckless Dolly, let me now argue,

    first, against this particular conclusion, and then, against the principle of

    weighted average in general. The central issue is this: can we do an overall

    evaluation of the candidates without asking how the importance of the

    two skills may vary as we consider different levels of achievement of the

    candidates? Suppose that a skill level of 1 in typing, which Lilly has, does

    not make it possible for letters to be typed well enough to be despatched,

    but level 2, which Dolly has, makes that possible, though it is nowhere near

    the superb level of typing skill that Janes mark of 10 indicates. Suppose

    also that a skill level of 1 in stenography, which Jane has, leads to totalchaos in the office (say that a third time please, Ms. Jones), whereas

    Dollys level 2, modest as it is, prevents that, even though the stenographic

    work would be massively better with a skill level of 10, which Lilly enjoys.

    Faced with these considerations, Ms. Jones may drop Jane to prevent chaos

    in office, and she may also let Lilly go so that some letters can actually

    get typed. Dolly satisfies the qualifying level in each skill, and may well

    be chosen on these grounds (despite her V-inadmissibility in terms of the

    weighted average principle). I rest my case for Dolly or more accurately

    for not giving Dolly the boot without checking what the importance of the

    different levels of skill are for the choice at hand (and not just how much

    skill there is).

    I turn now to the more general issue of the acceptability of the weightedaverage principle. Underlying my scepticism is a question about the inter-

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    11/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 53

    pretation of the valuational numbers related to each value commitment.

    What do the numbers given by vi stand for? Do they:

    (1) measure the levels of accomplishment in field i, or

    (2) measure the importance of these accomplishments for the purpose for

    which the choice decision is being taken?

    Levis language suggests that he takes the former interpretation, so that the

    numbers represent the levels of skill of Dolly and others. If so, we still have

    to ask how valuable is that skill for the decision at hand, and this cannot be

    answered independently of the levels of that skill and the presence of other

    factors that allow or facilitate or hinder the use of that skill. For example,

    Janes excellent typing skill (mark 10 no less) can be quite valueless

    in terms of Ms. Joness decisional problem if the woeful nature of her

    stenographic skill makes her an impossible holder of the office position in

    question. We need not only a valuation of the respective skills (and moregenerally, of the extent of accomplishment in each value commitment), but

    also an evaluation of the contingent importance of the exact level of skill

    (or accomplishment) given everything else that is involved in the decisional

    picture.

    If, on the other hand, the second interpretation is taken, then we have

    to ask how can the importance of a skill (or more generally, of a value

    accomplishment) for the decision at hand be represented independently of

    other factors in the choice? How can we, for example, determine that the

    choice- context importance of Janes typing skill, in an additive framework,

    is invariably 10 for this office job, no matter whether she can do anything

    else at all that may also be a part of the job in question? Something or

    other is clearly missing in this framework, and the operation of weighted

    addition, which leads the way to the weighted average principle, can be

    deeply problematic.

    Perhaps an analogy from social choice theory can help to clarify the

    issue. Consider a welfarist framework, in which the social value of a state

    of affairs is seen as a function of the welfare levels of all the people in

    that state.23 We can think of each persons well-being as a kind of value

    commitment, in terms of an analogy with Levis framework. To do this

    exercise, we need:

    (1) to evaluate each persons well-being (measured on its own);

    (2) to make interpersonal comparisons of the values of different personswell-being (putting them in a comparable scale);

    (3) to decide on the weights to be put on increments or diminutions in each

    persons well-being respectively vis-a-vis those of others (reflecting

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    12/18

    54 AMARTYA SEN

    what importance we want to attach respectively to distributive and

    aggregative considerations).24

    These distinct exercises cannot be combined in one assignment of vi

    functions (unique up to a positive affine transformation) which are thensimply added together with non-negative weights. No matter how we

    choose the values ofvi functions, something or other would not have been

    addressed. I would argue that a similar lacuna exists in the framework

    of V-admissibility with vi functions, limited to the class of fixed affine

    transformations and fixed non-negative weights. Judging the decisional im-

    portance of the accomplishments of different value commitments requires

    more than a weighted averaging of the different accomplishments.

    6. CAN WE USE V-ADMISSIBILITY WITHOUT THE WEIGHTED

    AVERAGE PRINCIPLE?

    Even though the particular proposal of using the weighted average prin-

    ciple with V-admissibility seems problematic that does not negate the

    motivation that led Isaac Levi to seek an extension of the reasoning under-

    lying intersection maximization. The maximal set given by the intersection

    of all the value commitments can be unhelpfully large, and it is sensible

    enough to try to see how that set can be reduced in size to give more bite

    to the decisional process. Dolly may be hard to eliminate from the list of

    three through the weighted average principle in particular, but that need not

    indicate that all three must be seen as fine appointees merely because the

    intersection partial ordering is empty. Levis motivation in seeking more

    stringent criteria in the form of tighter requirements of V-admissibility is

    in general just right.

