35
http://ant.sagepub.com Anthropological Theory DOI: 10.1177/1463499607077299 2007; 7; 217 Anthropological Theory R. Lee Lyman What is the `process' in cultural process and in processual archaeology? http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/7/2/217 The online version of this article can be found at: Published by: http://www.sagepublications.com can be found at: Anthropological Theory Additional services and information for http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Email Alerts: http://ant.sagepub.com/subscriptions Subscriptions: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.nav Reprints: http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.nav Permissions: http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/7/2/217 SAGE Journals Online and HighWire Press platforms): (this article cites 60 articles hosted on the Citations © 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.com Downloaded from

Anthropological Theory - kodu.ut.eekodu.ut.ee/~cect/teoreetilised seminarid_2009 sügis/1_seminar... · tory theory, that is, theory that ... duration, result in cultural change,

  • Upload
    vuxuyen

  • View
    219

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

http://ant.sagepub.com

Anthropological Theory

DOI: 10.1177/1463499607077299 2007; 7; 217 Anthropological Theory

R. Lee Lyman What is the `process' in cultural process and in processual archaeology?

http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/content/abstract/7/2/217 The online version of this article can be found at:

Published by:

http://www.sagepublications.com

can be found at:Anthropological Theory Additional services and information for

http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/alerts Email Alerts:

http://ant.sagepub.com/subscriptions Subscriptions:

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsReprints.navReprints:

http://www.sagepub.com/journalsPermissions.navPermissions:

http://ant.sagepub.com/cgi/content/refs/7/2/217SAGE Journals Online and HighWire Press platforms):

(this article cites 60 articles hosted on the Citations

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Anthropological Theory

Copyright © 2007 SAGE Publications(London, Los Angeles, New Delhi and Singapore)

http://ant.sagepub.comVol 7(2): 217–250

10.1177/1463499607077299

217

What is the ‘process’ incultural process and inprocessualarchaeology?R. Lee LymanUniversity of Missouri-Columbia, USA

AbstractThe concept of ‘cultural process’ has been of interest to anthropologists since the late19th century. Franz Boas indicated that investigating cultural processes was central toanthropology, but his failure to define the concept set a disciplinary precedent. Processhas seldom been discussed in theoretical detail because the basic notion iscommonsensical. A.L. Kroeber provided a definition in 1948 and distinguishedbetween short-term dynamics of how cultures operate and long-term dynamicsresulting in cultural change. Leslie White conflated the two families of processes.Archaeologists working before 1960 focused on processes resulting in the diachronicevolution of cultures; many of these involved cultural transmission. Initially, processesinvolving the synchronic operation of a culture were conflated with diachronicevolutionary processes by processual archaeologists. In the late 1960s and early 1970s,Lewis Binford, David Clarke, and Frank Hole and Robert Heizer all discussed culturalprocesses within the framework of systems theory. Simultaneously, growing concernover the formational processes that created the archaeological record shifted attentionfrom the original conception of cultural processes. Models of the temporal duration,scale, and magnitude of cultural processes illustrate their complexity and suggestavenues for further conceptualization.

Key Wordscause • cultural process • description • process • sequence of events

[W]e must develop not only better theory for conceptualizing processes but also moreadequate methods for studying them. (E.Z. Vogt, 1960: 28)

Like other fields, archeology is cursed with terms so vague and ambiguous that theytend to obscure more than they clarify. (K.V. Flannery, 1972: 400)

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

For more than a century, ‘cultural processes’ have been a guiding focus of anthropology(Bee, 1974). Whether the operation of one or more processes is studied within a particu-lar culture, or a specific process or two are called upon to explain particular culturalphenomena, cultural processes are central to the discipline. What, then, might culturalprocesses be in a conceptual or theoretical sense? One would think that given theircentral role in anthropology, a detailed and nuanced literature addressing this questionwould exist. An approximation of such a literature is scattered among journal articles,book chapters, and monographs, each containing no more than a sentence or twodevoted to the concept. Comprehensive treatments are virtually nonexistent; discussionsof theoretical models and conceptions of cultural process(es) are also scarce. Both Vogt’slament of more than 40 years ago and Flannery’s lament of more than 30 years ago inthe epigraph apply to the term ‘cultural process’. Yet, the so-called processual archaeol-ogy of the 1960s and 1970s had as a research focus the study of cultural process(es),sometimes written in the singular, sometimes in the plural form (Binford, 1968b;Flannery, 1967; Thompson and Longacre, 1966). I have found only two discussions ofthe cultural process concept in the literature of processual archaeology, and they areshort, given the apparent gravity of the concept.

The commonsensical understanding of (cultural) process held by anthropologists andarchaeologists concerns the dynamic of some (cultural) thing developing into some(other cultural) thing that may be different from the original. A series of stages or eventscan be used to illustrate a process but is descriptive rather than explanatory if the causeor causal mechanism producing the series is unspecified. Common sense understandingresulted in conflation of two families of cultural processes, a shift in the meaning ofcultural processes to the actions forming the archaeological record, and a muddling ofthe dynamic of becoming and the static state of being. This is not to say that the conceptof process has been useless, as evidenced, for example, by the plethora of researchaccomplished under the banner of processual archaeology (see articles introduced byA.L. Johnson [2004] and references therein).

Some argue that terminological clarity is either unnecessary (Salmon, 1982) ordifficult given the evolution of concepts that attends theory development (Hegmon,2003). Philosopher of archaeology Merilee Salmon (1982: 142) thus advocated a dialec-tic between a concept’s definition and how well it assists with building useful explana-tory theory, that is, theory that both constrains (by limiting the field of inquiry toparticular phenomena, questions, or both) and enables (by specifying explanatoryprinciples, how particular phenomena are thought to relate, and the like) how we under-stand and make sense of the world. Failure to make clear what a term means in a particu-lar context may, however, lead to confusion, disagreement, and lack of efficiency in theresearch enterprise; understanding is likely to be commonsensical and thus individual-istic. Further, a term’s meaning can transmogrify imperceptibly over time untilresearchers think they are talking about one thing when in fact they are talking aboutsomething else. Thus I believe that we must be concerned about conceptual and termi-nological ambiguity and seek to remove it (or at least identify it) whenever possible, butI also believe that definitions can and should shift as understanding changes and theoriesare rewritten.

In this article I do several things. First, I make four points with respect to the termculture/cultural process (both forms occur in the literature). In no particular order, these

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

218

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

points are: (1) labels for particular processes often conflate the dynamic of becomingwith the result or state of being, and also conflate process as cause with process as descrip-tion; (2) processes concerning the synchronic operation of a culture are sometimesconflated with those concerning the diachronic evolution of a culture; (3) a list ofprocesses gleaned from the literature published in the 1940s and 1950s includes nearlyall of those included in a list gleaned from the literature published in the 1970s and1980s; and (4) in archaeology, the concept of cultural process was subsumed withinformation processes in the 1970s, exacerbating terminological ambiguity.

To make these points, I explore the history of the term ‘cultural process’ to determinewhat it is thought to mean. My historical sketch is not exhaustive; such would take abook-length treatment. Instead, I summarize what is necessary to make the points I havejust listed. I first review how the concept has been used in cultural anthropology, wheremy focus is on the pre-1960 literature. This provides a context for discussing the conceptof culture process as it was used in archaeology; processual archaeology first emerged inNorth America where archaeologists are trained in departments of anthropology.Because I am particularly interested in the meaning(s) of the term with respect to proces-sual archaeology, I outline the history of the term in archaeology from the 1930s throughthe 1980s.

The historical review demonstrates that many who used the term often conflatedtwo families of processes. I term these the diachronic (historical) evolutionary familyand the synchronic operational family. The former are generally processes of longduration, result in cultural change, and implicitly indicate that culture is transmitted;processes include acculturation, enculturation, socialization, and diffusion.Synchronic operational processes are of relatively short duration and repetitive orcyclical; the state of a culture might fluctuate as that culture operates over time, butthe culture eventually returns to the state in which it began. One example is a first fruitsceremony held annually, and another would be a repetitive land-use pattern of seasonaltranshumance. Conflation of the two families was likely caused by common-senseunderstanding of the general concept; explicit definitional and theoretical understand-ing would likely have precluded such conflation. Common-sense understanding alsoseems to underpin the 1970s conflation of culture process with formation process byarchaeologists.

As a step toward replacing common sense with explicit models of cultural processes,I present a formal definition of the concept prior to presenting the historical overview.This should also help with perception of strengths and weaknesses in anthropologicaland archaeological use of the term. Toward the end of the discussion, I consider theimplications of differences in the duration and results of the two families of processes indetail, and also the scale and magnitude of processes. My intention is not to provide thefinal word on the concept. Rather, I present this discussion as a catalyst for additionalconceptualization of cultural process and how that term is used in the future. Archaeol-ogist Irving Rouse provided an excellent place to start the discussion:

By pattern is meant a configuration discernable in the archaeological [or anthropo-logical] record and by process, the actions that have produced the pattern. A patternis an empirical observation and a process, an explanation of that observation; it tellsus how the pattern came into existence. (1977: 1)

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

219

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

WHAT IS A CULTURAL PROCESS TO AN ANTHROPOLOGIST?Boas (1896: 905) stated that ‘the object of [anthropological] investigation is to find theprocesses by which certain stages of culture have developed’ (emphasis in original). Boashad in mind historical processes that accounted for why culture traits were found wherethey were and in the forms that they were (Bee, 1974; Rohner and Rohner, 1969).During the first half of the 20th century the major approach to anthropological researchwas ‘historical ethnology’ (Radin, 1933) or ‘historical particularism’ (Harris, 1968). Thisapproach examined the historical development of each individual culture by inferringthe age and distribution route of cultural traits (Lyman and O’Brien, 2003). Namesgiven to cultural processes indicate that they took place over time (were relativelydiachronic) and the analytical unit used (cultural traits or elements) implied that aculture consisted of independent, discrete parts. The processes included evolution anddiffusion (Boas, 1924), invention and innovation (Barnett, 1942, 1953; Ogburn, 1930;Steward, 1929), and convergence (Lowie, 1912). What exactly a cultural process wasconceptually went unremarked. Boas himself never was clear about what one was(Rohner and Rohner, 1969: xvii), and this set a precedent. It was not until historicalethnology was nearly dead that discussions of what processes are and definitions of thembegan to appear, yet these were brief and did not seek a general theoretical understand-ing that could assist future research (Barnett, 1940; Herskovits, 1945, 1948; Redfield,1934, 1941, 1953).

In the earliest explicit definition of which I am aware, Kroeber (1948: 344) defined‘processes of culture [as] factors which operate either toward the stabilization and preser-vation of cultures and their parts, or toward growth and change’. This statement refersto both synchronic operational processes and diachronic evolutionary ones, respectively.Kroeber listed the usual historical processes of diffusion, invention, and the like (e.g.Murdock, 1955, 1956), and he also observed that cultural processes ‘which in theabstract seem so neat and distinctive, are found to manifest themselves in associations’and that ‘conceptually distinct processes tend to come intertwined, and to interact, inthe actual operations and history of culture’ (Kroeber, 1948: 344–5). It will, Kroeberthought, be difficult to tease apart the complexities of distinct processes.

Moore (1954: 354) considered only diachronic evolution when he wrote that‘processes of a culture include not only changes in particular categories of the culturebut also changes in the relationships between categories and between individualsperforming the roles suited to the activity associated with each category. Thus culturalprocesses involve changes in the parts of a culture and changes in the interrelationshipsof the parts’. He, like Murdock (1955), used ‘cultural dynamics’ as a synonym for culturalprocesses (Moore, 1954: 355). Bidney (1953: 126) stated that the ‘cultural process, asapplied to man, differs from other natural processes in that the former is not autonomousand does not guide itself, but requires constant and deliberate selection and effort onthe part of its actual and potential adherents’. The culture process is dependent on‘human intelligence and voluntary effort’; it is the ‘creative inventions and insights’ ofhumans that are the ‘sources of all cultural processes’ (Bidney, 1953: 137, 138).

