Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    1/44

    Linguistic Society of America

    Autonomy and Functionalist LinguisticsAuthor(s): William CroftSource: Language, Vol. 71, No. 3 (Sep., 1995), pp. 490-532Published by: Linguistic Society of AmericaStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/416218

    Accessed: 11/09/2010 23:59

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless

    you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you

    may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.

    Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=lsa.

    Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed

    page of such transmission.

    JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    Linguistic Society of Americais collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access toLanguage.

    http://www.jstor.org

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=lsahttp://www.jstor.org/stable/416218?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=lsahttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=lsahttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/416218?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=lsa
  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    2/44

    AUTONOMY AND

    FUNCTIONALIST

    LINGUISTICS

    WILLIAM

    CROFT

    University

    of

    Manchester

    Functional

    analyses

    of

    grammatical phenomena,

    and

    the functionalist

    approaches

    that

    promote

    them,

    are

    appealing

    to those who believe that an

    integrated

    view of

    language

    structure and

    language

    function is desirable.

    But functional

    analyses

    have been

    held

    to

    founder

    on basic

    grammatical

    facts that are taken

    to

    support

    the

    autonomy

    of

    grammar.

    The

    concept

    of

    autonomy

    is a

    complex

    one,

    and at least two

    different notions are

    found

    in current

    linguistic theory:

    arbitrariness and

    self-containedness.

    These notions of

    auton-

    omy

    apply

    either to the

    syntactic component

    of the

    grammar,

    or

    (a

    more

    recent

    claim)

    to the

    grammar

    itself,

    with

    respect

    to

    change,

    use,

    and

    acquisition.

    The

    arbitrariness

    of

    syntax

    must be

    accepted;

    and

    many

    functional

    analyses

    are

    compatible

    with

    self-

    containedness. However, mixed formal/functional analyses provide an argument against

    the self-containedness of

    syntax,

    and in

    fact even

    many

    formal

    theories of

    syntax accept

    non-self-containedness. The arbitrariness

    of

    grammatical

    knowledge

    must also be

    ac-

    cepted;

    and

    many

    functional

    analyses

    of

    the

    dynamic

    process

    affecting

    grammar

    are

    compatible

    with self-containedness.

    An

    argument

    against

    the

    self-containedness of

    gram-

    mar

    comes

    not

    from these functional

    analyses

    but from

    sociolinguistics.*

    1.

    INTRODUCTION.

    Functional'

    analyses

    of

    grammar,

    though

    rather

    varied,

    center on

    linguistic

    explanation

    based

    on

    language's

    function in a

    larger

    con-

    text.'

    While

    t is

    commonlyagreed

    that

    many aspects

    of

    human

    inguistic

    behav-

    ior can

    be

    explainedonly

    in

    terms

    of

    the

    functionof

    language,

    what

    distinguishes

    functionalistapproaches s the hypothesisthat at least some basicfacts of syn-

    tax

    can

    be

    accounted for in

    functional

    terms as

    well. In

    this

    respect

    functional-

    ism

    appears

    to contrast with

    formalist or

    more

    accurately structuralist

    approaches,

    whose most

    prominentexample

    is

    generative

    grammar.

    Unfortunately,

    here

    has been

    very

    little

    dialogue

    between

    structuralists

    nd

    functionalists,

    and as a result

    there has been

    little

    serious

    comparison

    of their

    competinghypotheses

    about

    the

    nature

    of

    grammatical

    xplanation.

    The

    mutual

    isolation of

    theoristsand

    their

    approaches

    s in

    contrast

    to

    the

    dialogue,

    acrimo-

    nious

    though

    it

    was,

    in

    the

    'linguistic

    wars'

    between

    generative

    semanticists

    and

    interpretive

    emanticists

    n

    the

    early

    1970s

    Harris1993).Newmeyer (1983,

    1991,

    1992)

    s

    virtually

    the

    only linguist

    to

    examine

    seriously

    the

    literature

    on

    both

    sides of this divide

    and

    present

    provocative challenges

    and

    proposals

    to

    functionalist

    linguists (but

    see also

    Morgan 1982,

    Green

    1982,

    Sadock

    1984,

    Nichols

    1984).

    This

    paper

    addresses

    one issue that

    is central

    to

    language yet problematic

    for

    functional

    analyses:

    the

    notion of

    autonomy.

    The

    notion

    of

    autonomy

    emerges

    from

    a

    undeniable act

    of

    all

    languages,

    'the

    curious

    lack

    of accord

    ...

    *

    I

    would

    like to

    thank

    Matthew

    Dryer, Mark

    Durie, MartinHaspelmath, Frederick

    J.

    Newmeyer,

    and David Wilkins for reading and commenting extensively on earlier versions of this article; others

    too

    numerous

    to

    mention

    for

    their

    advice

    and suggestions on

    particular points; and

    especially the

    two

    referees,

    one of

    whom

    later

    revealed

    himself

    as Russell Tomlin. Their combined

    efforts vastly

    improved

    the

    result.

    I

    accept

    responsibility for

    all flaws in the final product.

    F

    or

    general

    approaches

    to

    functionalism,

    see

    Dirven

    &

    Fried

    1987,

    Givon

    1979,

    Hickmann

    1987,

    Langacker 1987,

    and

    Tomlin

    1990.

    490

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    3/44

    AUTONOMY AND FUNCTIONALIST LINGUISTICS

    between form

    and function'

    (Sapir

    1921:89).

    One could

    say

    that the basic

    differ-

    ence between structuralismand functionalism is the

    opposite

    direction

    each

    goes

    in

    from

    this fact. The structuralist akes the lack of accord to be

    evidence

    for

    autonomy,

    while

    the

    functionalist

    nsteadfocuses on the 'unconscious

    analy-

    sis into individual

    oncepts

    which is never

    entirely

    absentfrom

    speech,

    however

    it

    may

    be

    complicated

    with or overlaid

    by

    the more irrational actors'

    (Sapir

    1921:90).

    Of

    course,

    there are

    many

    intermediate

    positions

    that

    integrate

    he two reali-

    ties

    Sapir

    describes. In fact the structuralist-functionalist

    ichotomy

    s a contin-

    uum. This article discusses

    the issue of

    autonomy

    and

    how

    linguistic

    theories

    must accommodate

    the facts that are said to

    support autonomy,

    while

    finding

    a

    place

    for

    linguistic

    function.

    My goal

    here is

    to

    argue

    that structuralistand

    functionalistapproachescan be compared,even if theycannotalwaysbe recon-

    ciled;

    to raise the fundamentalssues on which

    they

    differ;

    and

    to

    suggest points

    at which differenttheorists are

    comparing

    similar

    phenomena.

    The

    question

    of

    autonomy

    is not a

    simple

    one.

    What

    s

    claimed to be

    autono-

    mous?

    In

    ?2.1,

    1

    argue

    that the

    autonomy thesis,

    and its functionalist

    critiques,

    have been

    applied

    to two

    very

    different

    linguistic systems.

    The

    autonomy

    de-

    bates

    of the 1970s

    largely

    centered

    around the

    status

    of

    syntax,

    relative to

    semantics

    or

    pragmatics that

    s,

    semiotic

    function)-all

    within

    the

    grammatical

    competence

    of

    the individual.

    Around 1980

    here

    were

    parallelconceptual

    shifts

    both in

    generative grammar

    and

    in

    functionalist

    thinking.

    The

    debate shifted

    to the status of the grammar, hat is, the linguisticknowledgeof an individual,

    relative

    to

    its

    larger socio-psychological

    context:

    language use, language

    change,

    and

    languageacquisition.

    Because

    of

    this,

    the

    notion

    of

    function

    also

    changed,

    from

    representing

    he

    signified

    n

    the

    semiotic

    system

    of the

    grammar

    to

    representing

    he

    goals

    and

    purposes

    of

    the

    linguistic

    behavior

    of

    the individual

    in the

    speech community(external function).

    In

    ?2.2,

    1

    argue

    that

    the

    autonomy

    thesis

    can be

    brokendown

    into two claims

    about

    a

    linguistic system:

    a

    weaker

    claim,

    that

    it

    includes

    arbitrariness,and a

    strongerclaim,

    that it

    is self-contained.

    Thus,

    for

    any given functionalanalysis

    (henceforthFA), one must ask: which of these autonomyclaims does it actually

    challenge?