    Consider a more general specification of the problem of going beyond

    intersection maximization through V-admissibility, by combining Levis

    motivation with formal investigations pursued in social choice theory. 25

    We follow Levi in considering valuation functions vi related to each value

    commitment, but do not necessarily constrain the uniqueness properties

    of each vi to the class of positive affine transformations. Depending on

    the type of values involves, the class may be wider (and the extent of

    measurability correspondingly less, e.g., ordinal), or narrower (and cor-

    respondingly have more measurability, e.g., ratio scale), and it is possible

    also to consider various intermediate possibilities of a hybrid kind.26 Wecan proceed from there to consider aggregation functions v = fk(v1, . . . ,

    vn), and impose invariance conditions that reflect the particular extents

    of measurability and any comparability restrictions that we may want to

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    13/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 55

    impose.27 We can consider a number of such aggregation functions fk, with

    k = 1, . . . , m, in a class F. If for some feasible y, for all fk in F, v(x) is less

    than v(y), then x is not V-admissible.

    This general structure can accommodate Levis weighted average prin-ciple if the valuation functions vi are cardinal and if the aggregation

    functions fk in F are restricted exactly to the class of weighted aver-

    ages. Similarly, by choosing ordinal vi functions and an ordinal class

    F of aggregation functions fk, we can get back to simple intersection

    maximization. But there are a great many other possibilities as well, and

    V-admissibility can be used to consolidate the minimal articulation of in-

    tersection maximization, and then to go beyond that to the extent that is

    permitted by our actual ability to marshall information and to scrutinize

    our assessments. Unresolved value conflicts leaves open many possibilities

    of methodical use of decisional reasoning, and V-admissibility can serve

    as a general format that accommodates as much articulation as we can

    reasonably justify.

    7. IS INCOMPLETENESS ALWAYS TENTATIVE, AWAITING

    RESOLUTION?

    In the preceding discussion the focus has been on reducing incomplete-

    ness as much as possible. But what about any remaining incompleteness?

    Should we see it as an embarrassment, or as a defect that calls for ways

    and means of total elimination. I would argue that the answer must depend

    on the nature of the remaining incompleteness.

    In many cases the incompleteness is best described as tentative. It

    awaits resolution (with more information, or deeper analysis, or closer

    scrutiny, or whatever), whether or not the resolution actually occurs. This

    kind of incompleteness has to be contrasted with the idea of assertive

    incompleteness.28 This category separates out cases of incompleteness in

    which the lack of completeness is positively asserted, yielding statements

    such as x and y cannot be ranked. It is radically different from incom-

    pleteness that is tentatively accepted, while awaiting or working for

    completion. The partial ranking may simply not be completable, and

    may not even be ideally completed. Rather, incompleteness may be the

    right answer in these cases.

    It is useful to distinguish between three different types of assertive

    incompleteness related to the source of the incompletability involved.First, when the inquiry concerns a specific field of ethical or decisional

    judgment (such as justice), the assertive incompleteness may relate to

    the domain of that type of judgment (for example, the reach of a theory

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    14/18

    56 AMARTYA SEN

    of justice). The recognition that incompleteness of judgments can be a

    constituent part of the definite conclusions advanced by a complete theory

    of justice can be quite momentous for practical reason.

    Indeed, even a complete theory of justice can yield and assert incomplete rankings of justice. Affirmed incompleteness (e.g., x and y

    cannot be ranked in terms of justice) may be as much a definite conclu-

    sion as the decision that x and y can be ranked in terms of justice (and

    in particular that, say, x is more just than y, or that x is just, whereas y

    is not). However, it must also be noted that even when it is assertively

    concluded that x and y cannot be ranked in terms of justice, this does not

    entail that they cannot be ranked in terms of some other type of ethical

    or political concern. There is a distinction here between this kind of field-

    specific conclusion (important as it may be) and more ambitious claims of

    assertive incompleteness for all things considered decisions.

    Second, even for an all things considered evaluation, a partial ranking

    (or a partial partition) may be a crucial assertion as the end product at a par-ticular stage of a multi-stage exercise. A theory may assert incompleteness

    for a well-defined purpose, leaving room for a possible extension through

    an appropriate subsequent stage. If some decisional issues are not decid-

    able by, say, general (or foundational) ethical reasoning, the incomplete

    ranking emerging from general ethical reasoning may be an appropriate

    assertion for that general stage. This may perhaps be supplemented by

    a subsequent stage using other procedures (for example, some kind of a

    democratic decision mechanism) that extend the general ethical reasoning

    by choosing between alternative courses of action that are all consistent

    with general ethical reasoning.29 The affirmation of incompleteness at one

    stage of the process may be critically important for the necessity andviability of the next stage.

