340
Decision Theory Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    18

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Decision Theory

Refail N. Kasimbeyli

Page 2: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Chapter 3

Page 3: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3 Utility Theory

3.1 Single-attribute utility

3.2 Interpreting utility functions

3.3 Utility functions for non-monetary attributes

3.4 The axioms of utility

3.5 More on utility elicitation

3.6 Attitudes Towards Risk

3.7 Risk

3.8 Risk Attitudes

3.9 Expected Utility, Certainty Equivalents, and Risk Premiums3.10 Risk Tolerance and the Exponential Utility function

3.11 Decreasing and Constant Risk Aversion

3.12 How useful is utility in practice?

3.13 Exercises

Page 4: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Utility Theory

Thus far, when applying EMV decision rule, we have

assumed that the expected payoff in monetary terms is

the appropriate measure of the consequences of

taking an action. However, in many situations

this assumption is inappropriate.

Page 5: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, suppose that an individual is

offered the choice of (1) accepting a 50 : 50 chance of

winning $100, 000 or nothing, or (2) receiving $40,000

with certainty. ...

Page 6: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.1 Single-attribute utility

The attitude to risk of a decision maker can be

assessed by eliciting a utility function.

Page 7: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To illustrate how a utility function can be derived,

consider the following problem. A business woman

who is organizing a business equipment exhibition in

a provincial town has to choose between two venues:

the Luxuria Hotel and the Maxima Center.

Page 8: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To simplify her problem, she decides to estimate her

potential profit at these locations on the basis of two

scenarios: high attendance and low attendance at the

exhibition. If she chooses the Luxuria Hotel,

she reckons that she has a 60% chance of achieving

a high attendance and hence a profit of $30,000

(after taking into account the costs of advertising,

hiring the venue, etc.).

Page 9: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

There is, however, a 40% chance that attendance will

be low, in which case her profit will be just

$11,000. If she chooses the Maxima Center,

she reckons she has a 50% chance of high

attendance, leading to a profit of $60,000, and

a 50% chance of low attendance leading to a loss of

$10, 000.

Page 10: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We can represent the business womans

problem in the form of a diagram known as a decision

tree (Figure 3.1).

Page 11: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 12: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In this diagram a square represents a decision point;

immediately beyond this, the decision maker can

choose which route to follow. A circle represents a

chance node. Immediately beyond this, chance

determines, with the indicated probabilities, which

route will be followed, so the choice of route is beyond

the control of the decision maker.

(We will consider decision trees in much more detail in

the next section.)

Page 13: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The monetary values show the profits earned by the

business woman if a given course of action is chosen

and a given outcome occurs.

Page 14: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now, if we apply the EMV criterion to the

decision we find that the business womans expected

profit is $22400 (i.e. 0.6× $30000+0.4× $11000) if

she chooses the Luxuria Hotel and $25000 if

she chooses the Maxima Center.

This suggests that she should choose the Maxima

Center, but this is the riskiest option, offering high

rewards if things go well but losses if things go badly.

Page 15: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Let us now try to derive a utility function

to represent the business woman’s attitude to risk.

We will use the notation u() to represent the utility of

the sum of money which appears in the parentheses.

Page 16: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

First, we rank all the monetary returns which appear

on the tree from best to worst and assign a utility of

1.0 to the best sum of money and 0 to the worst sum.

Page 17: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Any two numbers could have been assigned here as

long as the best outcome is assigned the higher

number. We use the numbers between 0 and 1,

which enable us to interpret what utilities actually

represent. If other values were used they could easily

be transformed to a scale ranging from 0 to 1 without

affecting the decision makers preference between the

courses of action.

Page 18: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus so far we have:

Page 19: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We now need to determine the business

woman’s utilities for the intermediate sums of money.

There are several approaches which can be adopted

to elicit utilities. The most commonly used methods

involve offering the decision maker a series of

choices between receiving given sums of money for

certain or entering hypothetical lotteries.

Page 20: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The decision maker’s utility function is then inferred

from the choices that are made. The method which we

will demonstrate here is an example of the

probability-equivalence approach (an alternative

elicitation procedure will be discussed in a later

subsection).