    With

    respect

    to an FA

    in

    syntax,

    there are

    three

    logically possible conclusions

    that

    might

    be

    drawn,

    with

    functionalist

    positions

    associated

    with each of the

    conclusions:

    (1)

    a.

    syntax

    is

    arbitrary

    and

    self-contained

    (AUTONOMIST

    FUNCTION-

    ALISM)

    b.

    syntax

    is

    arbitrary,

    but not

    self-contained

    (MIXED FORMAL/FUNC-

    TIONALISM

    and

    TYPOLOGICAL

    FUNCTIONALISM)

    c.

    syntax

    is not

    arbitrary

    r

    self-contained

    EXTREME FUNCTIONALISM)

    In

    ??3-6,

    I

    survey

    the

    four named

    functionalisms and the FAs that support

    them. In

    ?3,

    it

    is

    shown

    that

    many

    FAs

    simply provide

    a

    semiotic function that

    can

    explain

    constraintson

    syntactic

    behavior or

    which

    syntactic analyses have

    been

    offered; they

    do not

    challenge autonomy.

    In

    ?4,

    I

    argue that there are

    valid

    FAs that

    demonstrate that

    syntax

    is not

    self-contained-and that there

    491

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    4/44

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    5/44

    AUTONOMY AND FUNCTIONALIST LINGUISTICS

    syntc.ax

    refers to the

    relationship

    between

    the

    syntactic component

    and the

    com-

    ponents

    used

    to

    represent

    the semiotic functions. Functional

    analyses

    in

    syntax

    argue

    for a

    certain

    degree

    of

    interpenetration

    of semiotic

    function and

    syntactic

    form.

    In

    ?3-6

    I

    evaluate

    particular

    kinds of FAs as to whether

    they

    constitute

    valid

    arguments against

    the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax

    in

    any

    of its

    forms.

    All

    parties

    to the 1970s debate

    agreed

    that

    semantics

    was

    a

    component

    of

    the

    grammar.

    However,

    by

    the

    1980s,

    other critics

    questioned

    the

    autonomy

    of the

    grammatical system

    as a whole-from the

    forces or

    processes

    involved

    in

    language change,

    language

    use,

    and

    language

    acquisition.

    The fundamental

    relationship

    now

    highlighted

    is between the

    psychological

    linguistic system

    of

    the

    individual-called

    grammar-and language

    as a

    social

    entity,

    that

    is,

    some-

    thing resulting

    from

    the

    communicative interactions of individuals

    in

    social

    contexts. For lack of a better term, I will use

    language3

    to refer to this latter

    concept.

    This is a

    quite

    different

    relationship

    than

    that

    between

    syntax

    and

    semiotic

    function,

    and

    the

    term

    function has been redefined to

    accommodate this new

    perspective.

    In this

    context,

    function

    refers to

    EXTERNAL

    FUNCTION:

    the

    pur-

    poses

    to which the

    grammatical knowledge

    of the

    speaker

    is

    put

    in social

    interac-

    tions,

    most

    importantly

    the

    communication of

    information

    but

    also

    other social

    purposes.

    It

    is called

    external

    because

    it

    pertains

    to

    phenomena external to the

    psychological grammar. Nevertheless,

    these

    external

    functions

    interact

    with

    the

    grammar,

    the result

    being language

    use, language change,

    and

    language

    acquisition.-

    The

    question

    now

    is,

    how

    much

    interaction is

    there,

    and

    how much does it

    affect an

    individual's

    grammar'?

    The

    expression

    autonomy

    of graimnmar will

    be

    used

    to describe this issue-the

    relationship (or

    lack

    thereof)

    between the

    grammar

    of

    an

    individual and

    the external

    functions

    embodied in language as

    a

    social

    phenomenon.3

    This

    issue has

    importance

    beyond linguistics. The social

    sciences have

    long struggled

    with the

    dichotomy

    between

    the

    social and the

    psychological.

    Different

    subdisciplines

    of

    linguistics

    find

    themselves

    on either

    side of

    the divide. A

    better

    understanding

    of the

    issues

    underlying the autonomy

    of grammar may shed light on this very interdisciplinary problem. These issues

    will

    be

    discussed in

    ??7-8.

    So

    when the

    autonomy

    debate

    was

    resumed

    by Newmeyer in the 1980s (New-

    meyer

    1983),

    it

    was a different

    sort of

    autonomy

    that

    he

    was

    arguing

    for, and

    2

    There is

    another

    type

    of function that is often

    referred to in the

    literature,

    which can be called

    SYSTEMIC

    FUNCTION.

    Some

    European

    structuralists

    argue

    that

    (systemic) 'functional' forces cause

    languages

    to

    change

    in

    order to create or

    preserve symmetry

    in

    phonological,

    morphological, or

    syntactic paradigms

    (e.g..

    Martinet

    1952).

    This

    is not

    an

    external

    function

    as

    defined here. That

    is,

    preserving symmetry

    in

    formal

    paradigms

    in

    itself is

    not

    an

    interactive (communicative) goal.

    Only

    if

    preserving symmetry

    can be

    empirically

    demonstrated

    to

    serve

    a

    communicative goal can

    it be an external function. Some critiques of FAs (e.g. Labov 1994:547-68) are directed at systemic

    FAs. We

    will not

    discuss

    systemic

    FAs further

    here.

    3

    The

    autonomy

    of

    syntax

    and

    autonomy

    of

    grammar hypotheses must not be

    confused with yet

    another

    autonomy hypothesis,

    the

    autonomy

    of

    language

    from

    other human

    cognitive (and social)

    abilities.

    The

    autonomy

    of

    language hypothesis

    is

    logically independent

    of the

    other

    two autonomy

    hypotheses.

    493

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    6/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER 3

    (1995)

    it

    was

    a different

    sort

    of

    functionalism

    that

    he considered to be

    autonomy's

    opponent.

    Discussions about

    autonomy

    and

    function,

    however,

    still

    confuse

    the

    two issues.

    Newmeyer

    1992 does

    not

    clearly

    distinguish

    the two

    claims:

    in

    his

    argument

    that

    generative

    grammar

    already

    accommodates

    functionalist

    iconic

    principles,

    he

    argues

    that

    generative

    grammar

    already

    includes a

    seman-

    tic

    component,

    which

    does not tell us

    anything

    about

    the

    autonomy

    of

    grammar.

    And in

    many

    functionalist

    accounts of

    syntax,

    evidence

    that

    a

    particular

    con-

    struction has a

    discourse

    function is taken

    to

    entail that

    that

    function is

    external

    to the

    grammatical system,

    when it is in

    fact

    simply part

    of

    the

    signified

    for

    that

    construction

    (see

    ??4,

    9).

    2.2.

    THE

    DEFINITI()N

    OF

    AUTONOMY.

    The

    term

    AUTONOMY

    as been

    used

    am-

    biguously

    in the

    literature to

    express

    different claims.

    1 argue

    here

    that there

    are

    three different claims

    associated with

    autonomy

    that are

    relevant to the

    debates on the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax

    and

    the

    autonomy

    of

    grammar.

    Since

    autonomy

    has been central

    to

    generative

    grammar,

    it

    is

    logical

    to

    begin

    with the

    generative

    account as it was

    applied

    to the

    autonomy-of-syntax

    prob-

    lem. The

    principle

    of

    autonomy

    of

    syntax

    is

    most

    extensively

    discussed

    by

    Chomsky

    (1977,

    esp. pp.

    37-44).

    A

    succinct

    formulation of this

    autonomy

    thesis

    as

    generally

    understood is

    given by Newmeyer: 'According

    to the

    autonomy

    thesis,

    there exists a set of

    nonsemantic

    and

    nondiscourse-derived

    grammatical

    properties

    whose

    principles

    of

    combination make

    no

    reference to

    system-exter-

    nal factors' (Newmeyer 1992:783).

    The

    hypothesis

    of

    autonomy

    of

    syntax

    is

    not a

    take-it-or-leave-it

    claim. It

    can

    be

    broken down into

    three

    subclaims;

    the

    three

    need

    not

    be

    accepted

    or

    rejected

    in

    toto.

    The three

    subclaims are:

    (3)

    a.

    At

    least some

    elements of

    syntax

    are

    arbitrary (ARBITRARINESS);

    b.

    The

    arbitrary

    elements

    participate

    in a

    system (SYSTEMATICITY);

    c.

    That

    system

    is

    self-contained

    (SELF-CONTAINEDNESS).

    The first

    and

    in

    some

    respects

    most

    fundamental

    property

    of

    autonomy is

    ARBITRARINESS:

    he

    syntactic component

    contains

    elements

    and

    rules

    of

    combi-

    nation that are not derivable from semantic or discourse categories and their

    combination.

    By

    not

    derivable,

    it

    is

    meant

    that

    the

    syntactic

    element

    (say,

    adjective)

    or

    rule

    of

    combination

    (say, passive)

    cannot

    be

    replaced with some

    combination of

    semantic

    and/or

    discourse

    properties

    and

    produce

    the

    same

    (correct)

    predictions

    of

    syntactic

    behavior.