    Third, aside from field-specific and stage-specific assertive incomplete-

    ness, there is the possibility of an unqualified assertion of incompleteness.

    It is possible that incompleteness may be a durable and definitive part

    of the end product of all things considered and all stage included

    evaluation. It may be as far as we can proceed with reasoned discrim-

    ination, given the information that we can conceivably have. If so, the

    incompleteness will not await completion at a later stage or over a wider

    field of reference, and will yield such statements as: x and y definitely

    cannot be ranked for decisional purposes.30 There is a need to see as-

    sertive incompleteness as a conceptual category of its own. For example, a

    fine-grained discrimination between two value commitments with exactlyspecified weights may simply be beyond the reach of reasoned ethical

    scrutiny, or may demand information that may not only be contingently

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    15/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 57

    lacking but also impossible to obtain even in principle. For example, it

    can be argued that interpersonal comparisons of well-being, though by no

    means impossible, may not take us all the way to invariance conditions

    that yield one-to-one correspondence of everyones well-being numbersvis-a-vis each other.31

    I end by noting that the recognition of the possibility of assertive incom-

    pleteness does not reduce in any way the value of scrutiny and investigation

    aimed at reducing the extent of tentative incompleteness through continued

    scrutiny of unresolved conflicts. Nor, for that matter, does it rule out the

    possible usefulness of challenging whether a putative claim of assertive

    incompleteness is indeed justified. Assertive incompleteness no less than

    tentative incompleteness is well within the domain of inquiry and jus-

    tification which Isaac Levi has done so much to clarify for us. We know

    from Isaacs work how magnificently capacious that domain is.

    NOTES

    1 Isaac Levi, Hard Choice: Decision Making under Unresolved Conflict, Cambridge

    University Press, Cambridge (1986).2 Isaac Levi, Gambling with Truth, Knopf, New York (1967); Information and Inference,

    Synthese 17, 369379 (1967); On Indeterminate Probabilities, Journal of Philosophy 71,

    391 418 (1974); The Enterprise of Knowledge, MIT Press, Cambridge, MA (1980); Hard

    Choices (1986); Conflicts and Inquiry, Ethics 102, 814834 (1992); The Covenant of

    Reason, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1997). Levi has been concerned with

    decisions in epistemology as well as practical reason. The focus of this essay is, how-

    ever, exclusively on the latter, even though some of the basic issues have relevance to

    epistemology as well.3 The Covenant of Reason (1997, p. 236).4 As Isaac Levi explains, when the perspective on inquiry and justification is combined

    with a rejection of a single fixed standard of value, the key elements of the pragmatism of

    Peirce and Dewey which I admire are identified ( The Covenant of Reason, p. 218).5 Smith, The Theory of Moral Sentiments, revised edn., VII.ii.2.14 (1790). Republished,

    Clarendon Press, Oxford (1976, p. 299).6 See Choice, Welfare and Measurement, Blackwell, Oxford (1982); Harvard University

    Press, Cambridge, MA (1997); On Ethics and Economics Blackwell, Oxford (1987); and

    Rationality and Freedom, Harvard University Press, Cambridge, MA (2002).7 Levi, Hard Choices (1986, p. 10).8 I am abstracting here from the problem of infinite sets in which even a complete ordering

    need not necessarily yield a best or an optimal alternative. That raises a different range

    of issues, with which I shall not be concerned in this essay. In the present investigation,we may as well assume that the set of options is finite, so that a complete ordering will

    always identify a best alternative. Indeed, even an acyclic but complete ranking will do

    that; on this and related results, see my Collective Choice and Social Welfare, Holden-

    Day, San Francisco (1970). Republished, North-Holland, Amsterdam (1979, Chap. 1),

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    16/18

    58 AMARTYA SEN

    and Choice Functions and Revealed Preference, Review of Economic Studies 38 (1971);

    Hans Herzberger, Ordinal Preference and Rational Choice, Econometrica 41 (1973); and

    Levi, Hard Choices (1986).9 Levi, Hard Choices (1986, p. 9).

    10 An affine transformation is of the form: a + b.vi, and the positivity of such a trans-formation refers to b being positive. On the characteristics and uses of aggregations based

    on cardinal values (with uniqueness up to positive affine transformations), see my Col-

    lective Choice and Social Welfare (1970); Kotaro Suzumura, Rational Choice, Collective

    Decisions and Social Welfare, Cambridge University Press, Cambridge (1983); Levi, Hard

    Choices (1986).11 The weights w1, . . . , wn are not only non-negative each, but also they must sum to 1.12 Levi, Hard Choices (1986, Section 5.4, pp. 7779). See also the motivating discussion

    on pp. 6977.13 This may require us to go beyond the weighted average principle. An extreme case

    would be one in which there is a unique set of appropriate weights ( w1, . . . , wn). But

    categorical preferences over a subset of alternatives can arise in many different ways, and

    may even be precipitated, in some cases, by the weighted average principle.

