4
Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof Peter van Inwagen Analysis, Vol. 40, No. 2. (Mar., 1980), pp. 98-100. Stable URL: http://links.jstor.org/sici?sici=0003-2638%28198003%2940%3A2%3C98%3ACATBOP%3E2.0.CO%3B2-N Analysis is currently published by The Analysis Committee. Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/about/terms.html. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use. Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at http://www.jstor.org/journals/anacom.html. Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed page of such transmission. The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academic journals and scholarly literature from around the world. The Archive is supported by libraries, scholarly societies, publishers, and foundations. It is an initiative of JSTOR, a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community take advantage of advances in technology. For more information regarding JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. http://www.jstor.org Tue Nov 6 20:24:12 2007

Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

Peter van Inwagen

Analysis Vol 40 No 2 (Mar 1980) pp 98-100

Stable URL

httplinksjstororgsicisici=0003-26382819800329403A23C983ACATBOP3E20CO3B2-N

Analysis is currently published by The Analysis Committee

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTORs Terms and Conditions of Use available athttpwwwjstororgabouttermshtml JSTORs Terms and Conditions of Use provides in part that unless you have obtainedprior permission you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles and you may use content inthe JSTOR archive only for your personal non-commercial use

Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work Publisher contact information may be obtained athttpwwwjstororgjournalsanacomhtml

Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printedpage of such transmission

The JSTOR Archive is a trusted digital repository providing for long-term preservation and access to leading academicjournals and scholarly literature from around the world The Archive is supported by libraries scholarly societies publishersand foundations It is an initiative of JSTOR a not-for-profit organization with a mission to help the scholarly community takeadvantage of advances in technology For more information regarding JSTOR please contact supportjstororg

httpwwwjstororgTue Nov 6 202412 2007

98 ANALYSIS

This is not only an intuitively sound translation of (24) but clearly justifies the inference from (24) and (25) to (26)

I do not wish to suggest that Pollocks analyses of subjunctive even if conditionals is totally acceptable Nor do I wish to suggest that a satisfactory analysis of indicative even if conditionals exists Neverthe- less I think that there is strong if not conclusive evidence that even affects the truth conditions of both subjunctive and indicative con- ditionals

Youthern Illinois CTniversig at Edwardsville 0JOHN A BARKER1980

COMPATIBILISM AND THE BURDEN OF PROOF

RICHARD Foleys Compatibilism and Control Over the Past (ANALYSIS392) is an attack on James W Lambs On a Proof of

Incompatibilism (The Philosophical Review LXXXVI 1977 pp 20-31) and rather less directly on my The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism (Philosophical Studies 27 I 975 pp I 81-1 99) In this note I shall try to bring out the oddness of a certain argument that Foley employs

Foleys argument concerns a premise of Lambs that Lamb calls a principle of can entailment

If a set F of true propositions logically entails that S does action A then if S at time t can refrain from A there is some member of F such that at t S can make it false

In the course of a discussion of this principle Foley says I present an argument in its defence Well perhaps the argument of mine that Foley misquotes (p 70) could be adapted to defend Lambs principle though my argument was for a principle of my own what the relation is between my principle and Lambs is a rather tricky question I shall not attempt to answer (I do find Lambs principle-lets call it PCE-highly plausible whether or not its mine but I shall not defend it in this paper)

99 COMPATIBILISM AND THE BURDEN OF PROOF

Now for Foleys odd argument He first presents a certain analysis of could have done otherwise statements a version of the well-known conditional analysis of such statements and shows that if this analysis is right PCE is wrong He then argues as follows

Of course I do not endorse the above analysis of could have done otherwise I have used it only to show how compatibilistic analysis of can and could statements might be used to argue against the principle of can entailment and accordingly show why Lamb and van Inwagen if they wish their arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the in- adequacy of such analyses But this neither Lamb nor van Inwagen has done (Morover af plausible arguments against compatibilistic analyses of can and could statements were available then arguments using the principle of can entailment would seem to be unneeded And so it would seem that Lambs and van Inwagens argument at best is superfluous) (PP 71-72)

I shall first consider the parenthesis I am not sure what Foley means by compatibilistic analysis of can Perhaps he means analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals In that case he seems to be saying that if someone had a plausible argument for

