18
1 Heidegger’s Dasein and Luther’s Christian: Revealing an Ontic Source of Freedom and Servitude Though there is a strong body of work dealing with early Heidegger’s (Being and Time and prior) relation to Luther, generally such work focuses either on Heidegger’s use of Luther’s method of ‘destruction’ or the Lutheran origins of key concepts such as conscience and Angst. 1 There is, however, at least one theme that is as yet untouched. This theme concerns the way in which authentic Dasein is simultaneously free and bound, and which, in terms of Luther’s work, receives its most sustained and systematic treatment in the appropriately titled work, The Freedom of a Christian. While there is no direct evidence that Heidegger ever read The Freedom of a Christian, there are circumstantial reasons to suppose that he did and therefore reasons to raise the question of this work’s relation to Being and Time. First, it appears that Heidegger studied Luther’s work for more than a decade, and there are statements concerning Luther’s immense personal and philosophical importance. 2 Second, we know that Heidegger at least owned a copy of it. 3 Finally, for a period Heidegger and Julius Ebbinghaus read Luther’s “reformatory writings,” of which The Freedom of a Christian is generally considered among the 1 For strong representative works dealing with these relations see, Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995); John van Buren, The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994); Benjamin Crowe, Heidegger’s Religious Origins: Destruction and Authenticity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2006); Herman Philipse, Heidegger’s Philosophy of Being: A Critical Introduction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998); David Vessey, “Heidegger’s Existential Domestication of Luther,” in The Devil’s Whore: Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, ed. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2011), 131–139. 2 Heidegger’s earliest engagement with Luther seems to have been in 1908 and may have ebbed around 1923; Otto Pöggler, “Heideggers Luther-Lektüre im Freiburger Theologenkonvikt,” in Heidegger und die Anfänge seines Denkens, ed. Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth Gander, and Holger Zaborowski, vol. 1, Heidegger-Jahrbuch (München: Karl Alber, 2004), 192; van Buren, The Young Heidegger, 149; Kisiel, The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time, 452. Luther may have also been more than philosophically important to Heidegger if Heidegger wished “to be a new Luther.” Charles B. Guignon, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, 1st ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 41 n34. 3 In 1921 Heidegger was awarded the complete Erlangen edition of Luther’s works. van Buren, The Young Heidegger, 149; Kisiel, The Genesis of Heidegger’s Being and Time, 228.

Bonhoeffer-Heidegger__Luther__Freedom_and_Servitude-libre.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 1

    Heideggers Dasein and Luthers Christian: Revealing an Ontic Source of Freedom and Servitude

    Though there is a strong body of work dealing with early Heideggers (Being and Time

    and prior) relation to Luther, generally such work focuses either on Heideggers use of Luthers

    method of destruction or the Lutheran origins of key concepts such as conscience and Angst.1

    There is, however, at least one theme that is as yet untouched. This theme concerns the way in

    which authentic Dasein is simultaneously free and bound, and which, in terms of Luthers work,

    receives its most sustained and systematic treatment in the appropriately titled work, The

    Freedom of a Christian. While there is no direct evidence that Heidegger ever read The

    Freedom of a Christian, there are circumstantial reasons to suppose that he did and therefore

    reasons to raise the question of this works relation to Being and Time. First, it appears that

    Heidegger studied Luthers work for more than a decade, and there are statements concerning

    Luthers immense personal and philosophical importance.2 Second, we know that Heidegger at

    least owned a copy of it.3 Finally, for a period Heidegger and Julius Ebbinghaus read Luthers

    reformatory writings, of which The Freedom of a Christian is generally considered among the

    1 For strong representative works dealing with these relations see, Theodore Kisiel, The Genesis of Heideggers

    Being and Time (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1995); John van Buren, The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1994); Benjamin Crowe, Heideggers Religious Origins: Destruction and Authenticity (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2006); Herman Philipse, Heideggers Philosophy of Being: A Critical Introduction (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1998); David Vessey, Heideggers Existential Domestication of Luther, in The Devils Whore: Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, ed. Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2011), 131139.

    2 Heideggers earliest engagement with Luther seems to have been in 1908 and may have ebbed around 1923; Otto Pggler, Heideggers Luther-Lektre im Freiburger Theologenkonvikt, in Heidegger und die Anfnge seines Denkens, ed. Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth Gander, and Holger Zaborowski, vol. 1, Heidegger-Jahrbuch (Mnchen: Karl Alber, 2004), 192; van Buren, The Young Heidegger, 149; Kisiel, The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time, 452. Luther may have also been more than philosophically important to Heidegger if Heidegger wished to be a new Luther. Charles B. Guignon, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, 1st ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 41 n34.