The notion that society itself is a process and is continuously becoming was part ofthe ‘Chicago school’ of sociology in the 1920s and 1930s (Lerner, 1934), and reflectedthe general process of cultural transmission. This process had specific manifestations

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

220

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

such as enculturation, socialization, diffusion, borrowing, education, learning, and thelike, and was thought to be the ultimate cause of cultural change and, particularly,stability (M.W. Willey, 1931). It is apparent in a statement by Mead (1943: 633) that‘education is the cultural process, the way in which each newborn infant, born with apotentiality for learning greater than that of any other mammal, is transformed into afull member of a specific human society, sharing with the other members a specifichuman culture’. Herskovits (1943: 737) noted that researchers (including anthropol-ogists studying primitive societies) had focused on education as a stabilizing force butthey should also study mechanisms that encouraged cultural change.

The International Symposium on Anthropology held in 1952 resulted in a largevolume of papers (Kroeber, 1953a) and a volume of discussions (Tax et al., 1953). Ofthe latter’s 20 sections, four include ‘Problems of Process’ as part of their titles. Nadelconsulted a dictionary to determine what a process is (Tax et al., 1953: 156). Linton was‘struck by the very slight attention paid to what is thought of in the United States ascultural process, that is, the whole field of diffusion, integration, invention, etc.’ (Tax etal., 1953: 219). Greenburg noted the concept ‘seems to be of rather strategic import-ance’ but was basically restricted to language change and ‘historical diachronic’dynamics, and that many language processes had analogous processes in culture (Tax etal., 1953: 287–9). In his concluding essay Kroeber (1953b: 367) equated processes to‘causal factors’. A few years later, evolutionary biologist Julian Huxley defined culturalprocess in evolutionary terms: ‘Culture in the anthropological sense is neither an entitynor a principle; it can only be treated as a type of process. [A culture] constitutes a self-reproducing and self-varying process whereby the pattern of human activities is trans-mitted and transformed in the course of time’ (1958: 437). This echoes the ‘Chicagoschool’ of sociology of 20 years earlier.

Spindler and Spindler (1959: 37) equated cultural processes with ‘culture change’.They noted that prior to the 1940s, the focus was on cultural traits as particles of culture;groups of people were culturally differentiated and interacted via diffusion. After the1940s, in Spindler and Spindler’s view (see also Bee, 1974), a culture was an adaptationsuch that cultural interaction could involve impact and subsequent (adaptive) adjust-ment. The conceptual change arose because of White (1949, 1959) and Steward (1955),who focused on the adaptational and functional aspects of cultures rather than theirhistorical transmission. The structural-functionalism of Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown also contributed to the shift (Barnard, 2000; Harris, 1968), as did a similar shiftin sociology (Matthews, 1989).

White (1948: 586) was influenced by Boas (Carneiro, 1981) and defined the cultureprocess as ‘a stream of [culture] elements that are continually interacting with oneanother, forming new combinations and syntheses, eliminating some elements fromthe stream, and incorporating new ones’. Such a statement was lacking in historicalethnology. White (1947: 693) indicated that because culture was ‘dependent on the useof symbols . . . its elements are readily transmitted [and thus] culture becomes acontinuum; it flows down through the ages from one generation to another and laterallyfrom one people to another’. White (1948: 586) noted that the culture process ‘has itsown principles and its own laws of change and development’. In an expanded discussion,White (1950: 76) said:

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

221

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

[The culture process is] a stream of interacting cultural elements – of instruments,beliefs, customs, etc. In this interactive process, each element impinges upon othersand in turn is acted upon by them. The process is a competitive one: instruments,customs, and beliefs may become obsolete and eliminated from the stream. Newelements are incorporated from time to time. New combinations and syntheses –inventions and discoveries – of cultural elements are continually being formed.

For White, the culture process not only is transmission (dynamic becoming), it involvesadaptation (as both dynamic becoming and a state of being) and also interaction (a stateof being).

White (1959: 16, 17) later reiterated that culture was ‘a stream flowing down throughtime [comprising a] process’ and added that the ‘interrelationship of [culture traits] andtheir integration into a single, coherent whole comprise the functions, or processes, ofthe cultural system’. The operation of a culture involved ‘life-sustaining processes: subsis-tence, protection from the elements, defense from enemies, combating disease, etc.’(White, 1959: 19). He used the term process to denote both the diachronic evolutionand the synchronic operation of a culture. Others did likewise (e.g. Hsu, 1959).

Carneiro, a student of White’s (Carneiro, 1981), defined process as a general phenom-enon constituting ‘the interaction through time of the elements of a system as the systemchanges from one state to another’ (Carneiro, 1960: 145). Change is ‘determinate [and]is an expression of underlying natural laws’ (1960: 145). Elements are the structural unitsof a system, and they are ‘a conceptually separable class of phenomena’ including suchthings as the ‘division of labor, cannibalism, hunting magic, plow agriculture, and cross-cousin marriage’ (1960: 146). A system is ‘a set of structurally and functionally relatedelements articulated into a working whole’ (1960: 146). The ‘essence of process is changeof some kind’, and ‘we may think of process as a very rapid succession of synchronicstates of a system, each one only slightly modified over the preceding one’ (1960: 147).

Carneiro (1960: 148) argued that ‘We can arbitrarily, but quite justifiably, delimit aparticular segment of the culture process and proceed to investigate it by itself. [Onecould] analyze the culture process logically into a number of constituent subprocesses’.Cultural anthropologists had, he noted, ‘found it convenient to analyze [the cultureprocess] into such constituent [sub]processes as evolution, invention, diffusion, accul-turation, integration, segmentation, and many more’ (Carneiro, 1960: 148). These arethe standard historical processes; all are within the diachronic evolution family.

Steward (1949: 3) argued that to be a science, anthropology had to seek patterns incultural data and to ‘ascertain processes that are duplicated independently in culturalsequences, and to recognize cause and effect in both temporal and functional relation-ships’. In his view, recitation of history was not an explanation of process, nor was iden-tifying which process(es) occurred in a particular case a scientific explanation becausesuch did not fully account for why that process worked in that particular case. He couldnot define specific processes (Steward, 1949: 24) and concluded by quoting Strong(1943: 41): When sufficient ‘comparative data are in hand the generalizations that willemerge may well revolutionize our concepts of culture history and culture process overthe millennia’. More research was needed to define particular processes and to discoveras yet unknown ones. Strong (1943: 30) noted that ‘culture process throughout theworld seems to many of us to proceed according to as yet dimly perceived patterns which

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

222

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

only hard-won knowledge can clarify’. He was arguing, as did others at the time (e.g.Steward, 1949) and also later (e.g. Rouse, 1977; Terrell, 1986), that research shouldinvolve documentation of patterns in the archaeological record as prerequisite to discern-ing cultural processes.

White and Steward, along with Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown (Barnard, 2000;Harris, 1968), were concerned with cultural processes other than the standard histori-cal ones of diffusion, invention, and the like, and they influenced numerous individualswho followed them (Bee, 1974). Discussion of the historical processes did not, however,disappear after the 1950s. For example, some followed White and Steward and treatedadaptation as a process of becoming (e.g. Kaplan and Manners, 1972) or as a state ofbeing (e.g. Cohen, 1968).

When theoretically oriented discussions of cultural processes appeared in the 1960s,there was no guarantee they would clarify matters. Beals et al. (1967: 6) provide one ofthe only explicit definitions of process in the general anthropology literature of which Iam aware: ‘A process is a series of [causally, functionally, mechanically] interlinked eventswhich commences under certain defined conditions and which concludes under certaindefined conditions’. This definition leaves one wondering if the ‘defined conditions’ arespecified by the people whose actions comprise the events or by the anthropologist. Bealset al. (1967: 258–9) also imply that ‘processual analysis’ in cultural anthropologyinvolves, first, observing the same process multiple times, keeping track of all variablesthat seem to be interlinked, and those that seem to be independent and free to vary.Second, arranging observations in a temporal series such that ‘acts and circumstancesand variations that occur when the process is repeated’, both within a cultural systemand in multiple cultural systems, facilitates comparative analyses and the building ofabstract models of processes (Beals et al., 1967: 258–9). Whether the model comprisedonly a sequence of events, or the sequence plus their interlinkages, or the sequence plusthe interlinkages plus any causal variables is unclear.

Steward (1968: 321) clarified things a bit when he commented that the presentationsat the 1966 Man the Hunter conference indicated a discipline-wide failure to perfect ‘amethodology for determining cause-and-effect relationships in the evolution ofdifferent kinds of culture’. He noted that the flaw of the comparative method resided inthe presumption that similar cross-cultural patterns denoted similar processes (andadmitted to here contradicting his 1949 discussion). ‘Processes may be considered causesin one sense, [but] for present purposes [he defined them] as changes set in motion whenmore ultimate cultural and environmental factors are utilized by human societies’(Steward, 1968: 322). Instead of discussing processes per se, Steward (1968) stressed thedistinction between processes and ‘causal factors’. The latter included cultural andnatural variables such as available technology and environmental potentials. Causalfactors constituted the historical contingencies that constrained and channeled theoperation of processes, and thus they helped account for why one process rather thananother operated in a particular case. But what a process was other than a sequence ofinterlinked events remained unclear.

Bee (1974: 3) noted that ‘much of the theory and methodology of [cultural] changestudies has not rigorously and consistently dealt with the problem of processes ofchange’. He found that processes varied from approach to approach within anthropol-ogy. Bee (1974: 3–4) defined process as ‘the interaction of causal forces so as to produce

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

223

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

a given condition. By “change process”, I mean the interaction of causal factors so as toproduce a transformation of one condition into another’. In the first sentence he wasusing process to denote the synchronic operation of a culture and in the second sentenceprocess denotes the diachronic evolution of a culture. Bee, like others, used the termsprocess and mechanism as synonyms.

Bohannan (1995: 81) echoed Boas when the former said ‘Discovering the processesis the goal of every science’. Bohannan’s concern was with both how cultures operate andhow they change. He used more modern terms for some processes – transformation,turbulence, equilibrium – but also included older terms such as diffusion and innova-tion. He mentioned ‘cultural process theory’ (1995: 57), but never defined the term.Sometimes he contrasted ‘culture process’ and ‘culture change’ (and implied that theformer involved the synchronic operation of a culture; 1995: 83), and other times heindicated that cultural evolution itself was a process (1995: 131). Bohannan used‘process’ to denote both the synchronic operation and the diachronic evolution of aculture. Use of the same term between 1940 and 1990 to denote two distinct familiesof dynamics no doubt contributed to the conflation of the two in archaeology. I turnnext to the history of the term in that subfield.

PRE-PROCESSUAL ARCHAEOLOGYThe programmatic literature produced by processual archaeologists during the 1960sand 1970s gives the impression that earlier archaeologists were doing descriptive historyand were not interested in cultural processes (e.g. Binford, 1968a, 1968b; Flannery,1967; Judge, 1982; Watson et al., 1971). Even pre-processual archaeologists occasion-ally stated that this was indeed the case: ‘Americanist studies over the last thirty yearshave been largely preoccupied with historical rather than processual objectives’ (Willey,1953: 362). Willey (1953: 369) also noted that ‘the processes by which, or throughwhich, cultural continuity and change are maintained or accomplished have not receivedthe study and reflective thought commensurate with the way these concepts have beeninvoked by American archeologists’. But pre-processual archaeologists – those usuallyreferred to as culture historians who worked prior to the 1960s – were indeed concernedwith cultural processes. The family of processes they focused on, however, was thestandard historical one involving cultural transmission. What Willey (1953) and othersin the 1950s and 1960s had in mind was the other family of cultural processes – the oneinvolving the synchronic functional operation of cultures.