(I) All analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals are wrong

he would not need any further argument for

(2) Free will and determinism are incompatible

But at least one philosopher has accepted (I) and rejected ( 2 ) (see Keith Lehrer An Empirical Disproof of Determinism in Freedom and Deter- minirm ed K Lehrer Random House 1966) And whether or not that philosophers reasons for accepting (I) and rejecting ( 2 ) were good surely (2) does not follow from (I) A philosopher who wished to show that free will and determinism were incompatible could not accomplish this task by showing that some analysis or class of analyses of can was wrong Such an accomplishment could show no more than that a certain argument for compatibilism was unsound it could not show that com- patibilism was false So much for the charge that Lambs and my arguments are at best superfluous I turn now to Foleys contention that Lamb and I if we wish our arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the inadequacy of compatibilistic analyses of can

Why must we do this In order to accomplish what I t is not clear to me what general principles of argumentation Foley is appealing to Does he accept this principle

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its possible counter-analyses are incorrect

(Let us say that an analysis of a term or concept is a cont~ter-atzabsis to an

I00 ANALYSIS

argument if it follows from the assumption that that analysis is correct that that argument is unsound) If so he is being unreasonable since this principle obviously has the consequence that no argument is convincing for no one knows all the possible analyses of any term A more likely principle is this

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its well-known counter-analyses are incorrect

More likely perhaps but I dont believe it My argument and Lambs appear to me to be perfectly convincing though they are accompanied by no refutation of Foleys analysis or of any of the well-known family of conditional analyses of can7 Its true of course that my conviction that the premises of my argument are true depends on my pre-anabtical understanding of can7 But then so does Foleys conviction that his analysis of can is correct (or even worth considering) depend upon his pre-analytical understanding of this word Suppose I were to say that Foley has to show that one of the premises of my argument was false if he wanted his analysis of can to be convincing Wouldnt that be a pretty odd thing for me to say Isnt what Foley says Imust do if I want my argument to be convincing odd for just the same reason

I dont wish to appear intransigent however If Foley really must have an argument for the conclusion that his analysis is wrong Ill give him one

PCE is true So Foleys analysis is wrong

This strikes me as a pretty good argument Foley himself admits that its conclusion follows from its premise The premise as Lamb says verges on being tautological And the conclusion is not particularly paradoxical or counter-intuitive Nor indeed is the stronger statement (I) which I suppose also follows from PCE particularly paradoxical or counter- intuitive At any rate I see no particular reason to think that can statements are disguised conditionals Does anyonel

In the remainder of h s paper Foley does what he ought to have done in the first place and argues against PCE I shall not discuss his argument PCE is after all Lambs principle and I will leave it to Lamb to defend it In my papers Reply to Narveson and Reply to Gallois I have replied to certain criticisms of my own premises that are not entirely dissimilar to Foleys criticism of PCE Both these papers appeafed in Philarophical Studies 32 (1977)

Page 2: Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

98 ANALYSIS

This is not only an intuitively sound translation of (24) but clearly justifies the inference from (24) and (25) to (26)

I do not wish to suggest that Pollocks analyses of subjunctive even if conditionals is totally acceptable Nor do I wish to suggest that a satisfactory analysis of indicative even if conditionals exists Neverthe- less I think that there is strong if not conclusive evidence that even affects the truth conditions of both subjunctive and indicative con- ditionals

Youthern Illinois CTniversig at Edwardsville 0JOHN A BARKER1980

COMPATIBILISM AND THE BURDEN OF PROOF

RICHARD Foleys Compatibilism and Control Over the Past (ANALYSIS392) is an attack on James W Lambs On a Proof of

Incompatibilism (The Philosophical Review LXXXVI 1977 pp 20-31) and rather less directly on my The Incompatibility of Free Will and Determinism (Philosophical Studies 27 I 975 pp I 81-1 99) In this note I shall try to bring out the oddness of a certain argument that Foley employs

Foleys argument concerns a premise of Lambs that Lamb calls a principle of can entailment

If a set F of true propositions logically entails that S does action A then if S at time t can refrain from A there is some member of F such that at t S can make it false

In the course of a discussion of this principle Foley says I present an argument in its defence Well perhaps the argument of mine that Foley misquotes (p 70) could be adapted to defend Lambs principle though my argument was for a principle of my own what the relation is between my principle and Lambs is a rather tricky question I shall not attempt to answer (I do find Lambs principle-lets call it PCE-highly plausible whether or not its mine but I shall not defend it in this paper)

99 COMPATIBILISM AND THE BURDEN OF PROOF

Now for Foleys odd argument He first presents a certain analysis of could have done otherwise statements a version of the well-known conditional analysis of such statements and shows that if this analysis is right PCE is wrong He then argues as follows

