27
Review Article 387 CAPITALISM, LIBERALISM, AND SCHOOLING A discussion of Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, Schooling in Capitalist America (New York: Basic Books, 1976). DAVID HOGAN Historical analyses of the dynamics of educational change have for the most part assumed that ideological or political forces - whether progressive reformism or the imposition of social control - were the principal sources of educational change in America. 1 Other historians have assumed that the principal source of educational change was the profound and continuous effect of technological change upon the skill levels required of the labor force and the differentiation of the occupational structure; 2 occasionally these assumptions are explicitly acknowledged as derivatives of moderni- zation theory) With the publication of Schooling in Capitalist America, by Sam Bowles and Herb Gintis, we get an immensely important effort to provide an alternative conceptualization of the dynamics of educational change along Marxist lines, to lay bare, so to speak, the economic laws of motion of education in American capitalism. 4 The Functions of Capitalist Schooling The primary theoretical claim of Schooling is that the nature and func- tions of schooling cannot be understood apart from the matrix of economic life, specifically the dynamics of capitalism (pp. 224, 284). In Chapter Three ("At the Root of the Problem: The Capitalist Economy"), Bowles and Gintis therefore present a Marxist outline of the political economy of recent American capitalism. They stress in particular the control of the capitalist class over production or work - the "accumulation" process - institution- alized in various market and property relations (p. 57), and the historical processes through which this control was strengthened: the proletariani- zation of the labor force - the extension of the wage labor system to ever Educational Policy Studies, Universityof lllinois.

Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

Review Art icle

387

CAPITALISM, LIBERALISM, AND S C H O O L I N G

A discussion of Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis, Schooling in Capitalist America (New York: Basic Books, 1976).

DAVID HOGAN

Historical analyses of the dynamics of educational change have for the most part assumed that ideological or political forces - whether progressive reformism or the imposition of social control - were the principal sources of educational change in America. 1 Other historians have assumed that the principal source of educational change was the profound and continuous effect of technological change upon the skill levels required of the labor force and the differentiation of the occupational structure; 2 occasionally these assumptions are explicitly acknowledged as derivatives of moderni- zation theory) With the publication of Schooling in Capitalist America, by Sam Bowles and Herb Gintis, we get an immensely important effort to

provide an alternative conceptualization of the dynamics of educational change along Marxist lines, to lay bare, so to speak, the economic laws of motion of education in American capitalism. 4

The Functions of Capitalist Schooling

The primary theoretical claim of Schooling is that the nature and func- tions of schooling cannot be understood apart from the matrix of economic life, specifically the dynamics of capitalism (pp. 224, 284). In Chapter Three ("At the Root of the Problem: The Capitalist Economy"), Bowles and Gintis therefore present a Marxist outline of the political economy of recent American capitalism. They stress in particular the control of the capitalist class over production or work - the "accumulation" process - institution- alized in various market and property relations (p. 57), and the historical processes through which this control was strengthened: the proletariani- zation of the labor force - the extension of the wage labor system to ever

Educational Policy Studies, University of lllinois.

Page 2: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

388

larger portions of the labor force - and the extension of the hierarchical social division of labor. But because the accumulation process generated class conflict, the reproduction of the social relations of production, particularly the wage labor system necessary to the capitalist accumulation process has been contiuously threatened. It is this contradiction between accumulation and reproduction which is the basic dynamic of capitalism: the extension of the wage labor system and the maintenance of the hierarchical social division of labor "clashes with the objective of reproducing the social, political, and economic conditions for the perpetuation of capitalism as a system" (p. 279; see also pp. 203-4, 213-20. 271-81). During those critical junctures in American history when the process of capital accumulation was deepened or widened - in the 1830s and '40s with the emergence and consolidation of the factory system (Ch. 6), in the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries with the development of monopoly capitalism (Ch. 7), and in the 1960s with the expanded proletarianization of white-collar workers, their integration into the hierarchical division of labor, and the integration of blacks into the wage labor system (Ch. 8) - the class struggles attendant upon such transformations provoked capitalists and schoolmen to look to the schools as a means of resolving the conflict between labor and capital. That is, they looked to schools to eliminate threats to the reproduction of the social relations of production. Bowles and Gintis argue that each of these periods of acute social conflict was characterized by: 1) the extension and deepening of the process of capital accumulation and 2) a series of deliberate and conscious educational reforms to alleviate the class struggle between labor and capital. The 1830s and '40s were characterized by the common school movement, the 1890s and the first part of the twentieth century by the progressive movement, the 1960s by the Equal Opportunity Act, and the 1970s by the Carnegie Foundation's attempt to stratify further the system of higher education.

From this analysis of the dynamics of the capitalist economy, Bowles and Gintis derive the two "functions" of schooling in capitalist America: first, the reproduction of the labor power essential to the process of capital accu- mulation, and second, the reproduction of the social relations of production. The first function they define as the provision of students - future workers - with the "technical and cognitive skills required for adequate job perfor- mance" (p. 129). Included in these skills are also "those personal characteris- tics relevant to the staffing of positions" in the hierarchical social division of labor (pp. 130,11). The second function they define as the reproduction of those "institutions and social relationships which facilitate the translation of labor into profits" (pp. 129,11). This is apparently accomplished in two major ways: 1) the "education system legitimates economic inequality by

Page 3: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

389

providing an open, objective and ostensibly meritocratic mechanism for assigning individuals to unequal economic positions (pp. 103, 111, 114, 119, 123, 129-300); and 2) schooling reproduces those forms of "consciousness"

for example, with respect to the social relations of work, private owner- ship of the means of production, racism, sexism - that are conducive to the reproduction of the social order, including "the stratified consciousness on which the fragmentation of subordinate economic classes is based" (p. 130).

This formulation of the functions of schooling in capitalist America is inten- ded to explain the major causal relations between schooling and capitalism. This they do in Chapters Four and Five. They point out first that "although higher levels of schooling and economic success tend to go together, the intel- lectual abilities developed or certified in school make little causal contri- bution to getting ahead economically" (p. 110). The relationship between schooling and economic success, they argue, is not to be explained in terms of the cognitive skills that schooling imparts, but by the direct economic relationship among "four sets of noncognitive worker traits - work-related personality characteristics, modes of self preservation, racial, sexual and ethnic characteristics, and credentials" (p. 140) developed in schools. Schools in- culcate those "personality traits and forms of consciousness" necessary for successful job performance in the capitalist hierarchical social division of labor (pp. 94-100, 132-141). Schools are economically important to individual success because they socialize future workers into work habits that will successfully integrate students into the work place. Second, they argue that the level of income and the level of education achieved are principally determined, not by "intelligence," but by the familial socioecono- mic positions of the individual (pp. 30-36, 84-92). Moreover, while inequal- ity in the levels of schooling has declined, it is still substantially unequal and dependent "upon family background as much in the recent period as it did fifty years ago" (p. 33). Furthermore, income levels have not been equalized despite the reduction of inequality of educational attainment (p. 34). In short, the relationship between schooling and economic success is not meritocratic, nor a question of "luck" as Jencks suggested, but is systematically class based. Consequently, schools do not create inequality, but only reproduce existing inequalities in the economy (p. 248; pp. 11-12).

Finally, Bowles and Gintis provide an account of the mechanism through which these outcomes occur. Their argument centers upon the notion of "the correspondence principle," the claim that "the major aspects of edu- cational organization replicate the relationships of dominance and subordi- nancy in the economic sphere" (p. 125), specifically, that "the social rela- tions of education - the relationships between administrators and teachers,

Page 4: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

390

teachers and students, students and students, and students and their w o r k - replicate the hierarchical division of labor" (I 9. 131). Through the experience of schooling, students are socialized into the habits and personality traits appropriate for their later (alienated) work life in the hierarchical division of labor (pp. 131-141). Thus, on the basis of a correspondence between the

social relations of production and the social relations of education, Bowles

and Gintis assert the "ability of the educational system to produce an amen- able and fragmented labor force" (p. 125).