Page 21: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To obtain the business woman’s utility for $30,000

using this approach we offer her a choice between

receiving that sum for certain or entering

a hypothetical lottery which will result in either the

best outcome on the tree (i.e. a profit of $60, 000) or

the worst (i.e. a loss of $10, 000) with specified

probabilities.

Page 22: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

These probabilities are varied until the decision

maker is indifferent between the certain money and

the lottery. At this point, as we shall see, the utility

can be calculated. A typical elicitation session might

proceed as follows:

Page 23: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Question: Which of the following would you

prefer?

A $30, 000 for certain; or

B A lottery ticket which will give you a 70%

chance of $60, 000 and a 30% chance of −$10, 000?

Page 24: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Answer: A 30% chance of losing $10, 000 is too

risky, I’ll take the certain money.

We therefore need to make the lottery more

attractive by increasing the probability of the best

outcome.

Page 25: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Question: Which of the following would you

prefer?

A $30, 000 for certain; or

B A lottery ticket which will give you a 90%

chance of $60, 000 and a 10% chance of −$10, 000?

Page 26: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Answer : I now stand such a good chance of

winning the lottery that I think I’ll buy the lottery ticket.

Page 27: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The point of indifference between the certain

money and the lottery should therefore lie somewhere

between a 70% chance of winning $60,000

(when the certain money was preferred) and

a 90% chance (when the lottery ticket was

preferred). Suppose that after trying several

probabilities we pose the following question.

Page 28: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Question: Which of the following would you

prefer?

A $30, 000 for certain; or

B A lottery ticket which will give you an 85%

chance of $60, 000 and a 15% chance of −$10, 000?

Page 29: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Answer : I am now indifferent between the

certain money and the lottery ticket.

We are now in a position to calculate the utility

of $30, 000. Since the business woman is indifferent

between options A and B the utility of $30, 000 will be

equal to the expected utility of the lottery.

Page 30: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus:

u($30, 000) = 0.85u($60, 000) + 0.15u(−$10, 000)

Since we have already allocated utilities of 1.0

and 0 to $60, 000 and −$10, 000, respectively, we

have:

u($30, 000) = 0.85(1.0) + 0.15(0) = 0.85

Page 31: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Note that, once we have found the point of

indifference, the utility of the certain money is simply

equal to the probability of the best outcome in the

lottery. Thus, if the decision maker had been

indifferent between the options which we offered in

the first question, her utility for $30, 000 would have

been 0.7.

Page 32: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We now need to determine the utility of

$11, 000. Suppose that after being asked a similar

series of questions the business woman finally

indicates that she would be indifferent between

receiving $11, 000 for certain and a lottery ticket

offering a 60% chance of the best outcome ($60, 000)

and a 40% chance of the worst outcome (−$10, 000).

Page 33: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This implies that u($11, 000) = 0.6. We can now state

the complete set of utilities and these are shown

below in 3.2 :

Page 34: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

These results are now applied to the decision

tree by replacing the monetary values with their

utilities (see Figure 3.2). By treating these utilities in

the same way as the monetary values we are able to

identify the course of action which leads to the

highest expected utility.

Page 35: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Choosing the Luxuria Hotel gives an expected

utility of:

0.6 × 0.85 + 0.4 × 0.6 = 0.75

Choosing the Maxima Center gives an expected

utility of:

0.51.0 + 0.50 = 0.5

Page 36: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus the business woman should choose the

Luxuria Hotel as the venue for her exhibition. Clearly,

the Maxima Center would be too risky.

Page 37: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 38: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It may be useful at this point to establish what

expected utilities actually represent. Indeed, given

that we have just applied the concept to a one–off

decision, why do we use the term expected utility? To

see what we have done, consider Figure 3.3.

Page 39: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 40: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Here we have the business woman’s decision tree

with the original monetary sums replaced by the

lotteries which she regarded as being equally

attractive.

Page 41: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, receiving $30, 000 was considered to be

equivalent to a lottery offering a 0.85 probability of

$60,000 and a 0.15 probability of −$10,000.

Obviously, receiving $60, 000 is equivalent to a lottery

ticket offering $60, 000 for certain.

Page 42: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

You will see that every payoff in the tree is now

expressed in terms of a probability of obtaining either

the best outcome ($60, 000) or the worst outcome

(−$10, 000).

