19
From Devil’s Whore To Cloistered Handmaiden: Bonhoeffer's Engagement with Philosophy in Act and Being ——————————————— Student: Josh de Keijzer Date: 12/02/2012 Course: HC8810, Luther Seminary ——————————————— I. Introduction Another paper on Bonhoeffer, one may think, has not enough been written on a man who lived too short to write his most important and mature work? Indeed, Bonhoeffer has been analyzed back and forth and applied in widely varying contexts and for many purposes. He has been enlisted in support so many often incommensurate theological paradigms. People haven been fascinated with Bonhoeffer ever since he died as a martyr at the hand of the nazis. It is only fair to say that this same fascination has gripped the writer of this paper. For me as a budding theologian, consciously moving away from a foundationalist evangelicalism without wanting to surrender the vitality of a living re‐ lationship with God through Christ to a more abstract and moralizing liberalism, Bonhoeffer—and with him a good many other Lutheran theologians of the 20th century—provides an intellectually viable alternative. His interaction with continental philosophy makes for an interesting example of the integration of faith and reason, relevant for contemporary debates on this and related topics. Bonhoeffer is not merely a quotable hero of the German resistance, but a philosophical theologian in his own right. 1 His Act and Being, written as a Habilitationsschrift, shows the young Bonhoeffer in‐ teracting with philosophy from a Protestant dialectical perspective that is neither entirely antitheti‐ 1. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 12.

Bonhoeffer-Devil whore to cloistered handmaiden.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • From Devils Whore To Cloistered Handmaiden:

    Bonhoeffer's Engagement with Philosophy in Act and Being

    Student: Josh de Keijzer

    Date: 12/02/2012

    Course: HC8810, Luther Seminary

    I.Introduction

    Another paper on Bonhoeffer, one may think, has not enough been written on a man who lived too

    short to write his most important and mature work? Indeed, Bonhoeffer has been analyzed back

    and forth and applied in widely varying contexts and for many purposes. He has been enlisted in

    support so many often incommensurate theological paradigms. People haven been fascinated with

    Bonhoeffer ever since he died as a martyr at the hand of the nazis. It is only fair to say that this same

    fascination has gripped the writer of this paper. For me as a budding theologian, consciously moving

    away from a foundationalist evangelicalism without wanting to surrender the vitality of a living re

    lationship with God through Christ to a more abstract and moralizing liberalism, Bonhoefferand

    with him a good many other Lutheran theologians of the 20th centuryprovides an intellectually

    viable alternative. His interaction with continental philosophy makes for an interesting example of

    the integration of faith and reason, relevant for contemporary debates on this and related topics.

    Bonhoeffer is not merely a quotable hero of the German resistance, but a philosophical theologian in

    his own right.1 His Act and Being, written as a Habilitationsschrift, shows the young Bonhoeffer in

    teracting with philosophy from a Protestant dialectical perspective that is neither entirely antitheti

    1. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 12.

  • cal nor fully integrative. In the light of the fact that my future dissertation topic will most likely focus

    on this very integration in Bonhoeffer's thought, this exercise is, from a personal perspective, ex

    tremely meaningful. Since this integration has not often been the focus of attention in the scholarly

    Bonhoeffer community, probably out of eagerness to Nind useful application for his thought, re

    searchintothissubjectisultimatelyrelevantforBonhoefferscholarshipingeneral.

    Bonhoeffer's engagement with continental philosophy is not done on neutral ground nor

    does it serve the purpose of simply assembling building blocks that integrate with religious con

    cepts to form a contemporary theology. Rather the analysis of continental philosophy serves Bonho

    effer's moral indictment of it. This is very clear in Act and Being. There Bonhoeffer presents a con

    ceptual analysis of continental thought resulting in a judgment of philosophy that serves to create

    space for revelation and theology in the 20th century. This judgment is similar to Luther's. In doing

    so, Bonhoeffer proves himself to be a dialectical, and even somewhat existential thinker who stands

    Nirmly in the Lutheran tradition. This is what this paper tries to show. For Luther, philosophy was no

    longer, as in scholasticism, the handmaiden of theology but rather the devil's whore. Bonhoeffer

    doesn't quite treat philosophy that badly, but in the end philosophy doesn't receive a much better

    fate as she becomes a cloistered handmaiden. Philosophical concepts are used but in a radically dif

    ferentframeworkthatgivesprimacytorevelation.

