27
The study of international law and interna- tional relations has flourished in the past decade. This should hardly be surprising. These two disciplines have closely entwined historical roots in the traditional study of interstate relations and diplomacy (Jeffery 2006). The role of international law in inter- national relations has for a least a century been at the heart of some of the most impor- tant debates in international relations schol- arship. Something of an intellectual wedge was driven between these two disciplines when the social sciences and international relations in particular took a behavioralist turn in the 1940s and 1950s. The normative and doctrinal approach of many legal schol- ars seemed to have little intersection with the increasingly social scientific concerns of international relations scholars to explain, interpret, and increasingly to predict interna- tional politics. For a brief period coinciding with the apogee of structural realism of the 1970s and 1980s, international law was widely viewed as irrelevant to the study of international relations. The drought of scholarly work linking international law with international relations ended by the mid-1990s. The study of inter- national regimes in the 1970s and 1980s foreshadowed the current sharp upswing in interest in international law. Not only are scholars increasingly interested in the grow- ing “legalization” of international affairs, they are making tremendous strides in theo- rizing and documenting the consequences of international legal norms and agreements for our understanding of international affairs more generally. This has led to new fields of inquiry in international relations that were barely apparent two decades ago. The first section of this essay defines a few key terms and provides some historical back- ground on the relationship between interna- tional law and international relations. The second section discusses the major theoreti- cal approaches, from those that highlight material incentives to those that rest on more ideational foundations. The third section discusses international law development – concepts of legalization, judicialization, con- stitutionalization, and global administrative law. The fourth section reviews theories and empirical studies of compliance with public international law. The final section concludes that theory has become less com- partmentalized by “school” and empirical research has become more rigorous over the past decade. International Law Beth Simmons 14 5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 352 5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 352 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

Beth Simmons - Harvard University · interstate relations and diplomacy (Jeffery ... (see the chapter by Martin and Simmons in ... And the lessons of World War II

  • Upload
    vanque

  • View
    213

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

The study of international law and interna-tional relations has flourished in the past decade. This should hardly be surprising. These two disciplines have closely entwined historical roots in the traditional study of interstate relations and diplomacy (Jeffery 2006). The role of international law in inter-national relations has for a least a century been at the heart of some of the most impor-tant debates in international relations schol-arship. Something of an intellectual wedge was driven between these two disciplines when the social sciences and international relations in particular took a behavioralist turn in the 1940s and 1950s. The normative and doctrinal approach of many legal schol-ars seemed to have little intersection with the increasingly social scientific concerns of international relations scholars to explain, interpret, and increasingly to predict interna-tional politics. For a brief period coinciding with the apogee of structural realism of the 1970s and 1980s, international law was widely viewed as irrelevant to the study of international relations.

The drought of scholarly work linking international law with international relations ended by the mid-1990s. The study of inter-national regimes in the 1970s and 1980s

foreshadowed the current sharp upswing in interest in international law. Not only are scholars increasingly interested in the grow-ing “legalization” of international affairs, they are making tremendous strides in theo-rizing and documenting the consequences of international legal norms and agreements for our understanding of international affairs more generally. This has led to new fields of inquiry in international relations that were barely apparent two decades ago.

The first section of this essay defines a few key terms and provides some historical back-ground on the relationship between interna-tional law and international relations. The second section discusses the major theoreti-cal approaches, from those that highlight material incentives to those that rest on more ideational foundations. The third section discusses international law development – concepts of legalization, judicialization, con-stitutionalization, and global administrative law. The fourth section reviews theories and empirical studies of compliance with public international law. The final section concludes that theory has become less com-partmentalized by “school” and empirical research has become more rigorous over the past decade.

International Law

B e t h S i m m o n s

14

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3525769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 352 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 353

BACKGROUND

Scope and Definitions

International law can be defined as a body of principles, customs, and rules recognized as effectively binding obligations by sovereign states in their mutual relations. “What dis-tinguishes law from other types of social ordering is not form, but adherence to specific rules of legality: generality, prom-ulgation, non-retroactivity, clarity, non-contradiction, not asking the impossible, constancy, and congruence between rules and official action” (Brunnée and Toope 2010). International law’s distinguishing feature – that which sets it apart from an institution, practice, or political agreement – is its acceptance in principle as binding. Public international law comprises a set of binding rules among states. Increasingly we can find instances in which such rules govern individuals (international criminal law and some aspects of the laws of war, for example), but only states (or in some cases, organizations of states) can enter into inter-national legal agreements, or treaties. This binding state-to-state quality distinguishes international law from the broader concept of international institutions, which can include nonbinding practices and which, many would agree, can also include rules and principles devised by nonstate actors (see the chapter by Martin and Simmons in this volume).

Study and research on international law is also distinct from that of international organizations. While intergovernmental organizations are usually based on an inter-national legal agreement (the various bodies of the United Nations are obvious exam-ples), they are also actors in their own right, and are often studied as such. Many interna-tional legal agreements give rise to thin or even no international organizational struc-tures whatsoever. An extradition treaty, for example, creates no international organiza-tion whatsoever. The parties to the agree-ment decide when and how to carry it out.

Some scholars and practitioners make refer-ence to “soft law.” In international relations, this can have two meanings. One refers to any written international instrument, other than a treaty, containing principles, norms, standards, or other statements of expected behavior. Or, it sometimes is used to refer to the more hortatory or promotional provi-sions within a legally binding treaty (Shelton 2009: 69).

International law is found not only in trea-ties but in the body of custom that has devel-oped over time among states. Customary international law is based on state practice, combined with an understanding that such practice has developed into an obligatory norm (opinio juris). When a stable practice develops among a sufficiently broad number of states, and when a large number of them view the practice as legally binding, it becomes recognized as a binding principle of international law. Ius Cogens norms are con-sidered the most fundamental principles of customary international law, from which derogation is not ever allowed. While no single authoritative list of such norms exist, some examples include prohibitions against aggressive war and crimes against humanity. A similar set of basic norms are sometimes termed erga onmes – obligations owed to all. Examples include obligations to refrain from slavery and torture. Legal scholars have also given attention to a growing body of what they refer to as “interstitial law,” that is, the implicit rules operating in and around explicit normative frameworks (Lowe 2000). While an important source of international law in many areas, customary and interstitial inter-national law have been the subject of rela-tively little attention in international relations, perhaps because they can be difficult to establish empirically and their causal influ-ence is hard to study rigorously (Goldsmith and Posner 2005). Since much of interna-tional custom – from the law of the seas to prohibitions against torture to the law of trea-ties – has now been codified, IR scholars have largely concentrated on treaty law. This article will do the same.

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3535769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 353 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS354

International law in history

Some form of international system of rules has governed relations between independent political entities for centuries if not millen-nia. David Bederman argues that there was “a coherent sense among ancient peoples from Near East and Mediterranean traditions that state relations should be conducted in accordance with established norms and values” (Bederman 2009: 115). He notes that ancient law among nations was first and fore-most an instrument for order, used to secure not only stable power relations among sover-eigns but also to bolster their internal legiti-macy. While the prehistory of legal agreements between organized groups of humans has been lost in the mists of history, as early as 2500 BCE evidence can be found of third party arbitration awards regarding arable land among cities, as well as nonag-gression pacts (frequently violated) among the same (Altman 2004). Ancient Sumerians concluded “international” agreements regard-ing dynastic marriage alliances between rulers, arbitration in city-state conflict man-agement, and the laws of travel and extradi-tion for runaway slaves, refugees, and deserting soldiers at the dawn of recorded history (Altman 2009).

It is not the purpose of this article to develop a history of the development of international law. However, many such histo-ries note that international law has roots in the rules and principles developed by the Roman Empire to govern interactions between Roman citizens and citizens of the outside world (jus gentium, or the law among peoples, rather than jus civile, or the law among citizens of Rome). For centuries – at least until but perhaps well beyond Grotius’s treatise on The Laws of War and Peace (Grotius 1962) – international law was widely viewed as grounded in natural law, divine in origin. Of course, as Yasuaki reminds us, “The overwhelming majority of the human species lived in the areas where ‘universal’ natural law had no impact at all. It was only around the end of the nineteenth century that

the European international law actually became valid as universal law of the world in the geographical sense” (Yasuaki 2000). Most international law histories can therefore be considered the history of European tradi-tions and structures, developed in the wake of the crumbing Holy Roman Empire, the scourge of repeated wars, and the rise of trade and maritime transportation (Nussbaum 1954; Butler and Maccoby 1928).

THEORETICAL APPROACHES

The Early Twentieth Century

International law and international relations scholars began an intense, self-conscious dialog in the early twentieth century. One window into this conversation is the implicit debate that took place during the interwar years on the role of international law in reducing violent conflict among nations. In many ways, of course, this was a subset of the more general debate about the role of power, morality, and law that took place among a variety of so-called legal idealists and realists in the 1920s and 1930s. E.H. Carr was one of the most prominent com-mentators for the latter (and, in fact, is the likely source for the “idealist” label). The “idealists” held in common the notion that progress in international relations post World War I was indeed possible, and would likely be built upon the pillars of international trade, international organizations, and domes-tic democratic governance (Zimmern 1934; Angell 1911). Many expected international law to play a significant role in the interna-tional order of the time. Indeed, as the United States rose to power in the early twentieth century, it found itself with a weak foreign policy structure, but a well-developed notion of the role of law in ordering human affairs. Steinberg and Zasloff argue that it was there-fore natural that the United States would see international politics through a legalistic lens, as epitomized by such statesmen as

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3545769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 354 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 355

Elihu Root and Woodrow Wilson (Steinberg and Zasloff 2006).

In many ways, the interwar “debate” between the Idealists and realists has been exaggerated (Simpson 2001). Woodrow Wilson himself spoke publicly of law gener-ally as ‘subsequent to the fact;” as reflective of rather than transformative of social reali-ties (Wilson 1911). Yet realists such as E.H. Carr emphasized what they saw as naiveté in the hope that international law could contrib-ute much to the post-war peace, much less stave off general war in the 1930s. His work is enlightening as a succinct expression not only of classical realism: “... a state whose interests were adversely affected by a treaty commonly repudiated it as soon as it could do so with impunity ...” (Carr 1964: 169). Carr can also be read as a precursor of criti-cal legal theory. In his discussion of the post–World War I order, he described treaties as devoid of moral content, espoused by those satisfied with the status quo to secure their interests (Carr 1964: 166). High on his agenda was the project of deflating the pre-sumption that international law was particu-larly moral or legitimate1 – a message that resonates with critical theory today.

Post–World War II: International Law in a “Science” of Politics

Continuing many of the themes developed in the 1930s, the classical realists of the 1940s through 1960s can be read to have under-stood law as largely epiphenomenal, or worse yet, irrelevant to the more basic forces of international politics. The “science” of inter-national politics was designed explicitly to leave behind the normative wishful thinking of legal idealists, and to describe not the world one might wish, but the world as it actually is. And the lessons of World War II were fairly clear in this regard: power could not be contained by fragile legal tenets. Morgenthau, for example, complained that “the very structure of international relations – as reflected in … legal arrangements – has

tended to become at variance with and in large measure irrelevant to the reality of international politics” (Morgenthau 1985: 8). The central problem with international law, as he saw it, was its decentralized and essen-tially unenforceable nature (Morgenthau 1985: ch. 18). The message of the classical realists was pretty clear: nothing of real importance in international relations could be achieved through international law. As Raymond Aron put it, “One does not judge international law by peaceful periods and secondary problems” (Aron 1981: 733). At most, the classical realists thought that inter-national law could function in a limited way when the underlying balance of power kept the most violent ambitions of states in check. But shifting power balances exposed interna-tional law’s weaknesses and “created oppor-tunities for chaos” (Hoffmann 1987: 166).