The analysis Bowles and Gintis provide of the functions of schooling has much to commend it. First, it thoroughly undermines liberal functionalist-meri-

tocratic explanations of the functions of schooling. Functionalists typi- cally view the school as a market system in which education links the supply and demand for talent: schools are institutions which select and sort people on the basis of ability and achievement. Moreover, the intergenerational transmission of inequality is (allegedly) weakened as educational achivement becomes the principal determinant of success and equality of opportunity is obtained: the educational market is then free of imperfections. Bowles and Gintis demonstrate, however, that the meritocratic assumption that the inter- generational transmission of inequality is weakening is false, that educational achievement is not based on IQ or "ability," and that the assumption that it is cognitive skills that are crucial to economic success is invalid. Second,

Bowles and Gintis for the most part avoid the conceptual traps that plague most analyses of the functions of schooling, whether by historians, econo-

mists, or sociologists. Thus they refrain from reducing their analysis of the functions of education to an analysis of the purposes or intentions of those who designed or control the school system. Such analyses are analyses of ideologies, and while they are absolutely crucial to understanding how it is schools came to be what they are, and in determining the extent to which schools actually fulfill their stated goals, by themselves analyses of intentions or purpose will not tell us what schools do. Likewise, the analysis of parti- cular educational outcomes - for instance, the unequal distribution of edu- cational attainment between different student groups - is not sufficient by

itself or in conjunction with analyses of the ideology of schooling to provide an analysis of the functions of schooling. An argument about the functions of schooling, whether in historical or systemic terms, is an attempt to articulate the nature of the systematic interrelations between different social institutions and processes. Such an account incorporates analyses of the outcomes and ideology of schooling within a general theory about the political economy or the social system; needless to say, such a theory need not be "functionalist. ''~

Page 5: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

391

Finally, Bowles and Gintis avoid the mistake of assuming that the analysis of

the control of schooling is an analysis of the functions of schooling, a major

trap of educational historians. The historiography of education is replete with debates about the "class" composition of school boards, the development of

educational bureaucracies, or the professionalization of teachers, as if these issues will unlock the door to our understanding of what schools do.7 But to

assume that analyzing the composition of school boards or boards of regents or the process of decision-making will establish the function of the educa- tional system is only to perpetrate what might be called a "nominalist fallacy." Such studies will perhaps tell us who nominally controlled schooling, with what purposes elites viewed schooling, how the demands for labor power and

control of class conflict emanating from the political economy were trans- lated into educational policy, and the relative importance of the bureau-

cracies relative to school boards. But they will not tell us what schools do, in

the sense of either their outcomes or their functions. This conceptual hiatus

in educational history is indicative not only of a desperate need to develop a theory of schooling that is cognizant of the instrumentalist-structuralist debate on the theory of power, 8 but also of the failure of educational histo-

rians - and others clearly to differentiate class analysis from the analysis

of inequality.

Unfortunately Bowles and Gintis do not always sustain this distinction. To argue, for instance, that schools differentially train and insert workers

into the social division of labor is to point to the fact that schools are in-

stitutional mechanisms that produce a differentiated labor force, a claim

that is not equivalent to the claim that schooling reproduces inequality.

To say, for instance, that schooling reproduces patterns of inequality, is to

claim that there is a close association between family socioeconomic status

and years and/or type of schooling completed. This claim may be more or

less true independent of the fact that the schools produce a wage labor force; the reproduction of inequalities is not the same thing as the repro- duction of classes, although they are in fact closely related. Likewise, to empha-

size the hierarchical nature of the division of labor is to forego what is distinc- tive about a Marxist analysis of the political economy, namely the analysis of

class relations and class formation. 9 While Bowles and Gintis provide us with a lengthy and valuable account of the nature and types of inequality in America (pp. 26-36 , 84-100), we do not get a comparable analysis of class formations nor a sufficient explication of class relations. It is not that there

are any objections in principle to studying patterns of inequality, whether political, economic, educational, or cultural - indeed it is a task of immense theoretical and political importance - but only that it be remembered that

Page 6: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

392

such analyses do not constitute what is the core of a Marxist analysis, the analysis of class relations and their reproduction through various mechanisms, political, economic, cultural, or educational.

It was this task, particularly the reproduction of the pivotal class relationship of capitalism, the wage-labor relationship, that was the center of Marx's own research. The main task Marx set himself in Capital was not to identify, pace

Mills, Domhoff, or Miliband, those who were wealthy or poor, powerful

or powerless. Rather, it was "to lay bare the economic law of motion" of

capitalist society - viz., the contradiction between accumulation and repro- duction - and the reproduction of class relations. Marx was interested in

explaining how wealth and poverty, domination and subjugation, were

reproduced over time. That is, he was not primarily interested in who was wealthy, or powerful, or mobile, or even in patterns of such inequalities over

time, but in the structure and reproduction of social relations that gave rise

to these inequalities. The inequalities were to be explained by class relations.

In doing so, he focused not on the rich, the wellborn, and the powerful, nor on the poor, the lowly born, and the powerless, but on capital, i.e., upon the

relations of production (the relation between capitalist and wage earner),

and their connection to the productive forces, to the state, and to ideology.

The reproduction of capitalist society required at heart the reproduction of

the capital relations: "on the one side the capitalist, on the other the wage laborer. ''1~ Accordingly, the historical study of capitalism must have as a

primary focus the reproduction of the capital-labor relationship, in particular,

the process of its reproduction at various levels - economic, political, educational, ideological. Instead of starting with such questions as "who rules?" or "who is wealthy?" or ' 'who is immobile?," the critical question is

the reproduction of the labor-capital relation: what institutions support it?

What role does the state, or education, play? How does this happen? How does the class system work? Perhaps no one has made the point clearer than E. P. Thompson in his critique of stratification theorists:

Sociologists who have stopped the time machine and, with a good deal of conceptual huffing and puffing, have gone to the engine room to look, tell us that nowhere at all have they been able to locate and classify a class. They can only find a multitude of people with different occu- pations, incomes, status-hierarchies, and the rest. Of course they are right, since class is not this or that part of the machine, but the way the machine works. Once it is set in motion - not this interest and that in- terest, but the friction of interests - the movement itself, the heat, the thundering noise. Class is a social and cultural formation (often finding institutional expression) which cannot be defined abstractly, or in iso-

Page 7: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

393

lation, but only in terms of relationship with other classes; and ultimately,

the definition can only be made in the medium of t i m e - that is, action

and reaction, change and conflict. When we speak of a class we are thinking

of a very loosely defined body of people who share the same congeries of interests, social experiences, traditions and value-system, who have a

disposition to behave as a class, to define themselves in their actions and

in their consciousness in relation to other groups of people in class ways.

But class itself is not a thing, it is a happening. 11

Bowles and Gintis have done much to provide a concrete picture of how American capitalism works, but, as I shall argue later, they fall short of what

is required.

Schooling Viewed Historically

What is to be said, then, of Bowles and Gintis' historical treatment of the

functions of schooling? Three major problems stand out: a failure to develop

an historical account of the functions of schooling over time; a failure to develop a sufficiently comprehensive theory of reproduction and contra-

diction; and a misleading account of educational politics in America.

In Chapters Six, Seven, and Eight, Bowles and Gintis provide an account of the school as a reproducer of the social relations of production, but not of

the function of the school as a producer of labor power. In effect they do not provide any evidence that would enable the reader to decide what in fact has

been the historical relationship between the two functions over time. Have they changed relative to one another? If so, when, why, under what condi- tions, and with what implications for their analysis? In other words, Bowles and

Gintis do not indicate whether in fact, and if so, in what manner, and for what reasons, there have been changes in the ways schools have functioned.

This is an important point, since the relationship between schooling and the

capitalist political economy that Bowles and Gintis describe was not born

full-grown at the time of the Industrial Revolution, but slowly evolved over time with changes in the accumulation process and the level of class conflict.