    For

    example,

    the

    claim

    is made

    that one

    could

    not

    replace the category adjec-

    tive with a

    set

    of

    semantic

    properties

    and

    correctly predict the distribution

    of

    adjectives

    in

    English

    (and

    every

    other

    language),

    or

    replace the syntactic

    categories

    of the

    elements

    of the

    passive

    construction

    and

    rules of

    combination

    for

    creating

    the

    passive

    with

    a

    set of

    semantic or

    discourse-functional category

    definitions and rules of

    combination,

    and

    correctly predict

    the

    acceptable and

    unacceptable passives

    of

    English (and every

    other

    language).

    Arbitrariness is a

    property

    of

    the

    mapping

    between

    form

    and

    semiotic func-

    tion;

    if

    correct,

    it

    means

    that

    formal

    syntactic

    structure

    must

    be

    posited indepen-

    dent

    of

    semantic

    structures. In

    fact,

    arbitrariness

    alone

    appears to be what

    494

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    7/44

    AUTONOMY

    AND

    FUNCTIONALIST

    LINGUISTICS

    Chomsky

    (1977:37-40)

    refers to

    by

    the

    phrase

    'independence

    of

    grammar'.

    Chomsky

    makes his case for the

    independence

    of

    grammar

    (in

    our

    terms,

    the

    arbitrariness

    of

    syntax) by

    showing

    that some

    interpretations

    of

    ambiguous

    sentences are excluded by pragmatic or real-world factors, but others are ex-

    cluded

    by

    syntactic

    constraints. The existence of the

    syntactic

    constraints

    dem-

    onstrates the

    arbitrariness of

    syntax.

    Chomsky distinguishes

    the arbitrariness of

    syntax hypothesis

    from the 'thesis

    of

    autonomy

    of formal

    grammar'

    (Chomsky

    1977:42),

    or as

    it

    is called

    here,

    the

    autonomy-of-syntax

    hypothesis.

    The latter

    hypothesis

    is of course the

    stronger

    one.

    Autonomous

    syntax

    in the

    generative

    view is not

    simply

    a

    random

    inventory

    of

    lexical items and

    grammatical

    constructions

    governed by enough

    ad hoc constraints

    and rules of combination to be

    descriptively adequate

    for

    the range of facts to be analyzed. It is not just enough that the mapping relation

    between

    meaning

    and form

    is

    (at

    least

    partially) arbitrary;

    the form end

    of

    the

    mapping

    must itself

    be a

    system.

    We will take the term

    SYSTEM

    here to mean

    that

    there

    is a set of

    interlocking

    regularities

    that structure the

    phenomenon

    in

    question

    (in

    this

    case,

    the

    syntactic

    units and constructions of a

    language)

    that

    'holds

    together'

    overall-tout

    se

    tient,

    as the

    Saussurean

    saying goes

    (Koerner

    1989:404-6).

    The

    degree

    to

    which

    everything

    in the

    syntactic system

    must

    'hold

    together'

    is

    generally accepted

    to allow

    a bit of

    leeway

    for advocates of the

    systematicity

    of

    syntax.

    Some

    irregularity

    is not

    incompatible

    with

    systematicity

    in

    syntax.

    Irregularities and exceptional features have to be stipulated in an autonomous

    syntactic system, although

    such

    stipulation

    is

    kept

    to a minimum.

    While this

    is

    clearly

    a

    necessary

    and reasonable allowance-no

    theory

    would

    be

    empirically

    adequate

    if

    such

    an allowance were not made-it does lead

    to some

    degree

    of

    subjectivity

    in

    determining

    whether the data merit the

    establishment of a

    system

    in this

    sense.

    One

    linguist's elegant

    and

    principled system

    is

    another

    linguist's

    grab-bag

    of

    ad

    hoc

    generalizations;

    this

    is

    true

    of both

    structuralist and

    function-

    alist theories.

    Our definition of

    system deliberately

    leaves

    out the

    question

    of whether the

    regular, interlocking patterns in question include only the concepts of syntax

    or not.

    If

    they

    include

    only

    the

    concepts

    of

    syntax,

    then we

    may say

    the

    system

    is

    SELF-CONTAINED.

    That is to

    say,

    the rules of

    the

    system interact with each

    other

    but

    do not interact

    closely

    with

    the

    rules

    existing

    elsewhere.

    For the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax,

    'elsewhere'

    is

    generally

    taken to be

    semantics.

    Again,

    there must

    be a

    loose

    interpretation

    of

    self-containedness in the auton-

    omous

    syntactic system.

    Not

    all

    regularities

    in

    syntactic phenomena need be

    attributed to the

    autonomous

    syntactic system; some may be governed by other

    components

    of

    the

    grammar, specifically

    the

    semantic

    component (Chomsky

    1977:45-48). Chomsky suggests

    for

    example

    that the

    parallel syntactic and se-

    mantic differences between restrictive and nonrestrictive relative clauses are

    not

    a

    'choice

    of

    grammar [syntax-WAC]' (Chomsky 1977:46). There must

    also

    be

    interface rules between otherwise

    self-contained systems. For instance,

    the

    semiotic relation between

    syntax

    and

    semantics

    requires

    at

    the least inter-

    face rules

    referring

    to

    both

    form

    and

    meaning. To the extent that interface rules

    495

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    8/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER 3

    (1995)

    are

    allowed,

    a

    system

    is not

    self-contained

    in an absolute sense.

    However,

    it

    is

    generally

    taken that

    syntax

    is

    self-contained if at

    least statements

    of

    categories

    and

    rules of

    combination do not make reference to

    nonsyntactic

    elements

    (see

    the

    Newmeyer quote

    at the

    beginning

    of this

    section,

    and

    see

    ?4 for

    further

    discussion).

    Given these

    caveats,

    the

    autonomy-of-syntax

    hypothesis

    is

    the

    hypothesis

    that

    the

    syntactic component

    of

    the

    grammar

    is

    independent,

    (largely) system-

    atic and

    (largely)

    self-contained with

    respect

    to the

    semantic,

    pragmatic and/

    or discourse-functional

    components.

    But one need

    not

    buy

    the

    whole

    autonomy

    package.

    Syntax

    may

    be

    arbitrary

    relative

    to its semantic

    counterpart,

    and

    systematic

    also,

    yet

    not

    self-contained,

    the

    rules

    of

    syntax

    being

    interwoven

    with those of

    semantics

    (or discourse,

    or other

    components

    of

    the

    grammar).

    Arbitrariness and systematicity do not entail self-containedness. Arbitrariness

    does not

    entail

    systematicity

    either;

    it is

    logically possible

    to

    believe that

    syntax

    is

    arbitrary

    and not

    systematic

    as well

    as not

    self-contained,

    being merely

    a

    residue of

    irregularities.

    In

    fact,

    those

    functionalists who

    accept

    arbitrariness

    also

    accept

    systematicity

    (see

    n.

    20

    below).

    Hence,

    in

    the

    classification of

    func-

    tionalisms in this

    paper, acceptance

    of

    arbitrariness also

    includes

    acceptance

    of

    systematicity.

    The

    remainder of this

    article will

    survey

    FAs

    and

    the

    corre-

    sponding

    functionalist

    positions,

    in

    order

    to see

    what

    sorts

    of

    arguments

    have

    been,

    or

    can

    be,

    presented against

    which

    hypotheses

    of

    autonomy. Arguments

    can be

    made

    against

    the

    self-containedness of

    both

    syntax

    and

    grammar.

    The

    former

    argument

    is

    widely accepted

    in

    practice.

    The

    latter

    argument

    is

    much

    newer,

    and

    many questions

    still

    remain. I

    begin

    with

    the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax,

    proceeding

    from

    the

    fully

    autonomist

    position (?3)

    to

    various

    nonautonomist

    positions

    (??4-6).

    Turning

    to

    the

    autonomy

    of

    grammar,

    we

    proceed

    in

    the

    same

    fashion,

    from

    fully

    autonomist

    positions (?7)

    to

    the

    one

    plausible

    nonautonomist

    position

    (?8).

    I will

    specify

    what

    substantive

    claims are

    being

    made

    on

    each

    side,

    and-as

    much as

    can be

    done

    in a

    single

    article-evaluate

    those

    claims.

    3.

    AUTONOMIST

    FUNCTIONALISM:

    COMPATIBLE

    WITH

    THE

    SELF-CONTAINEDNESS

    OF

    SYNTAX.

    Many

    FAs of

    syntactic phenomena

    are in

    fact

    compatible with the

    strongest

    version of

    autonomy,

    self-containedness.

    Specifically,

    an

    FA that

    accounts

    for constraints

    on

    syntactic

    behavior in

    terms

    of the

    semiotic

    function

    of

    a

    syntactic

    construction,

    but

    does not

    attempt

    to

    account

    for

    the

    structure

    of

    that

    construction,

    is

    compatible

    with

    the

    self-containedness

    claim. I

    will call

    such

    analyses

    AUTONOMIST

    As,

    and

    linguists

    who

    make

    no

    stronger claims for

    their

    analyses

    AUTONOMIST

    UNCTIONALISTS;

    hese

    include

    Kuno,

    Prince, Ward

    and

    their

    associates and

    students

    (see

    Prince

    1991:79

    for a

    representative list).