Kenneth Waltz’s influential structural real-ism stripped law, rules, and norms away completely, until the only thing of relevance to a theory of international politics was “structure” – defined as power relations among states in a system of anarchy (Waltz 1979: 70–101). “Structure” thus defined, Waltz admitted, was “certainly no good on detail” (Chapter 2) – which is the status to which he evidently relegated international economic relationships, protection of the environment, and human rights. With these “details” removed from international poli-tics, law became largely irrelevant to the study of international relations. By the late 1970s, the study of international law in the social sciences was nearly moribund.

Nearly, but not completely, and not for long. The realist view of the world raised some uncomfortable theoretical puzzles. One was to explain why such a useless institution as international law existed at all. Surely there were costs involved in negotiating international legal agreements, seeking ratifi-cation, and dreaming up ways to fit specific agreements logically under broader norma-tive principles to which many if not most state adhered. Moreover, states seemed for the most part to be guided by the rules they

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3555769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 355 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS356

were negotiating. Morgenthau himself noted that “The great majority of the rules of inter-national law are generally observed by all nations without actual compulsion, for it is generally in the interest of all nations con-cerned to honor their obligations under inter-national law” (Morgenthau 1985: 112-3). Echoes of this sentiment could be heard years later in the writing of a scholar with realist roots who took the possibility of “international society” seriously. As Hedley Bull wrote, “The fact that these rules are believed to have the status of law ... makes possible a corpus of international activity that plays an important part in the working of international society” (Bull 1977: 136). In these views, we find two openings for theo-rizing the conditions under which interna-tional law can influence the actions of sovereign states; via their interests, and via their shared conceptions of appropriate behavior. Each of these has found expression in recent approaches to the study of interna-tional law in international relations

Contemporary Theories

Resistance to the utter irrelevance of interna-tional law has developed in two fairly distinct theoretical traditions in the past two decades. Both “rationalists” – a broad term used here to designate theorists who emphasize instru-mental behavior to achieve specific, often material ends – as well as constructivists – broadly, those who believe in the constructed nature of social reality – were intrigued by the puzzle of international law’s very exist-ence. Many wondered whether realism had any theoretical purchase on understanding a world in which rules, norms, dispute settle-ment procedures, and other law-like struc-tures were proliferating.

One of the most important theoretical developments in international relations to influence later scholarship on international law explicitly eschewed any connection to law per se. The “international regimes” litera-ture, exemplified in a volume edited by

Stephen Krasner, was an effort to understand a world that, while quite obviously anarchic, was nonetheless highly organized (Krasner 1983a). A cluster of scholars in the early 1980s began to work out theories of the for-mation, transformation, and decline of formal and informal arrangements they referred to as “international regimes,” or rules, norms, and decision-making procedures that shape actors’ expectations and thereby influence relations among other states and between states and other actors (Krasner 1983b: 2). The early regimes literature was theoretically eclectic. It ranged from structural/strategic approaches that linked the rise of regimes with specific power relations among states (Stein 1983; Keohane 1983) most especially with the hegemony, or dominance of a major power, to more “Groatian” approaches that assumed a common social purpose among states and to some extent other actors (Ruggie 1982).

Two distinctive theoretical traditions found in this early regimes literature continue to flourish in the social sciences today. To sim-plify the matter greatly, they were inspired by the seminal theoretical work of Robert Keohane and to a lesser extent Stephen Krasner on the one hand and John Ruggie and to a lesser extent Friedrich Kratochwil on the other. Keohane’s theory of the demand for “international regimes” spawned a hugely influential research agenda constructed on rationalist/functionalist premises to explain the rise and development of international regimes (Keohane 1983). Strongly influ-enced by institutional economics, Keohane proposed a “functional” theory of interna-tional regimes that analyzed why states would demand such structures, arguing that the existence of rules norms and agreed-upon procedures helped to reduce transactions costs among states, reduce uncertainty, and create focal points around which states could coordinate their behaviors and policies. Some regimes were also theorized to provide information that would assist in developing reputations, thereby reinforcing agreements for states that wanted to benefit from future contracting.

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3565769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 356 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 357

This general functional approach to inter-national institutions has had a tremendous impact on the study of international law in the social sciences, despite the fact that it was not conceived as a theory of interna-tional law per se.2 Many of the same assump-tions, concepts, and modes of reasoning could be found in the IR/IL theories that fol-lowed. Charles Lipson, for example, concen-trated on the focal qualities of international treaties and in particular their explicitness and precision which he and many others argue raises the reputational costs of non-compliance. States use very formal agree-ments (international law) when they have strong motives to try to overcome coopera-tion dilemmas; treaties are a way to be explicit and to signal seriousness in a way that distinguishes them from less formal agreements (Lipson 1991). Abbott and Snidal drew on the idea of transactions costs to explain why states would want to develop “hard law” agreements (Abbott and Snidal 2000). A similar rationalist logic character-izes a number of scholar-practitioners as well, from international jurist Rosalyn Higgins to Justice Department legal counsel Jack Goldsmith (Higgins 1994; Goldsmith and Posner 2005). Agreements regarding the law of the seas (Posner and Sykes 2009), trade liberalization, arms control, and even the laws of war (Morrow 2007) have been theorized as areas in which joint gains and the expectation of a future stream of benefit have been theorized in rationalist-functional-ist terms (see below).

Yet, rationalist theories have a number of bind spots that more social constructivist theories have to some extent been deployed to address. For example, it is quite obvious that focal points have to be intersubjectively recognized to be helpful at coordinating behavior. “Law” can only raise expectations of compliant behavior if actors share a mutu-ally constructed notion of its special obliga-tory status (Brunnée and Toope 2010). Most evidently, the concept of a reputation – the mechanism on which rationalists typically depend for reciprocity and ultimately

compliance – only has meaning when it is constructed by a community of actors about which a specific actor cares.

In constructivist theory, rules and norms are important, not only because they solve problems, but also because they condition actors’ self-understandings, references, and ultimately their behavior. Indeed, rules are crucial in determining who is a legitimate actor in world politics. The basic tenet of sov-ereign state equality that serves to privilege states as the relevant actors in international law itself is a social construction, and there-fore open to contention and redefinition.

Among the original “regimes theorists,” John Ruggie’s work represented and advanced this intersubjective approach. One of his much-cited articles interpreted the postwar set of rules governing international trade, not simply as rules about reciprocity and market access, but in terms of the broader social purpose of achieving employ-ment and income security as well (Ruggie 1982). The trade regime, he noted was gov-erned not only by material power distribu-tions, but also by what actors had come to regard as “acceptable” behavior, and what was acceptable was the product of intersub-jective meaning, not coercion or narrow material payoffs alone.

These insights have influenced a broad range of constructivist theorizing about inter-national law. Christian Reus-Smit, for exam-ple, argues that rules and norms are important because they “condition actors’ self-under-standings, references and behavior…” (Reus-Smit 2004: 3) Or as Friedrich Kratochwil put it, “Law is always more than simply an instrument of regulating present interfer-ences and the inevitable conflicts among self-interested actors; … it is one of the pri-mary means of making sense in individual and collective life” (Kratochwil 2009: 56) The reciprocity on which law depends for its existence – its very character as obligatory – “can only exist when actors collaborate to build shared understandings …” (Brunnée and Toope 2010: 7). Reciprocity in this view is deeper than a series of contracts for mutual

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3575769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 357 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS358

advantage. It is fundamental for the construc-tion of communities of mutual obligation.

In contrast to the more rationalist approaches, constructivists emphasize how rhetoric, deliberation, and persuasion influ-ence actors’ preferences. When actors debate the content, interpretation, and application of international law, they simultaneously engage in activities that potentially feed back into their understanding of their identities and therefore their preferences. Many scholars of international law insist that legal discourse is distinctive in this regard. Christian Reus-Smit claims, for example, that legal discourse differs from extra-legal discourse because it structures the discussion toward multilateral-ism, obligation, and legal justification (Reus-Smit 2004: 5). Legal discourse, relying as it does on rules, facts, precedents, and agree-ments, is a way to structure discussions that encourage actors to internalize broadly accepted principles rather than narrow con-ceptions of interest (Johnstone 2003). The central issue for constructivists is how actors come to accept certain rules and the interna-tional legal system itself as legitimate. For it is the legitimacy of these rules, and the extent to which they are widely viewed as “fair,” that helps to explain their importance in international affairs.

A broad range of scholarship has had an important presence in law schools, but has had a weaker influence in international rela-tions or political sciences departments, or in the social sciences more generally. Critical legal theory, for example, became a fairly well-developed school of thought in the 1970s, at about the time that regime theory was developing. Critical legal theory devel-oped from a radical left ideology, but in fact has much in common with realist theories of international relations (aside from the assumption of state centrism, which it does not particularly espouse). Along with real-ists, critical legal scholars generally viewed law in general and international law in par-ticular as indeterminate; its general provi-sions hardly dictated necessary outcomes, and there was a lot of room for manipulation.

Critical legal scholars generally agree with the realists that international law almost always operates to favor the powerful, wealthy, and dominant elites of any society.

The two branches of critical legal studies that are most relevant to international affairs include postcolonial studies and feminist theory (see the chapters by Zehfuss, and Sjoberg and Tickner, in this volume). Historical critical legal theory offers a strong critique of international law in the context of colonial and postcolonial studies. Marti Koskenniemi describes the role of interna-tional law – and, in particular, international lawyers – in legitimating the categories of “civilized” versus “uncivilized” while at the same time striving in an honorable if pater-nalistic fashion to protect the latter from the worst forms of exploitation by such private entrepreneurs as Cecil Rhodes (Koskenniemi 2002). More generally, critical legal scholars are concerned with “the management of the non-European world by international law and institutions” (Anghie 2005: 246). They insist that international law be analyzed not only from the point of view of its generators, but from the vantage point of the peoples who were in fact subject to it. Critical legal schol-ars such as David Kennedy come to the con-clusion that law in general and international law specifically rarely delivers on its hyped-up promises, for example, in the human rights arena (Kennedy 2004).

Feminist theories of international law echo the thrust of critical theory above, only the focus is on the public and the patrimonial nature of the international legal system, and hence its systematic silencing of issues of concern to women (Buss and Manji 2005). As in other areas of international relations, feminist theorists stress the disempowerment of women, in this case via “the role of the legal system in creating and perpetuating the unequal position of women” (Charlesworth et al. 1991: 613). In particular, the feminist critique is that public international law is just that – public – and is construed as relating to the male world of states rather than the “private” world of women’s issues

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3585769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 358 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 359

(Charlesworth et al. 1991: 627). Using human rights law as an example, feminists argue that the emphasis on such public acts as free speech and political participation, while important, hardly challenge the true rights abuses that women suffer daily in their private lives: a lack of reproductive auton-omy, battery, rape, and prostitution to name but a few (Stetson 1995).