Before the Industrial Revolution, and even up the 1880s, almost the exclusive purpose of the public school system was to insert children into the ideolo-

gical - particularly political - practices of the society, what was called "citizenship," or "character training." Training for participation in the labor

force was of secondary importance. Again, universities up to this time were largely finishing schools for the upper-middle classes; it was not until the

Page 8: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

394

twentieth century that they gained their stranglehold on professional educa-

tion. Only gradually over time were the schools and then the universities inte-

grated into the economy as suppliers of differentiated labor power, and in-

creasingly subject to the central dynamic of capitalist society, the contra-

diction between accumulation and reproduction: it was only after the emer-

gence of monopoly capitalism that educators self consciously made serious efforts to integrate the schools into the wage labor system as a supplier of differentiated labor power. In effect, American mass education was first

established not so much for industrial as for political reasons under the im- pact of ideological pressures from Republicanism and Protestantism in a time of acute social disorder.

Bowles and Gintis do not then develop an historical analysis of the functions

of schooling, a consequence I think of their restricted view of the nature of the social structure and of an exaggerated view of the economic significance of the schools in the nineteenth century. While it is true that the nature of

the social structure in capitalism - the structure of class relations - is "deter-

mined" in some sense by the economic class relations of capital, this is not a justification for reducing the social structure to the social relations of

production, particularly in the nineteenth century when the hegemony of capitalist class relations was much less complete that it is now. It is this

restricted view of social structure that is the source of their misleading

formulation of the economic functions of schooling in the nineteenth cen- tury, and of their almost complete reliance on the correspondence principle

to carry the burden of their theory of reproduction. (Of which more later.)

The initial integration of the schools into the political economy during the

nineteenth century was thus not so much because schools were to function as an economic institution, but because they were designed to integrate children into the ensemble of class relations - political, economic, cultural - of nineteenth century American capitalism, and not just the social relations of productions. This suggests the necessity of distinguishing between the importance and effect of the contradiction between accumulation and reproduction in drawing schools into the political economy, on the one hand, and. the extent to which schooling itself was subject to the contradiction between accumulation and reproduction, on the other hand. Not only was the expansion of schooling in the early nineteenth century more an issue of political reproduction than of economic reproduction, but also it was not until the early twentieth century that the schools became important institu- tions supplying labor power and reproducing the social relations of production. Moreover, it was not until this time that the schools themselves exhibited the impact of the contradiction between accumulation and reproduction in the

Page 9: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

395

form of a conflict between the demand for differentiated vocationally based schooling (vocationalism) and the traditional emphasis upon citizenship in common schools) 2 It was only at this point that the accumulation pressures upon the school reached a level of such significance that they threatened to overwhelm the traditional political role of the school. Thus, while capitalists and some educators demanded the integration of public schooling into the wage labor system through the introduction of vocational and differentiated education, vocational guidance, the junior high school, and the testing move- ment, it was a fear that such programs might undermine the reproduction of the social relations of liberal capitalist society that led other progressive reformers to strenuously oppose such legislation as the Cooley Bill in Illinois, to support the principle of the comprehensive high school, extra-curricular activities, activity pedagogies, and to dictate the incorporation of vocation- alism into the ideology of citizenship, in part through redefining the meaning of citizenship, equality of opportunity, and democratic education .13

The Correspondence Principle

The second major problem with Bowles and Gintis' treatment of the functions of education centers upon their concept of the correspondence principle. The principal source of their difficulties here, however, derives not so much from its functionalist overtones, or that it is applied too mechanically, but that Bowles and Gintis place the whole weight of their theory of repro- duction upon it, a consequence as I suggested earlier, of an economistic con- ception of the social structure.

In attempting to explain how it is that schools carry out their functions, Bowles and Gintis suggest first that "the educational system helps integrate

youth into the economic system, we believe, through a structural corre- spondence between its social relations and those of production" (p. 131, emphasis added), that is, there is a forward linkage between the school and the economy through a correspondence of the social relations of production and education. And second, they posit a backward linkage to the social structure

via the family by positing a cultural correspondence between the institutions of work, family and school such that "the reproduction of consciousness is facilitated by a rough correspondence between the social relations of pro- duction and the social relations of family life," that, following Melvin Kohn, they explain as a consequence of "the experiences of parents in the social division of labor" (p. 143).

Page 10: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

396

In explaining the causal mechanisms or processes which create and sustain the correspondence between the social relations of education and production, Bowles and Gintis very carefully emphasize that "the independent internal dynamics of the two systems (work and schooling) present the ever-present possibility of a significant mismatch arising between economy and education" (p. 236), while yet insisting that the history of education is replete with the efforts of capitalists and reformers to create such a correspondence between the work place and the school, and that in general, and in the long run, through processes of "pluralist accommodation" (pp. 236-237) and "con- crete political struggle along the lines of class interest" (p. 238), a consider- able correspondence has been effected between the work place and the schools. The existence of lags or mismatches does not invalidate this argu- ment, for they can be seen simply as cases where the exceptions prove the rule. This is a powerful argument, marred only by their faulty and misleading

application of it to American educational politics. 14

If theft account of the political processes through which the correspondence between work and schooling is created is cogent and provocative, the ex- planation they provide of the educational mechanisms sustaining it is sug- gestive but inadequate. They stress that the mechanism sustaining the corre- spondence is the experience of schooling itself, specifically the form of the social relations of education:

The heart of the process is to be found not in the content of the educa- tional encounter - or the process of the information transfer - but in the form: the social relations of the educational encounter. These corres- pond closely to the social relations of dominance, subordination, and motivation in the economic sphere. Through the educational encounter, individuals are induced to accept the degree of powerlessness with which they will be faced as mature workers (p. 265).

This is much too exaggerated. While Bowles and Gintis present evidence of the statistical correspondence between the personal attributes required for success in work and in schools (pp. 131-141), the evidence is at the most only suggestive and requires considerable further research. But more impor- tantly, they neglect mechanisms other than the correspondence between the social relations of production and education. Other features of the education- al process besides the form of the social relations of education might also have been considered: Basil Bernstein, for instance, has argued that the form of the relations between curriculum, pedagogy, and evaluation (that is, the nature of the "classification" and "framing" of "educational transmissions") embody important ideological messages and are a critical part of the process

Page 11: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

397

of cultural reproduction of class relations. 15 Others have pointed out that the

content of the educational process - the "cultural capital" - is also a signi- ficant aspect of the cultural reproduction of class relations. 16 In effect, Bowles and Gintis, by limiting their analysis of reproduction to the corres- pondence between the form of the social relations of education and pro- duction, have a much too restricted theory of the reproduction of class relations through schooling.17

The second string of Bowles and Gintis' correspondence theory is an account of the cultural correspondence between the social relations of work, family life and education: experience of the social relations of work strongly affects the social relations of family life which in turn correspond to the social re- lations of education that the children of the families experience. Drawing

upon the work of Melvin Kohn, they describe the cultural correspondences in the 1960s between work and family life; they do not note, however, the considerable cultural conflicts between schools and families, particularly along class and ethnic lines; even more significantly, they do not develop an historical account of the complex cultural relationships and conflicts (again along class and ethnic lines) among work, schools, and families, is the cultu- ral process of class formation, 19 and the persistent efforts of educational reformers to destroy what they considered to be antagonistic working class cultures. 2o Finally, the explication of the relationship between family culture and school life would have been considerably strengthened by utilizing Bourdieu's theory of "cultural capital" and Bernstein's work on language and class. 21 In short, subsequent researchers need to develop a more comprehen- sive theory of the impact of the social structure on education, the reasons for differential educational achievement, and the conflicts and contradictions among work, families, and schooling.

Educational Pofitics in America

The inadequacies of Bowles and Gintis' theory of reproduction and contra- diction is perhaps both cause and effect of a profoundly erroneous appli- cation of their theory of educational politics to America educational history. I have already commented that some of the formal claims of this theory - specifically, that the control of the educational system tends to become an overt political issue, occasionally with distinctive overtones of class con- flict, in those periods characterized by a serious disjuncture between the schools and the economy, and that for the most part, the correspondence between work and schooling is maintained through a politics of pluralist accommodation within the context of a wage labor political economy - are

Page 12: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

398

extremely valuable. But in their application of the theory, they seriously misconceive the relationship between capitalism and liberalism, a fact of both theoretical and political significance since this deficiency seriously impairs the value of Schooling as a history of American education, its ability to function as a starting point for a Marxist research program in the history of education, and its effectiveness as a contribution to socialist political strategy. This failure has two aspects: first, an inaccurate characterization of liberal social theory and educational objectives, and second, a seriously mis- leading account of the politics and relationship between liberal educational objectives and (capitalist) educational practice.