    3 In 1921 Heidegger was awarded the complete Erlangen edition of Luthers works. van Buren, The Young

    Heidegger, 149; Kisiel, The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time, 228.

  • 2

    most important.4 It is doubtful that such a lengthy and intensive engagement with Luther that

    spanned Luthers entire writing career would have skipped this fundamental text.5 It seems

    reasonable, then, to ask what, if any, influence The Freedom of a Christian had on Heidegger. In

    fact, as I will argue the Christian conceptions of freedom and servitude Luther explicates form

    important, though not necessarily exclusive, ontic material from which Heidegger draws in order

    to come to an ontological understanding of authentic Daseins power over its existence and

    servitude to its communal involvements.

    I. Luthers Law/Gospel Distinction

    From a Lutheran perspective, the specific similarities I propose to illuminate between

    Heideggers authentic Dasein and Luthers Christian lie within Luthers more general categories

    of the Law and the Gospel. Therefore, it is first necessary to provide a general overview of the

    way in which these categories function in relation to this specific topic.

    For Luther the Law/Gospel distinction has various functions depending on the sphere in

    which it is deployed; though it is important to bear in mind that these functions overlap and are

    complexly interrelated. Politically and socially the Law/Gospel distinction informs Luthers

    two kingdoms doctrine and the ways in which, somewhat anachronistically, church and state

    4 John van Buren, Heideggers Early Freiburg Courses, 1915-1923, Research in Phenomenology 23 (1993): 138. Lohse, for example, includes The Freedom of a Christian among the three central Reformation works. Bernhard Lohse, Martin Luther: An Introduction to His Life and Work, trans. Robert Schultz (Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1986), 489.

    5 The earliest of Luthers writings that Heidegger cites is Quaestio de viribus et voluntate hominis sine gratia

    disputata (1516), the latest is Luthers Lectures on Genesis (1544) both in Martin Heidegger, Das Problem der Snde bei Luther, in Sachgemsse Exegese: Die Protokolle aus Rudolf Bultmanns Neutestamentlichen Seminaren 1921-1951, ed. Wilfried Hrle and Dieter Lhrmann (Marburg: N.G. Elwert Verlag, 1996), 2833. Additionally, it cannot be overstressed how central The Freedom of a Christian is to understanding Luther. To be a Luther expert one must know The Freedom of a Christian; Charles B. Guignon, ed., The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger, 1st ed. (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 41 n34.

  • 3

    relate. In ecclesiology, it informs the distinction between the visible church and invisible church.

    In biblical hermeneutics it determines the ways in which one interprets the meaning and purpose

    of specific portions of scripture. Here I am concerned with what might be best termed, though

    also somewhat anachronistically, its existential function.6

    According to its existential function, the Law/Gospel distinction accounts for human

    existence in sin and in faith, the relation between the two, and how one transitions from the

    former to the latter. One may, initially, say that Law applies to and accounts for existence in sin;

    while the Gospel applies to and accounts for existence in faith. In other words, for Luther there

    are two general modes of being human. One may be human in sin under the Law; one may be

    human in faith under the Gospel. However, this relation is complicated, first, by the fact that

    according to Luther one cannot truly know ones existence in sin or under the Law until one has

    encountered the Gospel and received faith. Second, existence in faith is neither static nor

    perfect. For Luther, the Christian must continually encounter the Law, perhaps even daily, in

    order to come back to the Gospel. Third, on one reading of Luther, which Heidegger shares,

    existence in sin is neither negated nor destroyed in favor of a new existence in faith (GA 9:

    63/51). In technical Lutheran terms, a Christian is simul peccator et justus, simultaneously

    sinner and justified. Here one gains a new relation to ones existence in sin.

    Existence in sin is not Luthers primary concern in The Freedom of a Christian. Here

    Luther presupposes that one has already encountered the Gospel, received faith and become a

    Christian. However, because a Christians existence under the Law or in sin continues into

    existence in faith, though relationally modified, it is important to provide a brief overview of this

    6 For prominent examples of terming this function existential see Jaroslav Pelikan, From Luther to

    Kierkegaard: A Study in the History of Theology (St. Louis, MO: Concordia Publishing House, 1950); Bernhard Lohse, Martin Luthers Theology: Its Historical and Systematic Development, trans. and ed. Roy Harrisville (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1999).