While distinctive theoretical strands of international law scholarship can certainly be discerned in the literature, increasingly, empirical researchers are problem driven and use a combination of these theoretical insights to guide their inquiry. Much research attempts theoretical synthesis (see the chap-ter by Checkel in this volume) or at least displays declining respect for sharp theoreti-cal boundaries (Simmons 2009a). Long-standing theoretical traditions continue to inform research. But today’s realists are more likely to stress international law’s epi-phenomenality rather than its utter irrele-vance to international politics (Downs et al. 1996; Goldsmith and Posner 2005), and some acknowledge the possibility that inter-national law might influence state behavior – even in wartime – by theorizing and testing for its possible influence in their research (Valentino et al. 2006). The “irrelevance” of international law to international politics no longer has the status of a self-evident truth among realist theorists. Meanwhile, theorists of such processes as legalization and judi-cialization draw on both functionalist and constructivist insights in explaining thicken-ing international legal structures and institu-tions (Sandholtz and Stone Sweet 2004). Critical scholars are more explicitly norma-tively driven, but come to conclusions that would hardly surprise their conservative realist counterparts. One of the most gratify-ing aspects about the research on interna-tional law and international relations is that debates over meta-theoretical orientations have to some extent become muted in the interest of going after genuine puzzles (Simmons 2010), to which we turn in the following section.

CENTRAL PUZZLES: INTERNATIONAL LAW DEVELOPMENT

The “legalization” of international relations

International relations scholars seem to have (re)discovered not only that world politics are organized, but also quite legalized toward the end of the 1990s. The creation of the International Criminal Court, the appar-ently growing authority of the European Court of Justice, and the development of dispute settlement procedures within the WTO all seemed to signal that perhaps the post-Cold War years would indeed be a period of intense legalization of interna-tional affairs. At a minimum, these develop-ments drew scholars’ attention to the nature and extent of variation in regarding legal arrangements.

To explain patterns of legalization, Kenneth Abbot and his co-authors have pro-posed a multidimensional continuum rang-ing from an ideal-typical “highly legalized” setting to a weakly legalized, or even non-legalized, one. They distinguish three “ele-ments” of legalization: obligation, by which they meant the extent to which “state or other actors are [legally] bound by a rule or commitment”; precision, or the extent to which “rules unambiguously define the con-duct they require”; and delegation, or the extent to which third parties have been “granted authority to implement, interpret, and apply the rules; to resolve disputes, and (possibly) to make further rules” (Abbott et. al., 2000: 401).

Many scholars have used this framework to understand the varying density of legaliza-tion across time and space. Drawing on func-tionalist logic, Kenneth Abbot and Duncan Snidal argued that “international actors choose to order their relations through inter-national law and to design treaties and other legal arrangements to solve specific substan-tive and political problems” (Abbott and Snidal 2000: 421). They hypothesized that hard law was especially useful (and therefore

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3595769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 359 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS360

predicted) when actors wanted to make strong credible commitments, where the actors faced high transaction costs, and when they anticipate problems arising from incomplete contracting. On the other hand, soft law arrangements were rationally preferred, Abbott and Snidal surmised, when it would be politically costly to get states to agree, and when actors were uncertain about the conse-quences of an agreement in the future. While Abbot and Snidal claimed their approach “combines the rational incentives associated with ‘contracts’ and the normative considera-tions associated with ‘covenants’” (Abbott and Snidal 2000: 455), their explication clearly has its theoretical heavy foot in the rational world of contracting.

The framework on which the legalization project is based resonates with a number of rationalistic studies about the nature and especially the form of international legal agreements. The obverse of obligation is flexibility, and a number of studies have sought to use a rationalist framework to explain why it is that governments enter into binding agreements, only to design them with huge loopholes through which they can escape their obligations? Barbara Koremenos notes that such an apparent contradiction reflects states’ efforts to cope with uncer-tainty, which is rife in international coopera-tion problems (Koremenos 2005). States cannot predict the effects that various random shocks will have on the distribution of bene-fits from a particular agreement. The larger the variance in these shocks, more likely states are to include renegotiation clauses (though, curiously, not escape clauses) in international agreements (Koremenos 2005). The extent and conditions of legal obliga-tions are also influenced by uncertainty in Milner and Rosendorf’s model of interna-tional trade agreements. In their case, the uncertainty arises from domestic reactions to trade conditions; the less sure governments can be about how a trade agreement will affect domestic political demands, the more likely they are to assent to optimal escape clauses (Rosendorff and Milner 2001).

Lawrence Helfer and his co-authors develop a similar argument about uncertainty to explain derogations in international human rights treaties, which they argue are a response to domestic political uncertainty, enabling governments facing serious domestic threats to buy time to confront crises while signaling to various external or domestic audiences “that rights deviations are temporary and lawful” (Helfer et al. 2011). Alexander Thompson finds good support for the propo-sition that uncertainty helps to explain flexi-bility in the international law relating to climate change (Thompson 2010). In short, uncertainty has been a key explanation for variance along at least one of Abbott et. al.’s (2000) three dimensions of legalization: the extent and nature of legal obligation.

There are some trends in world politics that the functionalist vision advanced by the legalization project has a hard time explain-ing. One is the spatial variation in the phe-nomenon: why so much legalization in Europe but not in East Asia, for example? Miles Kahler tries to grapple with this in his discussion, but ultimately accepts that the Association of Southeast Asian Nations’ (ASEAN’s) fairly recent acceptance of cer-tain processes such as third party adjudica-tion of territorial disputes supports “demand driven” or possibly “strategic” explanations for Asia (Kahler 2000). Another puzzle, from this perspective, is the growth of the interna-tional law in the area of human rights. While in some loose sense “demand driven,” it is certainly hard to understand why rational self-interested states would find it in their interest to create binding international agree-ments to treat their own citizens with respect. Beth Simmons argues that it might have been more “functional,” from the point of view of state demand, to contract to maintain mutual silence in this issue-area (Simmons 2009a). And yet the legal regime for international human rights has increased and hardened substantially over the course of the past five decades.

The approach forwarded by the Legalization Project drew fairly immediate fire. The idea

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3605769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 360 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 361

of studying legalization struck legal scholars as a peculiar self-created puzzle that “it pre-supposes that a legal void is coming to be filled, without properly questioning whether that void existed to begin with” (Klabbers 2009: 8). Moreover, its narrow rationalist, formalist, and liberal approach drew criti-cism from constructivists in both law and the social sciences. Most irksome was the project’s effort to single out three dimensions of legalization, an exercise that seemed arbi-trary and not well justified to critics. Martha Finnemore and Stephen Toope argued that legalization was not in any sense dependent on precision or delegation, and pointed to entire areas of law governed by vague princi-ples of “equity” and whole international legal regimes such as human rights that involve very little delegation at all (Finnemore and Toope 2001: 747–8). What the project really missed, according to these scholars, was a good grip on obligation as a subjective sensa-tion. For these critics, the focus on formal agreements unnecessarily bureaucratized the notion of law and stripped it of its central claim on human action: acceptance of its legitimacy.

Judicialization and delegation

If explaining legalization proved to be a bite too big to chew, it has been somewhat more tractable to explain a related phenomenon: international judicialization. One of the most conspicuous developments in international law in the past few decades has been the emergence of authoritative third party bodies to help to settle international legal disputes among states, and sometimes between states and individuals (Alter 2011: Romano 1999: Spelliscy 2001). Examples of new interna-tional judicial institutions include those with a functional remit, such at the International Tribunal for the Law of the Sea and those with little more than a “quasi-judicial” (non-litigious, nonbinding) character, such as the recently acquired powers of the Committee on Economic Social and Cultural Rights to

hear and render views on complaints of individuals alleging noncompliance by their governments with their treaty obligations. It is always possible to dismiss these devel-opments as window dressings, but that raises its own puzzles: Why bother creating interna-tional tribunals? And why take the risk of an adverse decision and bad publicity, should one rule against you?

The judicialization of international politics has been explained in several different ways. One theme is to note that domestic politics are increasingly judicialized (Tate and Vallinder 1995), and we should therefore not be surprised to see these domestic forms of politics spreading to the international system. Some scholars attribute this global judiciali-zation to economic liberalization, which introduces new actors, increases demands for transparency, and extends the market for legal services globally (Kelemen and Sibbitt 2004; but for a critique, see Levi-Faur 2005).

Judicialization is central to the develop-ment of governance institutions more gener-ally. Alec Stone Sweet has developed a theory that links judicialization to the inter-ests of pairs of state actors, but his account links the process of deciding specific cases to the development of international norms. Blending elements of rationalist theorizing with constructivist ideational elements, he views judicialization as an essential aspect of normative development and change. Conflicts develop out of dyadic state interactions, and states have a strong interest in developing rules for the settlement of these disputes. Judicialization involves two disputants and a “resolver” whose narrow purpose it is to settle the dispute at hand, but whose broader social purpose includes the reproduction and reinforcing of broader norms of rule interpre-tation and behavior. At root, this is a func-tionalist account: the dyadic form “generates a massive functional demand for dispute resolution in the form of rule interpretation” (Stone Sweet 1999: 154). As in most tradi-tional functionalist accounts, states turn to third parties because they want to continue to enjoy the benefits of contracting with other

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3615769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 361 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS362

states. Stone Sweet relies on “identity” argu-ments to make this point: the parties have to understand their interests as being served by pursuing a common interest, and not as exclusively competitive with other states. “Resolvers” in turn are characterized as stra-tegic: they try to choose solutions to disputes within the “overlapping bargaining space” of the disputants. (Stone Sweet 1999: 156). In the process, however, the “resolver” responds to and generates social change.

Rational functionalist logic does seem to dominate the empirical research explaining the turn to third party dispute settlement. In some accounts, the logic of turning to an authoritative third party flows from domestic politics. For example, Christina Davis finds that democratic governments turn to third party dispute settlement at the WTO when executives face relatively protectionist legis-latures. Under these circumstances, using the dispute settlement panels of the WTO allows a leader to appear to be “doing something” to stand up to protectionism without responding with protectionist measures of their own (Davis 2012). Beth Simmons makes a similar argument about domestic dysfunctionality to explain the resort to third party arbitration to settle territorial disputes (Simmons 2002). While they deal with completely different issues, these studies share a logic that sees the turn to international dispute settlement as a strategy states adopt to circumvent the problems associated with divisive politics at home.

Others locate the impulse to delegate not in internal politics, but to external bargaining pressures. The trend in the international law of investment is an interesting example of judicialization as the results of hard-nosed bargaining: capital exporting companies are lobbied by international firms to demand international arbitration clauses in their investment agreements, and tend to get more stringent delegation from capital-importing countries in weak negotiating positions (Allee and Peinhardt 2010; Simmons 2011).

The example of investor protection draws attention to the fact that there are varieties of

judicialization, with varying consequences for law development and law compliance. Keohane and his co-authors were careful to distinguish between two ideal types of “judi-cialization” (Keohane et al. 2000): on the one hand, transnational adjudication is much more independent from the interests of the disputing parties, and tends to be relatively easy for individuals and other actors to access. On the other hand, state-to-state dis-pute resolution bodies tend to be character-ized by a low degree of independence from the disputants, and are harder for nonstate actors to access whether as parties or “friends of the court.”