    Note that

    this does

    not mean that

    linguists holding stronger functionalist posi-

    tions do not

    also

    offer

    autonomist

    FAs.

    However,

    autonomist

    FAs cannot be

    used to argue against the self-containedness of syntax, let alone against weaker

    claims of

    autonomy.

    Autonomist

    functionalists are

    chiefly

    concerned with

    determining the dis-

    course

    functions of

    the

    grammatical

    constructions

    sanctioned

    (or perhaps not

    sanctioned)

    by

    the

    autonomous

    syntactic component, using naturally occurring

    496

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    9/44

    AUTONOMY AND

    FUNCTIONALIST

    LINGUISTICS

    discourse data.

    No claim is made

    for a

    motivated

    (e.g.

    iconic)

    relationship

    between the

    syntactic

    structure

    of the

    construction in

    question,

    such as

    English

    it-clefts,

    and the discourse

    function that

    they

    perform-in

    fact,

    Prince

    explicitly

    argues

    against

    iconicity

    in

    this

    particular

    example

    (Prince

    1988:168-71).

    How-

    ever,

    autonomist

    functionalists do

    argue

    for a

    conventional relation

    between

    syntactic

    structure

    and discourse

    function,

    and

    moreover

    argue

    that

    'many

    sentences that are

    judged ungrammatical

    can be

    shown to be

    flawed

    for

    dis-

    course

    reasons,

    with

    no need to

    invoke the

    (autonomous)

    grammar

    to

    account

    for

    their

    infelicity'

    (Prince

    1991:80-81). In

    other

    words,

    many

    constraints on

    the

    behavior and/or

    distribution

    of sentences need

    not be

    provided

    by

    the

    syntactic

    component.

    Nevertheless,

    the

    conventions

    governing

    the

    formation

    of

    the

    syn-

    tactic

    structures themselves are

    not

    provided by

    discourse

    (or

    conceptual

    struc-

    ture, for that matter).

    Thus,

    functional

    explanations

    for

    constraints on

    the

    distribution of

    sentence

    types

    need not

    represent

    a

    direct attack on

    the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax.

    They

    may

    reduce the number

    of

    principles

    found in

    autonomous

    syntax.

    And

    with the

    increasing emphasis

    on

    principles

    governing

    constraints in

    generative

    syntactic

    theory

    over the

    past

    two

    decades,

    any

    research

    program

    that

    attempts

    to

    replace

    formal

    grammatical

    constraints with

    functional

    ones,

    if it

    is

    empirically

    success-

    ful,

    would

    narrow the

    scope

    of

    autonomous

    syntax

    considerably.

    But

    the

    sen-

    tence

    types

    themselves,

    that

    is the

    syntactic

    elements and

    the

    combinatoric

    rules

    by

    means

    of which

    they

    are

    formed,

    are

    left

    to the

    syntactic

    component.

    So there is no inherent contradiction in being a functionalist in this sense and

    believing

    in

    autonomous

    grammar

    (cf. Morgan

    1982:201).4

    In

    fact, many

    FAs

    challenge

    purely syntactic

    approaches

    even

    for

    basic con-

    straints in

    generative

    core

    grammar.

    The

    basic

    strategy

    in

    challenging

    a

    purely

    syntactic

    analysis

    is

    to

    demonstrate that

    sentences

    excluded

    by

    a

    given syntactic

    constraint are

    acceptable.5

    This would

    imply

    that

    the

    given syntactic

    constraint

    must

    at

    the

    least be

    weakened. At

    this

    point,

    a

    functional

    constraint

    may

    be

    sought

    that

    accounts

    for the

    exceptions

    as well

    as

    the

    normal

    cases. If

    total

    elimination of the

    syntactic

    constraint

    is

    possible,

    then

    the

    syntactic phenome-

    non can be shipped off to another autonomous component of the grammar. In

    the

    remainder

    of this

    section,

    I

    briefly

    examine

    examples

    of

    FAs that

    purport

    to

    provide

    a

    complete

    reduction:

    FAs of

    root

    transformations,

    the

    anaphoric

    island

    constraint,

    and

    constraints

    on

    extraction

    phenomena.

    Certain

    transformations were

    once

    argued

    to

    be

    restricted

    to the

    root S

    node

    of a

    syntactic

    tree

    (Emonds 1976;

    examples

    from

    Green

    1976:383):

    4

    One

    anonymous

    referee

    suggests

    that

    autonomist

    functionalists

    are

    not

    necessarily

    endorsing

    autonomous

    syntax.

    Instead,

    they

    are

    providing

    descriptions

    of

    semiotic

    functions without making

    any

    claim

    as

    to

    whether

    these

    functions in

    fact

    challenge

    or

    undermine

    the

    self-containedness of

    syntax.

    However,

    at

    least

    for

    those

    Prince

    (1988:165-66)

    calls

    'generative

    discourse

    analysts', it

    appears that the self-containedness of syntax is assumed.

    5

    A

    possible response

    is

    to

    argue

    that

    a

    reanalysis

    occurs

    that

    changes

    the exceptionally

    accept-

    able

    sentences

    into a

    structure that

    is not

    subject

    to

    the

    syntactic

    constraint. But

    then the question

    remains,

    how

    is

    reanalysis

    licensed in

    these

    cases

    but

    not in

    other

    structurally identical

    cases in

    a

    noncircular

    fashion'?

    497

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    10/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER 3

    (1995)

    (4)

    Never

    before

    have

    prices

    been so

    high.

    (5)

    *Nixon

    regrets

    that

    never

    before

    have

    prices

    been so

    high.

    There are many cases, however, in which root transformations are found in

    subordinate

    clauses.

    (6)

    1

    knewr

    hat never

    before

    had

    prices

    been so

    high.

    [Green

    1976:383]

    (7)

    I

    know that all too seldom

    does he

    bring

    her

    flowers.

    I[Bolinger

    1977:515]

    (8)

    I'm gonna

    have

    breaukfastnowt, becauLse

    am

    1

    ever

    hungry

    [Lakoff 1984:474]

    Grossly simplifying,

    the basic

    story

    on which FAs of

    4-8

    converge

    is

    this:

    root transformations

    are all what Lakoff calls SPEECH ACT

    CONSTRUCTIONS,

    con-

    structions

    which indicate some feature of an

    illocutionary

    act.

    Illocutionary

    acts are

    normally performed

    in main

    clauses;

    hence the

    apparent

    restriction to

    root Ss. But

    there are a number

    of

    contexts

    in

    which

    a

    speaker may perform

    an

    illocutionary

    act in a subordinate

    clause,

    and use a

    speech

    act

    construction

    in

    the

    process

    (see

    Hooper

    &

    Thompson

    1973,

    Green

    1976,

    Bolinger

    1977,

    Lakoff

    1984

    for

    the

    complex

    details).

    This

    argument appears

    to have been

    ac-

    cepted;

    more

    precisely,

    root transformations

    per

    se are no

    longer

    a

    part

    of

    core

    grammar and

    the

    phenomena analyzed

    in

    the references mentioned here

    have

    dropped

    out

    of

    the

    autonomous-syntax

    literature.

    Similarly,

    Ward et al. 1991 show

    that

    pronominal

    reference

    inside anaphoric

    islands is possible, contrary to the anaphoric island constraint (Postal 1969):

    (9)

    1

    think if

    I

    were

    a

    PERUVIAN

    I

    wouldn't

    want

    to

    live

    THEREffor

    the

    next

    couple of years. {Ward

    et al.

    1991:470,

    from

    a

    conversation]

    They argue

    that this

    phenomenon

    is

    governed by the same pragmatic principles

    governing pronominal anaphora,

    and the

    syntactic anaphoric

    island

    constraint

    should be

    dropped;

    and

    in fact it

    also

    has

    disappeared

    from

    the

    literature on

    core grammar.

    A

    similar tack

    has

    been

    taken

    on

    phenomena

    dearer to

    the heart of formal

    syntacticians,

    the

    constraints

    asSociated

    with

    extraction

    phenomena (Kuno

    1976, 1987; Erteschik-Shir & Lappin 1979, Grosu 1981, Lakoff 1986, Takami

    1989,

    Deane

    1991).

    This

    is

    a

    far

    more

    complex area of grammar than speech

    act

    constructions

    and

    we can

    only

    outline

    an

    equally oversimplified version of

    the

    proposed

    FAs. These constraints are

    manifested in a

    class of constructions

    usually called extraction constructions (including wH-questions and relative

    clauses).