  • 4

    existence, paying particular attention to the ways in which one transitions from Law or sin to

    Gospel or faith. This is equally true of Heidegger. That which composes ones inauthentic

    existence does not simply disappear in authenticity; rather it is modified. This, then, is the

    subject of the next section where I will show that Heidegger shares with Luther a cluster of

    concepts that may be grouped under the larger concept of Anfechtungen (trials, tribulations, or

    assaults). These Anfechtungen are the existential encounters of death, anxiety, and conscience

    and bring Dasein to authenticity and the Christian to faith. Thereafter, the ways in which

    Authentic Dasein and the Christian gain new sense of freedom and servitude may be illuminated.

    II. Becoming a Christian and Becoming Authentic

    For Heidegger, one of the first encounters that initiates the movement to authenticity is the

    encounter with death; though death not in the physical sense, which he terms perishing

    (Verenden), or the end of being-there that he reserves for demise or decease (Ableben), but

    death (Tod) as the end of possibilities of Dasein (GA 2: 328/247, 333/250-1). As with anxiety

    and conscience, the experience of projecting onto death or being-towards-death is individual and

    individualizing, something that no other Dasein can do or experience for another. Here Dasein

    projects itself forward and sees the certain possibility of the impossibility of it being-there.

    Essentially, Dasein meets a limit, discovers that it is finite, and is thrown back on itself, back on

    its being-in-the-world.

    For Luther, death is also often described as certain and individual. The summons of

    death comes to us all, and no one can die for another. Every one must fight his own battle with

    death by himself, alone. We can shout into anothers ears, but every one must himself be

  • 5

    prepared for the time of death, for I will not be with you then, nor you with me.7 This might

    sound, however, more like Heideggers perishing or demise. Though Luther does at times speak

    of death in the more straightforward sense of the end of human life, there are also times when

    Luther intends a deeper meaning. Luthers deeper understanding of death is one which

    signifies the death of our existence as a sinner and the rebirth in Christ as Christians: It [the

    sacrament of Christs suffering] signifies the death of sin in us and grants it [faith] to those who

    believe.8 In fact, for Luther it is possible, even necessary, to experience this sense of death

    multiple times. For Luther asserts that one is never forever rid of the Law and the Anfechtungen

    it brings: The more Christian a man is, the more evils, sufferings, and deaths he must endure. 9

    Luther, through his own experience, knew how slippery the footing of faith was and how

    easily one falls from faith back into the Law and its Anfechtungen.10 Christianness, for Luther,

    is then the art of continually reentering the Gospel and faith.11 In theory, this seems equally

    possible for Heidegger insofar as we may forget our ownmost possibility for being thereby

    requiring multiple encounters with death (Cf. GA 2: 384/289, 396/299). More importantly,

    Luthers death also seems to be a limit. This sense of death may be understood as the limit

    7 The First Sermon, March 9, 1522, Invocavit Sunday in LW 51, 392. In all candor, this is one of many points

    where Luther is not always consistent. For example, in his Sermon on Preparing to Die, he states that in the hour of death no Christian should doubt that he is not alone. For the eyes of God, Christ, the angels, the saints, and all Christians are on him; Martin Luther, Sermon on Preparing to Die, in Martin Luthers Basic Theological Writings, ed. Timothy E. Lull (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989), 651.

    8 Lectures on Galations, Chapters 1-6, 1519 in LW 27, 238. It is common practice to simply cite the volume of Luthers Work; since I, however, find it useful to know the exact work being drawn from I have included the title of the work in the initial citation. Also, to add textual and historical support to the present argument citations to Luther outside of The Freedom of a Christian have been limited almost exclusively to works Heidegger knew or likely to have read based on the volumes of the Weimar or Erlangen editions of Luthers work cited throughout Heideggers corpus.

    9 Luther, Martin, The Freedom of a Christian, in Martin Luthers Basic Theological Writings, ed. Timothy E.

    Lull (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989), 606. Hereafter cited parenthetically. 10 Lectures on Galatians (1535) in LW 26, 63-4. 11 Lectures on Galatians (1535) in LW 27, 27.