    We will proceed as follows. This paper will start with an initial exposition of Bonhoeffer's

    stance on the integration of philosophy into theology. We will limit our scope to Act and Being such

    that whether (and, if so, how) Bonhoeffer later modiNied his stance, will not be part of this investiga

    tion. After this we will examine how Bonhoeffer's move against continental philosophy compares to

    that of theologians/thinkers relevant to Bonhoeffer: Luther, Kierkegaard, and Barth. These compar

    isons will out of necessity be cursory but adequate enough to frame Bonhoeffer's thought. Lastly, we

    will then move on to discuss the value of philosophy for theology in Bonhoeffer's thought. This be

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 2

  • ing a project under development, it speaks for itself that we will merely get a general overview of

    the directions that Bonhoeffer was taking. It is a necessary stage on the way, useful for a general in

    troductionintothethoughtofthisimportanttheologian.

    II.TheConceptualFrameworkofActandBeinginPhilosophy

    A.TheConceptsofActandBeinginContinentalPhilosophy

    In Act and Being Bonhoeffer shifts his focus from sociality and church in Communio Sanctorum to

    the relationship between continental philosophy and revelation. Interestingly, but maybe not sur

    prisingly, sociality and church feature large in his theological response. As Bonhoeffer looks at the

    German philosophical tradition since and including Kant up to Heidegger, he distinguishes two

    broad movements that represent two contrasting attempts to comprehend reality and the self. He

    succinctly captures them with the two short hands 'act' and 'being.' On the one hand is the group of

    thinkers that belong to transcendentalism and idealism. Kant and Hegel are their main representa

    tives. Philosophers that belong to either school are aware of the self and its limitations. In order to

    preserve room for the transcendent, in the case of transcendentalism, thinking draws a boundary

    between thought and the transcendent self, which it realizes it can not know. Kant for instance, dis

    tinguishes between the noumenal and phenomenal. While he acknowledges that the self has access

    to the phenomena of things as they represent themselves to the self, he realizes that the thing in it

    self is inaccessible. There is a boundary between thought and the thing in itself, thought and the self,

    or thought and God. Kant draws that boundary as a thinking subject. Idealism follows a similar

    route in starting from the self, but rather than drawing a boundary between thinking and the

    transcendental it takes itself as the starting point for thinking through and mastering all of reality.

    Hegel, for instance, devised a grand system that accounted for everything that exists, in which di

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 3

  • vine consciousness and humanity, culture and the state blended into one as it became selfaware

    throughout time, i.e. in the historical dialectical process. Bonhoeffer summarizes this movement

    withtheterm'act.'Theself'sthinkingisanactofengagementwithreality.

    The other movement in German postEnlightenment philosophy approaches reality ontolog

    ically. In ontology being has the primacy over thought. Thought does not try to master reality but

    merely attempts to describe it, thereby honoring being's otherness. 'Ontological thinking gives up

    the creative power of thinking and wants to think only by viewing receptively.'2 Two thinkers Bon

    hoeffer focuses on in particular are Husserl and Heidegger.3 They represent phenomenology and ex

    istentialism respectively. Husserl's thought has a lot in common with transcendental realism as well

    as idealism. Since the observing object leaves room for the otherness of being without fully having

    access to it, that being stands as a transcendent reality over against the observer.4 However, since

    the main focus in Husserl is always on how consciousness is conscious of being, on how conscious

    ness can achieve a 'purely conceptual perception,' it seems that being is locked up or dependent on

    consciousness as much as it is in idealism.5 Heidegger's existentialism, lastly, is an ontology without

    a system. Being Ninds itself as Dasein, i.e. as existence, in the world. Thinking does not produce the

    world (as in idealism) or deNines the boundary between itself and the world (transcendentalism),

    but simply 'discloses the being of Dasein.'6 It means that in Heidegger 'being has priority over

    thought,andyetbeingequalsDasein,equalsunderstandingofbeing,equalsspirit.'7

    2. Christiane Tietz, Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy, in Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform

    Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor and Jens Zimmermann, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 33.

    3. Bonhoeffer also deals with the work of M. Scheler. I have left it out for considerations of clarity and brevity. Cf. Dietrich

    Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works, vol. 2

    (Fortress Press, 2009), 64 pp.

    4. Ibid., 34.

    5. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 63.

    6. Christiane Tietz, Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy, in Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform

    Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor and Jens Zimmermann, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 34.

    7. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 4

  • Act, then, is the collective name of the act of thinking that tries to deNine the boundary be

    tween itself and the transcendent self or the transcendent other, or the act of grasping and master

    ing reality in such a way that this reality is dependent upon thinking. Being on the other hand

    stands for all ontological approaches, whether they are variations on idealism and transcendental

    ismasinHusserl'sphenomenologyortrulyontologicalasinHeidegger'sexistentialism.