In Chapter Two ("Broken Promises - School Reform in Retrospect"), Bowles and Gintis delineate two strands of liberal theory, "one represented by John Dewey and his followers - the 'democratic school' - and the other represented by functional sociology and neo-classical economics - the technocratic-meritocratic school" (p. 20). They argue that both strands of liberal thought are committed, albeit in different ways, to three common educational objectives: 1) the integration of the individual into society; 2) the provision of equal opportunity; and 3) the promotion of the "psychic

and moral development of the individual" (p. 21).

Their problems begin almost immediately. In delineating the two strands of liberal social theory, the "democratic" and the "technocratic-meritocratic," Bowles and Gintis present no evidence or argument that two such indepen- dent liberal traditions exist - they simply assert their existence. Moreover, technocratic-meritocratic propositions have been and are the theoretical core of liberal social theory, including the "democratic" tradition of Dewey et al. 22 Even more significant, however, is their mischaracterization of liberal

educational objectives. While it is true that there is much in the liberal tradi- tion that is historically progressive (e.g., natural rights, respect for individual freedoms, the scientific method, a concern with problems of equality), we are

not committed on this account to accept specific liberal educational ob- jectives, particularly if these objectives are in fact authoritarian, anti-demo-

cratic, and anti-equalitarian. The liberal educational objective of integration described by Bowles and Gintis glosses over the twin processes of sociali- zation and differentiation that liberal sociologists usually subsume under the rubric of "integration. ''23 Their characterization of the "egalitarian" purposes of schooling is even more problematic, not only for their failure to develop an historical account of the meritocratic ideology, ~4 but also for their failure to sustain a genuinely critical analysis of the meritocratic vision of American society itself. While every American high school student believes that "egalitarianism" means equal opportunity, it is surely a distortion of

Page 13: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

399

egalitarianism to view it merely as the provision of equal opportunity. (One is also confused by the claim of Bowles and Gintis that the liberal egalitarian purpose of schooling was "equalizing the vast extremes of wealth and

poverty" (p. 21), when immediately preceding this definition, they defined it in terms of equal opportunity. We can grant that liberals have wished - primarily out of a fear of socialism, not out of a commitment to equalitarian or socialist principles of distributive justice - to reduce the extremes of wealth and poverty, but they have never advocated the abolition of inequa- lity, whether of power, wealth, or income.) Nor have liberals advocated the abandonment of labor market or meritocratic principles of distributive justice, both of which are explicitly committed to inequality of result or condition, surely quite incompatible with the socialist view of "economic democracy" that Bowles and Gintis themselves propose (pp. 249, 264-67, 282-83). Liberals have viewed schooling as a mechanism only to make the chance to become unequal less unequal, to syphon off the top of the working class, and to legitimate the alleged meritocratic nature of inequality in Ameri-

can society. Liberalism in education has persistently and unwaveringly been committed to an unequal society, and to a system of unequal education with equal opportunity that will help reproduce an unequal society. Surely we do not need Richard Hermstein's meritocratic arguments to remind us of the fact that America is a liberal-capitalist political economy and not simply a

capitalist economy.

Problems arise, also, in Bowles and Gintis' treatment of the third liberal

objective of schooling, self-development. What is critical here is the nature of the liberal view of self-development, its pedagogical implications, and the connections, between the liberal self-development perspective and the socia- list "self-development" perspective that the authors develop in other parts of the book. A fuller explication of a socialist conception of "self-development" would have been useful, for example, a discussion of "the types of authority

relations governing activity" (p. 272) is in crying need of elaboration. More- over, I am not as sanguine as the authors about the compatibility of present forms of technology and the prospects of self-development (pp. 56, 69, 74, 77,271). But the main difficulty with their analysis of "self-development" is a misinterpretation of the liberal meaning of self-development, and a failure to consider the relationship between the liberal view of self-development and the nature of the principal pedagogical changes in the twentieth century. Re- lying heavily on Dewey, Bowles and Gintis characterize the liberal notion of self-development as "the acquisition of control over personal and social re- lationships" (p. 22). This was simply not Dewey's view of self-development, nor was it that of progressive liberals generally, although it may have been of classical liberalism. The essence of Dewey's view of self-development, and that

Page 14: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

400

of new liberals generally, was the socialization and integration of the indivi- dual into the values and technocratic needs of the organic, well-ordered community. 25 Schooling was not intended to develop the autonomy or self-direction of individuals in conjunction with others, but to ensure the creation of particular habits and internalized self-discipline, through progres- sive pedagogical practices and group pressures, in order to end social conflict, alienation, and disorganization.

Apart from their inaccurate interpretation of liberal social theory and liberal educational objectives, Bowles and Gintis proceed to argue that American educational history is characterized by a disjuncture between liberal educa- tional objectives and (capitalist) educational practice. Assuming that liberal educational objectives were not implemented by schools, and bewitched by the ostensible democratic character of the objectives, they proclaim that it would have been a "good idea" if liberal educational objectives had been "adopted by the school system" (pp. 44, 46, 49,180-181). But not only are they mistaken in their account of the nature of liberal educational objectives, they are grossly inaccurate in their analysis of the relationship between liberalism and capitalism in education. In fact, liberal objectives and capitalist practice were not antithetical; liberal objectives were adopted by schools; and indeed, the nature of American schooling is as much liberal as it is capita- list. To recognize this provides the basis for a more coherent and compre- hensive explanation of the mechanisms and processes of educational change and stability than that provided by Bowles and Gintis.

The argument of Bowles and Gintis may be put in a series of three propo- sitions. The first proposition is that the three liberal objectives of integration, egalitarianism, and self-development have proved to be incapable of ful- fiUment because of the overpowering demands of the capitalist political economy: "the failure of progressive educational reforms stems from the contradictory nature of the objectives of its integrative, egalitarian, and developmental functions in a society whose economic life is governed by the institutions of corporate capitalism" (p. 45; also pp. 43, 49, 181,191-92, 194-95,200).

The second proposition, a corollary to the first, is that it is the objectives of the capitalist economy that have prevailed in the education systems:

The contradictory nature of liberal educational reform objectives may be directly traced to the dual role imposed on education in the interests of profitability and stability; namely, enhancing workers' productive capaci- ties and perpetuating the social, political, and economic conditions for the

Page 15: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

401

transformation of the fruits of labor into capitalist profits. It is these overriding objectives of the capitalist class - not the ideals of liberal reformers - which have shaped the actuality of U.S. education and left little room for the school to facilitate the pursuit of equality or full human development (p. 49).

The third proposition is an explanation of how liberal ideals were undermined by capitalist school objectives. To do this, they adopt a variant of Callahan's vulnerability thesis: "In short, the history of twentieth century education is the history not of Progressivism but of the imposition upon the schools of 'business values' and social relationships reflecting the pyramid of authori- ty and privilege in the burgeoning capitalist system" (pp. 44, 147-48, 180-81,195,240).

With respect to the first and second claims, liberal educational objectives were not self-"contradictory" because of the overpowering demands of the capitalist political economy. Rather, they were highly consistent with the demands of the capitalist economy. Progressive liberal objectives "triumphed in educational theory" (p. 43), and they did so for the very reason noted earlier: viz, that liberal objectives were highly consistent with capitalist objectives. There is little in the historical record to warrant the juxtaposition of liberal and capitalist educational objectives.