Scholars disagree about the extent to which international courts can effectively act inde-pendently from states. International legal scholars have advanced impressionistic notions, largely drawn from the European experience, to claim that independent tribu-nals are quite likely to be effective in settling disputes among states (Helfer and Slaughter 1997). However, legal realists Eric Posner and John Yoo contend that “independent tri-bunals pose a danger to international coop-eration because they can render decisions that conflict with the interests of state parties. Indeed, states will be reluctant to use interna-tional tribunals unless they have control over the judges. On our view, independence pre-vents international tribunals from being effective” (Posner and Yoo 2005: 7). Posner and Yoo argue that there is a narrow set of circumstances in which states find “inde-pendent” tribunals useful: when the tribunal can provide neutral, credible information about the law or about some set of facts that would be difficult otherwise to obtain. Only when states want to settle a legal problem, and have an interest in such information, do Posner and Yoo acknowledge that interna-tional courts are likely to play a useful dis-pute settlement role.

The empirical work to support these claims of the effectiveness of international judicial institutions has been relatively unsystematic. For one thing, not nearly enough care has been given to conceptualizing and measuring

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3625769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 362 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 363

“effectiveness” in this context. Posner and Yoo advance three “highly imperfect” meas-ures: “compliance,” “usage,” and “overall effectiveness” to try to establish that inde-pendent courts are no more effective than ones that are more controlled by states (Posner and Yoo 2005: 28–9). We will have more to say on compliance below, but note here that there is a growing literature on compliance with the decisions of interna-tional arbitral and/or adjudicative bodies (Paulson 2004). But because of the serious problem of designing research that takes good account of the processes whereby states choose judicial dispute settlement (these processes vary, but all involve some form of consent), it is hard to draw strong inferences about the impact of international tribunals on dispute settlement. There seems to be a growing recognition that international courts cannot be completely independent from states; if judges are concerned that their deci-sions be implemented, they must to some extent anticipate how the executives and leg-islatures in the countries concerned will implement their decisions (Carrubba et al. 2008; Busch and Pelc 2010).

Debates about the nature of international courts and their relationship with states have spawned research into judicial behavior at the international level. Much of this literature is clearly inspired by the domestic literature on courts and judicial behavior. The general finding that international judges – no less than domestic judges – can behave strategi-cally has opened up research into how inter-national judges are appointed and whether they can be considered mere puppets of state actors. Consistent with their realist perspec-tive, Posner and de Figueredo run regressions that suggest judges of the International Court of Justice favor the states that appoint them, as well as states at or near their own develop-mental level (Posner and de Figueiredo 2005). But it is hard to know whether this constitutes “bias” since there is no clear yardstick for a “fair” decision. Erik Voeten comes to a completely different conclusion about international judicial behavior when it

comes to cases decided by the European Court of Human Rights. In that context, he found fairly convincing evidence that judges did indeed have policy preferences over rights (and, in fact, judges from previously socialist governments were more likely to rule against their governments than in their favor) but that judges do not use the tribunal to make larger, geopolitically relevant points (Voeten 2008). Voeten also finds that govern-ments choose judges for the ECtHR that reflect their preferences for EU expansion (Voeten 2007), but this is not to say that these judges rule in a nationalistic way or are beholden to their appointers.

Global constitutionalism and Global Administrative Law – Solutions to Global Governance?

Globalization and its consequences have had a tremendous impact on the way that scholars are thinking about international law. Several concerns arise: the international legal system is growing increasingly complex, with law and jurisprudence developing at various levels of governance (global, regional, national) and across distinct issues areas (trade, human rights, the environment). International law is traditionally state-centric, yet modern problems raise issues of how to regulate the activities of nonstate actors. International law has traditionally not been especially transparent; that is, diplomatic traditions have influenced its development, and participation by stakeholders has hardly been a traditional core concern. Several research programs have developed – prima-rily in legal academies – in the past decade to address some of these issues. I discuss them in this section under the headings of constitu-tionalization, global administrative law, and private governance.

Regional experience with supranational law has led to some significant differences between Europeans and the rest of the world with respect to the possibilities of a more coherent and consistent international legal

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3635769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 363 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS364

system (Weiler and Wind 2003). While American scholars are quick to note the limits of international law and Asian voices are scarcely heard in the IL/IR literature, Europeans have begun to theorize and to assess the extent to which “… international law is increasingly starting to look like the sort of legal order we are familiar with from our domestic legal systems” (Klabbers 2009: 11). As law has become more fragmented across legally defined issue areas, is it pos-sible to articulate a more coherent set of principles for ordering the international legal system? A constitutional order is one that spells out relationships of authority among political institutions, how those institutions are to be controlled, and the fundamental rights of individuals vis-à-vis those public authorities. Moreover, “Constitutionalism promises to settle the score once and for all, by giving either jus cogens priority, or trade, or human rights, or erga omnes principles” (Klabbers 2009: 18).

Two branches of literature have developed: a normative literature that analyzes the prob-lems of a fragmented international order, and an empirical literature that – much like the legalization literature discussed above – that tries to assess the extent to which a constitu-tional order is developing or, in fact, already exists (Klabbers 2009: 4). International rela-tions scholar have noted what might be called “constitutional bargains” associated with the end of great wars (1815, 1914, and 1945) after which great powers design inter-national institutions in their own interests, locking other states into these structures, and yet creating stability in a “hegemonic” fash-ion by institutionalizing rules of the game (Ikenberry 2001). Legal scholars claim that constitutionalism has recently been on the rise around the world (Ackerman 1997). Joseph Weiler argues that this is a response to globalization, the erosion of state sover-eignty, and the attendant need to regulate the activities of nonstate actors – all of which seem to have put the credibility of the inter-national legal system under some stress (Weller 2009).

Where do scholars look for evidence of a waxing global constitution? The United Nations Charter is the usual candidate, by virtue of its attention to broader governance issues, to defining community membership, and to setting up a hierarchy of values (Fassbender 1998). The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (UDHR), sometimes in conjunction with the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights and the International Covenant on Economic, Social and Cultural Rights, is sometimes said to resemble and indeed to function as an “International Bill of Rights” (Gardbaum 2008). As the Security Council has taken actions in the name of peace and security that impinge on the rights of individuals (the maintenance of individuals on terrorist black-lists, for example), some scholars believe it has become urgent to think through the prin-ciples that govern the relationship between international authority and individual rights. Moreover, there is the question of the proper relationship between international legal authority and regional legal authority. The European Court of First Instance’s 2005 decision3 that the EU is bound by interna-tional law as decided by the Security Council certainly does pose “constitutional” ques-tions of the highest order.

Others point to governance within issue-specific functional areas as evidence that international law is becoming more “consti-tutional” in nature. Deborah Cass argues that the decisions of the appellate body of the WTO, for example, reflect growing attention to what one might term constitu-tional principles: concerns about democracy and governance, constitutional design, fair-ness, and allocation of policy responsibility (Cass 2005). Others disagree, and indeed are puzzled by debates of “the WTO’s (non-existent) constitutional features” and believe the debate over constitutionalism reflects anxieties about the status of international law rather than its real characteristics (Dunoff 2006).

The desirability of a constitutional moment for international law is hardly universally

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3645769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 364 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 365

embraced, of course. If something as foun-dational as an international constitution is developing, this raises serious concerns for the way in which a robust international con-stitutional structure is adopted. One critique focuses on the contribution that a global constitution in principle makes to the demo-cratic deficit posed by international law more generally. Indeed, Buchanan and Powell warn against the process of interna-tional law’s slow accretion of constitutional status, charging that “public constitutional deliberation and popular choice has been conspicuously absent” from the process (Buchanan and Powell 2008: 346). Democratic theorists chafe at the easy assumption that self-governance at the local level can be preserved without a significant if not Herculean effort at “contextualization, interpretation, and vernacularization by self-governing peoples” (Benhabib 2009). Perhaps it is best modestly to conclude, as does Andrew Hurrell, that if the international legal system is indeed constitutionalizing, it will at most evolve toward a “common law constitution” – one that is likely to be identi-fied over time rather than ratified in toto (Hurrell 2007).

On a more quotidian level, globalization has led to some very practical problems that demand the attention of scholars. The rapid growth of international and transnational regulatory regimes with administrative com-ponents and functions governing activities – from banking and finance (Büthe and Mattli 2011) to labor standards (Macdonald and Macdonald 2006) to the investment decisions of the World Bank (Fourie 2009) – has cre-ated an accountability deficit in the growing exercise of transnational regulatory power. One response has been an effort to document and theorize the development of “global administrative law … comprising the mecha-nisms, principles, practices, and supporting social understandings that promote or other-wise affect the accountability of global administrative bodies, in particular by ensur-ing they meet adequate standards of transpar-ency, participation, reasoned decision, and

legality, and by providing effective review of the rules and decisions they make” (Kingsbury et al. 2005: 17). By concentrating on what they view as the more technical administra-tive side of governance, this approach hopes to downplay the role for grand (and contro-versial) global values, and concentrates on how international institutions make the deci-sions they do (Klabbers 2009: 28). The study of global administrative law is related to concerns among normative social scientists about the extent to which international law is compatible with acceptable levels and modes of accountability generally (Buchanan and Powell 2008).

COMPLIANCE WITH INTERNATIONAL LEGAL AGREEMENTS

One of the greatest growth sectors in the study of international law and international relations in the past decade has been on the questions of compliance and effectiveness. Dogged by the realist challenge to show that international law and institutions matter to outcomes we may care about (Mearsheimer 1994–95), and the growing recognition even among international legal scholars that there are limits to international law’s influence on state behavior (Goldsmith and Posner 2005), scholars have devoted tremendous attention to designing research that can address the question of whether interna-tional agreements facilitate anything more than shallow cooperation; that is, do they influence states to behave in ways or to take policies that they might otherwise not have done, were it not for the existence of an international legal norm (Downs et al. 1996)? And does it matter whether a given state has explicitly subscribed to these norms through ratification?

In parallel with the discussion of theories of international law above, it is possible to distinguish two general clusters of theories of law compliance: theories of material pres-sures, and theories that depend primarily

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3655769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 365 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS366

on ideas, identity arguments, and persuasion. It may be also useful to distinguish theories that locate the primary source of compliance pressure at the interstate, transnational, and local levels. It is essential to reiterate, how-ever, that few actual accounts of compliance are clean examples of one causal mechanism. Most draw on both material pressures as well as nonmaterial influences. Many span more than one level of causal analysis. Moreover, almost all recognize different compliance mechanisms have varying relevance across a variety of issue areas.

Material “enforcement”: from international coercion to domestic constraints

Perhaps the most common theory of compli-ance with international law is most closely aligned with realist thinking: compliance depends on the willingness of states to enforce agreements, using material pres-sures if necessary. This is the case especially if the issue-area at stake is one regarding which governments are likely to renege on (arms control, prohibitions on the use of torture, trade liberalization). In the absence of material pressures to comply, we are only likely to see compliance based on a coinci-dence of interests (Goldsmith and Posner 2005) or very shallow compliance at best (Downs et al. 1996). Examples of state-to-state efforts to use material pressures to enforce international law include the use of authorized retaliation by the dispute settle-ment panels of the WTO, the linkage of trade to legal human rights practices , and enforcement actions authorized (or not) by the United Nations Security Council. The basic theory is simple: unless states face significant costs, they will violate the law if it is in their interest to do so. The approach predicts better compliance rates, other things being equal, where states face a credible threat of material punishment for their trans-gressions by their peers or international organizations.