  • 6

    separating Law and sin from Gospel and faith. The Laws ultimate function is to show the

    person to be limited or dead in sin such that one is wholly incapable of coming to faith by ones

    own means.

    Death then moves to the mutually entailing experience of anxiety (Angst), and here,

    Heidegger is uncharacteristically forthright about Luthers contribution (GA 2: 252-3n3/190n1).

    For Heidegger, while death is associated with understanding and projection, anxiety is associated

    with attunement and thrownness (GA 2: 333-5/251-2). In anticipating the indefinite certainty of

    death, Dasein opens itself to a constant threat arising out of its own there (GA 2: 352/265). In

    projecting towards and anticipating death we are thrown anxiously back on how we are in the

    world. Anxiety is anxiety before being-in-the-world when the involvements that compose the

    world collapse in on themselves and completely lack significance (GA 2: 247/186).

    For Luther, anxiety and death are also interwoven: But if you look at death in any other

    way [than through Christ], it will kill you with great anxiety and anguish.12 And there also

    seems, for Luther, to be a sense of the collapsing of significance with anxiety: Just as joy is a

    certain freedom of the heart, even in tribulation, so [anxiety] represents a certain narrowing and

    constriction in tribulation.13

    For Heidegger, both anxiety and death allow for the possibility of having a conscience

    [Gewissen], which mutually supports seeing death as an ownmost possibility and makes one

    ready for anxiety (GA 2: 392/296, 404/305, 410/310). The conscience is then a call from within

    Dasein itself to recognize itself as Being-guilty: The call of conscience has the character of an

    appeal of Daseins to its ownmost potentiality-for-Being-its-Self and that by way of a summons

    12 Martin Luther, Sermon on Preparing to Die, 643. The same word is variously translated as anxiety, anguish,

    and distress. 13 Lectures on Romans in LW 25, 179.

  • 7

    to its ownmost Being-guilty (GA 2: 358/269). Here, guilt actually strikes the conscience (GA

    2: 407/307).

    For Luther, death and anxiety are also tied up in the conscience that co-condemns the

    individual with God for their state of sin. Here Luthers and Heideggers language are

    remarkably similar: For it [the Lords Supper] is given to those who need strength and comfort,

    who have timid hearts and terrified consciences, and who are assailed by sin, or have even fallen

    into sin.14 Here we see the final step of the Law, its final Anfechtung, which reveals a unique

    ontic, Christian truth only available once one has traversed these trials.

    The ultimate purpose of the above encounters, for Heidegger and Luther, is to show

    Being-guilty (Schuldigsein) and sin, respectively. For Heidegger, Being-guilty is tied to lostness

    in the they and once this is revealed, then one is ready for authenticity: The understanding of

    the call of conscience exposes the lostness in the they. Resoluteness returns Dasein to its

    ownmost potentiality for-Being-its-Self. In the understanding of being towards death as the

    ownmost possibility, then ones own potentiality-for-Being becomes authentic and entirely

    transparent (GA 2: 406/307). Heidegger is in fact quite explicit that sin is the faithful or

    Christian, ontic understanding of Being-guilty (GA 2: 406n1/306n1).

    For Luther, these concepts and encounters have a similar function; however, rather than

    authenticity they lead one to the Gospel and Christ. For example, in The Freedom of a Christian

    he states, Now when a man has learned through the commandments [i.e. the Law] to recognize

    his helplessness and is distressedthen, being truly humbled and reduced to nothing in his own

    eyes, he finds in himself nothing whereby he may be justified and saved. Here the second part of

    Scripture [i.e. the Gospel] comes to our aid (FC, 600). And it is here that Dasein and the

    14 Martin Luther, The Sacrament of the Body and Blood of Christ-Against the Fanatics, in Martin Luthers

    Basic Theological Writings, ed. Timothy E. Lull (Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989), 248. Emphasis added.

  • 8

    Christian gain a unique sense of freedom, part of which will involve freedom from the above

    Anfechtungen, if only temporarily.

    III. Dasein, the Christian, and Their Freedom

    Having elucidated the basic process of becoming authentic for Heidegger and becoming a

    Christian for Luther, we may now turn to the central theme of The Freedom of a Christian. This

    works entire thematic purpose is to explain what the following two propositions are and how

    they work together: A Christian is a perfectly free lord of all, subject to none. A Christian is a

    perfectly dutiful servant of all, subject to all (FC, 596).