The same holds true of educational practice. Two examples will make this clear. First, the development of the progressive "different but equal" notion of equal opportunity within schooling throughout the twentieth century was undertaken as much by progressive liberals, including John Dewey, as it was by capitalists - indeed, more so. The "different but equal" interpretation of the equal opportunity principle was formulated as an educational objective by liberal thinkers and put into effect by them. There was no conflict be- tween intentions and practice, for the institutional differential treatment of students was justified by progressive liberal educational objectives, based on a thorough redefinition of the nineteenth century meaning of equal opportu- nity as "a common and therefore equal education for all" to the liberal- capitalist meaning of "a different and therefore equal education for all." This was justified by liberals in terms of the "democratic" concern for the child's future occupational needs, and formulated into "different therefore equal" principles of educational treatment (pp. 191,209). The rationale for such programs was principally "social efficiency," the desire to equip stu- dents with the appropriate habits and skills necessary for their integration into the differentiated occupational structure. Ironically, Bowles and Gintis seem to realize this themselves, but only belatedly in the latter half of the

Page 16: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

402

book. Thus they acknowledge that "control, not liberation, is the word on the lips of our most influential leaders" (p. 227), and that "the essence of Progressivism in education was the rationalization of the process of repro- ducing the social classes of modern industrial life" (p. 199; see also p. 235). One could not agree more. Why, then, did Bowles and Gintis not recognize the contradiction between these judgments and their argument in Chapter Two? (Compare, for example, pp. 45 and 199.) It would be contradictory to argue, in Chapter Two, that liberal objectives were subverted by capitalist educational practice, while seemingly arguing in Chapters Six, Seven, Eight, and Nine, that liberal educational reforms were in fact institutionalized in practice. In fact, the logic of their own argument must force them to give up their misleading charcterization of liberal educational objectives, and to recognize the consistency of liberal objectives with capitalist educational objectives, as well as the consistency of liberal and capitalist educational practice.

A second example of the compatability of liberal educational objectives and "capitalist" educational practice is evident from the nature and rationale of changes in pedagogical practice in the twentieth century. Traditionally, based in part upon a view of the mind derived from faculty psychology, schools were viewed as institutions where children learned through precept the rudiments of basic literacy and citizenship. By the turn of the century, compulsory attendance laws (initiated by progressive liberals) were bringing into the schools scores of immigrant and other working class children. By 1919, when the Cardinal Principles were published, the schools had adopted a new rationale and a new pedagogy. "Education for life adjustment" became the official expression of the social efficiency ideology that emphasized the needs and interests of the child on the one hand, and the commercial or in. dustrial interests of the nation and the need for social order, on the other. These two stands were not, however, believed to be inconsistent with each other, since the needs and interests of the child were viewed in terms of the industrial interests and social needs of the country. There was no substan- tive dichotomy between the needs and interests of the child and the needs and interests of the nation. At the same time, a number of psychological theorists undermined faculty psychology and the importance of intellectual understanding, and stressed the preeminence of the irrational and the emotive, particularly in the working class, the poor, and the blacks. In this context public schools were increasingly, and by 1919 officially, viewed by educators as institutions where children acquired habits of behavior and self- discipline through pedagogical practices that emphasized the "learn by doing rather than precept" that would fit them for their life's work as members of the "industrial army" and as loyal, contented citizens in the body politic. Of

Page 17: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

403

course, some children, particularly those of the upper middle class and elites

continued to receive a thorough intellectual education in private prep schools or in college preparatory tracks in public high schools. But the working class child engaged in various curricular and extra-curricular activities in order to develop habitual responses and accommodations to given contexts that prefigured his future roles in the economy and the polity. The pedagogy of "learn by doing" and "education for life," as expressed in the kindergarten movement, the play movement, extra-curricular activities (student clubs, student councils, athletics, music clubs) and in vocational education aimed at the internalization and adoption of forms of behavior through the con- trol and regulation of habituation processes that integrate schools into the social division of labor and ensure the stability of the social order. Education-

alists, in other words, did not develop a pedagogy, an educational practice, in any way opposed in design or execution to the needs of the economy and social control. 26

If all these points are valid, then it follows quite naturally that the vulner- ability thesis is absurd. Progressives and liberals were not overpowered by capitalists. Sometimes they were willing, deliberate partners in a common enterprise. At the very least, they were two groups who often shared parallel and consistent views and expectations about the purposes of schooling. Con- sequently, it is not the case that "the educational elite has not been able to mount an independent and sustained movement for overall reform" (p. 240),

for the simple reason that they succeeded very much in doing so. If "liberal professionals and enlightened school reformers" were "the essential media- tors" between liberalism and capitalism, it was not to effect a "compromise" between the two, but rather to oversee a very comfortable and happy mar- riage.

Yet despite these limitations, their insistence on class conflict (rooted in the accumulation-reproduction nexus) as the centerpiece of a general inter- pretation of the dynamics of educational change is a provocative, persuasive challenge to liberal and revisionist interpretations of the history of American

education (pp. 129, 148, 175 ,228-9 , 239-40). Both their substantive his- torical claims and their methodological injunctions directly undermine the consensus assumptions of liberal historiography. But they are also a challenge to the "social control" or "revisionist" historians (Karier, Violas, Lazerson, Spring) who have tended to emphasize class domination, rather than class conflict, by focusing on the ideologies, programs, and activities of elites in education. One can have little quarrel with the "social control" revisionists' claim that elites have dominated educational reform and policy, but this is not to say that their domination has been unlimited nor uncontested. Clearly

Page 18: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

404

it seems reasonable to interpret compulsory education as an attempt to use the coercive power of the state as a means of establishing broad hegemonic control of the social order through the insertion of children into the ensemble

of capitalist social relations. And the same can be said of the development of

"industrial intelligence" - specific forms or habits of behavior required for

proper job performance and industrial peace - in vocational education

programs or career education currently; these programs were and are efforts

designed to socialize students into acceptance of the social relations of pro-

duction. But such explanations need to avoid the trap of viewing these efforts

as a process of dissemination downwards from the upper classes to the

working class of the ruling class ideology, or as a process of embourgeoisment.

Rather, they should be understood as deliberate processes through which

elites desired to integrate an often intractable and hostile working class into

the ensemble of social relations of liberal-capitalist society.

Not only must the efforts of the hegemonic classes to ensure the repro-

duction of capitalist social relations be studied, but also the various forms of resistance, passive or active, of the working class. Despite the efforts of the

hegemonic classes to incorporate subordinate classes into a particular set of legitimating social practices, the social experience of the subordinate classes was such that it generated counterhegemonic practices and ideologies. This process was enhanced by virtue of the existance of what Raymond Williams has called "residual cultures," such that "some experiences, meanings and

values which cannot be verified or cannot be expressed in the terms of the dominant culture are . . . lived and practiced on the basis of the residue - cultural as well as social - of some previous social formation. ''27 The

exemplary, indeed paradigmatic, analysis of one such residual culture is E. P. Thompson's brilliant account of the making of the English working

class, specifically his analysis of the importance of historical artisan political

cultures within the process of class formation. 28 Similar research on working

class culture has recently commenced in America, but very little research on

the educational "mentalities" of the American working class has been under- taken. 29 It is clear, for instance, that in Chicago after 1880 the craftsmen's

producer ideology played an important role in the resistance of the Chicago labor movement to the efforts of educational elites to create a differentiated educational system in Chicago; likewise, it was basic to the unionist support for compulsory education as a means of securing an alternative political economy to the one developing in Chicago after 1880. It was not a merito- cratic vision of capitalism that unionists upheld, but a republican democracy, a commonwealth of independent producers and equal citizens in which un- American class distinctions and conflicts would have no place and the promise of the Declaration of Independence fulfilled. For John Walker, president of

Page 19: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

405

the Illinois State Federation of Labor in 1924, compulsory education was

necessary if the children of workingmen "are to be efficient, self respecting

citizens of a great country . . . . if they are not to be oppressed by avaricious

exploiters, they must not be slaves to ignorance. If they are to be flee, they must have knowledge." For Thomas Morgan, a leading socialist union leader

and educational activist, education was the "citadel of our national life, the foundation of the republic, the necessary base of the whole structure of

American society," enabling "future generations of Americans [to] think

and act as the Revolutionists had, and be ready and competent as men to rule

and govern themselves and to successfully resist all class rulership from

within and without and thereby preserve and develop the republican institu- tions which independent thought and manly courage had established." And

for Victor Olander, secretary-treasurer of the I.S.F.L. and chief antagonist of

the Cooley Bill and the "unholy trinity" - the junior high school, the testing

movement, and the platoon system - these developments represented a violation of the "meaning of the Declaration of Independence" with respect to