Surprisingly few studies of international law compliance rely exclusively on state-to-state coercion to explain international law compliance. In the nineteenth century, Krasner characterizes the enforcement of international law as episodic and based on various forms of retaliation. He argues, for example, that toleration of religious minori-ties primarily resulted from a concern about retaliation against one’s own nationals and not out of respect for treaties protecting their rights (Krasner 1999: 82). Studies of the laws of war have found that international norms that are not enforced – for example, norms proscribing the intentional killing of civil-ians – are likely to be sacrificed to military exigencies, an outcome not affected by inter-national law. Valentino et al. found that the intentional killing of civilians was correlated with the strategy chosen to prosecute the war, but not influenced at all by ratification of the relevant treaty for the time period under question. (Valentino et al. 2006). Realists have long asserted that “most human rights practices are explained by coercion or coinci-dence of interest” (Goldsmith and Posner 2005: 262); consequently, early quantitative studies of human rights agreements that found little improvement in rights practices upon their ratification assumed that this was because they were unlikely to be enforced (Hathaway 2002). Emelie Hafner-Burton infers state-to-state enforcement is important for compliance with international human rights norms from an observed correlation between trade agreements with stringent human rights provisions and rights improve-ments (Hafner-Burton 2005), although the nature of these agreements is likely highly endogenous to rights programs in the “target” country in the first place. One tantalizing possibility is that states use multilateral forums to manipulate sanctions to enforce international law. James Lebovic and Erik Voeten for example have shown that resolu-tions of the Human Rights Commission are linked with reductions in aid from the World Bank (Lebovic and Voeten 2009). State-to-state enforcement is certainly an important

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3665769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 366 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 367

part of trade law under the WTO dispute set-tlement panels, and while the decisions of these panels enjoy extremely high rates of compliance, these rates are not plausible linked to material coercion. There seems to be no clear relationship between the magni-tude of retaliation and the likelihood of compliance with a WTO panel.

One twist on coercion models assumes that states want to expose themselves to external enforcement. The assumption of credible commitment theory is that many states are unable to enjoy the “joint gains” implied by international agreements pre-cisely because their potential partners do not know if they will carry them out. Incentives to misrepresent true intentions aggravate the contracting problem. Almost all theories of credible commitments rest on the assumption of time-inconsistent preferences: it may be rational in time t to promise to behave according to an agreement, but in time t+1 it is likely that one or both parties will face incentives to renege on the agreement. One way to reduce these incentives is to increase costs a government will face if it reneges on an agreement. By tying their hands, govern-ments may be able to conclude profitable contracts that would have been difficult to conclude in the absence of high ex post violation costs. Enforcement in such models is a desirable feature of agreements that facilitate the realization of joint gains. Several scholars have argued that agreements that contain monitoring, arbitration, prosecution, or dispute settlement mechanisms are efforts to make commitments more credible by ram-ping up ex post costs. Examples include peace agreements that create international “audience costs” (Fortna 2003) the International Criminal Court (Simmons and Danner 2010), bilateral investment treaties (Elkins et al. 2006), territorial agreements with provisions that tend to tie the parties’ hands by raising ex post costs (Mattes 2008), and the more institutionalized provisions of some alliance pacts (Long et al. 2007).

Overall, the coercion hypothesis domi-nates the international relations literature

largely by default. Theories that posit that international law is weak because it is not enforced are likely to assume the converse: material coercion increases compliance. The indeterminacy of the decades-long debate about the effectiveness of sanctions – even in the unlikely event that states decide to bear the burden of imposing them (Hovi et al. 2005) – should cast some doubt on the easy assumption that international material coer-cion alone increases compliance with inter-national law. Scholars and observers, of course, have long recognized that with few exceptions enforcement – from military action to economic sanctions to diplomatic hardball – itself is costly. If we want to think of adherence to international law as an “international public good,” then no one actor is likely to want to bear the burden, and, as realists and others have noted, interstate enforcement of all kinds is likely to be under-supplied. Indeed, the observation that states rarely use available enforcement mechanisms to enforce international legal norms (Chayes and Chayes 1995) – even in such important areas as arms control – has led to a search for other plausible explanations for compliance with international norms.

The dominant rationalist rival to the com-pliance-by-coercion theory is the theory of self-enforcing agreement. Most international norms are not, in fact, enforced though the pressure of third parties or the explicit sanc-tions of a treaty partner. Rather, they are enforced simply by the threat of withdrawing from the agreement itself, and the risk of losing or reducing the future flow of benefits, not by third party sanctions. Reciprocity and reputation are the key enforcement mecha-nisms. Robert Keohane’s early theories of compliance with international regimes fol-lowed this logic (Keohane 1984). Since “enforcement” depends largely on reciprocity, this framework is useful for explaining stable trade agreements (Goldstein et al. 2007), some aspects of the laws of war, where mili-taries risk retaliation in kind (Morrow 2007), and obligations whose violation might pro-voke negative market reactions, as is plausible

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3675769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 367 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS368

in the area of monetary affairs and investment (Simmons 2000).

Theories of self-enforcing agreements and especially those based on reciprocity and the value of a reputation for compliance for pur-poses of contracting have inspired a rich empirical literature, much of it in the area of war fighting and security. James Morrow’s study of eight different subissue areas, includ-ing aerial bombardment, armistice/ceasefire, chemical and biological weapons, treatment of civilians, protection of cultural property, conduct on the high seas, treatment of pris-oners of war, and treatment of the wounded suggests that reciprocity is key to establish-ing stable compliance with international norms on war-fighting, and that treaties play a special role in facilitating this reciprocity (Morrow 2007). He argues that treaties clar-ify what is, and what is not acceptable behav-ior, which allows adversaries in war more precisely to respond to violations in kind. Alliance commitments may have self-enforc-ing features as well, that work largely through reputational mechanisms. Douglas Gibler produces evidence that governments (note: not “states”) that abrogate their alliances are less likely to be able to negotiate alliance relationships for the rest of their terms, making it harder to deter potential aggressors (Gibler 2008). Alliance treaties tend to be “self-enforcing agreements” in that the ex post consequences of abrogation entail very real risks to national security into the future. Consistent with this view, Leeds and Savun found that states do not abrogate alliance agreements lightly, but typically when they experience a drastic change in circumstances from those prevailing when the treaty was ratified (Leeds and Savun 2007).

The self-enforcing nature of much interna-tional law is perhaps best illustrated by com-mercial norms and agreements. In the area of trade, the role of reciprocity is thought to be so strong that there is no realistic option to compliance; no state would want to risk withdrawal from the network of liberalizing treaties that (presumably) have done so much to further market integration in goods and

services over the past several decades. Indeed, although recent experience demonstrates that multilateral trade agreements are difficult to reach, compliance tends to be high. Judith Goldstein and her co-authors have shown that there has been “enough” compliance with the various treaty obligations to make a marked positive impact on bilateral trade (Goldstein et al. 2007). Moreover, there seems to be a good deal of consensus that while some 90 of all adopted decisions of WTO involve a finding of a violation, in practically every case the violator complies with the decision of the panel (Wilson 2007). Why such a high compliance rate, especially given that many of these cases that escalate to a formal panel decision are politically “hard” cases to solve (Guzman and Simmons 2002; Davis 2012)? Daniel Kono’s study of how trade dispute settlement mechanisms facilitate reciprocity provides a potential answer (Kono 2007). He argues that defiance of WTO decisions inflicts too heavy a repu-tational toll. It is not the threat of retaliation as much as a loss of potentially rich contract-ing arrangements that inspires states to comply with their trade agreements.

Most international norms and agreements do not, of course, have strong external enforcement mechanisms. Some interna-tional legal norms, such as human rights, do not even involve international reciprocity in any clear way (Simmons 2009). Increasingly, research on compliance reflects the possibil-ity that some of these norms are enforced primarily through domestic rather than through international mechanisms. A grow-ing research stream now focuses on the domestic “audience costs” associated with noncompliance with international law. The notion that international legal commitments engage domestic audiences has reoriented some of the theoretical literature toward domestic and comparative politics. Xinyuan Dai theorizes that “toothless” international institutions’ legal agreements sometimes inform electorates that governments are pur-suing policies they do not perceive to be in their interest. Dai theorizes that compliance

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3685769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 368 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 369

with international agreements is enhanced through new information, generated by treaty bodies and monitoring systems, that inform and empower domestic voters to punish governments for actions of which they disapprove (Dai 2007). When a potential pro-compliance constituency is large (which is not always the case, even in democratic poli-ties), and when an international agreement sheds significant new information on the government’s record of compliance, a gov-ernment will have strong electoral reasons not to violate international agreements. Dai’s theory sheds light on why it is that liberal democracies are often better treaty compli-ers: they are populated by large numbers and dense networks of citizens with extensive interests in predictable and harmonious tran-snational relationships (Gaubatz 1996; Slaughter 1995) who are in a position to “punish” their governments electorally. But to the extent that the electoral “enforcement” mechanism is blunted or anticompliance groups dominate electoral politics, the pres-sure on states to comply will diminish.

Finally, nonstate national and transnational organizations can play a role in “enforcing” international law by virtue of their ability to manipulate the material incentives of decision makers. Elizabeth Desombre’s study of com-pliance with international environmental and labor laws in the international shipping indus-try stresses the exclusion of corporations from certain “club goods” such as port access (DeSombre 2006). She notes that despite the economic pressure to cut corners and violate agreements, the ability of port states, interna-tional labor unions, intergovernmental fishery organizations, and high-standard industry actors to exclude violators associated with particular flags of convenience has helped to nudge some of the worst polluters toward at least partial compliance. Since environmental protection is a regulatory policy that involves a broad array of nongovernmental actors, it is not surprising that models stressing the civil society and interest aggregation abound. Patrick Bernhagen proposes a model in which business organization, structural strength, and

information asymmetries predict low com-pliance with multilateral environmental agreements (MEAs) in general, and the 1992 UN Framework Convention on Climate Change in particular (Bernhagen 2008). In several studies, nongovernmental organiza-tions have been shown to be important to compliance outcomes, via lobbying and monitoring functions (Bernhagen 2008; see also Gulbrandsen and Andresen 2004). One key to compliance in the environmental area has been to understand the incentives of public and private actors, and the ways in which they interact.

Ideational Approaches: Legitimacy, Identity, Persuasion, and Socialization

A second class of mechanisms offered for explaining compliance with international law rests on its legitimacy as a social institution. Legal scholars emphasize the elevated status of legal commitments, which raise the repu-tational stakes associated with noncompli-ance (Guzman 2002; see also Schachter 1991). This special quality of international legal obligations may be due to the fact that they are embedded in a broader system of socially constructed interstate rule-making, normatively linked by the principle of pacta sunt servanda – the idea that agreements of a legally obligatory nature must be observed. Customary international law seems to carry a strong presumption of legitimacy; after all, one criterion for identifying custom in the first place is the criterion of opinion juris - the widespread sense that complying with a particular rule is “obligatory.”