    B.WhyPhilosophicalMethodsof'Act'and'Being'Fail

    For Bonhoeffer all these attempts fail at adequately providing space for revelation and therefore

    God. They are essentially expressions of the self turned in on itself. This is a moral indictment rather

    than a logical refutation. We will come back to this observation, including the logic behind the moral

    indictment. For now we are interested in how Bonhoeffer critiques these modes of thought in Ger

    man philosophy. Bonhoeffer rejects transcendentalism and idealism as attempts of thinking to be in

    charge, so to speak. Transcendentalism is quite willing to admit to the limits of thought. Kant's phe

    nomenal/noumenal distinction is a prime example of that. However, though correct in this willing

    ness, if we ask who or what is in charge of this distinction, we realize it is thought, the human logos,

    that draws the boundary. After all, 'if it [i.e. the transcendent] can never be objectively knowable,

    how can reason Nix its limits over against something unknown?'8 The transcendent self is thus de

    pendent, so to speak, on thinking's judgment for it's transcendence. It is autonomous thought that

    demarcates what is transcendent and what not, since it is, without anything but it's own judgment

    available to it, forced to independently do so. Things get worse when we come to idealism. Here

    thinking becomes the center and starting point for the world. The I becomes the creator of the

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 71.

    8. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 45.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 5

  • world.9 In Hegel, for instance, the world spirit comes to selfawareness as a synthesis between di

    vine being and humanity. It does so through human consciousness. It is an 'WethinkthereforeGod

    exists' kind of approach that makes everything (i.e. God plus all of reality) subordinate to the human

    logos. Bonhoeffer concludes: "[...] this means that God once again becomes 'objectiNied' in con

    sciousness and is thereby taken into the unity of transcendental apperception, becoming the prison

    eroftheconsciousness."10

    For all their heroic efforts, ontological approaches suffer from the same shortcoming: think

    ing autonomously gets in the way one way or another. In the foregoing this might already have be

    come clear. According to Bonhoeffer, Husserl's phenomenology doesn't completely get the ontologi

    cal project off the ground. On the one hand the observing subject draws a boundary between itself

    and the object observed much like it is done in transcendentalism, while on the other hand the

    emphasis on conceptual perception ensures that his phenomenology 'is in a way still under the spell

    of idealism.'11 Whichever way you look at it, thinking determines the rules of engagement: "the

    human logos has overcome being, preventing any clear grasp of the concepts of being and God. Be

    ing as existentia has been dissolved into essentia, and with that the transition to idealism is sealed."12

    Even though Heidegger seems to manage to create an "ontology without a system,"13 the priority of

    ontology is endangered by human existence's (i.e. Dasein's) understanding of being in its actual ex

    istence in time. Bonhoeffer says: "It can come to itself, for it is able to understand itself, but this

    means that Dasein is contained in the world, or, better, the world is contained in Dasein."14 While

    9. Christiane Tietz, Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy, in Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform

    Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor and Jens Zimmermann, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 33.

    10. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 51.

    11. Ibid., 62.

    12. Ibid., 64.

    13. Christiane Tietz, Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy, in Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform

    Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor and Jens Zimmermann, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 34.

    14. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 6

  • Bonhoeffer is really impressed with Heidegger's "enormous expansion through the discovery of the

    existential sphere" he considers Heidegger's thought "unsuitable for theology."15 This is because

    Heidegger looks at Dasein only as closed in by Ninitude and therefore unable to see Ninitude as a

    creatureliness that opens us for God. There is no room for revelation. While this rejection of Heideg

    ger seems not as rigorous as Bonhoeffer's rejection of the other philosophers, later in Act and Being

    even Heidegger (while again being praised for the critical suspension of thought in being) is accused

    ofidealism.16

    III.BonhoefferandLuther'sThought:aMoralIndictmentofPhilosophy

    Why is it that Bonhoeffer makes the moral move in rejection of continental philosophy?17 It is not

    that he Ninds nothing useful there, but there are good reasons why Bonhoeffer felt this move was

    necessary in order to create space for theology again. Rather than an allout antithetical rejection, as

    we see in Karl Barth, Bonhoeffer chooses a critical engagement. While consciously aligning himself

    with dialectical theology (he tried to get Act and Being published as a supplementary issue in Zwis

    chen den Zeiten18), Bonhoeffer "wished theology to speak with all the resources of modern thought,

    yet with its own distinctive voice. . ."19 Philosophy may be on the wrong track but can still be of use

    as a critical discipline: "Philosophy remains profane science; there is no Christian philosophy. But

    philosophy has to be critical philosophy, not systematic. [...] By doing so it gives room, as far as it can,

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 72.

    15. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 73.