Steward and Setzler (1938: 6–7) noted that archaeology ‘can shed light not only onthe chronological and spatial arrangements and associations of [cultural traits], but onconditions underlying their origin, development, diffusion, acceptance, and interactionwith one another. These are problems of cultural process, problems that archaeology andanthropology should have in common’. Although the terms differed from author toauthor between about 1920 and 1960, the cultural processes Steward and Setzler listedwere the standard historical ones.

McGregor (1941: 49) stated that the archaeologist is ‘interested in three sorts ofrelationships: a local series of genetically, or developmentally, related events; the influ-ence which this series had on other regions; and the influence outside areas had on itsdevelopment’. Here, ‘influence’ can be loosely glossed as ‘pathways or modes of culturaltransmission’. McGregor’s graph (Figure 1) illustrates well the basic transmission modes

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

224

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

of evolution: lineal, known in modern evolution as phyletic or anagenetic (1a); fusional,or reticulate, with two variants (1b, 1c); diversifying, or cladogenetic (1d); and replace-ment, or extirpation coincident with immigration (1e). A decade later McGregor (1950)noted that a cultural tradition depended on persistence created by continuous trans-mission – the American standard definition of a cultural tradition (Thompson, 1956;Willey, 1945).

Meggers (1955: 117), another student of White’s, implied that what would today becalled cultural transmission was a generic cultural process that could take the form ofdiffusion or migration. It is a stretch to perceive in Meggers’s (1955) discussion theimplication that invention and innovation are cultural processes, but I doubt that shewould disagree. In her view, archaeology deserved pride of place among anthropologicalsubfields because it was ‘shorn of the complicating and confusing psychological reactionsof numbers of unique human personalities [and thus] cultural processes emerge in a starkand clear light’ (Meggers, 1955: 129). Like many of her contemporaries, Meggers appar-ently assumed that everyone understood that the family of processes involved culturaltransmission. The family of processes of interest was, however, changing.

Taylor (1948: 108) stated that ‘cultural processes are the dynamic factors involvingcultural traits; they . . . comprise the relationships between cultural traits’. Cultural traitsfor Taylor were mental, ideological, conceptual. He explicitly identified the culturalprocesses of ‘diffusion, culture contact, and acculturation’ and implied that there wereothers (1948: 108). He insisted that archaeologists determine prehistoric ‘culturalcontexts’, defined as the ‘associations and relations of [cultural traits], of the balancebetween them, [and] of their relative quantitative and qualitative positions within the[cultural] whole’ (1948: 110). Study of artifact types that represented cultural traits

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

225

Formal variation

Tim

e

a

A B B B

A�

A� A� C CB B

A A A A

b c d e

Figure 1. McGregor’s models of historical processes: a, ‘genetic’ or lineal series; b andc, fusional series; d, divergence, or splitting; e, replacement of one series by another.Formal variation is continuous on the horizontal axis; capital letters signify form suchthat a change from one letter to another denotes a relatively major change whereasaddition of a prime symbol denotes a minor change. After McGregor (1941).

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

within a cultural context would, Taylor (1948: 36) argued, reveal ‘the nature of culture,of cultural constants, of processes, or regularities, and of chronological development’.This sort of archaeological research was, in Taylor’s view, equivalent to cultural anthro-pology and what he called historiography. It involved the study of the ‘statics anddynamics of culture, its formal, functional, and developmental aspects’ (Taylor, 1948;see also Taylor, 1972).

Taylor’s insistence on the importance of cultural context means that he was interestedin studying the synchronic operation of a culture. The ‘chronological development’ ofthose contexts was, apparently, to be discerned by ‘comparative study of the nature andworkings of culture in its formal, functional, and/or developmental aspects’ (Taylor,1948: 41). Taylor (1948) did not indicate the role of cultural processes in such studies.Despite the fact that Taylor’s A Study of Archeology is sometimes said to anticipate theprocessual archaeology of the 1960s and 1970s, Taylor (1948) said little else aboutcultural processes, and he did not (Taylor, 1972) complain that processual archaeologistshad ignored his discussion of cultural processes. He could not do the latter as there waslittle concerning cultural processes for the processualists to ignore.

Caldwell (1959: 304) claimed that ‘the new American archeology’ contrasted withthe earlier culture history approach, which had focused on ‘writing a history ofmaterial culture’; the new approach was ‘tending to be more concerned with cultureprocess’. Although he implied that culture processes included diffusion, innovation,and migration, his discussion suggests that by ‘culture process’ Caldwell meant in partthe interrelations between natural environment and culture – the functional adapta-tional processes. He, like others at the time (e.g. Griffin, 1956; Thompson, 1956),noted variation in the ‘rates and magnitudes of changes in cultural forms’, and thatthe rate could be zero or equivalent to stasis (Caldwell, 1959: 304). Caldwellconcluded with the hypothesis that ‘behind the infinite variability of cultural factsand behind the infinite and largely unknown detail of historical situations we shalldiscover the workings of a finite number of general cultural processes’ (1959: 306).Mimicking the disciplinary standard (e.g. Hawkes, 1954; MacWhite, 1956; Meggers,1955; Rowe, 1959), Caldwell did not distinguish the two families of processes or theprocesses within each.

Willey and Phillips (1958: 4–5) were interested in ‘processual interpretation’ ofcultural chronologies. ‘Processual interpretation’ was a rewording of what Phillips (1955:248) had termed ‘functional interpretation’. Willey (1953) had earlier equated the two.Willey and Phillips (1958: 5) indicated that by ‘processual interpretation’ they meant‘any explanatory principle that might be invoked’. They emphasized that processualinterpretation was ‘explanatory’ and that their favored agents of change were humangroups because of the latter’s ‘social reality’ (1958: 6). Willey and Phillips (1958) distin-guished the family of processes responsible for the synchronic operation of a culture fromthe family of processes responsible for the diachronic evolution of a culture.

Adams (1956, 1960) mentioned ‘processes’, ‘processes of growth’, ‘historicalprocesses’, ‘agencies of change’, and ‘social forces’, but did not indicate what these mightbe. Adams was following Steward (1949) and Willey (1950: 223), the latter of whomwas referring to ‘cultural growth and development’ when he posed the question ‘To whatextent can we reconstruct the determinative factors which are responsible for thesevertical [that is, temporal] patternings?’ Willey (1950) was no more explicit than Adams

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

226

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

when he listed various processes. He did, however, attempt to indicate how they inter-related when, in the last paragraph of his discussion, he stated

the interaction of technology and environment gives terrific impetus to the culture;and this impetus, mounting snowball fashion, carries the society along in itsmomentum. Sooner or later historical forces concur to smash or disarrange thesedynamic patterns. The result, cultural death, deflection, or a new integration,depends to a great extent on the rigidity and velocity with which the original culturalgrowth has been molded and propelled toward its fate. (Willey, 1950: 242)

Pre-processual archaeologists called upon various cultural processes to help explainvariation in the archaeological record that corresponded with the passage of time. Notsurprisingly, the processes they referred to were the standard ones of historical ethnol-ogy. By the 1950s, other sorts of processes were being mentioned, and these likely orig-inated in the shift in anthropology generally from historical ethnology to theevolutionism of White and Steward, along with doses of structuralism and functional-ism from Malinowski and Radcliffe-Brown. The shift began to crystallize in archaeol-ogy in the 1960s with the emergence of processual archaeology. It has been said thatprocessual archaeology ‘placed [emphasis] upon the explanation of change or stabilitywith a view to the understanding of general cultural processes’ (Sterud, 1978: 295). Butthe key concept – cultural process – was rarely discussed in detail.

WHAT IS A CULTURAL PROCESS IN PROCESSUAL ARCHAEOLOGY?Willey and Sabloff (1993: 221) believe that the ‘central concern [of processual archaeol-ogists] was the elucidation of cultural processes’, new archaeologists of the 1960s ‘felt thatthe time had come for serious attack on questions of process’, and processual archaeol-ogists sought to ‘reveal and explain cultural processes’. They equate a cultural process witha ‘causal factor’ (Willey and Sabloff, 1993: 170). In the ‘birth announcement’ of proces-sual archaeology, Binford (1962: 217) indicated that a culture was an extrasomaticadaptive system, and that ‘process’ concerned ‘the operation and structural modificationof systems’. He had both synchronic and diachronic processes in mind if by ‘the opera-tion’ he meant how the culture system worked at any one point in time and if by ‘struc-tural modification’ he meant change in how the system worked over time. Binford (1965:204) characterized the culture history approach as assuming one particular cultureprocess: ‘the dynamics of ideational transmission’. The process or dynamic was ‘learning[based on] cultural transmission between generations and diffusion between social unitsnot linked by regular breeding behavior’ (Binford, 1965: 204). Additional ‘dynamics’that contributed to the effects of cultural transmission were ‘barriers to social inter-course’, migration, ‘drift’ and innovation (1965: 204). Binford sought to replace thisnotion with a different conception of culture in order ‘to deal adequately with the expla-nation of cultural process’ (1965: 205); he followed White (1959: 8) and defined cultureas ‘an extrasomatic adaptive system’ and stated that ‘the locus of cultural process is inthe dynamic articulations of [cultural] subsystems’; this is process as synchronic opera-tion. Understanding of cultural processes demanded comparative study of the ‘rates andpatterns of change in different classes of cultural phenomena’ (Binford, 1965: 209); thisis diachronic evolution and seems to echo Carneiro (1960).

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

227

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

A few years later Binford (1968a: 14) wrote that:

Different authors have referred to different phenomena in their discussions of cultureprocess. The phrase has been used to refer to the dynamic relationships (causes andeffects) operative among sociocultural systems, to those processes responsible forchanges observed in the organization and/or content of the systems, or to the inte-gration of new formal components into the system. The term cultural process hasbeen used by others to refer to patterns or configurations in the temporal or spatialdistributions of the archeological materials themselves (see Wauchope, 1966: 19–38).The first set of meanings – that of dynamic relationships operative among culturalsystems – is the one used by this author and by the other authors in this volume.

The volume of which Binford spoke is New Perspectives in Archeology (Binford andBinford, 1968a). All contributors to that volume may indeed have subscribed to the defi-nition Binford presented, but only one of them used the term ‘process’. Sackett (1968:69) was concerned with ‘the processes that determined [the] form and mode of change’of cultural units within the upper Paleolithic of France.

Binford (1968a) accuses Wauchope (1966) of using ‘cultural process’ to refer to patternsof artifacts. Wauchope was, among other things, noting that the assumption underpin-ning archaeological studies of cultural process – stability in artifacts represents culturalstability, change in artifacts represents cultural change – was problematic. He was notsaying that patterns in artifacts were processes or even that they were representative ofprocesses, but rather that they might not represent cultural processes. I refer to this here-after as Wauchope’s dilemma and note that it anticipates the concern with formationprocesses that emerges in the 1970s. Wauchope was also concerned that there was no satis-factory means to ‘weigh the importance of different categories of cultural stability [andchange]’ such as whether, say, ‘changes in the amount of temper used in pottery paste [wasequivalent to] changes in the design or style of ceramic decoration’ (Wauchope, 1966:20). The magnitude of change among artifacts might not be directly related to themagnitude of a cultural process (assuming that it was related at all). But Wauchope(1966) was concerned with only the family of diachronic evolutionary processes; Binfordwas interested in both families, as were others (e.g. Longacre, 1968; Struever, 1968).What was the best way to access these processes and to conceive of them?