"what it means to the equality of men" and to "the meaning of the Constitu- tion." Clearly, while both the hegemonic classes and the working class desired "education for citizenship," their conceptions of citizenship were entirely different. 3~

In the same manner, traditional ethnic cultures were a source of counter-

hegemonic beliefs (cultural pluralism) and practices (e.g., Ihmify leisure and

educational behavior) among the immigrant working class. These practices

and beliefs were the subject of direct attacks by Americanizers, prohibitionists,

and compulsory education reformers, but the attendance of immigrant children at school, and indeed their demand for schooling, even for vocational

education, was not so much a victory for "ideological hegemony" as Michael Katz recently claimed, al but principally (apart from the compulsory edu- cation laws) the belief among working class people that in a wage labor society and the increasing importance of educational credentials in the division of labor, education was the key to economic survival. Immigrant acceptance of education then was very much a consequence of the immi- grants' perception of their class position in a class society: it was structurally, not ideologically, imposed. Within the limits imposed by poverty and the

struggle to survive, both unskilled immigrants and skilled workers increasingly

sent their children to school as a means of enhancing the value of their children's labor power in the labor market. And as a consequence, they were deeply embroiled in conflicts over the cultural content of schooling. 32

The existence of such oppositional visions of citizenship and cultural conflicts over the content of schooling suggests the imperative need for extensive

Page 20: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

406

studies of overt and covert forms of class conflict over the structure and content of education, of what Bourdieu calls conflicting class "strategies of reproduction. ''33 With such studies we will be in a much better position to develop an adequate theory politics, and the manner in which contradictions have been mediated by liberal reformers.

Strategies of Change

Part IV of Schooling is called "Getting There." For the most part, this is an analysis of a "socialist strategy for education." The logic of their argument proceeds thus: The two structural features of the political economy which fundamentally determine the possibilities and shape the nature of a socialist political strategy in America are the inherent contradiction between accumu- lation and reproduction in capitalist economies, and the fundamental corres- pondence between schooling and the work place. Given these two conditions, one providing the possiblility of structural changes in the political economy, the other seriously limiting the extent and scope of changes in the school system until changes occur in the economy, Bowles and Gintis propose a strategy that has two aspects: first, the politicization and delegitimation of inequalities, and second, the formation of alliances and the creation of revolu- tionary reforms.

The authors argue for the structural possibility of radical social change in terms of what they perceive as "a basic contradiction in the capitalist so- ciety," namely, that "while capitalism vigorously promotes the development of production, its basic social institutions are not geared to translating this development into balanced social development for fostering general human fulfillment and growth" (p. 275). That is, a fundamental conflict between "accumulation and reproduction" (p. 279) exist at the core American society. This contradiction has two important manifestations that bear on the poss~ility (though not the inevitability) of radical social change.

First, Bowles and Gintis assert that there is an "ever widening gulf between human needs - what people want - and the imperatives of further capitalist expansion and production" (p. 277), without providing convincing evidence of what it is that people want. Nor do they show that even if in fact people wanted what Bowles and Gintis believe them to, this is necessarily or po- tentially revolutionary. Their evidence on worker dissatisfaction is ambiguous (pp. 71, 79) both with respect to what people want and whether worker dis- satisfaction is important enough in the constellation of workers' perceived needs to be revolutionary. I know of no evidence, and Bowles and Gintis pro- vide none, that "most people are all too well aware of the fact of their

Page 21: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

407

oppression" (p. 285). People are certainly aware of particular annoyances or dissatisfactions in their lives, but whether they are slightly or even deeply felt does not constitute a consciousness of oppression. For this to happen, such dissatisfactions (whether work related, the cost of groceries, busing, pollution, the level of taxes, or sex discrimination) have to be politicized before they can become "forms of oppression" in the consciousness of people who experience these dissatisfactions. And surely it is a major task of socialists to politicize these issues; to simply assume that people are "all too well aware of

the fact of their oppression" is plain fantasy.

A second manifestation of the contradiction at the core of capitalist society is the emergence of a series of social conditions and conflicts that increasing- ly limit the capacity of capitalism to reproduce itself, both institutionally and in terms of its legitimation (pp. 279-81). Of particular importance here

is a contradiction between schooling and work based on the rapid upgrading of educational requirements (as described by I. Berg) of jobs that fail to pro-

vide high levels of job satisfaction commensurate with the skills and expecta- tions of highly trained people. At the same time that the demand for more schooling increases, the number of desirable jobs decreases. This aspiration- frustration contradiction creates a problem of legitimation within society. Un-

less, however, the criteria of contradiction are clearly spelled out, it could be alternatively argued that this situation is one simply of non-correspon- dence rather than contradiction, or that the oversupply of educated workers

relative to satisfying jobs is only the creation of a reserve army.

The second main feature of their political analysis centers on the impli- cations of the correspondence principle for socialist political strategy. They argue that because of the basic correspondence between schooling and the economy, such reforms as free schools and deschooling - and presumably community control - cannot hope to accomplish the creation of a truly liberating and humane education without revolutionary changes in the social relations of production. That is, the success of any radical reforms in school- ing depends in the last analysis upon radical changes in the work place. They

thus enjoin advocates of free schooling and deschooling to develop an aware- ness of the structural or class role that free schools play in present capitalist society, and of the need to develop a consciousness that does not look backward to the restoration of the lost world of middle-class professional privileges. Deschooling as a radical strategy of social change, they very con- vincingly argue, "is no more than whistling in the dark" (p. 262). Free schoolers need to politicize and integrate the free school movements into a general socialist movement for "a participatory and egalitarian workers' de- mocracy" (p. 255). Changes in the role of schooling in capitalist America ulti-

Page 22: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

408

mately require overcoming the correspondence between schooling and work by cutting the nexus between wage labor and schooling.

While the authors emphasize the limitations that the correspondence principle places upon the ultimate effectiveness of reforms, they strongly support any non-reformist, i.e., revolutionary, reforms (pp. 283-88) that are possible. For a book so obviously political in intent, however, the discussion of strategies of changes and guidelines to action is much too brief, a4 Little attention is given to delineating the criteria of reformist and non-reformist reforms, and for those inside the school system, like teachers and students, they provide almost no guidelines as to how they might alter, presumably within the limits of the correspondence principle, the process, pedagogy, or social relations of education in "revolutionary reformist" ways. Moreover, while there is politi- cal value, perhaps, in utilizing liberal rhetoric to gain access to liberals and to integrate them into movements for (revolutionary) reformist reforms, it is crucial that the substance of such liberal ideals as "equality" or "self-develop- ment" be Spelled out in socialist terms (as in, for example, pp. 264-67, 282-83,265-74) , that it not be blithely presupposed that the liberal and so- cialist explications of these ideals are compatible, let alone identical, and that a clear distinction between liberal-meritocratic and Marxist analytical frameworks and political alliances be maintained. Simply to ignore a distinc- tion between a liberal problematic and Marxist problematic out of a desire to create political alliance with "democratic liberals" undermines the pos- sibility of creating a theory about the operation of the political economy and appropriate strategies to change it. As capitalist practice flourishes amidst liberal consciousness, so too liberal theory nourishes capitalist praxis.

Finally, since a Marxist analysis should aim at indicating alliances that would work toward the elimination of class society (revolutionary reforms are obviously crucial here) and not just certain types of inequality, the absence of any analysis of the class structure and of the possibilities of different class formations and political alliances to achieve radical changes in the social order is a serious political deficiency.

Condu~on

Clearly, Schooling in Capitalist America is not without its limitations. It is charcterized by an ahistorical treatment of the functions of education, an economistic conception of social structure, an inadequate theory of repro- duction and contradiction, and a seriously inaccurate account of educational politics. Yet despite its problems, Schooling is a very important and valuable

Page 23: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

409

work. Bowles and Gintis are particularly successful in developing an effective critique of the liberal political economy of education, and a conceptuali- zation of a broad theory of the dynamics of educational change that con- founds all previous accounts, whether liberal or revisionist. Schooling in Capitalist America is therefore a valuable, if flawed, starting point for a Marxist research program into the history and political economy of educa- tion. Its contributions to that research program are significant, and its diffi- culties instructive. While Schooling therefore is not all that one could wish for, it is a significant and provocative beginning. Moreover it is model of engaged and committed scholarship that provides some understanding of what is required for the collective control of the future.