    We

    may

    divide the extraction

    constructions into three

    parts: the ex-

    tracted

    element,

    the

    matrix

    phrase

    from which the

    element was

    extracted,

    and

    the

    intervening syntactic structure.

    In

    essence,

    syntactic accounts argue that syntactic properties of the interven-

    ing structure

    render an extraction

    construction

    ungrammatical,

    while FAs point

    to exceptional extraction as counterexamples to the syntactic accounts.

    (10)

    a.

    Who

    did

    you

    see

    a

    picture

    oJY

    [Takami 1989:309, after the literature]

    b. *Who

    did

    you destroy a picture of? [ibid.]

    498

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    11/44

    AUTONOMY

    AND

    FUNCTIONALIST

    LINGUISTICS

    (11)

    a. *What did

    he

    grab

    and write

    to his

    Congressman?

    [after

    Deane

    1991:23]

    b. Who

    did

    he

    grah

    his

    pen Cind

    write to?

    [after

    Deane

    1991:24]

    c.

    Whalt

    did

    he

    gralb

    clnd

    throw to his

    sister?

    d. How

    manly

    courses

    caIn

    yol

    tClke

    or

    credit,

    still

    realnIin

    scane,

    and

    get

    all

    A 's

    in?

    [Lakoff

    1986:153]

    Deane's

    FA,

    the

    most

    general

    proposed, adapts

    Anderson's

    (1983)

    spreading

    activation

    model of

    memory

    and

    attention and

    argues

    that

    cognitive

    or

    discourse

    properties

    of all three

    parts

    of an

    extraction

    construction

    jointly

    license

    or

    prohibit

    extraction.

    Very roughly,

    the

    extracted

    element and the

    matrix

    phrase

    must be in the center

    of attention while

    the rest

    must

    be

    backgrounded.6

    Nor-

    mally,

    the lexical head

    noun that

    appears

    to

    block extraction

    is

    informative

    enough to attract the focus of attention (as in lOb), but in lOa it is evoked by

    the semantic frame of

    see

    and

    thus

    permits

    extraction. In 1

    a-b,

    Deane

    argues

    that the

    first event is a

    preparatory

    action

    for the

    second event

    in the

    coordinate

    structure. Hence the first

    event is

    backgrounded

    (although

    the

    structure

    remains

    coordinate;

    see

    Lakoff

    1986);

    extraction is

    possible

    from the

    second clause

    alone

    (but

    not

    the

    first

    clause

    alone)

    because it alone

    is the

    center

    of

    attention.

    The

    normal

    case for

    coordination

    is

    for both events

    jointly

    to be the

    center

    of

    attention,

    and so

    across-the-board extraction

    from

    all

    conjuncts

    is

    possible

    (I

    Ic); but

    any

    combination

    of

    focused/nonfocused events is

    possible

    (lid).

    All of

    these

    FAs postulate a semiotic

    function

    associated

    with

    the

    construc-

    tion

    in

    question and

    deduce the

    syntactic

    behavior from the

    conventional

    func-

    tion. Root

    transformations are

    speech

    act

    constructions; pronominal

    anaphora

    denote a

    salient

    entity in

    the

    discourse; and

    the

    extraction

    constructions

    signify

    a

    certain

    distribution of

    focus of attention.

    Likewise,

    Prince's

    accounts of var-

    ious

    clefting and

    fronting

    constructions

    (Prince

    1978,

    1981)

    specify an

    informa-

    tional status

    that they

    signify. This

    important

    point is

    often

    overlooked.

    Some

    functionalists

    claim

    that these

    FAs

    provide

    evidence

    against

    the

    autonomy

    of

    GRAMMAR,

    ecause

    they

    involve

    semantic,

    pragmatic

    and

    discourse-functional

    principles.

    But

    autonomist

    FAs

    make claims

    primarily

    about facts

    IN the

    gram-

    mar, namely that certain words or constructions have particular conventional

    discourse

    functions or

    cognitive

    statuses-that

    is,

    semiotic

    functions.

    It is

    by

    virtue of

    the

    semiotic

    functions

    of

    particular

    constructions that

    functional

    princi-

    ples

    account

    for the

    syntactic

    constraints.7

    4.

    MIXED

    FORMAL/FUNCTIONALISM:

    CHALLENGING

    THE

    SELF-CONTAINEDNESS

    OF

    SYNTAX. s

    demonstrated in ?3,

    complete

    reductions of

    syntactic

    constraints

    6

    Kuno

    1976 argues

    that

    the

    extracted element

    must

    be topical

    in order to

    be

    extracted,

    while

    Takami

    1989argues

    that the

    matrix

    must be the

    informational

    focus;

    Deane

    argues that both

    require-

    ments must be met to license extraction, and that both requirements may be analyzed in terms of

    focus

    of

    attention.

    7

    Of

    course,

    opinions may

    differ as

    to what

    needs to be

    specified as

    conventional and

    what

    is

    derived

    from

    pragmatic

    principles;

    'radical

    pragmatics'

    (Cole

    1981) tries to

    maximize

    the

    latter

    with

    respect to the

    former.

    499

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    12/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER 3

    (1995)

    to

    functional

    constraints

    do

    not

    challenge

    the self-containedness

    of

    syntax,

    though

    they may

    shrink

    the

    autonomous

    syntactic

    component significantly.

    Partial

    reductions of

    syntactic

    constraints to functional

    principles,

    however,

    pose

    a more serious

    problem

    for the self-containedness of

    syntax.

    If

    only

    a

    partial

    reduction

    is

    possible,

    then

    we

    are left

    with a

    partially

    structural,

    partially

    functional account,

    and

    the question can

    be

    raised as to how self-contained

    the

    syntactic

    component

    is.

    I

    argue

    here that such

    analyses

    are

    quite

    common,

    and

    in

    fact

    cannot

    reasonably

    be avoided. I will call such

    analyses

    MIXED

    FORMAL/

    FUNCTIONAL

    analyses,

    and the

    position

    that

    accepts

    such

    analyses

    MIXED

    FOR-

    MALISM/FUNCTIONALISM.

    will

    conclude

    this section

    by

    suggesting

    that

    indeed

    many

    structuralist

    as well as functionalist theories are

    mixed,

    that

    is,

    they

    accept

    mixed

    analyses.

    Existing FAs of control theory and binding theory do not fully replace syntac-

    tic accounts

    by

    functional ones. Ladusaw &

    Dowty

    (1988)

    argue

    that

    thematic

    control

    is determined

    by

    the

    semantic

    properties

    of the

    situation

    being

    described

    rather

    than

    thematic

    roles,

    but

    assume

    that

    obligatory

    control is

    at

    least

    partially

    syntactically

    determined.

    Farkas

    (1988)

    argues

    that the semantic

    relationship

    of

    responsibility

    determines

    the

    difference between

    promise-

    and

    persnuade-type

    obligatory

    control,

    but allows a stipulated but semantically

    motivated

    extension

    of her

    principle

    to accommodate

    the multiple control possibilities (for

    some

    speakers)

    in examples like 12 (Farkas

    1988:47).

    (12)

    THE

    PUPIL asked

    THE TEACHER to

    leave

    early.

    The

    literature

    on binding, both syntactic

    and functional,

    is as

    voluminous

    and

    the

    phenomenon

    is as complex as with constraints

    on extraction.

    Here

    there

    is

    also

    some

    question

    as to whether binding

    is a unified

    phenomenon.

    The contrast

    between anaphoric pronouns (Pronominals)

    and lexical

    NPs-the

    Principle

    B/C

    contrast-has

    been argued

    to be purely pragmatic, based

    on

    information

    structure

    and attentional phenomena

    (see inter

    alia Bolinger

    1979,

    Koster

    1986,

    Ariel 1990, van Hoek 1992, Gundel et al. 1993).

    In

    fact, it is

    widely

    accepted

    that

    most

    pronoun/NP

    choice is determined

    by pragmatic

    factors

    (Reinhart

    1983,

    Ward et al. 1991:440), and

    the dispute centers around whether

    a

    syntactic condition such as c-command is an appropriate description for certain

    intrasentential

    pronoun

    uses-for instance,

    Bolinger 1979 explicitly

    argues

    against

    the

    syntactic

    description; Koster

    1986 suggests it is purely

    pragmatic

    but

    sensitive

    to

    syntactic criteria;

    and Gundel et al. 1993 propose

    a

    general

    attentional

    account

    of

    pronoun/NP

    choice tested

    in texts in a variety of

    lan-

    guages

    (though

    not

    with

    attention to the c-command

    cases).