Binford (1962: 223) pointed out that models of how cultural systems worked andevolved had to be tested ‘against ethnographic data’ because it was only in the ethno-graphic context that one could see the actual operation of cultural processes. He(Binford, 1977: 7) later argued that archaeologists ‘evaluate ideas [that they] may holdabout the conditions that brought about change and modification in the organizationof dynamics occurring in past living systems. We seek understanding of the processesresponsible for change and diversification in the organizational properties of livingsystems’. The favor bestowed on systems theory by many processualists (see later in thisarticle) originated in part with the fact that the theory forced one to think of a cultureas a set of multiple variables with particular structural and functional interrelationships(Carneiro, 1960; Flannery, 1967; Watson et al., 1971: 85), somewhat like White,Steward, Malinowski, and Radcliffe-Brown urged, and how some of their predecessorshad conceived of a culture (e.g. Linton, 1936).

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

228

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Flannery (1968: 74) identified two ‘regulatory mechanisms’ that operated in a culturalsystem: ‘seasonality’ concerns when, during a year, plant and animal resources are avail-able or ripe for exploitation, and ‘scheduling’ concerns how humans resolve conflicts inseasonality such as when two resources are available simultaneously but in different areas,perhaps prompting men to exploit one and women the other resource. Within the overallresource procurement system, seasonality and scheduling constituted ‘deviation counter-acting’ mechanisms that promoted stability of the system (Flannery, 1968: 79). Flannery(1972: 404) later wrote of ‘mechanisms by which a “tribe” becomes a chiefdom, and achiefdom a state’; this is a thinly veiled reference to the generic process of culturalevolution.

In the second sentence of the text of what might arguably be the first programmatictextbook for processual archaeology, Watson et al. (1971: 3) include ‘cultural processes’,but the term is not defined there. Nineteen pages later, it is defined in a footnote:‘“Cultural process” or “culture process” usually means the synchronic or diachronicfunctioning and interrelationships of the systems and sub-systems that comprise aparticular culture or human society; that is, the way a culture works at any one point intime, or the way it changes through time’ (Watson et al., 1971: 22). In the second editionof their book they place this same definition in the text, but it is a parenthetical inclusion,and it appears considerably later in the book (Watson et al., 1984: 44). This is strangetreatment for a key concept, but it is not unique with respect to cultural process.

There are many examples of using but not defining the definitive concept of proces-sual archaeology (e.g. Arnold, 1985; Bender and Wright, 1988; Flannery, 1968, 1972,1999; Glasow, 1978; A.L. Johnson 2004; Preucel, 1991; Redman, 1973; Renfrew, 1969,1973, 1982, 1994; Rosenswig, 2000; Rowlands, 1982; Sterud, 1978). In his introduc-tion to an edited volume that resulted from a seminar explicitly meant to explore thevirtues of adopting systems theory, Hill (1977: 8) noted that many key concepts andterms used in the seminar were not discussed, ‘definitionally or otherwise. It was simplyunderstood that definitions would constitute irrelevant academics – these concepts arenot in need of definition’. Perhaps this sort of thinking contributed to the majority ofprocessual archaeologists not defining cultural process. Whatever the case, the authorscited in this paragraph imply that processes are internal to the subject culture, concernadaptation as a state of being or how things operated synchronically (a state of being),and/or concern adaptation as a diachronic dynamic of becoming that focuses oncause–effect relationships. Although using the same term to signify both a static state ofbeing and the dynamic of becoming reduces jargon, it seems to have resulted in ambi-guity with respect to whether an author was discussing a dynamic cause or describing astatic result. It also resulted in a general failure to explore precisely what a particularprocess is or does, what happens mechanically, structurally, and so forth when thatprocess is in operation, and if and how the entity under scrutiny differs between timeswhen the process is in operation and when it is not. I believe such concerns never arosein part because by the 1970s the commonsensical meaning of the concept had shifted.

SHIFTING MEANINGS OF CULTURAL PROCESSI suspect that what made the concept of cultural process difficult to discuss in the 1970sand 1980s was that it was a ‘vogue word’ – a word that was used to show that the userhad acquired the term and all the supposed intellectual accessories that went with it

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

229

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

(Service, 1969). M. Johnson (1999: 188) correctly suggested that conceptual ambiguitywas exacerbated because the term process could be ‘used by an author in one sense andread in quite another’. This ambiguity allowed an unremarked shift in the meaning ofthe term over time.

Binford (1968b; see also Binford and Binford, 1968b) not only recognized the differ-ence between the category of processes comprising the synchronic operation family andthe diachronic evolution family, but he also noted that the archaeological record hadbeen created by human behaviors, among other processes, and that the creation processescomprised a different category (Figure 2). He argued that an archaeologist must distin-guish between explaining the archaeological record – a modern static phenomenon –and an extinct cultural system – a past dynamic phenomenon. A processual archaeol-ogist seeks to understand ‘processual relationships among various classes of materialitems in the dynamics of cultural systems’, but such understanding can only come afterone has explained

observations made on the archaeological record [which] necessarily involves copingwith problems of process. We attempt to explain similarities and differences inarchaeological remains in terms of the functioning of material items in a culturalsystem and the processual features of the operation or evolution of the culturalsystems responsible for the varied artifact forms, associations, and distributionsobservable in the ground. (Binford, 1968b: 273)

In the last quoted sentence, the wording before the second ‘and’ refers to behavioralprocesses that create the archaeological record; the words after that refer to the dynamiccultural processes (both synchronic operational and diachronic evolutionary) at workwhen the culture existed.

The distinction is made by an archaeologist interested in contributing to anthropo-logical theory (Binford, 1962). It, along with Schiffer’s (1976) more detailed discussion,

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

230

1. formationalCategory

Family natural synchronicoperational

diachronicevolutionary

cultural

PROCESSES

2. cultural, social, behavioral

Figure 2. A taxonomy of processes discussed by archaeologists. The dashed linesymbolizes the fact that those interested in formation processes sometimes conflatecultural formation processes with the category of cultural, social, and behavioralprocesses.

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

ultimately led to refocusing the processual approach not on what might be thought ofas the ultimate goal of identifying category 2 processes – those involving the operationand evolution of dynamic cultural systems – but on the more archaeologically proximategoal of category 1 processes – what became known as processes that result in the forma-tion of the archaeological record (Schiffer, 1987). (I use 1 and 2 merely to signify orderof analysis.) By the middle 1980s, for example, the text of an edited book entitled Struc-ture and Process in Southeastern Archaeology, comprising 14 chapters authored by 16archaeologists (Dickens and Ward, 1985), hardly mentions category 2 (cultural)processes and instead focuses nearly exclusively on category 1 (formation) processes.Schiffer (1988) highlighted the distinctiveness of the two categories when he distin-guished between ‘reconstruction theory’ (concerning category 1 processes) and ‘socialtheory’ (concerning category 2 processes). In her introduction to the recent volumeProcessual Archaeology, A.L. Johnson (2004) suggests that processes involve how acultural system operates and also how the archaeological record is formed.

Additional evidence that formation processes usurped the priority of culturalprocesses is found in recent perspectives on Wauchope’s dilemma. Keegan (1991)suggests that at least some processes of interest are the behavioral processes that createdthe archaeological record, and others are the cultural processes or dynamics of an existingculture. Following Terrell (1986), Keegan (1991: 186–7) indicates that ‘culturalprocesses are the unfolding patterns of variability through time in conformity withnomothetic principles’. Terrell (1986) seems to have skirted Wauchope’s dilemma bysuggesting that repetitive archaeological patterns were the results of predictable types ofpatterned human behavior. Echoing Kroeber (1948), Cunningham (2003: 391) indi-cates that ‘causal processes interact and combine in the creation of material patterns’.This results in three things. First, a particular pattern ‘can be created by entirely differentsets of causal processes’ (2003: 392); this is equifinality (Lyman, 2004). Second, analyti-cal reconfiguration of processes allows one to ‘explain behavior that may differ substan-tially from any modern situation’ (Cunningham, 2003: 394). And third, differentprocesses and combinations thereof create different patterns in the material record(2003: 395). Identifying which processes and combinations thereof create whichpatterns is not only the goal of formation process studies (Schiffer, 1987) and middlerange research (Cunningham, 2003), but it is, seemingly, now of importance equal tothat of identifying the cultural, social, and behavioral processes that processual archaeol-ogists originally sought.

DISCUSSIONS OF CULTURAL PROCESS BY PROCESSUALARCHAEOLOGISTSEisenberg (1971) argued that Deetz’s (1965) analysis exemplifies processual archaeologybecause it adopts the view of a culture as a system and seeks to understand the role ofkinds of artifacts (in Deetz’s case, ceramic decorations) in a cultural system. It was infact a systems-theory perspective that produced the two most detailed discussions ofcultural processes by archaeologists of which I am aware. One was by David Clarke; theother was by Frank Hole and Robert Heizer.

Clarke (1968: 22) wrote that the ‘primary processes are those of inevitable variation,multilinear development, invention, diffusion and cultural selection. Combined inmany permutations and circumstances these processes give rise to such complex

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

231

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

processes as acculturation, and cultural growth, decay and disintegration’. He explicitlydefined a process as ‘a vector which describes a series of states of an entity or systemundergoing continuous change in space or time’ (Clarke, 1968: 42, 668). Clarke (1968:43) believed that a ‘general system model . . . should be representative of culturalprocesses at several levels within a sociocultural unit’. He sought ‘a model for archaeo-logical processes – archaeological entities changing as special kinds of dynamic systems,susceptible to analysis in terms of general systems theory’ (1968: 72). He indicated that‘We should not expect the processes that operate upon cultures or culture groups to bethe same as those that operate upon artifact attributes, although since the former entitiesare compounds of the latter elements we might expect the processes appropriate tohigher entities to integrate the simpler processes as well’ (1968: 409). The first part ofthe immediately preceding sentence echoes Wauchope’s dilemma, and the last partconcerns the magnitude and scale of processes.

Clarke (1968) lists various processes and provides a detailed and relatively lengthystatement on category 2 (cultural, behavioral, social) processes that he thought operatedon or within most sociocultural entities. He specified three ‘general processes’ –ontogeny, migration, interaction – and then suggested that each was manifest in variousways by development of variants, decrease of variety, increase of variety, and transform-ation of variety of cultural elements (Clarke, 1968: 409–10). The problem, Clarkethought, was to derive a ‘nested hierarchy of socio-archaeological processes’ – processesthat linked sociocultural change to change in artifacts of whatever scale (Clarke, 1968:411); this is an effort to resolve Wauchope’s dilemma. Each process Clarke listed is ageneral kind that includes more specific kinds of processes. Many of his processes fallwithin the diachronic evolutionary family.

Changes in Hole and Heizer’s multi-edition introductory textbook capture thegrowing importance of culture processes in archaeology. There is minimal mention ofculture processes in the first two editions (Hole and Heizer, 1965, 1969), but the 1969edition contains a discussion of the importance of systems theory to understandingcultural dynamics. The third edition (Hole and Heizer, 1973: 439) discusses culturalprocesses explicitly.

The term ‘process’ or ‘processes’ crops up frequently in the writings of scientificarcheology, and it is also used in history, in manufacturing, and in analysis. As weunderstand the term colloquially it refers to the sequential set of operations that leadfrom A to B . . . [Given examples in history, manufacturing and research one] canreadily see that process means two quite different things. First, it may refer to asequence of events. Second, it may refer to the causes of the sequence of events. Inboth meanings, process is conceptually linked with the states or conditions of thethings under observation at different times. As process is used in archeology, it refersto an analysis of the factors that cause changes in state.

The authors provide the same discussion in an abridged version of their book (Hole andHeizer, 1977: 358), where they also define ‘process’ in the glossary as ‘the operation offactors that result in a change of culture’ (1977: 387). Note that Hole and Heizerindicate that a process can be a simple description of a sequence of events, or it canrefer to cause(s) of that sequence. Given processual archaeology’s hopes to explain the

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

232

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

archaeological record rather than just describe it (Lyman and O’Brien, 2004), a reason-able inference is that processualists sought to identify causal processes that operatedprehistorically.