    The first statement concerns the inner man, while the second concerns the outer (FC,

    596, 610). Admittedly, Heidegger does prefer to avoid such distinctions. Yet, it is important to

    note that for Heidegger, Luther is operating primarily at the ontic level, and therefore, it is at

    least in a formal sense, appropriate for him to make such distinctions. However, there is a

    striking similarity between Heideggers distinction between the they (das Man) and authentic

    self (eigentlichen Selbst) (GA 2: 173/130, 420/317). This should not be confused with the

    distinction between the they-self (Man-selbst), which is inauthentic, and the authentic being-

    ones-self (eigentliche Selbstsein), which is authentic (ibid). Rather the they and authentic

    self are existentials that may be modified in ones becoming either the inauthentic they-self or

    authentic authentic being-ones self (ibid). Here we are concerned with how the they and

    authentic self appear under the auspices of authentic being-ones-self. Ultimately, I am

    arguing that there are correspondences between the authentic self and Luthers free, inner

    Christian, and between the they and Luthers bound, outer Christian, though again as they are

  • 9

    authentically modified.

    I will begin with the inwardly free Christian. First, this freedom in its more negative

    formulation, derived from the clause subject to none, is freedom from works, or the belief and

    requirements that to receive justification and salvation one needs to perform any acts. This, then,

    is essentially freedom from the Law (FC, 601).15 Freedom from the Law carries with it freedom

    from sin and the Anfechtungen that brought one to faith: Thus the believing soul by means of

    the pledge of its faith is free in Christ, its bridegroom, free from all sins, secure against death and

    hell (FC, 604).

    Christian freedom, for Luther, does not stop with the above negative sense of freedom,

    however. It has a more vital, positive formulation derived from the clause lord of all. Though

    of course this freedom does not physically free the Christian from the world nor grant some

    physical power over the world (FC, 606). Christians and non-Christians alike are subject to

    the vagaries of the world (FC, 606). But it does make everything bend to the power of faith and

    aid the Christian in salvation. Every Christian is by faith so exalted above all things that, by

    virtue of a spiritual power, he is lord of all things without exception, so that nothing can do him

    any harm. As a matter of fact, all things are made subject to him and are compelled to serve him

    in obtaining salvation (FC, 606). For example, the Lords Supper taken in sin is useless for

    salvation, perhaps even detrimental. [F]or one who does not believe is not served by

    anythingand all things turn out badly (FC, 607). But in faith the same acts are turned to the

    salvific advantage of the Christian. In fact, Luther takes the phrase lord of all quite seriously

    for even the above encounters that brought one to faith and seemed most threatening to ones

    salvation work in the Christians favor: [I]n all things I can find profit toward salvation, so that

    the cross and death itself are compelled to serve me (FC, 607). 15 Also see LW 27, 49-50.

  • 10

    For Heidegger, this freedom given by Christ to the Christian has its ontological

    foundation in his understanding that in anticipatory resoluteness (vorlaufende Entschlossenheit),

    which is an authentic projection onto death that reveals Being-guilty, Dasein is given power over

    its existence in the technical sense associated with projection and understanding (GA 2: 405/305-

    6, 410/310). Power over existence then means power over possibilities. Here it seems that what

    was once detrimental to Daseins authenticity, the possibilities it unreflectively took over from

    the they, work to its advantage in being authentic. Just as the Lords Supper appears the same

    in sin or in faith, yet functions quite differently depending on which one is in, the possibilities

    and roles that Dasein takes up may appear the same yet function very differently. Dasein may

    take up the roles of mother or professor. In inauthenticity these roles work against Dasein. In

    inauthenticity these roles are a part of the everyday concerns into which Dasein falls. Dasein

    unreflectively does what such roles entail. Once authentic, however, these roles become

    advantageous. Here such roles work to fill out and complete Dasein. They aid in making Dasein

    a whole. Just as for the Christian the ontic conception of death is turned to aid in salvation,

    ontological death also becomes advantageous for Dasein. The authentic appropriation of roles or

    possibilities turns death, as the possibility of being whole or complete, to Daseins advantage.