    If

    these analysts

    are

    correct,

    then

    an

    autonomist

    FA can be provided

    for the Principle

    B/C

    contrast.8

    Levinson

    (1987,

    1991), on the

    other hand, argues for only a partial

    pragmatic

    x Incidentally, the relationship between functional accounts of pronoun/NP choice and con-

    straints on

    extraction

    constructions

    in terms of levels of attention (Ariel 1990 for the former,

    Deane

    1991

    for

    the

    latter)

    suggests

    that even for functionalists, these two phenomena

    are related,

    while

    NP-movement

    phenomena

    are distinct; cf. Levinson 1991:133,

    fn. 31. This is an interesting

    example

    where

    otherwise

    conflicting

    formalist and functionalist

    analyses both converge on the same

    ideep'

    relationships

    among

    syntactic

    phenomena.

    500

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    13/44

    AUTONOMY AND

    FUNCTIONALIST LINGUISTICS

    account

    of

    the

    Principle

    A/B contrast-the

    distribution

    and

    interpretation

    of

    reflexives and

    reciprocals

    (Anaphors)

    vs.

    Pronominals. He

    argues against

    speci-

    fying

    (non)coreference

    as

    part

    of the

    meaning

    of the

    Anaphor

    or

    Pronominal,

    depending

    on the status of

    Anaphors

    in the

    language.

    In

    B-FIRST

    anguages,

    with

    no

    Anaphors

    or

    weakly grammaticalized

    Anaphors,

    Principle

    B

    is

    grammatical,

    while

    Principle

    A is

    pragmatic;

    in

    A-FIRST

    anguages,

    with

    grammaticalized

    Ana-

    phors,

    it is the other

    way

    around.

    These mixed

    analyses

    are

    controversial.

    However,

    apparently

    mixed

    syntac-

    tic

    phenomena

    are

    quite commonplace

    in

    syntactic

    descriptions.

    I will use

    two

    simple

    examples

    to illustrate

    the

    plausibility

    of

    the mixed

    analysis

    and

    argue

    that an

    attempt

    to

    reanalyze

    the

    phenomenon

    as

    purely syntactic

    smuggles

    semantic

    properties

    into the

    self-contained

    syntactic

    component.

    Babungo is a Grassfields Bantu language (Schaub 1985).Its noun class system

    is

    typical

    of

    Bantu

    languages,

    in that

    nouns

    fall

    into a

    range

    of noun

    classes,

    and the noun classes are

    quite

    arbitrary

    in

    their class

    membership.

    That

    is,

    there

    is no

    way

    one could

    completely predict

    noun class

    membership

    on

    semantic

    principles, although

    Schaub notes some

    correlations,

    e.g.

    class 1/2 with

    humans

    (1985:174;

    the

    paired

    numbers refer

    to

    singular/plural

    forms).

    These

    agreement

    patterns

    indicate

    that

    noun

    classes are not

    only

    arbitrary

    but

    participate

    in

    a

    system

    of

    syntactic

    rules. Modifiers

    agree

    with

    their head

    nouns in

    class,

    and

    verbs

    agree

    with

    their core

    arguments

    in

    class.

    Anaphoric

    pronouns

    agree

    with

    their

    antecedents

    in

    noun class

    in the same

    way.

    There is

    one

    exception

    to

    this

    generalization: anaphoric pronouns that refer to humans, regardless of the noun

    class of the human

    noun,

    take

    class

    1/2

    agreement

    (Schaub

    1985:193).

    Ana-

    phoric pronouns

    that refer to nonhumans

    agree

    in

    the noun

    class of their

    nominal

    antecedent.

    The facts

    as

    just

    described

    argue

    against

    the

    self-containedness of

    syntax. If

    one

    ships

    out the

    human-anaphoric

    agreement generalization

    to the

    semantic

    component,

    then a

    very unsystematic

    hole

    has been

    punched

    into the

    syntax

    of

    agreement

    in

    Babungo,

    and

    hence into

    the

    system

    of

    a

    large range of

    syntactic

    dependencies.

    If

    one

    tries to

    ship

    out a

    more

    natural

    class of

    phenomena, say

    the phenomena of anaphoric reference, then one loses an important linguistic

    generalization

    also: the

    anaphoric

    agreement patterns with

    respect to nouns

    referring

    to

    nonhumans are the

    same as

    those

    for

    modifiers and verbs,

    which

    remain

    in

    the

    syntactic

    component.

    The

    simplest

    way to save

    systematicity and

    the

    linguistic generalization

    (applying Ockham's

    razor) is

    to say

    that there is a

    single grammatical

    system here,

    but

    syntactic

    and

    semantic primitives

    coexist

    peacefully

    in the

    statement

    of

    grammatical rules

    (using

    graminatical

    in the sense

    of

    grammar

    as

    defined in

    ?2.1).

    Phenomena of the

    Babungo type

    are

    quite

    common

    in

    the

    world's languages: a

    particular syntactic

    phenomenon

    is

    sometimes

    constrained by (at least

    partially

    arbitrary) syntactic factors, sometimes by purely semantic or discourse-func-

    tional

    ones,

    and

    they

    are

    interconnected

    to

    a

    high degree.

    Many field

    linguists

    write

    mixed

    grammatical

    descriptions,

    including some

    who

    call themselves

    functionalists

    (e.g.

    Haiman

    1980a,

    McGregor

    1990). These

    functionalists as-

    sume

    the

    independence

    and

    systematicity

    of

    syntax. But in

    practice they deny

    5O1

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    14/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER

    3

    (1995)

    the self-containednessof

    syntax: they

    make reference to functional

    categories

    and features

    in their

    syntactic descriptions. Although

    these functionalists

    do

    not

    generally

    work in one of the

    officially

    named theoretical

    frameworks,

    it

    is

    a

    logically possible

    and

    empiricallyplausible

    intermediate

    position,

    and some-

    thing

    like it

    has been

    developed

    in Dik's

    Functional Grammar

    Dik

    1981)

    and

    in Role and Reference Grammar

    Foley

    & Van Valin

    1984,

    Van Valin

    1993).

    All

    of

    these

    approaches

    fit

    the

    definition of

    mixed

    formal/functionalism

    t

    the

    beginning

    of

    this section.9

    There

    is a

    solution to

    the

    Babungo problem

    that

    appears

    to

    save

    the

    self-

    containednessof

    syntax.

    One could

    provide

    an

    additional ormalfeature

    to the

    lexical

    entries

    of

    nouns,

    let's

    call

    it

    [

    +

    H],

    which is

    [+

    H]

    for nouns

    referring

    to humans and

    I

    -

    H]

    for nouns

    referring

    o

    nonhumans.

    Rules for

    agreement

    other thananaphoricpronominalagreementwill requirematchingof the class

    value with

    the class of the noun

    agreed

    with. The

    rule for

    anaphoric

    reference

    will

    yield

    [class

    1/2]

    for

    IL

    H]

    nouns and

    [class

    a]

    for

    I

    -H]

    nouns

    (a

    referring

    to

    the class feature for

    the

    L-Hi nouns).

    This

    may appear

    to

    be

    an ad

    hoc

    description

    of the

    anaphoricagreement

    system.

    But

    the mixed

    syntactic-seman-

    tic

    account also has to

    specify

    when the

    syntactic

    classes

    dictate

    agreement

    and

    when

    the semantic

    property

    of

    humanness

    does;

    so

    both

    accounts are

    equally

    ad

    hoc

    in

    this

    respect (but

    see

    ?5.1).

    And

    the

    purely syntactic

    account

    preserves

    the

    self-containednessof

    syntax.

    This

    strategy

    is

    in fact

    an

    instance

    of

    a

    general technique

    for

    reanalyzing

    putative

    mixed

    syntactic-semantic

    rules. In the mixed

    formulation,

    there is a

    grammatical

    rule that makes

    reference

    to

    both

    syntactic

    and

    semantic

    primi-

    tives.

    The

    purely syntactic

    formulation

    shifts the

    semantic

    part

    of the

    mixed

    formulation

    o

    a

    mapping

    rule

    between

    syntax

    and

    semantics,

    namely

    the

    map-

    ping

    rule

    that

    specifies

    that

    the

    syntactic

    feature

    [?

    H]

    is

    mapped

    into the

    se-

    mantic

    feature

    [?

    HUMAN].

    In

    general,

    this

    strategy

    can be

    employed so as

    to restrict

    reference

    to semantic

    primitives

    to

    mapping

    rules

    between

    syntax

    and

    semantics.

    Nevertheless,

    an

    important eneralization

    has

    been lost

    in

    the

    purely syntac-

    tic account. There is a precise match between the distributionof the [?H]

    featureand the

    semantic

    property

    of

    humannessof

    referents.

    That

    is,

    the

    feature

    ?

    H]

    CAN

    be

    reduced to

    a

    nonsyntactic primitive(cf. Newmeyer's definition

    of

    autonomy

    at

    the

    beginning

    of

    ?2.2).

    The

    self-containednessof

    syntax can only

    be

    maintained

    by essentially replicating

    a

    semantic

    primitive

    in

    the

    syntactic

    component.