One of the alleged benefits of archaeologists adopting systems theory was that ‘ques-tions phrased in terms of [systems] concepts direct our attention away from institutionsand events and toward processes, away from efforts to discover the first appearance ofparticular cultural practices and toward efforts to understand their gradual evolution,and away from constructions of these events that are relatively hard to define in termsof archaeological observations toward ones that are more sensitive to the data with whichwe deal’ (Plog, 1975: 215). Plog is unclear, but I suspect he hoped to identify dynamiccause(s) rather than describe static events in temporal terms. Thus perhaps Plog wasconcerned with how a cultural system operates. Salmon (1978: 175), after all, pointedout that ‘anthropologists were engaged in analyzing social and cultural systems longbefore the advent of modern systems theory’ (see for example Kluckhohn’s [1951]discussion of Linton [1936]). This is particularly evident if one is aware of the struc-tural–functional approaches in anthropology early in the 20th century, and also of thetypical definition of a system as the relationships (mechanical, structural, functional)between entities comprising the system (Hill, 1977; Maruyama, 1963; Plog, 1975;Salmon, 1978). Systems theory seems to be preadapted to studying the dynamic oper-ation (static state of being) of a cultural system.

When Clarke wrote his magnum opus, he modeled his recommendations for archaeo-logical research on systems theory. But he did so with the following explicit and emphaticcaution:

It would be all too easy to take systems theory as our model for archaeological [thatis, sociocultural] processes and the cultural entities that generate them, without isolat-ing precisely the kind of system these entities represent. This would simply extendsystems theory and its terminology as yet another vague analogy of no practicalpotential. (Clarke, 1968: 39)

Because in Clarke’s (1968: 39) view, anthropologists were ‘only just beginning to analyzesocial systems in [systems theory] terms’, he devoted the majority of the nearly 700 pagesof Analytical Archaeology to building a model of culture, including artifacts, as a system.He used systems theory concepts and terms such as ‘feedback’ and ‘homeostasis’ in hismodeling efforts, but his cultural processes were not categorized by him as the genericdeviation counteracting ones of the first cybernetics meant to study stasis nor the devi-ation amplifying ones of the second cybernetics meant to study change (Maruyama,1963). Rather, they were ‘technocomplex repatterning’, ‘culture group repatterning’,‘acculturation’, ‘diffusion’, ‘invention’, and the like (Clarke, 1968: 410–12). Flannery(1968, 1972), on the other hand, categorized the cultural processes he identified (season-ality, scheduling, centralization, segregation) as either one or the other of these twogeneral categories (deviation counteracting or amplifying), and he, like Clarke, identi-fied and named specifically cultural processes.

A significant influence on processual archaeologists’ focus on cultural processes wasMaruyama’s (1963) discussion of the second cybernetics, or ‘deviation-amplifyingmutual causal processes’ (see Flannery, 1968, 1972; Hill, 1977; Plog, 1975 for an

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

233

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

introduction). In his 16-page article, Maruyama used the term ‘process’ 40 times, or 2.5times per page. What Maruyama means by the term is never explicit. I suggest that hemeant several things, including dynamic causes, relationships (mechanical, functional)between variables or entities, and influences of one variable or entity on another. Perhapsbecause it is unclear whether he meant static mechanical relations or causally dynamicones, to this day some authors define a cultural process such as ‘centralization’ as ‘thedegree of linkage between the various subsystems and the highest-order controls of acultural system’ (Spencer, 1997: 215). This definition does not identify a dynamic causethough it does imply some kind of mechanical or functional relationship betweenphenomena. The name of a process has been applied to both a dynamic cause and itsresult. This seems to be the way that Maruyama (1963) used the term process, and hisuse likely influenced archaeologists.

DISCUSSIONCordell states that:

process refers to quite abstract and repeatable events rather than to particular historiccontingencies. The phrase ‘historical process’ can only refer to general statementsabout the course of history . . . [H]istorical processes are not laws of human behavioror empirical generalizations about how the world works. There are no historicalprocesses. (1994: 157)

Sebastian and McGuire (2001) respond that Cordell incorrectly equated processes withlaws, that history itself is a process, and that a critical analytical hurdle concerns how oneintegrates historical particularities with general processes. The latter problem is, in fact,easily solved (Lyman and O’Brien, 2004; Sengör, 2001). Recognizing this, Sebastian andMcGuire (2001: 15) pose two questions: ‘How can we use specific, historical processesto inform our explanations and account for change in the past? How can we use ourincreasingly sophisticated understanding of general processes as a source of hypothesesabout the constraints under which particular societies operated?’ Answers to these ques-tions will be easier to construct with a nuanced understanding of cultural process.

Prior to about 1990 ‘cultural process’ was a commonsensical expression for anythingdynamic and operating in a culture over some time span. A few researchers were awareof the difference between synchronic operational and the diachronic evolutionaryprocesses. Consider a chronological list of cultural processes mentioned in the literature(Table 1). To keep the list manageable, processes listed in only one publication (e.g. hier-archization, individualization, intensification, replacement, secularization, tribalization,unification) are not included. The 27 processes in Table 1 include numerous ones withinthe family of processes concerning cultural transmission. Most concern diachronicevolutionary change; only enculturation/socialization and persistence imply stability,and persistence is descriptive of stasis rather than explanatory (M.W. Willey, 1931). Acumulative list of processes given between 1941 and 1954 includes all but five of thelisted processes; all 27 processes are included in a cumulative list dating from 1964 to1987. This cross-listing of processes mentioned prior to 1960 with those mentioned after1960 may indicate why few archaeologists discussed the concept – everyone thoughtthey agreed on what it meant and what it comprised.

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

234

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

235

Tab

le 1

.C

hro

no

log

ica

l lis

t o

f cu

ltu

ral p

roce

sses

men

tio

ned

in s

elec

ted

lite

ratu

re

Pro

cess

Red

fiel

dH

ersk

ovit

sK

roeb

erB

arne

ttK

roeb

erR

ouse

Stew

ard

Will

ey 1

953

Will

ey a

ndW

hite

1941

1948

1948

1953

1953

a19

5319

49an

d 19

55P

hilli

ps 1

958

1959

accu

ltura

tion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

accu

mul

atio

nye

sye

sas

sim

ilati

onye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sce

ntra

lizat

ion

circ

umsc

ript

ion

com

mer

cial

izat

ion

yes

conv

erge

ncea

yes

yes

yes

yes

decl

ineb

yes

yes

yes

diff

eren

tiat

ion

yes

yes

diff

usio

nye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sdo

mes

tica

tion

yes

yes

yes

drift

yes

emer

genc

ecye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sen

cultu

rati

onye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sin

corp

orat

ion

yes

indu

stri

aliz

atio

nye

sye

sin

nova

tion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

inte

grat

ion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

inva

sion

mig

rati

onye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

snu

clea

tion

d

prog

ress

ion

yes

yes

yes

yes

segm

enta

tion

yes

soci

aliz

atio

neye

sye

sye

sye

sye

ssp

ecia

lizat

ion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

stra

tific

atio

n ye

sur

bani

zati

onye

sye

s

cont

inue

d

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

236

Tab

le 1

.C

on

tin

ued

Pro

cess

Spin

dler

and

Tax

Frie

dB

info

rd a

ndR

enfr

ewB

eeC

ohen

and

Ren

frew

John

son

and

Heg

mon

Spin

dler

195

919

6419

67B

info

rd 1

968

1973

1974

Serv

ice

1978

1982

Ear

le 1

987

2003

accu

ltura

tion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

accu

mul

atio

nye

sas

sim

ilati

onye

sye

sce

ntra

lizat

ion

yes

yes

circ

umsc

ript

ion

yes

yes

yes

com

mer

cial

izat

ion

yes

conv

erge

ncea

yes

decl

ineb

yes

yes

yes

yes

diff

eren

tiat

ion

yes

yes

diff

usio

nye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sdo

mes

tica

tion

yes

yes

yes

drift

yes

emer

genc

ecye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sye

sen

cultu

rati

onye

sye

sye

sin

corp

orat

ion

yes

indu

stri

aliz

atio

nye

sin

nova

tion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

inte

grat

ion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

inva

sion

yes

yes

mig

rati

onye

sye

sye

sye

snu

clea

tion

dye

sye

spr

ogre

ssio

nye

sye

sse

gmen

tati

onye

sso

cial

izat

ione

yes

yes

yes

spec

ializ

atio

nye

sye

sye

sye

sst

rati

ficat

ion

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

yes

urba

niza

tion

yes

aan

dpa

ralle

lism

.bco

llaps

e,de

cay,

dege

nera

tion,

devo

lutio

n,di

sorg

aniz

atio

n.c

deve

lopm

ent,

evol

utio

n,fo

rmat

ion,

grow

th.d

and

aggr

egat

ion.

ean

dcu

ltura

ltra

nsm

issio

nan

dle

arni

ng.

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Notice that I said ‘everyone thought they agreed’ on what ‘cultural process’ meant.Many used the term without definition, only a few defined it in commonsensical terms,and rarely was it discussed in nuanced theoretical terms. The apparent results are three.First, the list of processes did not really change between about 1950 and 1980 (Table I).Thus processual archaeology had trouble building explanations that did not include thetraditional historical processes involving cultural transmission. Second, when a dynamiccultural process is named, the name is usually coined from the result of the process (orvice versa). For example, the process of social stratification is applied to the developmentof social strata, begging the question of whether we have explained anything by saying‘the process of social stratification’. And third, the meaning of cultural processes shiftedto include formation processes in the 1970s (Figure 2). Interest in the latter spawnedethnoarchaeology, middle range theory, experimental archaeology, and the like. Noone commented on the potential confusion of the two categories of processes, likelybecause of the ambiguity of the original concept and a commonsensical notion thathuman behavioral processes created observed archaeological patterns. Which process isresponsible for which pattern – Wauchope’s dilemma – became the problem requiringsolution.

More or less redundant cultural processes (e.g. borrowing and diffusion; inventionand innovation; evolution, development and florescence) are lumped together in onecategory in Table 1. Such lumping was not always easy because specific processes areseldom defined, leaving their theoretical implications, their scale, their duration, andother potentially critical aspects of them obscure. A necessary step toward improving thesituation, then, is to consider these properties of cultural processes.

Culture Process DefinedPsychobiologist Henry Plotkin (2003: 121) indicates that ‘a process is a sequence ofevents that occurs in time and leads to an outcome, a result or end-state of some form.It is a means of proceeding or doing, involving change’. Continuing, ‘processes are drivenby specific causal mechanisms’ (2003: 161). One can study process with no knowledgeof mechanism, such as Darwin (1859) did when he discussed evolution as a process of‘descent with modification’ or inheritance with change, without knowledge of thegenetic mechanisms of mutation, transmission, and so on. What might, then, bethought of as subprocesses of evolution include transmission or heritability, sorting(including selection), and the generation of variation; in the case of biological evolution,these subprocesses act via genetic mechanisms (Plotkin, 2003: 133).

We are interested in cultural processes. A culture is a set of interrelated parts (sub-systems) that is greater than the simple sum of the parts; cultures have emergentproperties – properties of the aggregate but not of the parts comprising the aggregate.Cultures grow or decay (have more, or fewer, emergent properties over time, respec-tively). The rate of culture change can be zero (stasis), slow, or fast. One variable at atime in a (sub)system can change value; or multiple variables can change at the sametime (at the same or different rates, the latter comprising mosaic evolution). Thestructural and functional (causal) interrelations of two or more variables can change asone or more of their respective values change.

A cultural process is the dynamic, cause–effect interrelations (implying stasis) andinteractions (implying nonstasis) of multiple variables at least one of which is cultural.