    16. Ibid., 106.

    17. Ibid., 8.

    18. Ibid., 5.

    19. Ibid., 7.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 7

  • for God's revelation, which indeed makes room for itself by itself."20 Above all, in order to fully ap

    preciate Bonhoeffer's handling of philosophy, we need to locate him in his Lutheran context. We Nind

    Bonhoeffer strongly embedded in a critical tradition that goes from Luther through Kierkegaard and

    Barth (as a nonLutheran). Interestingly, the very philosophers Bonhoeffer criticizes (Kant, Hegel)

    were by and large Lutherans with a solid theological education, who themselves were inNluenced by

    Luther and lutheran thought.21 So there is a dialectical tension in Bonhoeffer's engagement with

    continental philosophy: on the one hand there is conceptual and historical afNinity while on the oth

    er hand he considers these approaches not viable theologically for reasons that have equally strong

    lutheran overtones. These lutheran traits reoccur in Kierkegaard's existentially oriented philosophy

    and Barth's dialectical theology. We need to look then at the historical (Luther), existential

    (Kierkegaard), and dialectical/contextual (Barth) dimensions that function as background to Bon

    hoeffer'sengagementwithphilosophy.

    A.BonhoefferandLuther

    Luther's disdain for philosophy is generally well known. Throughout his works he has scathing re

    marks for Aquinas and other classic scholastics. The labeling of philosophy as 'devil's whore'22 is a

    good example. He laments the fargoing integration between philosophy and theology at the ex

    pense of the emphasis on faith. This emphasis was exactly what Luther rediscovered in his return to

    the Scriptures: justiNication by faith. Pelikan writes: "...it is clear that it was because of what they had

    done to free grace, and not principally because of what they had done with Aristotle, that Luther re

    20. Dietrich Bonhoeffer and Clifford J. Green, Barcelona, Berlin, New York 1928/1931, Dietrich Bonhoeffer Works, vol. 10

    (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2008), 124.

    21. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth, The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, (Minneapolis:

    Fortress Press, 2011), 1.

    22. Martin Luther, Henry Eyster Jacobs; Adolph Spaeth, Works of Martin Luther : With Introductions and Notes, (Philadelphia:

    Muhlenberg Press, 1943), Volumes 40:175; 51:374.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 8

  • pudiated the systems of the medieval thinkers."23 Apart from this contention which very well ex

    plains his harsh remarks, however, we notice a remarkable inNluence from philosophy. Luther relied

    very strongly on Cicero's rhetoric for his christologically oriented practical reason.24 Simpson points

    out that Luther was attracted to Cicero's ideas of how humans beings need to be lifted above their

    primordial animallike nature to become social beings that are socially responsible.25 He summoned

    Cicero's rhetoric to wisely love the neighbor, while reserving faith and grace for the relationship

    with Christ. Morality and grace belong to different categories. As a late medieval nominalist Luther

    was part of the via moderna which leveled a critique against medieval philosophy. This inNluence

    would last a lifetime.26 While considering Aristotle's Nicomachean Ethics 'the worst enemy of

    grace,'27 the Aristotelian thread present in nominalism led him to reject a priori neoPlatonic ideas,

    except the idea of God.28 All other things are known by sensory perception. Religiously, this meant

    for Luther that God is beyond human understanding. God cannot be grasped by either observation

    or reason. Dragseth puts it well: "For Luther, the only thing we can know of God is as God revealed

    himself in the person of Jesus Christ, and Jesus, in this world, is the only way that we can think

    about God. We accept Christ as the love of God in faith. We know him as portrayed in Scripture."29

    This nominalism would resurface in the empiricist and rationalist traditions in the Enlightenment.

    23. Jaroslav Pelikan, From Luther to Kierkegaard, a Study in the History of Theology, (St. Louis, Missouri: Concordia

    Publishing House, 1965), 4.

    24. Gary M. Simpson, "Putting on the Neighbor": The Ciceronian Impulse in Luther's Christian Approach to Practical Reason,

    in The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, ed. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth, (Minneapolis:

    Fortress Press, 2011), 31.

    25. Simpson, 36-38

    26. Jaroslav Pelikan, From Luther to Kierkegaard, a Study in the History of Theology, (St. Louis, Missouri: Concordia

    Publishing House, 1965), 6.

    27. Martin Luther, Henry Eyster Jacobs; Adolph Spaeth, Works of Martin Luther : With Introductions and Notes, (Philadelphia:

    Muhlenberg Press, 1943), Volume 31:12.

    28. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth, The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, (Minneapolis:

    Fortress Press, 2011), 4.