    In authenticity, anxiety even comes with a prepared joy (gerstete Freude) (GA 2:

    410/310). Here, it seems, that though authentic Dasein is powerless in the face of fortunate

    circumstances and the cruelty of accidents, it gains a certain superior power that makes it

    ready for adversity (GA 2: 508-9/385). Again, even adversities seem to bend to the power of

    Daseins authenticity. This powerless superior power, also has its correlate in Luther: Christ

    says, Come to me, all who labor and are heavy-laden and I will give you rest [Matt. 11:28],

    That is to say: If things go badly, I will give you courage even to laugh about it; and if even

  • 11

    though you walk on fiery coals, the torment shall nevertheless not be so severe and the devil

    shall nevertheless not be so bad, and you will rather feel that you are walking on roses.16

    There is even a temporal correlation between Luthers ontic, Christian freedom

    understood as Gods futural promise of sanctification and Heideggers ontological freedom of

    Dasein as fate (Schicksal). For Luther, the Christian must turn [their] eyes to God, to whom the

    path of death leads and directs [them]. Here [they] find the beginning of the narrow gate and of

    the straight path to life.17 First, this is an extreme focusing of the Christians life. The reason all

    things turn to the Christians salvific advantage is that they have turned completely to God, and

    understand and orient all things according to this single path, a theme of which Heidegger was

    well-aware (GA 60: 96-7/67-8). Second, the Christian, according to Luther, understands this

    individual path to lie between Gods past promise of salvation, constantly made present in the

    sacraments and preaching, and to be fulfilled in the future. Heideggers temporal category of

    fate has a similar formal structure: Only anticipating death drives out every incidental and

    tentative possibility. Only the freedom for death gives Dasein its aim outright and thrusts

    existence into its finitude. The striking finitude of existence tears Dasein back from the endless

    multiplicity of possibilitiesand brings Dasein into the simplicity of its fate (GA 2: 507/384).

    So in authenticity for Dasein and faith for the Christian there is freedom. This is not,

    however, freedom from external coercion or an unhindered ability to choose. Rather this sense

    of freedom modifies the way in which Dasein or the Christian relates to the world. This new

    relation discloses the truth of possibilities, which, for Luther, is determined by their relation to

    God (See GA 2: 394-5/297-8). And with this new relation to the world and others comes a

    16 LW 51, 392. 17 LW 42, 99.

  • 12

    unique responsibility or servitude.

    IV. Dasein, the Christian and Their Servitude

    For Luther, having become a Christian through faith, she now has Christ within her.

    Christ has conquered and freed the Christian from death, sin, the terrors of conscience and so

    forth. Having done so, Christ has at the same time bound the Christians outer self to ones

    neighbors. Hence, as our heavenly Father has in Christ freely come to our aideach one

    should become as it were a Christ to the other that we may be Christs to one another and Christ

    may be the same in all, that is, that we may be truly Christians (FC, 619-20). In becoming

    Christian one also becomes Christ for others. A function Christ has for the Christian is to bring

    one to the Gospel and faith. Christians, therefore, should aid others in overcoming the Law and

    coming to faith. Much of how Heidegger conceives of authentic Dasein being bound to others is

    contained within this one formulation by Luther. This might, for instance, remind one of

    Heideggers distinction in the existential structure of solicitude between the authentic leaping

    ahead (vorausspringen) and the inauthentic leaping in for (einspringen). In the inauthentic

    leaping in for Dasein disburdens others and accomplishes their possibilities. In the authentic

    leaping ahead authentic Dasein helps make the Other transparent to itself thereby helping to

    free it as authentic Dasein is free (GA 2: 163/122). Authentic Dasein can do so by becoming

    the conscience of Others. Functioning as Christ for one another may at first sound like

    inauthentic solicitude; however, being Christ for the other does not disburden the other of the

    task of being Christian. Rather, the fellow Christ functions as the vehicle of the Word that calls

    one to faith. For example, in Luthers The Sacrament of Penance he is careful to distinguish

  • 13

    between the human ability to actually forgive sins and the human ability to convey the Word:

    For any Christian can say to you, God forgives you your sins, in the name, etc., and if you

    accept that word with a confident faith, as though God were saying it to you, then in that same

    faith you are surely absolved.18 The fellow Christian can give another the word, but only the

    individual can accept it in faith.