Page 43: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now, if the business woman chooses the Luxuria

Hotel she will have a 0.6 probability of finishing with

a profit which she perceives to be equivalent to

a lottery ticket offering a 0.85 probability of $60, 000

and a 0.15 probability of −$10, 000.

Page 44: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Similarly, she will have a 0.4 probability of a profit,

which is equivalent to a lottery ticket offering a 0.6

probability of $60, 000 and a 0.4 chance of −$10, 000.

Therefore the Luxuria Hotel offers her the equivalent

of a 0.6 × 0.85 + 0.4 × 0.6 = 0.75 probability of the

best outcome (and a 0.25 probability of the worst

outcome). Note that 0.75 is the expected utility of

choosing the Luxuria Hotel.

Page 45: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Obviously, choosing the Maxima Center offers

her the equivalent of only a 0.5 probability of the best

outcome on the tree (and a 0.5 probability of the worst

outcome). Thus, as shown in Figure 3.4, utility allows

us to express the returns of all the courses of action in

terms of simple lotteries all offering the same prizes,

namely the best and worst outcomes, but with

different probabilities. This makes the alternatives

easy to compare.

Page 46: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 47: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The probability of winning the best outcome in these

lotteries is the expected utility. It therefore seems

reasonable that we should select the option offering

the highest expected utility.

Page 48: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Note that the use here of the term ’expected’

utility is therefore somewhat misleading. It is used

because the procedure for calculating expected utilities

is arithmetically the same as that for calculating

expected values in statistics.

Page 49: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It does not, however, necessarily refer to an average

result which would be obtained from a large number of

repetitions of a course of action, nor does it mean

a result or consequence which should be ’expected’.

In decision theory, an ’expected utility’ is only

a ’certainty equivalent’, that is, a single ’certain’ figure

that is equivalent in preference to the uncertain

situations.

Page 50: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.2 Interpreting utility functionsThe business woman’s utility function has been plotted on a

graph in Figure 3.5.

Page 51: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If we selected any two points on this curve and drew

a straight line between them then it can be seen that

the curve would always be above the line.

Utility functions having this concave shape provide

evidence of risk aversion (which is consistent with the

business woman’s avoidance of the riskiest option).

Page 52: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This is easily demonstrated. Consider

Figure 3.6, which shows a utility function with a similar

shape, and suppose that the decision maker, from

whom this function has been elicited, has assets of

$1000. He is then offered a gamble which will give him

a 50% chance of doubling his money to $2000 and

a 50% chance of losing it all, so that he finishes with

$0.

Page 53: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The expected monetary value of the gamble is $1000

(i.e. 0.5 × $2000 + 0.5 × $0), so according to the EMV

criterion he should be indifferent between keeping his

money and gambling.

Page 54: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

However, when we apply the utility function to

the decision we see that currently the decision maker

has assets with a utility of 0.9.

Page 55: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If he gambles he has a 50% chance of increasing his

assets so that their utility would increase to 1.0 and

a 50% chance of ending with assets with a utility of 0.

Hence the expected utility of the gamble is

0.5 × 1 + 0.5 × 0, which equals 0.5. Clearly,

the certain money is more attractive than the risky

option of gambling.

Page 56: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In simple terms, even though the potential wins and

losses are the same in monetary terms and even

though he has the same chance of winning as he

does of losing, the increase in utility which will occur

if the decision maker wins the gamble is far less than

the loss in utility he will suffer if he loses. He therefore

stands to lose much more than he stands to gain, so

he will not be prepared to take the risk.

Page 57: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 58: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Figure 3.7 illustrates other typical utility functions.

Page 59: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Figure 3.7(a) shows a utility function which

indicates a risk-seeking attitude (or risk proneness).

A person with a utility function like this would have

accepted the gamble which we offered above.

The linear utility function in Figure 3.7(b)

demonstrates a risk-neutral attitude. If a person’s

utility function looks like this then the EMV criterion will

represent their preferences.

Page 60: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Finally, the utility function in Figure 3.7(c) indicates

both a risk-seeking attitude and risk aversion.

If the decision maker currently has assets of $y then

he will be averse to taking a risk. The reverse is true

if currently he has assets of only $x. It is important to

note that individual’s utility functions do not remain

constant over time.