    29. Ibid., 5.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 9

  • Because of it, Luther was never certain of his faith: "faith required a radical and irrational leap."30

    Rather than solving the riddle of predestination, he would simply retort: "Let God be God."31 Luther

    thus did not mind to leave contradictions for what they were. We can see the beginnings of dialectic

    thought "in the dynamic tension presented in Luther's attention to opposing theological and exis

    tential constructs, beginning with philosophy and theology, but focusing on letter and spirit, law

    and gospel, law of nature and law of obligation, person and work, faith and love, the kingdom of

    Christ and the kingdom of the world, freedom and bondage, and God hidden and revealed."32

    Comparing Luther and Bonhoeffer is a natural thing to do. We notice a similar indictment of philos

    ophy as a moral failure, i.e. a failure to provide adequate space for faith (Luther) or revelation (Bon

    hoeffer). Where Luther speaks of a cor curvum in se (a heart turned in on itself) Bonhoeffer adds

    that the ratio is curvatus in se; human reason is turned in on itself as well.33 If for Luther Christ is

    our only means of access to God and knowledge of God, Bonhoeffer sees faith in Christ as the mode

    of access (through an act surrender) to participation in Christ which manifests itself (in a manner of

    speaking) materially as the church.34 Luther's Deus absconditus is Bonhoeffer's transcendental Other

    who should not be subjected to any system of thought. The Luther connection is not immaterial to

    Act and Being itself. Bonhoeffer purposed to connect consciousness and conscience with Luther's

    commentary on Galatians for his postdoctoral dissertation.35 The editor's introduction remarks (in

    a footnote!) that "One of the surprising discoveries of a careful reading of Act and Being may be the

    30. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth, The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, (Minneapolis:

    Fortress Press, 2011), 6.

    31. Ibid.

    32. Ibid., 9.

    33. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 41.

    34. Ibid., 115.

    35. Ibid., 3.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 10

  • discovery of the extent to which the central philosophical sections of the book are deeply indebted

    totheologicalinsightsfromMartinLuther..."36

    B.BonhoefferandKierkegaard

    This language of Luther's conception of faith as a radical and irrational leap is reminiscent of

    Kierkegaard. His concept of the leap of faith is not to be equated with that of Luther, but there are

    similar traits. Just as for Luther we can know God only through his revelation in Christ so, according

    to Kierkegaard, the self can only live in transparency to the power that constitutes it (i.e. God) by

    properly being related to itself by means of a relation. This in turn can only take place through the

    possibility of offense in the encounter with the GodMan (i.e. Christ) which either leads to the leap

    of faith or the conscious despair to will to be oneself in rejection of him.37 In Kierkegaard there is no

    clear concept of original sin, but the possibility of sin is a pervasive possibility.38 For Kierkegaard

    most people live in some form of despair or another.39 Apart from a similar christological center in

    both there is also the ambiguous attitude toward philosophy. Luther rejected scholasticism's faith

    stiNling synthesis of philosophy and theology while Kierkegaard resisted the totalizing synthesis of

    Hegel that made the particularity of Christ, his incarnation, and the possibility of individual faith

    subject to the philosophical system.40 Yet, like Luther, Kierkegaard borrowed ideas from philosophy:

    Hegel's idea of dialectic and synthesis as well as Hegel's conception of the self as a selfrelation. We

    see Kierkegaard's radical rejection of idealism in favor of the autonomous reality of revelation (and

    36. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 7.

    37. Sren Kierkegaard and Walter Lowrie, The Sickness Unto Death, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1941), 212.

    38. Cf. Jason A. Mahn, Fortunate Fallibility : Kierkegaard and the Power of Sin, (New York: Oxford University Press, 2011), 2.

    39. Sren Kierkegaard and Walter Lowrie, The Sickness Unto Death, (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1941), 210.

    40. Cf. Merold. Westphal, Kierkegaard's Critique of Reason and Society, (University Park, Pa.: Pennsylvania State University

    Press, 1991), 34.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 11

  • thus the incarnation) return in Bonhoeffer's dealing with continental philosophy, resulting in an

    equally Christcentered focus. Geffrey Kelly notes that around the time Bonhoeffer studied at Union

    Theological Seminary he was clearly "convinced that Kierkegaard, alone among nineteenthcentury

    theologians and philosophers, had correctly perceived the true dialectic of faith and obedience

    presentinLuther'searlierinterpretationofthebiblicalwordonjustiNication."41

    C.BonhoefferandBarth

    Bonhoeffer used the conceptual pair 'act' and 'being' not only to classify approaches in philosophy

    to reality. Theologies too were categorized as either act of being. DeJonge explains: "Bonhoeffer un

    derstands 'act' and 'being', then, as basic, formal, oppositional terms. 'Act' means the discontinuous,

    contingent, and structurally open; 'being' means the continuous, the possible, and the structurally

    closed."42 The latter (being) group reduces revelation to human possibility (the Bible as God's Word,

    theologies of conscience). For Bonhoeffer Barth is the most important representative of acttheolo

    gy. In Barth the mistake is avoided of "the reduction of revelation from a divine act to a human pos

    sibility."43 Yet, according to Bonhoeffer, it results in another form of transcendentalism whereby the

    gap between God and humans is never overcome.44 Though DeJonge provides an excellent analysis

    of how and why Bonhoeffer critiques Barth, it is nevertheless also true that there is a strong conti

    nuity between Barth and Bonhoeffer. Andreas Pangritz even contends that "Bonhoeffer's intention

    was not to overcome Barth's theology but to develop some aspects within Barth's approach in a way,