NO TES

1. See, for example, E. Cubberley, Public Education in the U.S. (Boston: Houghton- Mifflin, 1934); L. Cremin, The Transformation of the School (New York. Vintage Books, 1961); M. Katz, "The Origins of Public Education. A Reassessment," History of Education Quarterly, 16(4), 1976; C. Karier, P. Violas, J. Spring, Roots of Crisis (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1973); P. Violas, The Training of the Urban Working Class (Chicago: Rand McNally, 1978); M. Lazerson, Origins of the Urban School (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971).

2. See E. Cubberley, Changing Conceptions of Education (Cambridge: Harvard Uni- versity Press, 1909), 18-19, 53-57; D.C. North, "Capital Formation in the United States During in the Early Period of Industrialization: A Reexamination of the Issues," in R.W. Fogel and S.L. Engerman (eds.), The Reinterpretation of American Economic History (New York: Harper & Row, 1971), 277; H.J. Habbakuk,Ameri- can and British Technology in the Nineteenth Century (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962), 25; J.R. Bright, "The Relationship of Increasing Auto- mation and Skill Requirements in the Employment Impact of Technological Change," National Commission on Technology, Automation, and Economic Pro- gress (Washington, D.C.: Government Printing Office, 1966), Vol. II, 207; M. Trow, "The Second Transformation of American Secondary Education," in R. Bendix and S.M. Lipsett, Class, Status and Power (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1967), 438. Additional statements of these arguments appear in B. Clark, Educating the Expert Society (San Francisco: Chandler, 1962); C. Kerr, J. Dunlop, F. Harbi- son, and C. Myers, Industrialism and Industrial Man (Cambridge: Harvard Univer- sity Press, 1960); W.L. Warner, R.J. Havinghurst, M.B. Loeb, Who Shall be Educat- ed? (New York: Harper & Bros., 1944), Ch. 2; D. Adams, Schooling and Social Change in Modern America (New York: McKay, 1972), Chs. 1, 5. For a critique, see R. Collins, "Functional and Conflict Theories of Educational Stratification," in B.R. Cosin, Education Structure and Society (Baltimore: Penguin Books, 1972).

3. See for example M. Hatz, The People of Hamilton, Canada West (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1975), 5-6 , 7, 18-19, 45, 47.

4. See also S. Bowles, "Unequal Education and the Reproduction of the Social Divi- sion of Labor," Review of Radical Political Economy, 3(4), 1971; S. Bowles and H. Gintis, "IQ in the US Class Structure," Social Policy, Nov.-Dec./ Jan.-Feb. 1972-1973.

5. A number of important issues will not be pursued in this essay. First, Bowles and Gintis fail to describe adequately the relationship between reproduction and

Page 24: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

410

7.

legitimation. Thus, for example, they overstate that relationship when they argue that education reproduces inequality because of its meritocratic ideology (p. 123), when it is clear from other parts of their book that schooling is an institution that materially reproduces the labor power necessary for adequate job performance, and differentially integrates workers into different levels of the social division of la- bor through such devices as vocational education (pp. 191-95), testing and track- ing (pp. 195-98), and a differentiated system of higher education (Ch. 8). That is, schooling operates as an institutional mechanism to reproduce inequality, as well as to legitimate it. For this reason, their argument that educational credentials are merely legitimation devices (p. 202) ignores the importance of credentials as a deter- minant of the supply and demand of workers. Credentials are not only a certifi- cation of the workers charcteristics relevant to worker productivity but also a means of regulating the size of the reserve army, i.e., the supply of labor. The "great training robbery" and the custodial role of schooling since the 1920s of removing adolescents from the labor market in "disaecumulationist" capitalism cannot be ignored in a comprehensive formulation of the functions of schooling. See E.A. Krug, The Shaping of the American High School, Vol. Two (Madison: University of Wisconsin Press, 1972); I. Berg, Education and Jobs: The Great Training Robbery (Boston: Beacon Press, 1971). See also R.B. Carson, "Youth- ful Labor Surplus in Disaccumulationist Capitalism," Socialist Revolution, Vol. 9 (1972), pp. 15-44. Second, from the point of view of systematic Marxist theory, the formulation of the functions of schooling raises an interesting theoretical pro- blem. Insofar as schooling reproduces labor power, is schooling to be viewed as a part of the forces of production (i.e., the base)? Or, insofar as schooling legi- timates inequality and reproduces a consciousness compatible with the capitalist social relations of production (i.e., as an institution of the ideological network), is it a part of the superstructure? And if schooling is a part of the base, in what sense does it involve the direct appropriation of children's labor power and of surplus value? It is clear that attention to this problem could throw some light on marxian political economy of schooling and on marxist theory in general, by attempting clearer formulations of the meaning of "reproduction" and of the relationship of the base and the superstructure. D. Cohen and B. Rosenberg, "Functions and Fantasies: Understanding Schools in Capitalist America," History of Education Quarterly, 17(2), Summer 1977, fails to grasp this point. On the other hand, Sherry Gorelick, "Undermining Hierarchy: Problems of Schooling in Capitalist America," Monthly Review, October 1977, pp. 20-36, argues that Bowles and Gintis have failed to adequately extract them- selves from a functionalist conceptualization of the relationship between schooling and the economy. For an excellent discussion of the conceptual and epistemological issues involved in functionalist theories, see R. Keat and J. Urry, Social Theory as Science (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975), esp. Ch. 5. See also D.H.J. Morgan, Social Theory and the Family (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975), Ch. 1. See for example R.E. Callahan, Education and the Cult of Efficiency (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1962); W.A. Bullough, Oties and Schools in the Gilded Age (Port Washington, N.Y.: Kennikat Press, 1974); M. Katz, Class, Bureaucracy and Schools (New York: Praeger Publishers, 1971); C.F. Kaestle, The Evolution of an Urban School System (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1973); J. Cronin, The Control of Urban Schools (New York: The Free Press, 1973); D. Rabitch, The Great School Wars, New York Oty, 1805-1973 (New York: Basic Books, 1974); D. Tyack, The One Best System: A History of American Urban Education (Cam- bridge: Harvard University Press, 1974); G.E. Counts, "The Social Composition of Boards of Education: A Study in the Social Control of Public Education," Supple- mentary Educational Monographs, July 1927; Harvard Educational Review, "Special

Page 25: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

411

Issue: Social Class Structure and American Education," 23(4), Fall 1953. 8. For reviews of the instrumentalist-structuralist debate, see D.A. Gold, C.Y.H. Lo,

and E. Wright, "Recent Developments in Marxist Theories of the State," Monthly Review (October and November, 1975); G. Therborn, "What Does the Ruling Class do When it Rules? Some Reflections on Different Approaches to the Study of Power in Society," Insurgent Sociologist, 6(3), 1976. See also N. Poulantzas, "The Power of the Capitalist State," New Left Review, 59 (1969), and his Political Power and Social Classes (London: New Left Books, 1973); and Amy Beth Bridge's excellent critique of Poulantzas, "Nicos Poulantzas and the Marxist Theory of the State," Politics and Society, Winter 1974.

9. See Gorelick, pp. 28-33 , for further elaboration of this point. 10. K. Marx, Capital (New York: International Publishers, 1967), I, p. 578. 11. E.P. Thompson, "The Peculiarities of the English," Socialist Register, 1965, p. 357.

(Emphasis in the original.) 12. In this connection it is worth noting that Bowles and Gintis do not provide clear

criteria that would enable the historian to know a contradiction when he sees one: when, for instance, is a conflict a contradiction and not simply a conflict? A useful analysis of contradiction can be found in Michael Carter's essay.