Of course I do not endorse the above analysis of could have done otherwise I have used it only to show how compatibilistic analysis of can and could statements might be used to argue against the principle of can entailment and accordingly show why Lamb and van Inwagen if they wish their arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the in- adequacy of such analyses But this neither Lamb nor van Inwagen has done (Morover af plausible arguments against compatibilistic analyses of can and could statements were available then arguments using the principle of can entailment would seem to be unneeded And so it would seem that Lambs and van Inwagens argument at best is superfluous) (PP 71-72)

I shall first consider the parenthesis I am not sure what Foley means by compatibilistic analysis of can Perhaps he means analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals In that case he seems to be saying that if someone had a plausible argument for

(I) All analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals are wrong

he would not need any further argument for

(2) Free will and determinism are incompatible

But at least one philosopher has accepted (I) and rejected ( 2 ) (see Keith Lehrer An Empirical Disproof of Determinism in Freedom and Deter- minirm ed K Lehrer Random House 1966) And whether or not that philosophers reasons for accepting (I) and rejecting ( 2 ) were good surely (2) does not follow from (I) A philosopher who wished to show that free will and determinism were incompatible could not accomplish this task by showing that some analysis or class of analyses of can was wrong Such an accomplishment could show no more than that a certain argument for compatibilism was unsound it could not show that com- patibilism was false So much for the charge that Lambs and my arguments are at best superfluous I turn now to Foleys contention that Lamb and I if we wish our arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the inadequacy of compatibilistic analyses of can

Why must we do this In order to accomplish what I t is not clear to me what general principles of argumentation Foley is appealing to Does he accept this principle

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its possible counter-analyses are incorrect

(Let us say that an analysis of a term or concept is a cont~ter-atzabsis to an

I00 ANALYSIS

argument if it follows from the assumption that that analysis is correct that that argument is unsound) If so he is being unreasonable since this principle obviously has the consequence that no argument is convincing for no one knows all the possible analyses of any term A more likely principle is this

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its well-known counter-analyses are incorrect

More likely perhaps but I dont believe it My argument and Lambs appear to me to be perfectly convincing though they are accompanied by no refutation of Foleys analysis or of any of the well-known family of conditional analyses of can7 Its true of course that my conviction that the premises of my argument are true depends on my pre-anabtical understanding of can7 But then so does Foleys conviction that his analysis of can is correct (or even worth considering) depend upon his pre-analytical understanding of this word Suppose I were to say that Foley has to show that one of the premises of my argument was false if he wanted his analysis of can to be convincing Wouldnt that be a pretty odd thing for me to say Isnt what Foley says Imust do if I want my argument to be convincing odd for just the same reason

I dont wish to appear intransigent however If Foley really must have an argument for the conclusion that his analysis is wrong Ill give him one

PCE is true So Foleys analysis is wrong

This strikes me as a pretty good argument Foley himself admits that its conclusion follows from its premise The premise as Lamb says verges on being tautological And the conclusion is not particularly paradoxical or counter-intuitive Nor indeed is the stronger statement (I) which I suppose also follows from PCE particularly paradoxical or counter- intuitive At any rate I see no particular reason to think that can statements are disguised conditionals Does anyonel

In the remainder of h s paper Foley does what he ought to have done in the first place and argues against PCE I shall not discuss his argument PCE is after all Lambs principle and I will leave it to Lamb to defend it In my papers Reply to Narveson and Reply to Gallois I have replied to certain criticisms of my own premises that are not entirely dissimilar to Foleys criticism of PCE Both these papers appeafed in Philarophical Studies 32 (1977)

Page 3: Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

99 COMPATIBILISM AND THE BURDEN OF PROOF

Now for Foleys odd argument He first presents a certain analysis of could have done otherwise statements a version of the well-known conditional analysis of such statements and shows that if this analysis is right PCE is wrong He then argues as follows

Of course I do not endorse the above analysis of could have done otherwise I have used it only to show how compatibilistic analysis of can and could statements might be used to argue against the principle of can entailment and accordingly show why Lamb and van Inwagen if they wish their arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the in- adequacy of such analyses But this neither Lamb nor van Inwagen has done (Morover af plausible arguments against compatibilistic analyses of can and could statements were available then arguments using the principle of can entailment would seem to be unneeded And so it would seem that Lambs and van Inwagens argument at best is superfluous) (PP 71-72)

I shall first consider the parenthesis I am not sure what Foley means by compatibilistic analysis of can Perhaps he means analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals In that case he seems to be saying that if someone had a plausible argument for