    41. Geffrey B. Kelly, Kierkegaard and Bonhoeffer, in Bonhoeffer's Intellectual Formation : Theology and Philosophy in His

    Thought, ed. Peter Frick, Religion in Philosophy and Theology (Tbingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2008).

    42. Michael P. DeJonge, Bonhoeffer's Theological Formation, Berlin, Barth & Protestant Theology, (Oxford, UK: Oxford

    University Press, 2012), 19.

    43. Ibid., 17.

    44. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 84-5.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 12

  • which had not been carried out by Barth himself."45 Barth's acttheology (and we must remember

    this is not Barth's category but Bonhoeffer's) was a skillful attempt at breaking away from the dom

    inating 'being' approach of liberal theology, where the gospel was reduced to the ethical, and human

    thought lorded it over revelation. The young Bonhoeffer can be described as a Barthian theologian.46

    He took the transcendence of God seriously. Bonhoeffer wanted to take Barth's theology a step fur

    ther in that the latter's theology was still very heavily inNluenced by Kantian transcendentalism.

    Bonhoeffer's persontheology retrieves an important Lutheran concept: God who freely makes him

    self known in the person of Jesus Christ. The transcendent God is knowable in the act of faith by

    which one becomes one with Christ and member of the body of Christ, while for Barth God in his

    sovereignty remains far beyond human grasp. God is safeguarded, but at the same time locked up in

    his transcendence. Bonhoeffer's persontheology overcomes this by equating the presence of Christ

    in the world today with the church, the body of Christ. In creating space for revelation this way, Bon

    hoeffer had less need of categorically rejecting philosophy. And thus, rather than a rejection of phi

    losophy, Act and Being represents a proposal to critically use philosophy in a constructive way. Both

    in his appropriation of Barthian theology and his critical engagement with it, then, we note the

    Lutheran aspects in Bonhoeffer's thought. In continuity with Barth and Luther there is the rejection

    of philosophy's attempt at mastering reality and revelation by means of reason, of integrating phi

    losophy and theology at the expense of genuine faith and God's revelatory freedom. We also note

    the dialectical method used by both Barth and Bonhoeffer which is similar to Luther's unresolved

    conceptual and existential opposites.47 In discontinuity with Barth, Bonhoeffer develops his person

    45. Andreas Pangritz, Dietrich Bonhoeffer: "Within Not Outside, the Barthian Movement", in Bonhoeffer's Intellectual

    Formation : Theology and Philosophy in His Thought, ed. Peter Frick, Religion in Philosophy and Theology (Tbingen: Mohr

    Siebeck, 2008), 245.

    46. Michael P. DeJonge, Bonhoeffer's Theological Formation, Berlin, Barth & Protestant Theology, (Oxford, UK: Oxford

    University Press, 2012), 2.

    47. With regard to dialectic thinking it is important to note the difference between Realdialektik and dialectics as Denkform. The

    former understands reality to move from dialectic to synthesis; the latter uses opposite forms of thought that are left unresolved.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 13

  • theology as a further elaboration of Luther's concept of God as accessible and knowable only in the

    person of Jesus Christ, a move Barth as a Reformed theologian was less likely to make. Interestingly

    thisestablishesalinkbetweenBonhoefferandmedievalnominalism.

    Having brieNly examined Luther, Kierkegaard, and Barth on their inNluence on Bonhoeffer we

    may safely conclude that Luther's inNluence, both directly and as mediated through Kierkegaard and

    Bonhoeffer's interaction with Barth is substantial and important for understanding Bonhoeffer's

    engagementwithphilosophy.

    IV.TheFunctionofPhilosophyinBonhoeffer'sThought

    A.Uselessnessandusefulness:corcurvuminseorcriticalinstrument

    As we near the end of this paper what is left for us is a brief sketch of Bonhoeffer's engagement with

    philosophy as it emerges in Act and Being against his Lutheran background. Following Christiane Ti

    etz we will adopt the categories 'usefulness' and 'uselessness' to assess Bonhoeffer's ideas on phi

    losophy.48 After that we shall relate these ideas to Luther's in order to evaluate how strongly Bonho

    effer'sLutherantheologicalformationinNluenceshisstanceonphilosophy.

