29
Common Knowledge: The Math

Common Knowledge: The Math

  • Upload
    milton

  • View
    35

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Common Knowledge: The Math. We need a way to talk about “private information” . We will use an information structure < Ω , π 1 , π 2 , μ > . Ω is the (finite) set of “states” of the world ω  Ω is a possible state of the world E ⊆ Ω is an event Examples: - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Common Knowledge: The Math

Page 2: Common Knowledge:  The Math

We need a way to talk about “private information”

Page 3: Common Knowledge:  The Math

We will use an information structure

< Ω, π1, π2, μ >

Page 4: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Ω is the (finite) set of “states” of the worldω Ω is a possible state of the world

E⊆Ω is an event

Examples:

Ω = {(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny), (cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)}ω=(hot,rainy)E={(hot,rainy),(hot,sunny)}

Page 5: Common Knowledge:  The Math

πi “partitions” the set of states for player i into those he can and those he cannot distinguish.

E.g., Suppose player 1 is in a basement with a thermostat but no window

π1 = {{(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)}, {(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)}}

We write: π1((hot, sunny)) = π1((hot, rainy)) π1((cold, sunny)) = π1((cold, rainy))

Page 6: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Suppose player 2 is in a high-rise with a window but no thermostat

π2 = {{(hot, rainy), (cold, rainy)}, {(hot, sunny), (cold, sunny)}}

π2((hot, sunny)) = π2((cold, sunny)) π2((hot, rainy)) = π2((cold, rainy))

Page 7: Common Knowledge:  The Math

We let μ represent the “common prior” probability distribution over Ω

I.e. μ: Ω [0, 1] s.t. Σ μ(ω) = 1

We interpret μ(ω) as the probability state ω occurs

E.g., μ((hot, sunny)) = .45μ((hot, rainy)) = .05μ((cold, sunny)) = .05μ((cold, rainy)) = .45

Page 8: Common Knowledge:  The Math

We can likewise write μ(E) or μ(E|F), using Bayes Rule.

E.g., μ((hot, sunny)|hot) = = .9

Page 9: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Now, we want to investigate how this private information can influence play in a game.

We assume that in every state of the world the players play the same coordination game.

(But they may play different actions in different states!)

Page 10: Common Knowledge:  The Math

a, a b, c

c, b d, d

A

B

A B

a > c , d > b(Interpret?)

Page 11: Common Knowledge:  The Math

What are the strategies in this new game? The payoffs?

si: πi {A, B}

e.g. s1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=A s1({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=B

s2({(hot, sunny), (cold, sunny)})=A s2({(hot, rainy), (cold, rainy)})=B

Nots1({(cold, rainy)})=B s1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny), (cold,sunny)})=A

Page 12: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Ui: s1 × s2 lR s.t. Ui(s1, s2) = Σω μ(ω) Ui(s1(π1(ω), s2(π2(ω)))

How did we get this? Expected Utility=Weighted average of payoff in each state (given common priors, and prescribed action in each state)

Page 13: Common Knowledge:  The Math

E.g.

s1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=As1({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=B

s2({(hot, sunny), (cold, sunny)})=As2({(hot, rainy), (cold, rainy)})=B

1, 1 0,0

0,0 5,5

A

B

A B

Page 14: Common Knowledge:  The Math

U1(s1, s2) =μ((hot,sunny)) U1(s1(π1((hot,sunny), s2(π2((hot,sunny)))+…=μ((hot,sunny)) U1(s1({(hot,rainy),(hot,sunny)}, s2({(hot,sunny),(cold,sunny)})+…=μ((hot,sunny)) U1(A, A)+…=.45×1+.05×0 + .05×0 + .45×5=2.7

Page 15: Common Knowledge:  The Math

What is the condition for NE?