    14 Levi, Hard Choices (1986, pp. 8355). Levi discusses these structures in the context ofexamining values revealed by choices, but they throw light also on the movement from

    values to choices, and not merely from choices to revealed values.15 There are many other structural features which Levi has investigated, which I shall not

    examine in this essay.16 Combined use of maximization and intersection can be found in many exercises in

    public economics. See for example A. B. Atkinson, The Measurement of Inequality,

    Journal of Economic Theory 2 (1970); Amartya Sen, On Economic Inequality, Clarendon

    Press, Oxford (1973); extended edition, with a joint Annexe with James Foster (1997).17 In On Economic Inequality (1973) it was called the intersection approach, taking

    maximization for granted.18 N. Bourbaki, Elements de Mathmatique, Herman, Paris, and Theory of Sets, Addison-

    Wesley, Reading, MA (1968); Gerard Debreu, The Theory of Value, John Wiley, New York

    (1959).19 Levi, Hard Choices (1986, p. 9).20 On this see my Maximization and the Act of Choice, Econometrica 65 (1997).21 Some of these possibilities have been explored in my Maximization and the Act

    of Choice (1997) and Consequential Evaluation and Practical Reason, Journal of

    Philosophy 97 (2000).22 I have a natural sympathy here for various reasons, including the fact that I had a similar

    motivation in trying to move social choice theory towards accommodating more informa-

    tion on cardinality and interpersonal comparability of well-being and also including more

    cognizance of freedoms and liberties, in Collective Choice and Social Welfare (1970).23 This is, of course, a very limited model of social choice, but adding further consid-

    erations, such as freedoms, liberties or rights, will not make the problem at hand any

    easier.24

    For the distinctions involved see my Collective Choice and Social Welfare (1970) andChoice, Welfare and Measurement (1982).25 For assessments of alternative contributions to the ways and means of using more in-

    formation in social evaluation, see my Social Choice Theory, in Kenneth Arrow and

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    17/18

    INCOMPLETENESS AND REASONED CHOICE 59

    Michael Intriligator (eds.), The Handbook of Mathematical Economics, North-Holland,

    Amsterdam (1986); and Kenneth Arrow, Amartya Sen and Kotaro Suzumura (eds.), Social

    Choice Re-examined, Elsevier, Amsterdam (1997).26 See my Collective Choice and Social Welfare (1970, Chaps. 7 and 8).

    27 The form offk may or may not be additive.28 I have discussed the notion of assertive incompleteness in Maximization and the

    Act of Choice, Econometrica 65 (1997); and in Justice and Assertive Incompleteness,

    Rosenthal Lectures (Lecture 2), Northwestern University Law School (1998).29 The fact that despite my arguing for the use of the capability perspective in comparing

    individual advantages and my attempt to highlight the relevance of some basic capabilities

    in particular (for example in Well-being, Agency and Freedom: The Dewey Lectures

    1984, Journal of Philosophy 82 (1985)), I have failed to specify a fixed list of distinct

    capabilities (with specified weights or other ways of prioritization) has been the source

    of some chastisement I have received. However, if such a fixed list with fixed priorities and

    fixed weights were indeed arrived at by general ethical reasoning, it is not clear to me how

    this would be consistent with the democratic process of setting priorities and precedence.30 Assertive incompleteness must not be confused with an assertion of indifference. If it is

    claimed that x and y cannot be ranked, then that is what it says, not that they can be rankedas equals. Indeed, in some ways incompleteness is the opposite of indifference. Consider

    two possible claims: (1) x is at least as good as y, and (2) y is at least as good as x. If x

    and y are indifferent, then both (1) and (2) are true, whereas if their ranking is assertively

    incomplete, then (1) and (2) are both denied. On this distinction, see my Collective Choice

    and Social Welfare (1970, Chap. 1), and Maximization and the Act of Choice (1997).31 I have tried to discuss the class of limited though possibly quite extensive

    informational discrimination in Interpersonal Aggregation and Partial Comparability,

    Econometrica 38 (1970), and in Collective Choice and Social Welfare (1970), and also

    in On Weights and Measures: Informational Constraints in Social Welfare Analysis,

    Econometrica 45 (1977).

    Trinity College

    Cambridge, CB2 1 TQ

    U.K.

    and

    Harvard University

    Cambridge, MA 02138

    U.S.A.

  • 8/6/2019 Amartya Sen - Incompleteness and Reasoned Choice 2004

    18/18