    Semantics is

    smuggled

    into

    the

    syntax

    via a

    syntactic

    feature

    that

    duplicates

    a

    semantic

    one.

    If

    the

    employment

    of

    this sort

    of reformulationof

    syntactic

    rules

    is

    taken as

    proof

    of

    the

    self-containednessof

    syntax, then the

    self-containedness

    of

    syntax

    is

    an

    unfalsifiable

    proposition.'0

    9

    Van Valin

    refers to

    Role and

    Reference

    Grammar

    as a

    'structural/functionalist' theory (Van

    Valin

    1993:2).

    '0

    This

    last

    statement

    must be

    qualified.

    The

    self-containedness of

    syntax, while not falsifiable

    in

    this sense,

    may

    be

    proven

    to

    be true if

    every

    case

    in

    which

    a

    grammatical rule is described to

    be

    sensitive

    to

    a

    semantic,

    pragmatic

    or

    discourse-functional

    property

    is

    empirically demonstrated

    to

    be false. This

    is

    unlikely

    and as

    we will

    see

    shortly,

    is

    hardly

    an

    issue any more.

    I

    am indebted

    502

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    15/44

    AUTONOMY AND

    FUNCTIONALIST LINGUISTICS

    One

    might

    consider the

    Babungo

    example

    as an

    instance in

    which the

    price

    to

    pay

    for semantic

    smuggling

    is

    relatively small,

    since

    the

    agreement

    rules are

    by

    and

    large governed by syntactic

    factors.

    However,

    one finds

    examples

    of

    all

    proportions

    of mixture of

    syntactic

    and semantic or other functional rules

    in

    the

    grammars

    of the

    world's

    languages.

    Obviation

    in

    Cree is an

    example

    of

    the

    opposite

    balance between

    syntax

    and

    semiotic function. Cree

    (and

    other

    Algonquian

    languages) possesses

    a nominal

    inflection whose values are

    termed

    PROXIMATEnd OBVIATIVE.n

    general,

    the

    rules for the

    employment

    of

    the

    proximate

    and

    obviative are

    exclusively

    a matter of

    discourse

    pragmatics

    (see

    for

    example

    the brief remarks in Wolfart

    & Carroll

    1981:25-27).

    That

    is,

    there

    is a

    mapping

    rule between the

    noun forms and

    the

    values

    [proximate,

    obviative]

    and

    discourse-functional

    properties,

    and the

    distribution

    of

    proximate

    and

    obvi-

    ative noun phrases is dictated by the discourse component of the grammar.

    There are

    a

    few

    cases,

    however,

    in

    which

    choice of form

    is

    determined

    by

    the

    syntax.

    Specifically,

    in a

    possessive

    construction

    the

    possessed

    item

    is

    always

    obviative,

    though

    the

    possessor may

    be

    proximate

    or

    obviative

    (Wolfart

    & Carroll

    1981:47-49).

    In some

    sense,

    this is worse

    for the

    self-containedness

    of

    syntax

    than the

    Babungo

    case.

    One could

    provide

    a

    wholly syntactic

    account

    only by

    importing all of obviation into the

    syntax.

    In

    this

    case,

    the

    syntactic

    component would

    dictate

    the distribution

    of

    proximate

    vs.

    obviative

    in

    possess-

    ive

    constructions. But it would

    only

    be able

    to

    specify

    that

    either

    value is

    licensed in

    virtually

    every

    other

    syntactic

    context,

    and leave it

    to the

    discourse

    component to filter out the discourse-functionally inappropriate utterances. In

    contrast, a mixed

    formal-functional

    account

    would license

    only

    the

    syntactically

    and

    discourse-functionally

    acceptable

    utterances.

    As a matter

    of fact,

    it

    may

    be

    that semantic

    (or

    discourse)

    smuggling

    is

    no

    longer a

    black

    market

    activity. Consider the

    grammatical structures

    of Head-

    driven

    Phrase Structure Grammar

    (HPSG;

    Pollard &

    Sag

    1987, 1994)

    and

    Fill-

    more &

    Kay's

    version of

    Construction Grammar

    (1993). Both

    theories use

    typed

    feature

    structures to

    represent

    grammatical

    structures,

    including elements and

    rules of

    combination. Each typed

    feature structure

    contains

    both

    syntactic and

    semantic information, as values for the (syn) and (sem) features respectively.

    They are

    both

    semiotic theories in the

    Saussurean

    sense. Neither

    theory,

    as

    far as I

    can

    tell,

    explicitly excludes reference

    to either

    (syn) or

    (sem) values

    or

    subvalues

    in the

    formulation

    of

    grammatical

    generalizations,

    though particular

    generalizations

    may

    involve only

    (syn)

    subvalues. Both

    of these

    theories are

    mixed

    theories, by our

    definition.

    It

    is worth

    quoting the

    proponents of

    the

    supposedly more

    formalist

    of

    these two

    theories:"1

    to

    Matthew Dryer

    and Russell

    Tomlin

    for providing

    essential

    parts of

    the semantic

    smuggling

    argument.

    "

    At this point, it

    is also worth

    pointing out another

    use of the term

    formal

    in describing

    linguistic

    theories,

    namely that a

    formal

    theory is one in

    which

    descriptions of

    grammatical structures

    and

    generalizations are

    formulated in a

    rigorous

    mathematical

    metalanguage.

    In

    principle, it is

    quite

    possible to

    characterize any

    formalist or

    functionalist

    theory in a

    rigorous

    mathematical

    metalan-

    guage, although in

    practice

    rejection

    of formalism

    has often

    included

    rejection of

    mathematical

    formalization.

    503

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    16/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME 71,

    NUMBER

    3 (1995)

    HPSG differs

    from all the

    syntactic

    theories which have influenced its

    development,

    for

    it

    is

    not at heart a

    theory

    of

    syntax.

    Rather, it is concerned with the interaction

    among

    all

    the

    forms of information that

    bear

    upon

    the

    linguistic meaning

    relation,

    including

    (inter

    alia)

    both

    the syntactic information borne by signs as well as their semantic content ... syntactic and

    semantic

    aspects

    of

    grammatical

    theory

    are built

    up

    in an

    integrated way

    from the start,

    under

    the

    assumption

    that neither can be well understood in isolation from the other.

    (Pollard

    &

    Sag

    1987:16-17)

    Finally,

    it

    is

    a serious

    question

    as to whether even recent versions

    of

    Chom-

    skyan generative

    grammar

    are autonomous in the sense of a

    self-contained

    syntactic component.

    For

    example,

    the

    theta-criterion

    (Chomsky

    1981:36,

    335)

    imposes

    a

    restriction

    on

    syntactic

    structure

    depending

    on whether a theta-role

    is

    assigned

    to

    a

    particular

    position,

    but

    theta-roles

    are

    semantic entities

    (Chomsky

    1981:35).

    This

    appears

    to

    be

    a

    constraint on

    syntactic

    structures

    in

    which

    seman-

    tic structure

    plays

    a direct role. Matthews makes this

    point

    more

    generally,

    discussing

    different

    passages

    in

    Chomsky's

    recent work

    (Chomsky

    1981,

    1986)

    which

    appear

    to

    equivocate

    on

    whether certain

    components

    of the

    grammar

    (in

    particular,

    LF)

    are

    syntactic

    or

    semantic.

    In

    citing

    these

    passages

    I

    am

    not

    trying

    to

    suggest

    that

    Chomsky

    was

    confused or

    inconsistent,

    but rather

    to

    illustrate what

    now

    seemed to be

    true,

    that in the

    'principles-and-parameters'

    model'

    to

    call one level

    'syntactic'

    and

    another 'semantic'

    no

    longer

    made

    any

    real

    sense

    ..

    Insofar

    as

    [the

    levels]

    were

    like

    those

    envisaged

    before what

    Chomsky

    calls his

    second 'concep-

    tual shift', we could

    perhaps

    continue to

    use the

    old names. But if

    I

    have

    understood

    the

    logic

    correctly,

    they

    were mere names.

    (Matthews

    1993:245)

    LF

    may

    have

    begun

    as

    a

    semantic

    level;

    when

    syntactic

    processes

    such

    as

    movement were

    sanctioned

    in

    LF,

    it

    appears

    to have

    become a

    syntactic

    level;

    but

    Matthews

    suggests

    that

    LF hasn't

    fully

    lost

    its

    semantic

    character in

    the

    process.

    Properties

    internal

    to

    the

    grammatical

    system,

    some

    of

    which

    were

    once

    called

    semantic,

    now

    appear

    to be

    part

    of the

    grammar;

    and

    what really

    matters is whether

    they

    are

    a

    manifestation

    of

    Universal

    Grammar.

    More

    re-

    cently,

    Jackendoff

    writes,

    'we

    ought

    now to

    be

    willing

    to consider

    mixed alter-

    natives

    when

    the facts

    push

    us that

    way'

    (1992:30).