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

237

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

It is the causal, structural, or functional linkages between variables and the mechanismsoperating to affect the linkages that result in interrelations, interactions and reactions ofor changes in values of one or more variables when one or more other variables changevalue. Certain variables will comprise significant contingencies that influence whichprocess(es) operates at some magnitude or intensity for some duration at some scale (howmuch of the cultural [sub]system is affected) in any particular case.

The magnitude of a cultural process can vary (Hsu, 1959). Magnitude can be modeledas intensity – the degree of a process’s effect – and extent – how much time and howmany people are involved. The number of people and the time involved in the opera-tion of a process are likely to be positively related (Figure 3). Change need not occurover the long term, though it may well occur over the short term only to return to someinitial state, as with the synchronic operation of a culture. Intensity can be conceived ofas the amount of change that occurs per unit of time; the more change (in technology,subsistence, social organization, whatever; any or several or all) per time unit, the greaterthe intensity of the process. If a process is synchronic and cyclical, then the amplitudeof the cycle is indicative of intensity. Units to measure intensity will depend on theprocess under consideration.

Longacre (1966: 95) argued that cultural processes took place over time spans betterwitnessed archaeologically than ethnographically. Some cultural anthropologists woulddisagree (e.g. Redfield, 1934, 1941). Vogt suggested that an ethnographic study should

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

238

nation

community

family

person

few manyNumber of people

shor

tlo

ngT

empo

ral d

urat

ion

Figure 3. Variation in the scale of cultural processes (modified from Landres, 1992).Note the direct correlation of number of people (scaled as discontinuous socialentities denoted by dashed-line rectangles) and temporal duration. Scale is depen-dent on the process(es) of concern; scales shown here are for illustration.

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

minimally involve continuous observation over a span of 20 years; this would besufficient to ‘define and conceptualize the types of directional processes that are at workin social and cultural systems’ (Vogt, 1960: 29).

Vogt defined a directional process as one that occurs ‘on macro time-scales withsequences that are cumulative and pervasive and involve alterations in the structures ofsocial and cultural systems’ (1960: 22); such processes include cultural evolution, elab-oration, florescence, involution, drift, and growth. He defined recurrent processes asones that occur on micro time scales and that ‘recur with regularity as individualmembers are born into and socialized by a society, and later as they die and leave thesociety; or they recur regularly as the society adjusts each year to the natural passage ofthe seasons; or as the system regularly makes adjustments to contacts with other societies’(Vogt, 1960: 21; see also Gluckman, 1968). These are similar to diachronic evolution-ary processes and synchronic operational processes, respectively, but the important pointis that different subsystems operate over different spans of time. Explicit definition ofthe kind of subsystem and specification of its attendant processes are required to deter-mine if a month or two, or several decades of ethnographic field work are necessary toobserve the total operation of a particular process from start to finish, whether of therecurrent/operational family or the directional/evolutionary family. In some cases, onlyobservation may determine duration.

An anonymous reviewer of this article suggested that noting process duration and thedistinction of synchronic and diachronic processes are conceptually unhelpful for tworeasons. First, evolution is ongoing all the time so no process is truly cyclical or repeti-tive. Second, the distinction of kinds of synchronic and diachronic processes (Figure 2)could be equated with the distinction of ecology and function relative to evolution. Idisagree because each reason rests on an implicit definition and theory of cultural processand an equally implicit theory of how we classify phenomena (Lyman and O’Brien,2002). Different theories, different definitions, and different classifications will producedifferent results (Gould, 1987; Lyman and Harpole, 2002).

Synchronic operational processes require a return to a particular state of being; thatstate defines the beginning and the ending points of the temporal duration of asynchronic operational process. Diachronic evolutionary processes require explication ofan initial state and an end state that are different from one another (and neither initia-tion or termination necessarily implying evolutionary stasis) in order to determineprocess duration. Once states are defined for either family of processes (classification),process duration (and intensity and magnitude) will vary depending on the historicalcontingencies of the particular case (Steward, 1968).

Vogt (1960: 18) observed that despite ‘our traditional American interest in cultureprocess and history’, anthropology had shifted in the middle of the 20th century fromexamination of historical diachronic processes to study of structural, functional andsynchronic processes evident in the ethnographic (and, I would add, archaeological)record(s) (see also Barnard, 2000; Bee, 1974; Harris, 1968). The new approach assumed‘that social and cultural systems tend to maintain equilibrium unless (a) they are either“hit” by some force from outside, or (b) develop some strain within the system whichdisturbs the equilibrium. Then we concentrate on finding out how equilibrium isrestored’ (Vogt, 1960: 19). The result is that we describe the stable-state structure andfunction of a cultural (sub)system at several points in time (say, t2, t4, and t6), and then

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

239

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

compare the descriptions and imply that processes of change happened between thetemporal periods of stability or equilibrium (see also Bee, 1974: 3).

Vogt’s (1960: 20) model of a structural–functional approach and his model of aprocessual approach are shown in Figure 4 where I have added an indication of recur-rent operational and directional evolutionary processes. The structural–functional modelepitomizes a synchronic perspective whereas the processual model epitomizes adiachronic one. The former is not concerned with whether continuity or discontinuityexists between entities occupying distinct temporal positions. Rather, one or more steadystates are assumed and their operation(s) is studied. Or, heritable continuity created bycultural transmission is assumed and processes of change between steady states areinferred. Vogt’s processual model (not to be confused with processual archaeology)assumes an explicitly diachronic perspective and analysts search for the process(es) result-ing in continuity and some sort of connection between states. For Vogt, the two modelscomprise equally valid analytical approaches. But after the 1950s the tempo andprocesses of change were seldom studied directly; instead, differences between snapshotsof the temporal continuum were assumed to represent change (or stasis) and to showthe effects of the operation of (inferred) cultural processes. Plog (e.g. 1973, 1974, 1977)made this point repeatedly during the 1970s’ heyday of processual archaeology. Withoutciting Vogt (1960), Plog (1977: 24) contrasted ‘organizational change’ – caused by orequivalent to Vogt’s directional processes – and cyclical change – caused by or equiva-lent to Vogt’s recurrent processes.

A means to integrate analytically and theoretically Vogt’s two models is provided byDarwinian evolutionism, an approach to history that can be adapted to cultural

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

240

directional process recurrent process

Time

or or

A

B

t1 t2 t3 t4 t5 t6 t7

Figure 4. Vogt’s models of a structural–functional approach (A, above the time line)and of a processual approach (B, below the time line). Time can pass from right to left,or from left to right; combinations of rectangles signify different structures or formalvariants. After Vogt (1960).

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

phenomena (O’Brien and Lyman, 2000). An advantage to starting with that approachis that many evolutionary processes have already been identified, discussed, refined, andmodeled (Shanahan, 2004). Adaptation of those processes to cultural phenomena maybe relatively easy, and in fact was originally attempted more than 30 years ago whenWarwick Bray (1973) equated mutation with innovation, anagenesis with tradition andseries, adaptive radiation with cultural diversification, and the like. Various processes ofcultural evolution were proposed throughout the 20th century (see Lyman, 2007 fordiscussion and references); perhaps it is time to revisit those processes and adjust themaccording to our increased understanding of how the generic evolutionary process works.In doing so, the means to integrate Vogt’s two models (Figure 4) will be apparent.

Considering both the synchronic operation and the diachronic evolution of a culture,we can model the operation of processes. Synchronic operational processes are repetitiveand cyclical (Figure 5a). A culture is dynamic, change is incessant, but over the longterm, things do not really change, they just operate. A good example is the academicschool year – fall semester, winter break, spring semester, summer school, repeat.Diachronic evolutionary processes produce change over either the long term or the shortterm, depending on the magnitude and rate of change (Figure 5b). These processes do

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

241

(b) Diachronic evolution(a) Synchronic operation

(d) Combined

Tim

eT

ime

(c) Chaotic

Figure 5. General types of cultural processes. The vertical axis represents thepassage of time (from bottom to top); the horizontal axis represents the formalvariation in a cultural system.

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

not produce repetitive results but rather are constantly producing something new anddifferent. Chaotic change is relatively intense, it will tend to be unpredictable and it canalter the trajectory of evolutionary processes (Figure 5c). A volcanic eruption, aninvasion, and a fatal epidemic are examples; think about their influence on the processescomprising an academic school year if one of them occurs unexpectedly. Add synchronicoperational processes, diachronic evolutionary processes, and chaotic processes togetherand an appreciation of the complexity of reality emerges (Figure 5d).

CONCLUSIONKroeber (1953b: 362–3) contrasted what he called the ‘historical’ approach to anthro-pology with what he called the ‘processual’ approach, noting that the latter wasconcerned with causes whereas the former was mostly concerned with gathering andclassifying facts. Thus Kroeber may have been the ultimate source of inspiration for theterm ‘processual archaeology’ as a label for a nomothetic approach rather than an idio-graphic one (e.g. Watson, 1973). Looking back at the 1960s and 1970s, Redman (1991)made two observations about processual archaeology. First, no more than two or threepeople could agree on what it was, and second, it was not entirely clear how tooperationalize it. The history presented here confirms both observations. Perhaps poorconceptualizaion not only made it difficult to operationalize the concept but alsocontributed to why there were few new ideas about cultural processes.

Hegmon (2003) applied the label ‘processualism plus’ to archaeology of the early 21stcentury, and published that label in the leading journal of archaeology in the Americas –American Antiquity. The June 2004 issue of American Anthropologist – the leading journalof anthropology in the world – included four articles under a section heading entitled‘Modeling Social Processes’. Clearly, cultural processes are still important to both anthro-pology and archaeology. Future conceptualization must specify the duration of the processof interest such that the family of synchronic operational processes is distinguished fromthe family of diachronic evolutionary processes. Such conceptualization will requireexplicit definitions of operation and evolution. Here, I have tried to take the first stepstoward answering the question: ‘What is the “process” in cultural process?’ and haveidentified the importance of process duration, magnitude, and scale. Future thinking,theorizing, and modeling of cultural processes will be easier, I think, in light of my histori-cal review of the concept in anthropology generally and archaeology in particular.

AcknowledgementsPerceptive comments by Christine VanPool, Todd VanPool, and several anonymous,unsympathetic reviewers helped considerably.

ReferencesAdams, R.M. (1956) ‘Some Hypotheses on the Development of Early Civilizations’,

American Antiquity 21(3): 227–32.Adams, R.M. (1960) ‘The Evolutionary Process in Early Civilizations’, in S. Tax (ed.)

Evolution After Darwin, vol. 2: The Evolution of Man: Mind, Culture, and Society,pp. 153–68. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Arnold, D.E. (1985) Ceramic Theory and Cultural Process. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

242

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Barnard, A. (2000) History and Theory in Anthropology. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversity Press.

Barnett, H.G. (1940) ‘Cultural Processes’, American Anthropologist 42(1): 21–48.Barnett, H.G. (1942) ‘Invention and Culture Change’, American Anthropologist 44(1):

14–30.Barnett, H.G. (1953) Innovation: The Basis of Cultural Change. New York:

McGraw-Hill.Beals, A.R., G. Spindler and L. Spindler (1967) Culture in Process. New York: Holt,

Rinehart and Winston.Bee, R.L. (1974) Patterns and Processes. New York: Free Press.Bender, S.J. and G.A. Wright (1988) ‘High-Altitude Occupations, Cultural Process,

and High Plains Prehistory: Retrospect and Prospect’, American Anthropologist90(3): 619–39.