While enforcement theories typically assume the pursuit of material interests or office seeking (as posited by the analyst), constructivists tend to view law as more than a way to improve payoffs; it embodies norms which reflect the social meanings and pur-poses of the relevant community. Rules and norms are important because they “condition actors’ self-understandings, references, and

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3695769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 369 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS370

behavior ...” (Reus-Smit 2004).. As such, they become a key focal point for discursive struggles over legitimate political agency and action and critical resources in the interna-tional politics of legitimacy. International law has a special place in the array of social norms, some constructivists argue, because it shapes the justificatory politics that ultimate inform official actions.

Some empirical work is beginning to test arguments about the power of perceived legitimacy of international legal obligations to explain state policies and behavior. Judith Kelley’s empirical work stresses the princi-pled commitment of states to comply with their legal obligations associated with the International Criminal Court, and finds an impressive rate of compliance with those obligations, despite very material pressure by the George W. Bush administration not to cooperate with the ICC (Kelley 2007). She argues that a strong commitment to the rule of law highly conditions any general claims about the overall “compliance pull” of trea-ties generally. Consistent with normative theories of behavior, the “tug” is strongest for those polities that place the highest value on the rule of law.

The notion that international law may have more legitimacy than other kinds of commit-ments has been recently subjected to empiri-cal investigation at the individual level of analysis as well. Michael Tomz has recently used survey evidence to test the proposition that there are more significant “audience costs” (reputational repercussions) associ-ated with law violation than with an other-wise similar behavior that does not violate international law (Tomz 2008). Just what gives rise to any potential audience costs is unclear, but one prime candidate is the legiti-macy of a legal obligation: a sense on the part of survey respondents that international legal commitments are somehow more compelling that run-of-the-mill policy pronouncements.

The legitimacy of international legal norms is also reflected in some studies of compli-ance with international judicial and quasi-judicial bodies. Arguably, compliance with a

legal decision of an authoritative body has a different social meaning than compliance with the demands of an adversary. (Simmons 2002; Allee and Huth 2006). Sara Mitchell and Paul Hensel use a selection model to demonstrate empirically that governments are more likely to comply with the decisions of an authoritative third party than they are with an agreement reached on their own (Mitchell and Hensel 2007). These findings illuminate how the legal context potentially shapes the meaning of actions: deferring to legal authority signals a law- abiding charac-ter, while deferring to an adversary signals nothing but weakness. This is a powerful demonstration of the need to marry rational accounts with subjective understandings of behavior.

If discourse and ideas inform politics, then law compliance is explicable in terms of what actors come to believe and value. Compliance with rules can be enhanced through efforts at socialization, or what Kathryn Sikkink and Thomas Risse define as the process by which principled ideas become broadly accepted norms. Once they are inter-nalized, these norms can lead to changes in interests, values, and even identities, which in turn ultimately shape state behavior (Risse et al. 1999).

Compliance is enhanced in this view when actors become socialized to comply. Socialization can mean three kinds of proc-esses in this literature. In a crude sense, actors (state elites) can be “socialized” through a system of rewards and punishments (Schimmelfennig 2005). This form of social-ization shades into incentive-based induce-ments discussed above. More subtly, actors can be encouraged through various cues indicative of social acceptance or approba-tion to bring their practices in line with inter-national standards. Ryan Goodman and Derek Jinks refer to this as a process of accultura-tion by which they mean the “general process by which actors adopt the beliefs and behav-ioral patterns of the surrounding culture” (Goodman and Jinks 2004). Acculturation involves “social costs” associated with

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3705769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 370 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 371

shaming or shunning as distinct from the more material costs associated with overt coercion. These pressures may lead to super-ficial compliance with international norms as reflected in treaty obligations, not necessarily the internationalization of norms as deeply held values (Strang and Chang 1993). Institutional sociologists touted the (nonmate-rial) power of “world society” to generate and diffuse norms of behavior that mimic accepted scripts of modernity – encouraging countries on the periphery to display outward forms in conformity with the institutions and forms of leading states of the Western world – without internalizing the values behind these forms (Cole 2005; Wotipka and Ramirez 2008; Hafner-Burton and Tsutsui 2005).

Acculturation can be contrasted with a more fundamental form of socialization, often referred to in the literature as normative persuasion. Persuasion depends on the power of argumentation and deliberation as distinct modes of social interaction which when suc-cessful changes what an actor values and sometimes even his or her very identity (Risse 2000; Johnston 2001). Jeffrey Checkel defines persuasion as “a social process of interaction that involves changing attitudes about cause and effect in the absence of overt coercion” (Checkel 2001). He argues that persuasion is more likely to play an impor-tant role in explaining compliance behavior when elites do not have deeply held priors, and they are therefore open to new ways of thinking about issues.

Whether because of their persuasive func-tion or their information-providing function (or both), constructivists often agree with rational theorist that pressures applied by (often transnational) civil society tend to pressure or persuade governments to comply with international legal standards and obliga-tion. Sally Merry’s transnational ethnography of the role of transnational actors provides a rich description of how the process of persua-sion and communication operates transna-tionally (Merry 2006). Transnational human rights ideas become part of local social movements and local legal consciousness

through the work of individuals who have one authentic foot in the local culture and the other in the transnational world of United Nations conferences, meetings and work-shops. These individuals play a crucial role Merry’s felicitous phrase in “translating global principles into the local vernacular” (Merry 2006). This is a two-way form of communication, often supporting new ideas and identities at the local levels but also educating the global community about the local realities on the ground.

Capacity ConstraintsSometimes neither incentives nor ideas are the primary determinant. Brief mention should be made of the very real capacity constraints that many governments face when they try to comply with their international legal obligations. Vast swathes of interna-tional law, of course, do not typically encoun-ter capacity constraints: nearly all of customary international law requires states to recognize principles (the 12 mile territorial limit from one’s coastline) or to refrain from particular actions (genocide), but by its nature makes no demands that large numbers of states have the capacity to respect. Much treaty law (the “first generation” of human rights that limit government interference with free expression spelled out in the International Covenant on Civil and Politic Rights; the requirement established under the auspices of the WTO to reduce import quotas) is of the same quality. Where international law calls for governments to refrain from particular policies, their capacity to comply is usually not at stake.

International law appears to have become increasingly demanding over time – in terms of the bureaucratic capabilities, technical sophistication, and resource base needed to comply. Compliance with international envi-ronmental requirements is a clear example. Accordingly, early studies emphasized a lack of capacity as one of the most serious barriers for compliance with international environ-mental accords (Weiss and Jacobson 1998). Capacity constraints have also been important

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3715769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 371 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS372

compliance hurdles in the provision of positive rights such as basic health care for children, as required by the Convention on the Rights of the Child (Simmons 2009: ch. 8). European law has long stressed the capacities of some states to “keep up” with their obligations. In a study of 6,300 viola-tions of European law, Tanja Börzel and her colleagues have found that bureaucratic inef-ficiency helps to account for much of the variance in compliance (Börzel et al. 2010). As international law becomes more demand-ing of state bureaucracies and resources – for example, as norms shift from nonintervention in the affairs of other states to a “responsibil-ity to protect” foreign civilians in humanitar-ian crises – we can expect capacity constraints to become an increasingly important expla-nation for noncompliance.

* * *

Despite the temptation to contrast so-called “ideational” theories with “rationalist” ones, the complementarities are striking. Like rationalists, constructivists recognize that reputation surely matters to governments and their constituencies, but reputational con-cerns themselves are hardly exogenously given constructs; they are the result of intense socialization among state elites within a par-ticular region (Lutz and Sikkink 2000). Game theorists posit such concepts as “common conjectures” that facilitate reciprocation, but what are common conjectures but commonly shared assumptions about certain basic prin-ciples or beliefs about how the “game” should be played (Morrow 2007)? Beth Simmons explicitly combines both rational-ist (treaty as legal leverage) and constructiv-ist (treaty as an educative device) approaches when she discusses the influence that ratified human rights conventions may have on domestic political organization and mobiliza-tion (Simmons 2009). Habermasian theories of communicative action (Risse 2000) have something in common with the Chayes’ notion of “jawboning” (Chayes and Chayes 1993). Theorists of law compliance have

been borrowing from one another’s concep-tual toolkits for years. That few any longer feel obliged to declare an exclusive theoreti-cal affiliation has largely promoted theoreti-cal rigor, not undercut it.

CONCLUSION

Two broad theoretical approaches have done most to advance the study of international law as a social science in the past decade: constructivist theories and rationalist theories of rules and behavior. The former has its roots in the recognition that norms and norm-governed behavior generally play an impor-tant role in human relations, and that there was no reason to think that this role should end abruptly at the water’s edge. The latter grew out of the “neo-functional” theories of international institutions pioneered by Keohane in the 1970s. Both approaches have given rise to a broad range of fruitful research that has moved the theoretical but especially empirical frontiers well beyond that of earlier decades. Today, it is still possible to see the influence of these two areas of theorizing studies of international law and international relations, but the most interesting work draws insights from both.

The literature on international law and international relations has developed both theoretically and empirically in the past decade. Theory has become less compart-mentalized even as it has become more rigorous. Empirical testing has gained a tremendous amount from decades of data collection by governments, nongovernmental organizations, and teams of scholars. The frontier of research now seems to be at the nexus of international law, international rela-tions, and domestic politics and legal sys-tems. New research is beginning to explore the globalization of law into domestic con-texts, but at the same time the differentiated ways in which international rules are absorbed and resisted by local political, social, reli-gious, and legal traditions. Another frontier

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3725769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 372 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 373

for research is presented by the slow fading of the sharp distinction between international law and more informal forms of international governance. International governance is a product of both interstate agreements but also the myriad understandings, procedures, and standards that develop between states and private actors and among private actors (operating in the shadow of states) them-selves. Not only can the pubic international law scholarship be faulted for being too state-centric, but scholars of “global govern-ance” should think about the international legal context in which private groups operate. It is surprising during a time when interna-tional law is flourishing that a recent collec-tion of essays on global governance had not a chapter, not a subheading, not even an index entry on international law (Avant et al. 2010).

The most significant feature of the new research is the pervasive assumption that legal institutions are worthy of scholarly study. In international relations, space has opened up as realism has lost its near monop-oly position of decades past. Critical legal theory has also probably run its course, although it has left many valuable insights in its wake. This is not to say that there is not some quite intelligent and insightful work in these traditions. It is only to say that both of these approaches from very different ideo-logical perspectives failed to inspire young researchers who could hardly square the dour messages of the law’s irrelevancy on the one hand and its essentially tragic nature on the other hand with what anyone with eyes could observe: actors from the largest to the small-est nations, in the regulation of everything from human rights to tax coordination; from land mines to investment agreements were turning to law or law-like instruments to nur-ture their identities and/or to achieve their objectives. International law was an empiri-cal reality that was not melting away, and indeed seemed to enjoy a huge boost from the end of the Cold War. Much needed explaining – from the sprouting of regional trade agreements to a new global institution

with the power individuals for war crimes. The new attitude seems to be that skepticism, too, no less than “idealism,” has empirical burdens to bear. The past two decades have demonstrated the value of taking these burdens seriously.