13. See Violas, The Training of the Urban Working Class, Ch. 6; D. Hogan, "Capitalism and Schooling: A History of the Political Economy of Education in Chicago 1880- 1930," unpublished Ph.D. dissertation, University of Illinois, 1978, Ch. 7. It would be interesting to assess whether this shift to vocationalism can be interpreted as a shift from what Basil Bernstein calls "collection codes" to "integration codes." See his Class Codes and Control, Vol. III (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975), 90-111. There is also a sense in which the clash between the "instrumental order" and the "expressive order" that Bernstein describes parallels the clash between vocationalism and citizenship. Unfortunately Bernstein's approach is not historical, although in the revised edition of Volume III of Class Codes and Control (1977) he offers an analytic framework centering around the concepts of education and production codes that might prove useful to an analysis of the changing relation- ship between the school and the economy.

14. The nature and extent of the autonomy of the educational system has been discussed by Pierre Bourdieu and Jean Claude Passeron, Reproduction: In Education, Society and Odture (Beverly Hills, CA: Sage, 1977), especially pp. 195-198. This question is of course concerned with the relationship between base and superstructure. For an excellent recent theoretical discussion, see R. Williams, Marxism and Literature (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1977), 75-114.

15. See Bernstein, Class Codes and Control, Vol. III; R. Sharp and A. Green, Education and Social Control (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1975).

16. Ibid. See also Boudieu and Passeron, Reproduction; Bourdieu, "Cultural Repro- duction and Social Reproduction," in J. Karabel and A.H. Halsey, Power and Ideo- logy in Education (New York: Oxford University Press, 1977), pp. 487-511; M. Apple, "The Hidden Curriculum and the Nature of Conflict," Interchange, 2(4), 1971, 27-40 ; D. Sallach, "Class Domination and Ideological Hegemony," The Sociological Quarterly, 51, Winter 1974; H. Zeigler and W. Peak, "The Political Functions of the Educational System," Sociology of Education, 43, Spring 1970, 129-142; Violas, Training of the Urban Working Class, Chs. 4, 5, 7; Hogan, "Capitalism and Schooling," Chs. 7, 8.

17. See above footnotes 4 and 5; the "Introduction" by Karabel and Halsey in their Power and Ideology in Education, pp. 1-85; and M. Apple and P. Wexler, "Cul- tural Capital and Educational Transmissions," Educational Theory, 28(1), Winter 1978, 34-43 .

18. See for example H. Gutman, "Work, Culture and Society in Industrializing Ameri- ca, 1815-1919,"American HistoricalReview, 78, June 1973; A. Dawley, Classand

Page 26: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

412

Community. The Industrial Revolution in Lynn (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1976); B. Laurie, "Nothing on Compulsion: Life Styles of Philadelphia Artisans, 1820-1850," Labor History, 15(3), Summer 1974; P. Faler, "Cultural Aspects of the Industrial Revolution: Lynn, Massachusetts, Shoemakers and In- dustrial Morality, 1826-1860," Labor History, 15(3), Summer 1974; Christopher Lasch, Haven in a Heartless World (New York, Basic Books, 1977); N. Cott, The Bonds of Womanhood: Women's Sphere in New England 1780-1835 (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1977); D. Miller and G. Swanson, The Changing American Parent (New York: John Wiley, 1958); M. Zuckerman, "Dr. Spock: The Confi- dence Man," in C. Rosenberg (ed.), The Family in History (Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1975); J. Seeley, R.A. Sun, E.W. Loosley, Crestwood Heights (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1956); and Gorelick, pp. 25-27.

19. See for example E.P. Thompson, The Making of the English Working Class (Lon- don: Victor Gollancz, 1963).

20. Violas, Training the Urban Working Class, Chs. 2, 3; Hogan, "Schooling and Capita- lism," Chs. 4, 5, 6.

21. See B. Bernstein, "Social Class and Linguistic Development: A Theory of Social Learning," in A.H. Halsey et al., Education, Economy and Society (New York: Free Press, 1961), pp. 288-314; Bernstein, Class Codes and Control, Vol. I (Lon- don: Paladin, 1973); Bernstein, "Class and Pedagogies: Visible and Invisible," in Karabel and Halsey, Power and Ideology in Education, pp. 511--534; Sharp and Green, Education and Social Control; Bordieu, Reproduction; Karabel and Halsey, "Introduction," pp. 52-71 .

22. See for example C.B. MacPherson, Democratic Theory (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1973), especially Essays IV and XI. See also P. Bachrach, The Theory of Demo- cratic Elitism (Boston: Little, Brown & Co., 1967); H. Croly,ProgressiveDemocra- cy (New York: Macmillan, 1914); and D. Hogan and C.J. Karier, "Democracy as Organic Community," unpublished paper, University of Illinois.

23. For example, see T. Parsons, "The School Class as a Social System: Some of its Functions in American Society," in A.H. Halsey, J. Floud, C.A. Anderson, Edu- cation, Economy and Society (New York: Free Press, 1961), p. 31. Bowles and Gintis also overlook the fact that from the perspective of Marxist theory, the theo- ry of integration is essentially a liberal description of the process of cultural and ideological hegemony or reproduction.

24. Rather than treating, as Bowles and Gintis do in Chapter Four, the meritocratic ideology as a set of hypocricies perpetuated by elites, it would have been much more useful to provide an historical explication of the meritocratic ideology in terms of its conditions of production and reproduction, including: a) the exten- sion of the wage labor system which eliminated ascriptive and particularistic forms of social differentiation; b) the creation of the hierarchical division of labor, the character of the class structure and mechanisms of integration into it; c) the extent and nature of class conflicts; and d) the formulation, by liberal social scientists, of the basic premises of meritocratic theory (including, incidentally, the central pro- positions not only of the theory of human capital and the functionalist theory of stratification, but also of the theory of democratic elitism - Goddard, Thorndike, Terman, as well as Lippmann, LassweU, Schumpeter - interest group pluralism, for example, Dahl on the control of schooling in New Haven, the marginal producti- vity of labor theory of income determination, and the consensus theory of social order.

25. See Hogan and Karier, "Democracy as Organic Community." 26. My analysis of the nature of twentieth century pedagogy relies heavily on the work

of Paul Violas and my own research of pedagogical practices in Chicago. 27. R. Williams, "Base and Superstructure in Marxist Cultural Theory," New Left

Review, 82 (1973), 10.

Page 27: Capitalism, liberalism, and schooling

413

28. Thompson, Making. 29. For the most part, even these efforts have simply looked at the educational beha-

vior of different immigrant groups without analyzing either associated behavior (home ownership, child labor) or the cultural process of class formation. See for example D.K. Cohen, "Immigrants and the Schools," Review of Educational Re- search, 40, Feb. 1970, 13-27; C. Greer, The Great School Legend (New York: Basic Books, 1972), Chs. 6,7; M. R. Olneck and M. Lazerson, "The School Achieve- ment of Immigrant Children, 1900-1930," History o f Education Quarterly, XIV,. Winter 1974, pp. 453-464; T. Smith, "Immigrant Social Aspirations and American Education, 1880-1930," American Quarterly, XXI, Fall 1969, 523-543. For the two efforts that go beyond these studies, see I. Bodnar, "Materialism and Morality: Slavic-American Immigrants and Education, 1890-1940," Journal of Ethnic Studies, 3(4), Winter 1976; and D. Hogan, "Education and the Making of the Chicago Working Class," History o f Education Quarterly, forthcoming, and "Capitalism and Schooling," Ch. 9

30. These quotes are all taken from my "Capitalism and Schooling," Ch. 10. 31. See Katz, "The Origins of Public Education." 32. Hogan, "Capitalism and Schooling," Ch. 9; "Education and the Making of the

Chicago Working Class." 33. See Bourdieu, Reproduction; and E. Dunkheim, The Evolution o f Educational

Thought (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1977). 34. For a fuller discussion of socialist strategy, see Martin Carnoy and Henry Levin,

The Limits o f Educational Reform (New York: David McKay, 1976).

Acknowledgment

In the preparation o f this essay, I have benefited from the advice o f Sam

Bowles, Walter Feinberg, Herb Gintis, Bob Halstead, Jerry Karabel, Clarence

Karier, Ira Katznelson, Ralph Page, Jerry Selig, and Paul Violas.

Theory and Society 8 (1979) 387-413 �9 Elsevier Scientific Publishing Company, Amsterdam - Printed in the Netherlands