Bidney, D. (1953) Theoretical Anthropology. New York: Columbia University Press.Binford, L.R. (1962) ‘Archaeology as Anthropology’, American Antiquity 28(2):

217–25.Binford, L.R. (1965) ‘Archaeological Systematics and the Study of Cultural Process’,

American Antiquity 31(2): 203–10.Binford, L.R. (1968a) ‘Archeological Perspectives’, in S.R. Binford and L.R. Binford

(eds) New Perspectives in Archeology, pp. 5–32. Chicago, IL: Aldine.Binford, L.R. (1968b) ‘Some Comments on Historical versus Processual Archaeology’,

Southwestern Journal of Anthropology 24(3): 267–75.Binford, L.R. (1977) ‘General Introduction’, in L.R. Binford (ed.) For Theory Building

in Archaeology, pp. 1–10. New York: Academic Press.Binford, S.R. and L.R. Binford, eds (1968a) New Perspectives in Archeology. Chicago,

IL: Aldine.Binford, S.R. and L.R. Binford (1968b) ‘Archeological Theory and Method’, in

S.R. Binford and L.R. Binford (eds) New Perspectives in Archeology, pp. 1–3.Chicago, IL: Aldine.

Boas, F. (1896) ‘The Limitations of the Comparative Method in Anthropology’,Science 6: 901–8.

Boas, F. (1924) ‘Evolution or Diffusion?’, American Anthropologist 26(3): 340–4.Bohannan, P. (1995) How Culture Works. New York: Free Press.Bray, W. (1973) ‘The Biological Basis of Culture’, in C. Renfrew (ed.) The

Explanation of Culture Change: Models in Prehistory, pp. 73–92. London:Duckworth.

Caldwell, J.R. (1959) ‘The New American Archeology’, Science 129(3345): 303–7.Carneiro, R.L. (1960) ‘The Culture Process’, in G.E. Dole and R.L. Carneiro (eds)

Essays in the Science of Culture in Honor of Leslie A. White, pp. 145–61. New York:Thomas Y. Crowell.

Carneiro, R.L. (1981) ‘Leslie A. White’, in S. Silverman (ed.) Totems and Teachers:Perspectives on the History of Anthropology, pp. 209–51. New York: ColumbiaUniversity Press.

Clarke, D.L. (1968) Analytical Archaeology. London: Methuen.Cohen, R. and E.R. Service, eds (1978) Origins of the State: The Anthropology of

Political Evolution. Philadelphia, PA: Institute for the Study of Human Issues.

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

243

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Cohen, Y.A. (1968) ‘Culture as Adaptation’, in Y.A. Cohen (ed.) Man in Adaptation:The Cultural Present, pp. 40–60. Chicago, IL: Aldine.

Cordell, L.S. (1994) ‘The Nature of Explanation in Archaeology: A Position Paper’, inG.J. Gumerman and M. Gell-Mass (eds) Understanding Complexity in thePrehistoric Southwest, pp. 149–59. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley.

Cunningham, J.J. (2003) ‘Transcending the “Obnoxious Spectator”: A Case forProcessual Pluralism in Ethnoarchaeology’, Journal of Anthropological Archaeology22(4): 389–410.

Darwin, C. (1859) On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection; or thePreservation of Favoured Races in the Struggle for Life. London: Murray.

Deetz, J. (1965) The Dynamics of Stylistic Change in Arikara Ceramics. Urbana:University of Illinois Press.

Dickens, R.S. Jr. and T.H. Ward, eds (1985) Structure and Process in SoutheasternArchaeology. Tuscaloosa: University of Alabama Press.

Eisenberg, L. (1971) ‘Anthropological Archaeology: Ethnography or Ethnology?’,Plains Anthropologist 16(54): 298–301.

Flannery, K.V. (1967) ‘Culture History v. Culture Process: A Debate in AmericanArchaeology’, Scientific American 217(2): 119–22.

Flannery, K.V. (1968) ‘Archeological Systems Theory and Early Mesoamerica’, inB.J. Meggers (ed.) Anthropological Archeology in the Americas, pp. 67–87.Washington, DC: Anthropological Society of Washington.

Flannery, K.V. (1972) ‘The Cultural Evolution of Civilizations’, Annual Review ofEcology and Systematics 3: 399–426.

Flannery, K.V. (1999) ‘Process and Agency in Early State Formation’, CambridgeArchaeological Journal 9(1): 3–21.

Fried, M.H. (1967) The Evolution of Political Society: An Essay in Political Anthropology.New York: Random House.

Glasow, M.A. (1978) ‘The Concept of Carrying Capacity in the Study of CultureProcess’, Advances in Archaeological Method and Theory 1: 31–48.

Gluckman, M. (1968) ‘The Utility of the Equilibrium Model in the Study of SocialChange’, American Anthropologist 70(2): 219–37.

Gould, S.J. (1987) Time’s Arrow and Time’s Cycle: Myth and Metaphor in the Discoveryof Geological Time. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Griffin, J.B. (1956) ‘The Study of Early Cultures’, in H.L. Shaprio (ed.) Man, Cultureand Society, pp. 22–49. New York: Oxford University Press.

Harris, M. (1968) The Rise of Anthropological Theory. New York: Crowell.Hawkes, C.F.C. (1954) ‘Archaeological Theory and Method: Some Suggestions from

the Old World’, American Anthropologist 56(2): 155–68.Hegmon, M. (2003) ‘Setting Theoretical Egos Aside: Issues and Theory in North

American Archaeology’, American Antiquity 68(2): 213–43.Herskovits, M.J. (1943) ‘Education and Cultural Dynamics’, American Journal of

Sociology 48(6): 737–49.Herskovits, M.J. (1945) ‘The Processes of Cultural Change’, in R. Linton (ed.) The

Science of Man in the World Crisis, pp. 143–70. New York: Columbia UniversityPress.

Herskovits, M.J. (1948) Man and His Works. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

244

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Hill, J.N. (1977) ‘Introduction’, in J.N. Hill (ed.) Explanation of Prehistoric Change,pp. 1–16. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.

Hole, F. and R.F. Heizer (1965) An Introduction to Prehistoric Archeology. New York:Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Hole, F. and R.F. Heizer (1969) An Introduction to Prehistoric Archeology (2nd edn).New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Hole, F. and R.F. Heizer (1973) An Introduction to Prehistoric Archeology (3rd edn).New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Hole, F., and R.F. Heizer (1977) Prehistoric Archeology: A Brief Introduction. New York:Holt, Rinehart and Winston.

Hsu, F.L.K. (1959) ‘Structure, Function, Content, and Process’, AmericanAnthropologist 61(5): 790–805.

Huxley, J.H. (1958) ‘Cultural Process and Evolution’, in A. Roe and G.G. Simpson(eds) Behavior and Evolution, pp. 437–54. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.

Johnson, A.L. (2004) ‘The Goals of Processual Archaeology’, in A.L. Johnson (ed.)Processual Archaeology, pp. 11–27. Westport, CT: Praeger.

Johnson, A.W. and T. Earle (1987) The Evolution of Human Societies: From ForagingGroup to Agrarian State. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Johnson, M. (1999) Archaeological Theory: An Introduction. Oxford: Blackwell.Judge, W.J. (1982) ‘Will the Real Archeology Please Stand Up? Comments on the

Status of American Archeology, ca. AD 1982’, George Wright Forum 2(4): 17–34.Kaplan, D. and R.A. Manners (1972) Culture Theory. Englewood Cliffs, NJ:

Prentice-Hall.Keegan, W.F. (1991) ‘Culture Processes and Culture Realities’, in R.W. Preucel (ed.)

Processual and Postprocessual Archaeologies: Multiple Ways of Knowing the Past,pp. 183–96. Carbondale, IL: Center for Archaeological Investigations, SouthernIllinois University at Carbondale (Occasional Paper No. 10).

Kluckhohn, C. (1951) ‘The Study of Culture’, in D. Lerner and H.D. Lasswell (eds)The Policy Sciences, pp. 86–101. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Kroeber, A.L. (1948) Anthropology (rev. edn). New York: Harcourt, Brace andCompany.

Kroeber, A.L., ed. (1953a) Anthropology Today. Chicago, IL: University of ChicagoPress.

Kroeber, A.L. (1953b) ‘Concluding Review’, in S. Tax, L.C. Eisley, I. Rouse andC.F. Voegelin (eds) An Appraisal of Anthropology Today, pp. 357–76. Chicago, IL:University of Chicago Press.

Landres, P.B. (1992) ‘Temporal Scale Perspectives in Managing Biological Diversity’,Transactions of the North American Wildlife and Natural Resources Conference 57:292–307.

Lerner, M. (1934) ‘Social Process’, Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences 14: 148–51.Linton, R. (1936) The Study of Man. New York: Appleton-Century.Longacre, W.A. (1966) ‘Changing Patterns of Social Integration: A Prehistoric

Example from the American Southwest’, American Anthropologist 68(1): 94–102.Longacre, W.A. (1968) ‘Some Aspects of Prehistoric Society in East-Central Arizona’,

in S.R. Binford and L.R. Binford (eds) New Perspectives in Archeology, pp. 89–102.Chicago, IL: Aldine.

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

245

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Lowie, R.H. (1912) ‘On the Principle of Convergence in Ethnology’, Journal ofAmerican Folk-Lore 25(95): 24–42.

Lyman, R.L. (2004) ‘The Concept of Equifinality in Taphonomy’, Journal ofTaphonomy 2(1): 15–26.

Lyman, R.L. (2007) ‘Cultural Transmission in North American Anthropology andArchaeology, ca. 1895–1965’, in M.J. O’Brien (ed.) Cultural Transmission andArchaeology: Issues and Case Studies. Washington, DC: Society for AmericanArchaeology.

Lyman, R.L. and J.L. Harpole (2002) ‘A.L. Kroeber and the Measurement of Time’sArrow and Time’s Cycle’, Journal of Anthropological Research 58(3): 313–38.

Lyman, R.L. and M.J. O’Brien (2002) ‘Classification’, in J.P. Hart and J.E. Terrell(eds) Darwin and Archaeology: A Handbook of Key Concepts, pp. 69–88. Westport,CT: Bergin & Garvey.

Lyman, R.L. and M.J. O’Brien (2003) ‘Cultural Traits: Units of Analysis in EarlyTwentieth-Century Anthropology’, Journal of Anthropological Research 59(2):225–50.

Lyman, R.L. and M.J. O’Brien (2004) ‘Nomothetic Science and Idiographic Historyin Twentieth-Century Americanist Anthropology’, Journal of the History of theBehavioral Sciences 40(1): 77–96.

MacWhite, E. (1956) ‘On the Interpretation of Archeological Evidence in Historicaland Sociological Terms’, American Anthropologist 58(1): 3–25.

Maruyama, M. (1963) ‘The Second Cybernetics: Deviation-Amplifying CausalProcesses’, American Scientist 51(2): 164–79.

Matthews, F. (1989) ‘Social Scientists and the Culture Concept, 1930–1950: TheConflict between Processual and Structural Approaches’, Sociological Theory 7(1):87–101.

McGregor, J.C. (1941) Southwestern Archaeology. New York: Wiley.McGregor, J.C. (1950) ‘Weighted Traits and Traditions’, in E.K. Reed and D.S. King

(eds) For the Dean, pp. 291–97. Tucson: Hohokam Museums Association, andSanta Fe: Southwest Museums Association.

Mead, M. (1943) ‘Our Educational Emphases in Primitive Perspective’, AmericanJournal of Sociology 48(6): 633–9.

Meggers, B.J. (1955) ‘The Coming of Age of American Archaeology’, in B.J. Meggersand C. Evans (eds) New Interpretations of Aboriginal American Culture History,pp. 116–29. Washington, DC: Anthropological Society of Washington.

Moore, H.C. (1954) ‘Cumulation and Cultural Processes’, American Anthropologist56(3): 347–57.

Murdock, G.P. (1955) ‘Changing Emphases in Social Structure’, Southwestern Journalof Anthropology 11: 361–70.