NOTES

1 For this position, many thought of him as an apologist for Nazi Germany. See the preface to The Twenty Years’ Crisis

2 For example, despite his focus on international rules and norms, Robert Keohane’s work never explicitly engaged international law until 1997 (Keohane 1997) . For a review of the literature in international institutions that has been influenced by rational functionalism, see the chapter by Martin and Simmons in this volume.

3 Case T-306/01 Yusuf and Al Barakaat v Council and Commission [2005] ECR II-3533 and Case T-315/01 Kadi v Council and Commission [2005] ECR II-3649.

REFERENCES

Abbott, Kenneth W., Robert O. Keohane, Andrew Moravcsik, Anne-Marie Slaughter, and Duncan Snidal. 2000. “The Concept of Legalization.” International Organization 54 (3):401–19.

Abbott, Kenneth W., and Duncan Snidal. 2000. “Hard and Soft Law in International Governance.” International Organization 54 (3):421–56.

Ackerman, Bruce. 1997. “The Rise of World Constitutionalism.” Virginia Law Review 83:771–97.

Allee, Todd L., and Paul K. Huth. 2006. “Legitimizing Dispute Settlement: International Legal Rulings as Domestic Political Cover.” American Political Science Review 100 (02):219–34.

Allee, Todd L., and Clint Peinhardt. 2010. “Delegating Differences: Bilateral Investment Treaties and Bargaining over Dispute Resolution Provisions.” International Studies Quarterly 54:1–26.

Alter, Karen J. 2011. The Evolving International Judiciary. Annual Review of Law and Social Science 7 (1): 387-415.

Altman, Amnon. 2004. “Tracing the Earliest Recorded Concepts of International Law: The Early Dynastic Period in Southern Mesopotamia.” Journal of the History of International Law 6 (2):153–72.

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3735769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 373 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS374

Altman, Amnon. 2009. “Tracing the Earliest Recorded Concepts of International Law. (4) The Near East in the Late Bronze Age (1600–1200 BCE) (concluded).” Journal of the History of International Law 11 (2):333–56.

Angell, Norman. 1911. The Great Illusion; A Study of the Relation of Military Power in Nations to Their Economic and Social Advantage, 3d rev. and enl. ed. New York, London: G. P. Putnam’s Sons.

Anghie, Antony. 2005. Imperialism, Sovereignty, and the Making of International Law. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Aron, Raymond. 1981. Peace and War: A Theory of International Politics. Malabar Florida: Krieger Publishing Company.

Avant, Deborah D., Martha Finnemore, and Susan K. Sell, eds. 2010. Who Governs the Globe? New York: Cambridge University Press.

Bederman, David J. 2009. “International Law in the Ancient World.” In Routledge Handbook of International Law, ed. J. D. Armstrong and J. Brunée. London; New York: Routledge.

Benhabib, Seyla. 2009. “Claiming Rights across Borders: International Human Rights and Democratic Sovereignty.” American Political Science Review 103 (04):691–704.

Bernhagen, Patrick. 2008. “Business and International Environmental Agreements: Domestic Sources of Participation and Compliance by Advanced Industrialized Democracies.” Global Environmental Politics 8 (1):78–110.

Börzel, Tanja A., Tobias Hofmann, Diana Panke, and Carina Sprungk. 2010. “Obstinate and Inefficient: Why Member States Do Not Comply with European Law.” Comparative Political Studies 43 (11):1363–90.

Brunnée, Jutta, and Stephen J. Toope. 2010. Legitimacy and Legality in International Law: An Interactional Account. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Buchanan, Allen, and Russell Powell. 2008. “Survey Article: Constitutional Democracy and the Rule of International Law: Are They Compatible?” The Journal of Political Philosophy 16 (3):326–49.

Bull, Hedley. 1977. The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics. New York: Columbia University Press.

Busch, Marc, and Krzysztof J Pelc. 2010. “The Politics of Judicial Economy at the World Trade Organization.” International Organization 64 (2):257–80.

Buss, Doris, and Ambreena S. Manji, eds. 2005. International Law: Modern Feminist Approaches. Oxford, Portland, OR: Hart.

Büthe, Tim, and Walter Mattli. 2011. The New Global Rules: The Privatization of Regulation in the world Economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Butler, Geoffrey Gilbert, and Simon Maccoby. 1928. The Development of International Law. London: Longmans Green.

Carr, Edward Hallett. 1964. The Twenty Years’ Crisis, 1919–1939: An Introduction to the Study of International Relations. New York: Harper & Row.

Carrubba, Clifford J., Matthew Gabel, and Charles Hankla. 2008. “Judicial Behavior under Political Constraints: Evidence from the European Court of Justice.” American Political Science Review 102 (04):435–52.

Cass, Deborah Z. 2005. The Constitutionalization of the World Trade Organization: Legitimacy, Democracy, and Community in the International Trading System. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

Charlesworth, Hilary, Christine Chinkin, and Shelley Wright. 1991. “Feminist Approaches to International-Law.” American Journal of International Law 85 (4):613–45.

Chayes, Abram, and Antonia Handler Chayes. 1993. “On compliance.” International Organization 47 (2):175–205.

Chayes, Abram, and Antonia Handler Chayes. 1995. The New Sovereignty: Compliance with International Regulatory Agreements. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.

Checkel, Jeffrey T. 2001. “Why Comply? Social Learning and European Identity Change.” International Organization 55 (3):553–88.

Cole, Wade M. 2005. “Sovereignty Relinquished? Explaining Commitment to the International Human Rights Covenants, 1966–1999.” American Sociological Review 70 (3):472–96.

Dai, Xinyuan. 2007. International Institutions and National Policies. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Davis, Christina L. 2012. Why Adjudicate? Enforcing Trade Rules. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

DeSombre, Elizabeth R. 2006. Flagging Standards: Globalization and Environmental, Safety, and Labor Regulations at Sea. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Downs, George W, David M. Rocke, and Peter N. Barsoom. 1996. “Is the Good News about Compliance Good News about Cooperation?” International Organization 50 (3):379–406.

Dunoff, Jeffrey L. 2006. “Constitutional Conceits: The WTO’s ‘Constitution’ and the Discipline of

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3745769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 374 5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM5/3/2012 12:57:31 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 375

International Law.” European Journal of International Law 17 (3):647–75.

Elkins, Zachary, Andrew T. Guzman, and Beth A. Simmons. 2006. “Competing for Capital: The Diffusion of Bilateral Investment Treaties, 1960–2000.” International Organization 60 (4):811–46.

Fassbender, Bardo. 1998. “The United Nations Charter as Constitution of the International Community.” Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 36:529–619.

Finnemore, Martha, and Stephen J. Toope. 2001. “Alternatives to ‘Legalization’: Richer Views of Law and Politics.” International Organization 55 (3):743–58.

Fortna, Virginia Page. 2003. “Scraps of Paper? Agreements and the Durability of Peace.” International Organization 57 (2):337–72.

Fourie, Andria Naudé. 2009. The World Bank Inspection Panel and Quasi-Judicial Oversight: In Search of the ‘Judicial Spirit’ in Public International Law. Utrecht: Eleven International Publishing.

Gardbaum, Stephen. 2008. “Human Rights as International Constitutional Rights.” European Journal of International Law 19 (4):749–68.

Gaubatz, Kurt Taylor. 1996. “Democratic States and Commitments in International Relations.” International Organization 50 (1):109–39.

Gibler, Douglas M. 2008. “The Cost of Reneging: Reputation and Alliance Formation.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 52 (2):426–54.

Goldsmith, Jack L., and Eric A. Posner. 2005. The Limits of International Law. New York: Oxford University Press.

Goldstein, Judith L, Douglas Rivers, and Michael Tomz. 2007. “Institutions in International Relations: Understanding the Effects of the GATT and the WTO on World Trade.” International Organization 61 (1):37–67.

Goodman, Ryan, and Derek Jinks. 2004. “How to Influence States: Socialization and International Human Rights Law.” Duke Law Journal 54:621–701.

Grotius, Hugo. 1962. The Law of War and Peace. De jure belli ac pacis, libri tres, ed. F. W. Kelsey. Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill.

Gulbrandsen, Lars H., and Steinar Andresen. 2004. “NGO Influence in the Implementation of the Kyoto Protocol: Compliance, Flexibility Mechanisms, and Sinks.” Global Environmental Politics 4 (4):54–75.

Guzman, Andrew, and Beth A. Simmons. 2002. “To Settle or Empanel? An Empirical Analysis of Litigation and Settlement at the WTO.” Journal of Legal Studies 1 (part 2):S205–S36.

Guzman, Andrew T. 2002. “International Law: A Compliance Based Theory.” California Law Review 90:1823.

Hafner-Burton, and Emilie M. 2005. “Trading Human Rights: How Preferential Trade Agreements Influence Government Repression.” International Organization 59 (3):593–629.

Hafner-Burton, Emilie M., and Kiyoteru Tsutsui. 2005. “Human Rights in a Globalizing World: The Paradox of Empty Promises.” American Journal of Sociology 110 (5):1373–411.

Hathaway, Oona. 2002. “Do Human Rights Treaties Make a Difference?” Yale Law Journal 111 (8):1935–2042.

Helfer, Laurence R., Emilie M Hafner-Burton, and Christopher J Fariss. 2011. “Emergency and Escape: Explaining Derogation from Human Rights Treaties,” International Organization 65 (4): 639-672.

Helfer, Laurence R., and Anne-Marie Slaughter. 1997. “Toward a Theory of Effective Supranational Adjudication.” Yale Law Journal 107 (2):273–391.

Higgins, Rosalyn. 1994. Problems and Process: International Law and How We Use It. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Hoffmann, Stanley. 1987. Janus and Minerva: Essays in the Theory and Practice of International Politics. Boulder CO: Westview Press.

Hovi, Jon, Robert Huseby, and Detlef F Sprinz. 2005. “When Do (Imposed) Economic Sanctions Work?” World Politics 57 (4):479–99.

Hurrell, Andrew. 2007. On Global Order: Power, Values, and the Constitution of International Society. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

Ikenberry, G. John. 2001. After Victory: Institutions, Strategic Restraint, and the Rebuilding of Order after Major Wars. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

Jeffery, Renée. 2006. “Hersch Lauterpacht, the Realist Challenge and the ‘Grotian Tradition’ in 20th-Cen-tury International Relations.” European Journal of International Relations 12 (2):223–50.

Johnston, Alastair Iain. 2001. “Treating International Institutions as Social Environments.” International Studies Quarterly 45 (4):487–516.

Johnstone, Ian. 2003. “Security Council Deliberations: The Power of the Better Argument.” European Journal of International Law 14:437–80.

Kahler, M. 2000. “Legalization as Strategy: The Asia-Pacific Case.” International Organization 54 (3):549–71, IX.

Kelemen, R. Daniel, and Eric C Sibbitt. 2004. “The Globalization of American Law.” International Organization 58 (1):103–36.

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3755769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 375 5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS376

Kelley, Judith G. 2007. “Who Keeps International Commitments and Why? The International Criminal Court and Bilateral Nonsurrender Agreements.” American Political Science Review 101 (3):573–89.

Kennedy, David. 2004. The Dark Sides of Virtue: Reassessing International Humanitarianism. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Keohane, Robert O. 1983. “The Demand for International Regimes.” In International Regimes, ed. S. D. Krasner. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Keohane, Robert O. 1984. After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Keohane, Robert O. 1997. International Relations and International Law: Two Optics. Harvard International Law Journal 38 (2): 487-502.