    On the one hand philosophy is useless. Continental philosophy of the 19th and early 20th

    century allows no room for revelation. Philosophy thinks from its own thinking as it tries to under

    stand itself. As a result it doesn't understand itself.49 Reason shows human autonomy at work as an

    expression of the sinful heart turned in on itself. Since there is noone or nothing to show reason its

    Barth's and Bonhoeffer's dialectical theology is o the latter kind. Cf. Michael P. DeJonge, Bonhoeffer's Theological Formation,

    Berlin, Barth & Protestant Theology, (Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press, 2012), 38.

    48. Christiane Tietz, Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy, in Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform

    Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor and Jens Zimmermann, (Bloomington, IN: Indiana University Press, 2009), 35 pp.

    49. Ibid., 37.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 14

  • limits it knows no boundaries. As a result it has to draw those boundaries itself, thereby proving its

    autonomous nature and its inability to recognize and make room for revelation. Any system created

    byphilosophyisthereforeuseless.

    Philosophy is also useful, however. Bonhoeffer recognized (contra Barth) that one cannot do

    without philosophy. In the introduction to Act and Being the editor makes the point (quoting Derri

    da) that one can move beyond philosophy but not by simply turning the page on it.50 While rejecting

    philosophy as a systematic discipline, Bonhoeffer regarded philosophy important as a critical tool.

    As a systematic discipline philosophy departs from and arrives at thought, while losing itself in the

    process. It cannot provide room for revelation for it is not able to recognize it. Theology has a syste

    matic function for it starts with revelation and is thus able to do the job of constructing a system

    that is dependent on and submissive to the demands of revelation. Yet theology needs the critical

    function of philosophy. The latter provides the concepts for theology in order to think through its

    own system in the light of revelation. Concepts like 'transcendence,' 'ontology,' 'existence,' and 'be

    ing,' are part of a symbolic vocabulary that helps to achieve clarity and to critically engage the na

    ture, meaning, and purpose of revelation as the theologian thinks about theological anthropology,

    hamartiology, soteriology, christology, ecclesiology, and eschatology. Revelation may be a fact, a

    properresponsetoitisnotautomaticallyagiven.

    B.FromDevil'sWhoretoCloisteredHandmaiden

    In conclusion, then, there is a lot of similarity between Luther's and Bonhoeffer's approach to phi

    losophy. The latter was clearly inNluenced by the former's categorical rejection of philosophy. Yet,

    while his approach is consciously more nuanced, even there we see a clear resemblance with

    50. Dietrich Bonhoeffer, Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology, Dietrich Bonhoeffer

    Works, vol. 2 (Fortress Press, 2009), 11.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 15

  • Luther. The context of both Luther and Bonhoeffer is similar in that the intellectual climate was

    dominated by an integration of philosophy and theology that obfuscated faith. In both cases, it can

    be argued, human reason (in the form of neoPlatonism and Aristotelianism in scholasticism and

    Kantian dualism, Hegelian idealism, and existentialism in Bonhoeffer's time) had usurped the realm

    of faith. There are differences too. Where reconciliation with and access to God through faith was at

    stake in the Reformation, revelation itself was at stake in Continental philosophy. Luther then used a

    rejection of scholasticism to get to the heart: justiNication by faith. Bonhoeffer uses the act of faith as

    the starting point for his persontheology as an attempt to preserve room for revelation. Another

    difference is that Luther was the prophet who nailed 95 confrontational theses on the door of the

    Castle Church in Wittenberg, while Bonhoeffer was able to walk in the footstep of the slightly older

    dialectical school of Barth and Gogarten that had already fulNilled the role of iconoclast for its time.

    Consequently Bonhoeffer was already moving more towards a synthesis between Barthian theology

    and the philosophical tradition. As a result Bonhoeffer's engagement with philosophy is both very

    similar and yet subtly different. Core components remain the same. Even in going beyond Luther he

    wants to be in accord with him.51 God's knowability as found exclusively in Christ allowed Bonhoef

    fer to judge philosophy as wanting. It helped him too to develop a persontheology as a third way

    beyond the impasse of kantian dualism and usurping idealism. This basic pattern in Luther's

    thought allowed for ambiguity, opposites, and dialectical tension. But just as Luther continued to

    make use of Ciceronian rhetoric and for him the nominalist hiddenness of God played a foundation

    al role in his theology so Bonhoeffer was able to integrate core concepts of philosophy as a critical

    tool to elucidate a theology that started with revelation. Luther may have called philosophy names

    at times, but this was always in relation to philosophy's obscuring of faith. Bonhoeffer is perhaps

    51. Wolf Krtke, Dietrich Bonhoeffer and Martin Luther, in Bonhoeffer's Intellectual Formation : Theology and Philosophy in