    Thus,

    it

    appears

    that

    in

    fact even

    contemporary

    Chomskyan

    generative

    gram-

    mar is mixed. Instead, it appears that Chomsky's attention has now turned to

    the

    autonomy

    of

    grammar.

    Chomsky

    describes

    'real

    semantics'

    as 'the

    study

    of the

    relation between

    language

    or

    language

    use and

    the

    world'

    (1981:324).

    The

    minimalist

    program

    takes

    X

    (formerly

    LF)

    as the

    interface between

    the

    grammar

    and the

    'conceptual-intentional

    system'

    (Chomsky

    1993:2),

    not

    as

    an

    interface between a

    syntactic

    and a

    semantic

    component

    of

    the

    grammar.

    These

    issues

    will be

    taken

    up again

    in

    ?7,

    after a

    survey

    of

    two

    stronger

    positions

    that

    have been taken

    against

    the

    autonomy

    of

    syntax.

    5.

    TYPOLOGICAL

    FUNCTIONALISM:

    LIMITING

    ARBITRARINESS IN

    SYNTAX.

    Some

    typologists

    have

    argued

    for

    grammatical

    analyses

    that

    integrate

    form and func-

    tion

    more

    profoundly

    than

    other

    mixed

    models.

    These

    accept

    that

    the

    grammar

    includes

    arbitrariness,

    and

    they provide

    mixed

    analyses.

    However,

    the

    mixed

    analyses

    are

    such

    that the

    arbitrary

    parts

    of

    the

    analysis

    are

    language-specific,

    while

    the

    universal

    properties

    instantiated

    in

    the

    analysis

    are

    functional.

    These

    5()4

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    17/44

    AUTONOMY AND

    FUNCTIONALIST

    LINGUISTICS

    FAs are more functional than

    mixed

    analyses

    with

    regard

    to

    universals,

    not

    with

    regard

    to

    autonomy.

    We will

    call such

    analyses

    TYPOLOGICAL

    As,

    and

    their

    proponents

    TYPOLOGICAL

    UNCTIONALISTS.

    The

    basic

    strategy

    for

    constructing

    a

    typological

    FA is to examine a

    correla-

    tion

    between

    syntax

    and

    semantics

    (or

    perhaps

    discourse

    function),

    seek

    a

    functional

    prototype

    that is

    found across

    languages,

    and construct

    implicational

    universals

    (particularly

    implicational

    hierarchies)

    holding

    between

    nonproto-

    typical

    semantic

    types

    and

    the

    prototypical

    ones. The

    universal hierarchies and

    prototypes

    are

    the

    crosslinguistic

    manifestation of

    particular

    kinds of

    relation-

    ships

    among

    semantic and/or discourse

    elements

    in a

    speaker's

    mind.

    These

    functional elements

    and

    relationships

    partake

    in the

    grammatical

    knowledge

    of

    an individual. Hence the

    grammatical

    system

    is

    mixed,

    but

    the

    mixture

    is

    of a

    specific type: it is made up of functionally defined universal elements and rela-

    tions

    as well

    as

    arbitrary language-specific

    elements and

    relations.

    We illustrate this

    analytical strategy

    first with a

    typological

    FA

    of

    basic

    syn-

    tactic

    category membership-a

    fundamental

    syntactic

    primitive

    if there

    ever

    was one. As with the FAs in

    ?3-4,

    this

    illustration

    is

    highly

    simplified

    (the

    general

    analysis

    is based on Dixon 1977 and

    Croft

    1991:36-148;

    other

    studies

    are cited

    below).

    The basic

    syntactic

    categories

    Noun,

    Verb

    and

    Adjective

    are

    generally

    de-

    fined

    in

    terms

    of

    morphological properties,

    mainly

    inflectional categories (tense-

    aspect,

    number,

    case, etc.),

    and

    syntactic

    distributional

    criteria

    (e.g.

    occurrence

    with articles, auxiliaries, etc.). These properties are language-specific, but we

    may compare

    the

    major syntactic categories

    of

    languages

    by comparing across

    languages

    the

    function

    of the

    inflections and

    co-occurring

    words

    used to define

    category

    membership

    and

    the

    semantics

    of

    the

    word

    classes that

    combine with

    them. In

    particular,

    the

    functions of

    the

    usual

    inflectional

    and

    syntactic criteria

    used to define

    the

    major syntactic categories

    are

    associated

    with

    the pragmatic

    functions

    of

    reference,

    predication

    and

    modification

    (Searle 1969; Croft 1991:

    101-26

    integrates

    Searle's

    pragmatic

    analysis

    with

    conceptual-semantic

    and

    discourse-functional

    analyses

    of the

    same

    concepts).

    Dixon (1977) observes that in comparing adjective classes across languages,

    using

    comparable

    syntactic-semantic

    criteria,

    certain

    semantic

    classes of prop-

    erty

    concepts

    form the

    prototype

    of

    the

    adjective

    category. Wetzer (1992)

    slightly

    modifies

    Dixon's

    analysis

    and

    argues

    that

    even

    in languages

    where

    adjectives appear

    to be a

    subset

    of nouns

    or

    verbs on

    the usual morphosyntactic

    criteria,

    peculiarities

    in

    morphosyntactic

    behavior

    distinguish

    the adjectival se-

    mantic

    classes

    (properties)

    from

    true

    verbal

    semantic

    classes

    (actions or pro-

    cesses).

    Croft

    (1991)

    extends

    this

    typological

    FA

    to

    nominal and

    verbal categories.

    Certain

    semantic

    classes of

    words

    consistently display

    the

    full

    range of morpho-

    syntactic behavior and the most simply encoded syntactic structure for the

    pragmatic

    functions of

    reference and

    predication-that

    is, they are unmarked

    in

    the

    typological

    sense

    (Croft

    1990:64-154).

    Words

    denoting

    objects are the

    least

    marked

    referring expressions,

    and

    words

    denoting actions are the least

    marked

    predications.

    Consider

    the

    following English examples:

    5()5

  • 8/10/2019 Autonomy of Functional Linguistics - William Croft

    18/44

    LANGUAGE,

    VOLUME

    71,

    NUMBER

    3

    (1995)

    (13)

    The BIRD

    lew

    away.

    [object,

    reference]

    (14)

    The bird FLEW

    way.

    [action,

    predication]

    (15)

    That WASA BIRD.

    [object, predication]

    The

    word

    bird

    in

    15 is considered

    syntactically

    to be a

    noun;

    it shares

    nounlike

    morphosyntactic

    behavior with bird in

    13,

    and in contrast it is

    unable to

    take

    verbal

    inflections of the sort

    acceptable

    with

    flew

    in 14.

    However,

    bird in

    15

    is also

    characterized

    by

    the fixed

    use

    of a

    (or

    bare

    plural

    for

    plural subjects),

    in contrast with

    ordinary

    nouns

    (as

    in

    13)

    and the

    obligatory presence

    of

    the

    copula

    in

    predication,

    in contrast with

    ordinary

    verbal

    predications

    (as

    in

    14).

    In other

    words,

    the

    English predicate

    nominal

    does not

    display

    the

    full

    range

    of

    morphosyntactic

    behavior

    of

    a

    noun

    in

    a

    referring expression.

    Also,

    unlike

    verbal

    predications,

    the

    predicate

    nominal

    requires

    a

    copula.

    And

    even

    though

    the copula expresses some verbal categories such as tense, others such as the

    progressive

    are

    unacceptable:

    (16)

    *That was

    being

    a

    bird.

    Moreover,

    in other

    languages,

    the

    predicate

    nominal

    displays

    even

    fewer

    noun-like

    properties,

    in fact almost none at

    all,

    as

    in

    Classical

    Nahuatl

    (Andrews

    1975:146):

    (17)

    n-

    oqiiich

    -tli

    1ST-

    man

    -sG

    'I

    am a

    man.

    Predication of object concepts varies considerably across languages, but are

    consistent in

    lacking

    some

    morphosyntactic

    nominal

    criteria in

    comparison

    to

    reference with

    object concepts,

    and

    in

    lacking

    some verbal

    criteria in

    compari-

    son to

    predication

    of action

    concepts.

    In

    other

    words,

    predication

    of

    object

    concepts

    is

    nonprototypical

    in

    comparison

    to

    reference to

    objects

    and

    predica-

    tion

    of

    actions,

    both

    of

    which are

    consistent in their

    coding

    and

    behavior across

    languages.

    If

    one

    brings adjectives (more precisely,

    word

    classes

    denoting

    properties),

    into

    the

    picture,

    one

    can

    construct more

    precise crosslinguistic generalizations

    about the predication of various sorts of semantic word classes. The (non)use

    of a

    copula

    conforms

    to

    a

    hierarchy

    of

    predication:

    (18)

    Action word

    (verb)