Keohane, Robert O., Andrew Moravcsik, and Anne-Marie Slaughter. 2000. “Legalized Dispute Resolution: Interstate and Transnational.” International Organization 54 (3):457–88.

Kingsbury, Benedict, Nico Krisch, and Richard B Stewart. 2005. “The Emergence of Global Administrative Law.” Law and Contemporary Problems 68:15–61.

Klabbers, Jan. 2009. “Setting the Scene.” In The Constitutionalization of International Law, ed. J. Klabbers, A. Peters and G. Ulfstein. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

Kono, Daniel Y. 2007. “Making Anarchy Work: Inter-national Legal Institutions and Trade Cooperation.” The Journal of Politics 69 (3):746–59.

Koremenos, Barbara. 2005. “Contracting around Uncertainty.” American Political Science Review 99 (4):549–65.

Koskenniemi, Martti. 2002. The Gentle Civilizer of Nations: The Rise and Fall of International Law, 1870–1960. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Krasner, Stephen D. 1983a. International Regimes. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Krasner, Stephen D. 1983b. “Structural Causes and Regime Consequences: Regimes as Intervening Variables.” In International Regimes, ed. S. D. Krasner. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Krasner, Stephen D. 1999. Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

Kratochwil, Friedrich. 2009. “Legal Theory and International Law.” In Routledge Handbook of International Law, ed. J. D. Armstrong and J. Brunée. London, New York: Routledge.

Lebovic, James H., and Erik Voeten. 2009. “The Cost of Shame: International Organizations and Foreign Aid in the Punishing of Human Rights Violators.” Journal of Peace Research 46 (1):79–97.

Leeds, Brett Ashley, and Burcu Savun. 2007. “Terminating Alliances: Why Do States Abrogate Agreements?” The Journal of Politics 69 (4):1118–32.

Levi-Faur, David. 2005. “The Political Economy of Legal Globalization: Juridification, Adversarial Legalism, and Responsive Regulation: A Comment.” International Organization 59 (2):451–62.

Lipson, Charles. 1991. “Why Are Some International Agreements Informal?” International Organization 45 (4):495–538.

Long, Andrew G., Timothy Nordstrom, and Kyeonghi Baek. 2007. “Allying for Peace: Treaty Obligations and Conflict between Allies.” The Journal of Politics 69 (04):1103–17.

Lowe, Vaughan. 2000. “The Politics of Law-Making: Are the Method and Character of Norm Creation Changing?” In The Role of Law in International Politics: Essays in International Relations and International Law, ed. M. Byers. Oxford, New York: Oxford University Press.

Lutz, Ellen, and Kathryn Sikkink. 2000. “International Human Rights Law and Practice in Latin America.” International Organization 54 (3):633–59.

Macdonald, Terry, and Kate Macdonald. 2006. “Non-Electoral Accountability in Global Politics: Strengthening Democratic Control within the Global Garment Industry.” European Journal of International Law 17 (1): 89–119.

Mattes, Michaela. 2008. “The Effect of Changing Conditions and Agreement provisions on Conflict and Renegotiation between States with Competing Claims.” International Studies Quarterly 52 (2):315–34.

Mearsheimer, John. 1994–95. “The False Promise of International Institutions.” International Security 19 (3):5–26.

Merry, Sally Engle. 2006. Human Rights and Gender Violence: Translating International Law into Local Justice. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Mitchell, Sara McLaughlin, and Paul R. Hensel. 2007. “International Institutions and Compliance with Agreements.” American Journal of Political Science 51 (4):721–37.

Morgenthau, Hans. 1985. Politics among Nations: The Struggle for Power and Peace, 6th ed. New York: Alfred Knopf.

Morrow, James D. 2007. “When Do States Follow the Laws of War?” American Political Science Review 101 (03):559–72.

Nussbaum, Arthur. 1954. A Concise History of the Law of Nations. Rev. ed. New York: Macmillan.

Paulson, Colter. 2004. “Compliance with Final Judgments of the International Court of Justice since

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3765769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 376 5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM

INTERNATIONAL LAW 377

1987.” American Journal of International Law 98 (3):434–61.

Posner, Eric A., and Alan O Sykes. 2009. “Economic Foundations of the Law of the Sea.” University of Chicago Law & Economics, Olin Working Paper No. 504.

Posner, Eric A., and John C Yoo. 2005. “Judical Independence in International Tribunals.” California Law Review 93 (1):1–74.

Posner, Eric A., and Miguel F. P. de Figueiredo. 2005. “Is the International Court of Justice Biased?” The Journal of Legal Studies 34 (2):599–630.

Reus-Smit, Christian. 2004. “The Politics of International Law.” In The Politics of International Law, ed. C. Reus-Smit. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Risse, Thomas. 2000. “‘Let’s Argue!’: Communicative Action in World Politics.” International Organization 54 (1):1–39.

Risse, Thomas, Steve C. Ropp, and Kathryn Sikkink. 1999. The Power of Human Rights: International Norms and Domestic Change. Cambridge, UK; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Romano, Cesare. 1999. “The Proliferation of International Judicial Bodies: The Pieces of the Puzzle.” New York University Journal of International Law and Politics 31 (summer):709–51.

Rosendorff, B. Peter, and Helen V. Milner. 2001. “The Optimal Design of International Trade Institutions: Uncertainty and Escape.” International Organization 55 (4):829–57.

Ruggie, John Gerard. 1982. “International Regimes, Transactions, and Change: Embedded Liberalism in the Postwar Economic Order.” International Organization 36 (2):379–415.

Sandholtz, Wayne, and Alec Stone Sweet. 2004. “Law, Politics, and International Governance.” In The Politics of International Law, ed. C. Reus-Smit. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Schachter, Oscar. 1991. International Law in Theory and Practice. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff Publishers.

Schimmelfennig, Frank. 2005. “Strategic Calculation and International Socialization: Membership Incentives, Party Constellations, and Sustained Compliance in Central and Eastern Europe.” International Organization 59 (4):827–60.

Shelton, Dinah. 2009. “Soft Law.” In Routledge Handbook of International Law, ed. J. D. Armstrong and J. Brunée. London ; New York: Routledge.

Simmons, Beth A. 2009a. Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Simmons, Beth A. 2010. “Treaty Compliance and Violation.” Annual Review of Political Science 13:273–96.

Simmons, Beth A. 2011. “Bargaining over BITs: Development and Consequences of a ‘Hands-Tying’ Regime for International Investment.”

Simmons, Beth A., and Allison Marston Danner. 2010. “Credible Commitments and the International Criminal Court.” International Organization 64 (2)225–256:.

Simmons, Beth A. 2000. “International Law and State Behavior: Commitment and Compliance in International Monetary Affairs.” American Political Science Review 94 (4):819–35.

Simmons, Beth A. 2002. “Capacity, Commitment, and Compliance – International Institutions and Territorial Disputes.” Journal of Conflict Resolution 46 (6):829–56.

Simmons, Beth A. 2009. Mobilizing for Human Rights: International Law in Domestic Politics. Cambridge, New York: Cambridge University Press.

Simpson, Gerry J. 2001. The Nature of International Law. Aldershot, Hants, England; Burlington, VT: Ashgate.

Slaughter, Anne-Marie. 1995. “International Law in a World of Liberal States.” European Journal of International Law 6:503–38.

Spelliscy, Shane. 2001. “The Proliferation of International Tribunals: A Chink in the Armor.” Columbia Journal of Transnational Law 40 (3):143–75.

Stein, Arthur. 1983. “Coordination and Collaboration: Regimes in an Anarchic World.” In International Regimes, ed. S. D. Krasner. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.

Steinberg, Richard H, and Jonathan M Zasloff. 2006. “Power and International Law.” American Journal of International Law 100 (1):64–87.

Stetson, Dorothy McBride. 1995. “Human Rights for Women: International Compliance with a Feminist Standard.” Women and Politics 15 (3):71–95.

Stone Sweet, Alec. 1999. “Judicialization and the Construction of Governance.” Comparative Political Studies 32 (2):147–84.

Strang, David, and Patricia M. Y. Chang. 1993. “The International Labor Organization and the Welfare-State – Institutional Effects on National Welfare Spending, 1960–80.” International Organization 47 (2):235–62.

Tate, C. Neal, and Torbjorn Vallinder, eds. 1995. The Global Expansion of Judicial Power. New York: NYU Press.

Thompson, Alexander. 2010. “Rational Design in Motion: Uncertainty and Flexibility in the Global

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3775769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 377 5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM

HANDBOOK OF INTERNATIONAL RELATIONS378

Climate Regime.” European Journal of International Relations 16 (2):269–96.

Tomz, Michael. 2008. “The Effect of International Law on Preferences and Beliefs.” Stanford, California.

Valentino, Benjamin, Paul Huth, and Sarah Croco. 2006. “Covenants without the Sword: International Law and the Protection of Civilians in Times of War.” World Politics 58 (3):339–77.

Voeten, Erik. 2007. “The Politics of International Judicial Appointments: Evidence from the European Court of Human Rights.” International Organization 61 (04):669–701.

Voeten, Erik. 2008. “The Impartiality of International Judges: Evidence from the European Court of Human Rights.” American Political Science Review 102 (04):417–33.

Waltz, Kenneth Neal. 1979. Theory of International Politics. Reading, MA: Addison-Wesley Pub. Co.

Weiler, Joseph, and Marlene Wind, eds. 2003. European Constitutionalism beyond the State. Cambridge; New York: Cambridge University Press.

Weiss, Edith Brown, and Harold Karan Jacobson. 1998. Engaging Countries: Strengthening Compliance with International Accords. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.

Weller, Marc. 2009. “The Struggle for an International Constitutional Order.” In Routledge Handbook of International Law, ed. J. D. Armstrong and J. Brunée. London; New York: Routledge.

Wilson, Bruce. 2007. “Compliance by WTO Members with Adverse WTO Dispute Settlement Rulings: The Record to Date.” Journal of International Economic Law 10 (2):397–403.

Wilson, Woodrow. 1911. “The Law and the Facts: Presidential Address, Seventh Annual Meeting of the American Political Science Association.” American Political Science Review 5 (1):1–11.

Wotipka, Christine Min, and Francisco O. Ramirez. 2008. “World Society and Human Rights: An Event History Analysis of the Convention on the Elimination of all Forms of Discrimination against Women.” In The Global Diffusion of Markets and Democracy, ed. B. A. Simmons, F. Dobbin, and G. Garrett. New York: Cambridge University Press.

Yasuaki, Onuma 2000. “When Was the Law of International Society Born – An Inquiry of the History of International Law from an Intercivilizational Perspective.” Journal of the History of International Law 2 (1):1–66.

Zimmern, Alfred Eckhard. 1934. International Law and Social Consciousness, ed. G. Society. London: Grotius Society.

Carr, Edward Hallett. 1964. The twenty years’ crisis, 1919-1939; an introduction to the study of interna-tional relations. New York,: Harper & Row.

Keohane, Robert O. 1997. International Relations and International Law: Two Optics. Harvard International Law Journal 38 (2): 487-502.

5769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 3785769-Carlsnaes_14.indd 378 5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM5/3/2012 12:57:32 PM