    If one goes outside The Freedom of a Christian to another work Heidegger is likely to

    have read, the communal link of Christians, as a church, is even stronger: Hence it is that

    Christ and all saints are one spiritual body, just as the inhabitants of a city are one community

    and body, each citizen being a member of the other and of the entire city. All saints, therefore,

    are members of Christ and of the church, which is a spiritual and eternal city of God.19 Here

    having faith and Christ does not merely link one individually existing Christian to another, rather

    having Christ and faith, and being in the community of Christ are mutually necessary and

    entailing. You cannot have one without the other, and the existence of one Christian is bound up

    with the existence of all other Christians in virtue of belonging to one body, or one church. An

    ontological understanding of this might also be found in Being and Time.

    First, Dasein is not simply the authentic self which calls itself to authenticity. Dasein still

    has the existential structure of the they that must also be modified in authenticity. Dasein is

    still bound insofar as the possibilities that it freely takes up, the power it has to exist or project, is

    still dependent on the they. This point is particularly strong in Heideggers communal correlate

    to fate, i.e. destiny (Geschick). But, as being-in-the-world, if fateful Dasein exists essentially in

    Being-with Others, its happening [or historizing (Geschehen)] is a co-happening (Mitgeschehen)

    and is determined as destiny (GA 2: 508/384). Dasein never exists as an independent fate. Or

    18 The Sacrament of Penance, 1519,in LW 35, 12. (My emphasis)

    19 The Blessed Sacrament of the Holy and True Body of Christ, and the Brotherhoods (1519) in LW 35, 51.

  • 14

    for Luther, the Christian never exists alone on its individual path to salvation. First, Daseins

    fate is still dependent on the heritage (Erbe) that has come down to it. Second, in authentically

    choosing and taking up the possibilities in its heritage as fate, it necessarily does so with others.

    Only as fateful destiny [schicksalhafte Geschick]in and with its Generation is there a full

    authentic happening of Dasein (GA 2: 508/384-5). In fact, the earliest signs of Heidegger

    understanding community in this way are religious. In his lectures on Pauls letters to the

    Thessalonians, Heidegger makes statements such as the following: He [Paul] necessarily co-

    experiences [miterfhren] himself in them [the Thessalonians] (GA 60: 93/65). And Their

    having-become [Gewordensein] is also a having-become of Pauls (ibid). So it seems that just

    as a Christian cannot exist alone for Luther, authentic Dasein cannot either.

    Conclusion

    In a 1927 letter to Rudolf Bultmann, Heidegger names Luther as philosophically essential for

    the cultivation of a more radical understanding-of-Dasein. 20 The above has then shown one

    way in which Heidegger found Luther philosophically essential. In Being and Time,

    Heidegger explicitly states that his method is to work from the ontic to the ontological (GA 2:

    412-4/311-3). If one wishes to pursue, understand, and evaluate Heideggers thought, then

    knowing his ontic sources and how he used them is indispensible. The preceding has sought to

    demonstrate that many of Luthers ontic understandings of what it means for a Christian to be

    both free and bound fit within Heideggers ontological structures. Coupled with Heideggers

    extensive knowledge of and self-professed indebtedness to Luther, it should be evident that,

    along with the method of destruction and the existential encounters of death, anxiety and 20 Kisiel, The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time, 452.

  • 15

    conscience, Heidegger draws on Luthers ontic understanding of a Christian to inform authentic

    Daseins freed existence and servitude to communal involvements.

    I hope the preceding has mitigated the perception of Heideggers Being and Time as

    fundamentally and extremely individualistic. There are undoubtedly extreme and important

    individualistic elements in Being and Time. Most notably, death, anxiety, and conscience are all

    fundamentally defined as individualizing moments (GA 2: 249-50/187-9, 350/263-4, 406-7/307).

    However, on the other side of these moments, in authenticity, Dasein is necessarily once again

    communal. For while it is true that, for Heidegger, Dasein can be authentically itself only if it

    makes this possible for itself of its own accord, the structures of concern and solicitude are

    never severed from Dasein and share in conditioning the possibility of any existence [either

    authentic or inauthentic] whatsoever (GA 2: 350/263). For Luther and much of the Lutheran

    tradition, it is impossible to be Christian outside the community. A Christian is always Christian

    in Christ with others all drawing on and repeating anew a shared heritage. This seems equally

    ontologically true for Heidegger. Whether ontically understood as the church, the polis, or,

    controversially, the Volk, authenticity involves co-existing, in the technical sense, with a

    community and appropriating the heritage contained within that community.