Murdock, G.P. (1956) ‘How Culture Changes’, in H.L. Shapiro (ed.) Man, Culture,and Society, pp. 247–60. New York: Oxford University Press.

O’Brien, M.J. and R.L. Lyman (2000) Applying Evolutionary Archaeology: A SystematicApproach. New York: Kluwer Academic/Plenum.

Ogburn, W.F. (1930) ‘Change, Social’, Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences 3: 330–34.Phillips, P. (1955) ‘American Archaeology and General Anthropological Theory’,

Southwestern Journal of Anthropology 11(3): 246–50.

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

246

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Plog, F.T. (1973) ‘Diachronic Anthropology’, in C.L. Redman (ed.) Research andTheory in Current Archeology, pp. 181–98. New York: Wiley.

Plog, F.T. (1974) The Study of Prehistoric Change. New York: Academic Press.Plog, F.T. (1975) ‘Systems Theory in Archeological Research’, Annual Review of

Anthropology 4: 207–24.Plog, F.T. (1977) ‘Explaining Change’, in J.N. Hill (ed.) Explanation of Prehistoric

Change, pp. 17–57. Albuquerque: University of New Mexico Press.Plotkin, H. (2003) The Imagined World Made Real: Towards a Natural Science of

Culture. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.Preucel, R.W. (1991) ‘The Philosophy of Archaeology’, in R.W. Preucel (ed.)

Processual and Postprocessual Archaeologies, pp. 17–29. Carbondale, IL: Center forArchaeological Investigations, Southern Illinois University at Carbondale(Occasional Paper No. 10).

Radin, P. (1933) The Method and Theory of Ethnology: An Essay in Criticism. New York:McGraw-Hill.

Redfield, R. (1934) ‘Culture Changes in Yucatan’, American Anthropologist 36(1):57–69.

Redfield, R. (1941) The Folk Culture of Yucatan. Chicago, IL: University of ChicagoPress.

Redfield, R. (1953) The Primitive World and Its Transformations. Ithaca, NY: CornellUniversity Press.

Redman, C.L., ed. (1973) Research and Theory in Current Archeology. New York: Wiley.Redman, C.L. (1991) ‘Distinguished Lecture in Archeology: In Defense of the

Seventies – The Adolescence of New Archeology’, American Anthropologist 93(22):295–307.

Renfrew, C. (1969) ‘Trade and Culture Process in European Prehistory’, CurrentAnthropology 10(2/3): 151–69.

Renfrew, C., ed. (1973) The Explanation of Culture Change: Models in Prehistory.London: Duckworth.

Renfrew, C. (1982) ‘Explanation Revisited’, in C. Renfrew, M.J. Rowlands andB.A. Segraves (eds) Theory and Explanation in Archaeology: The SouthamptonConference, pp. 5–23. New York: Academic Press.

Renfrew, C. (1994) ‘Concluding Remarks: Childe and the Study of Culture Process’,in D.R. Harris (ed.) The Archaeology of V. Gordon Childe: Contemporary Perspectives,pp. 121–33. London: University College London Press.

Rohner, R.P. and E.C. Rohner (1969) ‘Franz Boas and the Development of NorthAmerican Ethnology and Ethnography’, in R.P. Rohner (ed.) The Ethnography ofFranz Boas, pp. xiii–xxx. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Rosenswig, R.M. (2000) ‘Some Political Processes of Ranked Societies’, Journal ofAnthropological Archaeology 19(4): 413–60.

Rouse, I. (1953) ‘The Strategy of Culture History’, in A.L. Kroeber (ed.) AnthropologyToday, pp. 57–76. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

Rouse, I. (1977) ‘Pattern and Process in West Indian Archaeology’, World Archaeology9(1): 1–11.

Rowe, J.H. (1959) ‘Archaeological Dating and Cultural Process’, Southwestern Journalof Anthropology 15(4): 317–24.

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

247

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Rowlands, M.J. (1982) ‘Processual Archaeology as Historical Social Science’, inC. Renfrew, M.J. Rowlands and B.A. Segraves (eds) Theory and Explanation inArchaeology: The Southampton Conference, pp. 155–74. New York: Academic Press.

Sackett, J.R. (1968) ‘Method and Theory of Upper Paleolithic Archeology inSouthwestern France’, in S.R. Binford and L.R. Binford (eds) New Perspectives inArcheology, pp. 61–83. Chicago, IL: Aldine.

Salmon, M.H. (1978) ‘What Can Systems Theory Do for Archaeology?’, AmericanAntiquity 43(2): 174–83.

Salmon, M.H. (1982) Philosophy and Archaeology. New York: Academic Press.Schiffer, M.B. (1976) Behavioral Archeology. New York: Academic Press.Schiffer, M.B. (1987) Formation Processes of the Archaeological Record. Albuquerque:

University of New Mexico Press.Schiffer, M.B. (1988) ‘The Structure of Archaeological Theory’, American Antiquity

53(3): 461–85.Sebastian, L. and R.H. McGuire (2001) ‘History, Contingency, and Process: Ways of

Thinking about Change in the Past’, in D.A. Phillips Jr and L. Sebastian (eds)Examining the Course of Southwest Archaeology: The Durango Conference, September1995, pp. 11–17. Albuquerque: New Mexico Archaeological Council (SpecialPublication No. 3).

Sengör, A.M.C. (2001) Is the Present the Key to the Past or the Past the Key to the Present?Geological Society of America (Special Paper 355).

Service, E.R. (1969) ‘Models for the Methodology of Mouthtalk’, Southwestern Journalof Anthropology 25(1): 68–80.

Shanahan, T. (2004) The Evolution of Darwinism: Selection, Adaptation, and Progress inEvolutionary Biology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

Spencer, C.S. (1997) ‘Evolutionary Approaches in Archaeology’, Journal ofArchaeological Research 5(3): 209–64.

Spindler, L.S. and G.D. Spindler (1959) ‘Culture Change’, in B.J. Siegel (ed.) BiennialReview of Anthropology 1959, pp. 37–66. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.

Sterud, E.L. (1978) ‘Changing Aims of Americanist Archaeology: A Citations Analysisof American Antiquity’, American Antiquity 43(2): 294–302.

Steward, J.H. (1929) ‘Diffusion and Independent Invention: A Critique of Logic’,American Anthropologist 31(3): 491–5.

Steward, J.H. (1949) ‘Cultural Causality and Law: A Trial Formulation of theDevelopment of Early Civilizations’, American Anthropologist 51(1): 1–27.

Steward, J.H. (1955) Theory of Culture Change. Urbana: University of Illinois Press.Steward, J.H. (1968) ‘Causal Factors and Processes in the Evolution of Pre-Farming

Societies’, in R.B. Lee and I. DeVore (eds) Man the Hunter, pp. 321–34. Chicago,IL: Aldine.

Steward, J.H. and F.M. Setzler (1938) ‘Function and Configuration in Archaeology’,American Antiquity 4(1): 4–10.

Strong, W.D. (1943) Cross Sections of New World Prehistory. Smithsonian MiscellaneousCollections 104(2).

Struever, S. (1968) ‘Problems, Methods and Organization: A Disparity in the Growthof Archeology’, in B.J. Meggers (ed.) Anthropological Archeology in the Americas,pp. 131–51. Washington, DC: Anthropological Society of Washington.

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

248

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Tax, S., ed. (1964) Horizons of Anthropology. Chicago, IL: Aldine.Tax, S., L.C. Eisley, I. Rouse and C.F. Voegelin, eds (1953) An Appraisal of

Anthropology Today. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.Taylor, W.W. (1948) A Study of Archeology. American Anthropological Association,

Memoir 69.Taylor, W.W. (1972) ‘Old Wine and New Skins: A Contemporary Parable’, in

M.P. Leone (ed.) Contemporary Archaeology: A Guide to Theory and Contributions,pp. 28–33. Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press.

Terrell, J. (1986) ‘Causal Pathways and Causal Processes: Studying the EvolutionaryPrehistory of Human Diversity in Language, Customs, and Biology’, Journal ofAnthropological Archaeology 5(2): 187–98.

Thompson, R.H., ed. (1956) ‘An Archaeological Approach to the Study of CulturalStability’, in R. Wauchope (ed.) Seminars in Archaeology: 1955, pp. 31–57. Societyfor American Archaeology (Memoir no. 11).

Thompson, R.H. and W.A. Longacre (1966) ‘The University of Arizona ArchaeologicalField School at Grasshopper, East-Central Arizona’, The Kiva 31(4): 255–75.

Vogt, E.Z. (1960) ‘On the Concepts of Structure and Process in CulturalAnthropology’, American Anthropologist 62(1): 18–33.

Watson, P.J. (1973) ‘The Future of Archeology in Anthropology: Culture History andSocial Science’, in C.L. Redman (ed.) Research and Theory in Current Archeology,pp. 111–24. New York: Wiley.

Watson, P.J., S.A. LeBlanc and C.L. Redman (1971) Explanation in Archeology: AnExplicitly Scientific Approach. New York: Columbia University Press.

Watson, P.J., S.A. LeBlanc and C.L. Redman (1984) Archeological Explanation: TheScientific Method in Archeology. New York: Columbia University Press.

Wauchope, R. (1966) Archaeological Survey of Northern Georgia, with a Test of SomeCultural Hypotheses. Society for American Archaeology (Memoir no. 21).

White, L.A. (1947) ‘Culturological vs. Psychological Interpretations of HumanBehavior’, American Sociological Review 12(6): 686–98.

White, L.A. (1948) ‘The Individual and the Culture Process’, Science 108(2813):585–6.

White, L.A. (1949) The Science of Culture. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Company.White, L.A. (1950) ‘The Individual and the Culture Process’, in Centennial,

pp. 74–81. Washington, DC: American Association for the Advancement ofScience.

White, L.A. (1959) The Evolution of Culture. New York: McGraw-Hill.Willey, G.R. (1945) ‘Horizon Styles and Pottery Traditions in Peruvian Archaeology’,

American Antiquity 10(1): 49–56.Willey, G.R. (1950) ‘Growth Trends in New World Cultures’, in E.K. Reed and

D.S. King (eds) For the Dean, pp. 223–47. Tucson, AZ: Hohokam MuseumsAssociation, and Santa Fe, NM: Southwest Museums Association.

Willey, G.R. (1953) ‘Archaeological Theories and Interpretation: New World’, inA.L. Kroeber (ed.) Anthropology Today, pp. 361–85. Chicago, IL: University ofChicago Press.

Willey, G.R. and P. Phillips (1958) Method and Theory in American Archaeology.Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.

LYMAN What is the ‘process’ in cultural process?

249

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from

Willey, G.R. and J.A. Sabloff (1993) A History of American Archaeology (3rd edn). NewYork: W.H. Freeman.

Willey, M.W. (1931) ‘Continuity, Social’, Encyclopaedia of the Social Sciences 4:315–18.

R. LEE LYMAN received his PhD in anthropology from the University of Washington in 1982. He is Professor

and Chair of Anthropology at the University of Missouri-Columbia. Research interests include zooarchaeol-

ogy and the history of American archaeology. He recently published ‘Paleozoology in the Service of Conser-

vation Biology’ in Evolutionary Anthropology, ‘Archaeological Evidence of Anthropogenically Induced

Twentieth-Century Diminution of North American Wapiti (Cervus elaphus)’ in American Midland Natural-

ist, and Measuring Time with Artifacts: A History of Methods in American Archaeology through the University

of Nebraska Press. Address: Department of Anthropology, 107 Swallow Hall, University of Missouri-Columbia,

Columbia, MO 65211–1440, USA. [email: [email protected]]

ANTHROPOLOGICAL THEORY 7(2)

250

© 2007 SAGE Publications. All rights reserved. Not for commercial use or unauthorized distribution. by Peeter Torop on November 30, 2007 http://ant.sagepub.comDownloaded from