    His Thought, ed. Peter Frick, Religion in Philosophy and Theology (Tbingen: Mohr Siebeck, 2008), 53.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 16

  • more nuanced when he distinguishes between systemic and critical function. In the end Bonhoeffer

    only slightly improves philosophy's status. While she seems to be theology's critical handmaiden

    once again, she is now cloistered, i.e. walled in by Bonhoeffer's judgment of her autonomous drive

    that leaves no room for revelation. Bonhoeffer sets the priorities right. Continental philosophybe

    ing heavily inNluenced by Luther itselfhas given in to the rationalistic temptation resulting from

    Luther's Deus Absconditus and must be called to account. We must start with revelation, says Bonho

    effer, for with Luther he is Nirmly convinced that God is only knowable through his selfrevelation in

    Christ.

    This basic pattern of thought with its roots in scholastic nominalism returns in Bonhoeffer's

    Christocentric persontheology, his rejection of systems based on human thought, and the attempt

    to create space for the uniqueness of revelation and the otherness of God as the One overagainst us,

    free, independent, hidden, accessible through faith alone. This theology and engagement with phi

    losophy is highly relevant for our postmodern world as it opens a door beyond the modernist reign

    of reason while not succumbing to radical postmodern relativism. It insists that we start with reve

    lation as the a priori condition for thinking about and knowing God. It also allows room for dialecti

    cal tension in its insistence that the revealed God is also the hidden God. We need to start afresh

    withrevelationandBonhoefferbelongstothosewhowillshowtheway.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 17

  • Bibliography

    Bonhoeffer,Dietrich.SanctorumCommunio.NewYork:HarperandRow,1963.

    ________. Act and Being: Transcendental Philosophy and Ontology in Systematic Theology. Vol. 2, Diet

    richBonhoefferWorks,FortressPress,2009.

    Bonhoeffer, Dietrich, and Clifford J. Green. Barcelona, Berlin, New York 1928/1931. Vol. 10, Dietrich

    BonhoefferWorks,Minneapolis:FortressPress,2008.

    DeJonge, Michael P. Bonhoeffer's Theological Formation, Berlin, Barth & Protestant Theology. Oxford,

    UK:OxfordUniversityPress,2012.

    Dragseth, Jennifer Hockenbery. The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition.

    Minneapolis:FortressPress,2011.

    Peter Frick, ed. Bonhoeffer's Intellectual Formation : Theology and Philosophy in His Thought. Vol. 29,

    ReligioninPhilosophyandTheology.Tbingen:MohrSiebeck,2008.

    Gregor, Brian., and Jens Zimmermann. Bonhoeffer and Continental Thought : Cruciform Philosophy.

    Bloomington,IN:IndianaUniversityPress,2009.

    Kelly, Geffrey B. Kierkegaard and Bonhoeffer. In Bonhoeffer's Intellectual Formation : Theology and

    PhilosophyinHisThought,ed.PeterFrick,145165.Tbingen:MohrSiebeck,2008.

    Kierkegaard, Sren, and Walter Lowrie. The Sickness Unto Death. Princeton: Princeton University

    Press,1941.

    Krtke, Wolf. Dietrich Bonhoeffer and Martin Luther. In Bonhoeffer's Intellectual Formation : Theol

    ogyandPhilosophyinHisThought,ed.PeterFrick,5382.Tbingen:MohrSiebeck,2008.

    Pangritz, Andreas. Dietrich Bonhoeffer: "Within Not Outside, the Barthian Movement". In Bonhoef

    fer's Intellectual Formation : Theology and Philosophy in His Thought, ed. Peter Frick,

    245282.Tbingen:MohrSiebeck,2008.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 18

  • Pelikan, Jaroslav. From Luther to Kierkegaard, a Study in the History of Theology. St. Louis, Missouri:

    ConcordiaPublishingHouse,1965.

    Simpson, Gary M. "Putting on the Neighbor": The Ciceronian Impulse in Luther's Christian Ap

    proach to Practical Reason. In The Devil's Whore : Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran

    Tradition,ed.JenniferHockenberyDragseth,3138.Minneapolis:FortressPress,2011.

    Tietz, Christiane. Bonhoeffer on the Uses and Limits of Philosophy. In Bonhoeffer and Continental

    Thought : Cruciform Philosophy, ed. Brian. Gregor, and Jens Zimmermann, 3145. Blooming

    ton,IN:IndianaUniversityPress,2009.

    Westphal, Merold. Kierkegaard's Critique of Reason and Society. University Park, Pa.: Pennsylvania

    StateUniversityPress,1991.

    From Devil's Whore to Cloistered Handmaiden | 19