(I) All analyses that treat can statements as disguised conditionals are wrong

he would not need any further argument for

(2) Free will and determinism are incompatible

But at least one philosopher has accepted (I) and rejected ( 2 ) (see Keith Lehrer An Empirical Disproof of Determinism in Freedom and Deter- minirm ed K Lehrer Random House 1966) And whether or not that philosophers reasons for accepting (I) and rejecting ( 2 ) were good surely (2) does not follow from (I) A philosopher who wished to show that free will and determinism were incompatible could not accomplish this task by showing that some analysis or class of analyses of can was wrong Such an accomplishment could show no more than that a certain argument for compatibilism was unsound it could not show that com- patibilism was false So much for the charge that Lambs and my arguments are at best superfluous I turn now to Foleys contention that Lamb and I if we wish our arguments to be convincing must demonstrate the inadequacy of compatibilistic analyses of can

Why must we do this In order to accomplish what I t is not clear to me what general principles of argumentation Foley is appealing to Does he accept this principle

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its possible counter-analyses are incorrect

(Let us say that an analysis of a term or concept is a cont~ter-atzabsis to an

I00 ANALYSIS

argument if it follows from the assumption that that analysis is correct that that argument is unsound) If so he is being unreasonable since this principle obviously has the consequence that no argument is convincing for no one knows all the possible analyses of any term A more likely principle is this

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its well-known counter-analyses are incorrect

More likely perhaps but I dont believe it My argument and Lambs appear to me to be perfectly convincing though they are accompanied by no refutation of Foleys analysis or of any of the well-known family of conditional analyses of can7 Its true of course that my conviction that the premises of my argument are true depends on my pre-anabtical understanding of can7 But then so does Foleys conviction that his analysis of can is correct (or even worth considering) depend upon his pre-analytical understanding of this word Suppose I were to say that Foley has to show that one of the premises of my argument was false if he wanted his analysis of can to be convincing Wouldnt that be a pretty odd thing for me to say Isnt what Foley says Imust do if I want my argument to be convincing odd for just the same reason

I dont wish to appear intransigent however If Foley really must have an argument for the conclusion that his analysis is wrong Ill give him one

PCE is true So Foleys analysis is wrong

This strikes me as a pretty good argument Foley himself admits that its conclusion follows from its premise The premise as Lamb says verges on being tautological And the conclusion is not particularly paradoxical or counter-intuitive Nor indeed is the stronger statement (I) which I suppose also follows from PCE particularly paradoxical or counter- intuitive At any rate I see no particular reason to think that can statements are disguised conditionals Does anyonel

In the remainder of h s paper Foley does what he ought to have done in the first place and argues against PCE I shall not discuss his argument PCE is after all Lambs principle and I will leave it to Lamb to defend it In my papers Reply to Narveson and Reply to Gallois I have replied to certain criticisms of my own premises that are not entirely dissimilar to Foleys criticism of PCE Both these papers appeafed in Philarophical Studies 32 (1977)

Page 4: Compatibilism and the Burden of Proof

I00 ANALYSIS

argument if it follows from the assumption that that analysis is correct that that argument is unsound) If so he is being unreasonable since this principle obviously has the consequence that no argument is convincing for no one knows all the possible analyses of any term A more likely principle is this

No argument is convincing unless it is accompanied by arguments showing that all its well-known counter-analyses are incorrect

More likely perhaps but I dont believe it My argument and Lambs appear to me to be perfectly convincing though they are accompanied by no refutation of Foleys analysis or of any of the well-known family of conditional analyses of can7 Its true of course that my conviction that the premises of my argument are true depends on my pre-anabtical understanding of can7 But then so does Foleys conviction that his analysis of can is correct (or even worth considering) depend upon his pre-analytical understanding of this word Suppose I were to say that Foley has to show that one of the premises of my argument was false if he wanted his analysis of can to be convincing Wouldnt that be a pretty odd thing for me to say Isnt what Foley says Imust do if I want my argument to be convincing odd for just the same reason

I dont wish to appear intransigent however If Foley really must have an argument for the conclusion that his analysis is wrong Ill give him one

PCE is true So Foleys analysis is wrong

This strikes me as a pretty good argument Foley himself admits that its conclusion follows from its premise The premise as Lamb says verges on being tautological And the conclusion is not particularly paradoxical or counter-intuitive Nor indeed is the stronger statement (I) which I suppose also follows from PCE particularly paradoxical or counter- intuitive At any rate I see no particular reason to think that can statements are disguised conditionals Does anyonel

In the remainder of h s paper Foley does what he ought to have done in the first place and argues against PCE I shall not discuss his argument PCE is after all Lambs principle and I will leave it to Lamb to defend it In my papers Reply to Narveson and Reply to Gallois I have replied to certain criticisms of my own premises that are not entirely dissimilar to Foleys criticism of PCE Both these papers appeafed in Philarophical Studies 32 (1977)