    Finally, with Luther playing such a vital role in Heideggers early projects, it seems

    worth investigating the continuities and discontinuities between Heideggers understanding and

    appropriation of Luther with that of his immediate predecessors and contemporaries. During

    Heideggers most intensive engagement with Luther, a Luther renaissance was underway. In

    section 3 of Being and Time, Heidegger mentions this renaissance in contemporary theology and

    its positive potential for properly grounding theology. Heidegger knew this community and in

    some respects engaged with it. If we then apply Heidegger to himself, then it is reasonable to

  • 16

    assume that he is also bound to the Luther renaissance that surrounds him. Understanding

    Heidegger might just then also require understanding the various Luthers surrounding him.

  • 17

    References

    van Buren, John. Heideggers Early Freiburg Courses, 1915-1923. Research in Phenomenology 23 (1993): 132152.

    . The Young Heidegger: Rumor of the Hidden King. Bloomington: Indiana University

    Press, 1994.

    Crowe. Heideggers Religious Origins: Destruction and Authenticity. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 2006.

    Guignon, Charles B., ed. The Cambridge Companion to Heidegger. 1st ed. New York:

    Cambridge University Press, 1993. Heidegger, Martin. Das Problem der Snde bei Luther. In Sachgemsse Exegese: Die

    Protokolle aus Rudolf Bultmanns Neutestamentlichen Seminaren 1921-1951, edited by Wilfried Hrle and Dieter Lhrmann, 2833. Marburg: N.G. Elwert Verlag, 1996.

    . Phnomenologie des Religisen Lebens. Vol. 60. Gesamtausgabe. Frankfurt: Vittorio

    Klostermann, 1995. Kisiel, Theodore. The Genesis of Heideggers Being and Time. Berkeley: University of

    California Press, 1995. Lohse, Bernhard. Martin Luther: An Introduction to His Life and Work. Translated by Robert

    Schultz. Philadelphia: Fortress Press, 1986. . Martin Luthers Theology: Its Historical and Systematic Development. Translated and

    edited by Roy Harrisville. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1999. Luther, Martin. The Blessed Sacrament of the Holy and True Body of Christ, and the

    Brotherhoods, 1519. edited by E. Theodore Bachmann, translated by Jeremiah Schindel, 35:4574. Luthers Works. Philadelphia: Muhlenberg Press, 1960.

    . The Freedom of a Christian. In Martin Luthers Basic Theological Writings, edited by

    Timothy E. Lull, 585629. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989. . Lectures on Galatians, 1519, Chapters 1-6. edited by Jaroslav Pelikan, translated by

    Richard Jungkuntz, 27:153410. Luthers Works. Saint Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1964.

    . Lectures on Galatians, 1535, Chapters 1-4. Translated and edited by Jaroslav Pelikan.

    Vol. 26. Luthers Works. Saint Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1963. . Lectures on Romans: Glosses and Scholia. Edited by Hilton C. Oswald. Vol. 25.

    Luthers Works. Saint Louis: Concordia Publishing House, 1972.

  • 18

    . The Sacrament of the Body and Blood of Christ-Againtst the Fanatics. In Martin

    Luthers Basic Theological Writings, edited by Timothy E. Lull. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989.

    . The Sacrament of Penance, 1519. translated and edited by E. Theodore Bachmann,

    35:322. Luthers Works. Philadelphia: Muhlenberg Press, 1960. . Sermon on Preparing to Die. In Martin Luthers Basic Theological Writings, edited by

    Timothy E. Lull, 63854. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 1989. Pelikan, Jaroslav. From Luther to Kierkegaard: A Study in the History of Theology. St. Louis,

    MO: Concordia Publishing House, 1950. Philipse, Herman. Heideggers Philosophy of Being: A Critical Introduction. Princeton, NJ:

    Princeton University Press, 1998. Pggler, Otto. Heideggers Luther-Lektre Im Freiburger Theologenkonvikt. In Heidegger und

    die Anfnge seines Denkens, edited by Alfred Denker, Hans-Helmuth Gander, and Holger Zaborowski, 1:185196. Heidegger-Jahrbuch. Mnchen: Karl Alber, 2004.

    Vessey, David. Heideggers Existential Domestication of Luther. In The Devils Whore:

    Reason and Philosophy in the Lutheran Tradition, edited by Jennifer Hockenbery Dragseth, 131139. Minneapolis: Fortress Press, 2011.