Same as before…

(s1,s2) is NE iffU1(s1,s2) ≥ U1(s1’,s2) for all s1’U2(s1,s2) ≥ U2(s1,s2’) for all s2’

Page 16: Common Knowledge:  The Math

E.g.

s1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=As1({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=B

s2({(hot, sunny), (cold, sunny)})=As2({(hot, rainy), (cold, rainy)})=B

1, 1 0,0

0,0 5,5

A

B

A B

Is (s1,s2) NE?

Page 17: Common Knowledge:  The Math

U1(s1,s2)=2.7

Let’s consider all possible deviations for player 1

Let s’1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=s’1 ({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=A U1(s’1,s2)=.45*1+.05*0+.05*1+.45*0=.45 U1(s’1,s2)<U1(s1,s2)

Let s’1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=s’1 ({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=BU1(s’1,s2)=2.5U1(s’1,s2)<U1(s1,s2)

Let s’1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=B s’1 ({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=A U1(s’1,s2)=.3 U1(s’1,s2)<U1(s1,s2)

(Similarly for player 2) (s1,s2) is NE

Page 18: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Now assume μ((hot, sunny)) = .35μ((hot, rainy)) = .15μ((cold, sunny)) = .35μ((cold, rainy)) = .15

Is (s1,s2) still NE?

Page 19: Common Knowledge:  The Math

U1(s1,s2)=.35*1+.15*0+.15*0+.35*5=2.1

Consider:s’1({(hot, rainy), (hot, sunny)})=s’1 ({(cold, rainy), (cold, sunny)})=B

U1(s’1,s2)=.35*0+.15*5+.15*0+.35*5=2.5

U1(s’1,s2)>U1(s1,s2)(s1,s2) isn’t NE

(in fact, can similarly argue no other (s1,s2) are NE that condition action on information!)

Page 20: Common Knowledge:  The Math

So sometimes it is possible to condition one’s action on one’s information, and sometimes it isn’t

Can we characterize, for any coordination game and information structure, when this is possible?

It turns out the answer will have to do with “higher order beliefs.” To see that we will need to define concepts called p-beliefs and common p-beliefs

Page 21: Common Knowledge:  The Math

We say i p-believes E at ω, if

μ (E|πi (ω)) ≥ p

E.g., consider our original information structure and let E={(hot,sunny),(cold,sunny)}

player 1 .7-believes E at (hot,sunny)

μ ({(hot,sunny),(cold,sunny)}|π1 ((hot,sunny)))= μ ({(hot,sunny),(cold,sunny)}|{(hot,sunny),(hot, rainy)}) =

(.45+0)/.5=9/10>.7

Page 22: Common Knowledge:  The Math
Page 23: Common Knowledge:  The Math

I.e.Both p-believe EBoth p-believe that both p-believe EBoth p-believe that both p-believe that both p-believe E…

Page 24: Common Knowledge:  The Math
Page 25: Common Knowledge:  The Math
Page 26: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Suppose (s1, s2) is a Nash equilibrium such that for i=1,2

si(ω) = A for all ω Esi(ω) = B for all ω F

Then Ω/F is common p-belief at E, and Ω/E is common (1-p)-belief at F

Page 27: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Intuition…

If 1 is playing A when she observes the event E, then he better be quite sure it isn’t F (b/c 2 plays B on F)

How sure? At least p!

Is this enough? What if 1 p-believes that it isn’t F, but doesn’t think 2 p-believes it isn’t F?

Well then 1 thinks 2 will play B! How confident does 1 have to be, therefore, that 2 p-believes it isn’t F? At least p!

Page 28: Common Knowledge:  The Math

If Ω/F is common p-belief at E, and Ω/E is common (1-p)-belief at F

Then there exists a Nash Equilibrium (s1, s2) s.t.

si(ω) = A for all ω Esi(ω) = B for all ω F

Page 29: Common Knowledge:  The Math

Note:

-higher order beliefs matter IFF my optimal choice depends on your choice! (coordination game, hawk dove game, but not signaling game!)

-Even if game state dependent!