Page 61: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

They may vary from day to day, especially if the

person’s asset position changes. If you win a large

sum of money tomorrow then you may be more willing

to take a risk than you are today.

Page 62: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.3 Utility functions for non-monetary attributes

Utility functions can be derived for attributes other

than money. Consider the problem which is

represented by the decision tree in Figure 3.8.

Page 63: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 64: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This relates to a drug company which is hoping to

develop a new product. If the company proceeds with

its existing research methods it estimates that there is

a 0.4 probability that the drug will take 6 years to

develop and a 0.6 probability that development will

take 4 years.

Page 65: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

However, recently a ”short-cut” method has been

proposed which might lead to significant reductions in

the development time, and the company, which has

limited resources available for research, has to decide

whether to take a risk and switch completely to the

proposed new method.

Page 66: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The head of research estimates that, if the new

approach is adopted, there is a 0.2 probability that

development will take a year, a 0.4 probability that it

will take 2 years and a 0.4 probability that the

approach will not work and, because of the time

wasted, it will take 8 years to develop the product.

Page 67: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Clearly, adopting the new approach is risky, so

we need to derive utilities for the development times.

The worst development time is 8 years, so

u(8 years) = 0 and the best time is 1 year, so

u(1 years) = 1.0.

Page 68: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

After being asked a series of questions, based on the

variable probability method, the head of research is

able to say that she is indifferent between

a development time of 2 years and engaging in

a lottery which will give her a 0.95 probability of a 1-

year development and a 0.05 probability of an 8-year

development time.

Page 69: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus:

u(2 years) = 0.95u(1 year) + 0.05u(8 years) =

0.95(1.0) + 0.05(0) = 0.95.

By a similar process we find that

u(4 years) = 0.75 and u(6 years) = 0.5.

Page 70: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The utilities are shown on the decision tree in

Figure 3.8 , where it can be seen that continuing with

the existing method gives the highest expected utility.

Note, however, that the two results are close, and

a sensitivity analysis might reveal that minor changes

in the probabilities or utilities would lead to the other

alternative being selected.

Page 71: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The utility function is shown in Figure 3.9. This has

a concave shape indicating risk aversion.

Page 72: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 73: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It is also possible to derive utility functions for

attributes which are not easily measured in numerical

terms. For example, consider the choice of design for

a chemical plant. Design A may have a small

probability of failure which may lead to pollution of the

local environment.

Page 74: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

An alternative, design B, may also carry a small

probability of failure which would not lead to pollution

but would cause damage to some expensive

equipment. If a decision maker ranks the possible

outcomes from best to worst as: (i) no failure,

(ii) equipment damage and (iii) pollution then, clearly,

u(no failure)= 1 and u(pollution) = 0.

Page 75: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The value of u(equipment damage) could then be

determined by posing questions such as which would

you prefer:

Page 76: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(1) A design which was certain at some stage to

fail, causing equipment damage; or

(2) A design which had a 90% chance of not

failing and a 10% chance of failing and causing

pollution? Once a point of indifference was

established, u(equipment damage) could be derived.

Page 77: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Ronen et al. [20] describe a similar application in

the electronics industry, where the decision relates to

designs of electronic circuits for cardiac pace- makers.

The designs carry a risk of particular malfunctions and

the utilities relate to outcomes such as ”pacemaker

not functioning at all”, ”pacemaker working too fast”,

”pacemaker working too slow” and

”pacemaker functioning OK”.

Page 78: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.4 The axioms of utility

In the last few sections we have suggested that

a rational decision maker should select the course of

action which maximizes expected utility. This will be

true if the decision makers preferences conform to the

following axioms:

Page 79: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 1: The complete ordering axiom

To satisfy this axiom the decision maker must be

able to place all lotteries in order of preference.

For example, if he is offered a choice between two

lotteries, the decision maker must be able to say

which he prefers or whether he is indifferent between

them. (For the purposes of this discussion we will also

regard a certain chance of winning a reward as

a lottery.)

Page 80: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 2: The transitivity axiom

If the decision maker prefers lottery A to

lottery B and lottery B to lottery C then, if he conforms

to this axiom, he must also prefer lottery A to lottery C

(i.e. his preferences must be transitive).

Page 81: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 3: The continuity axiom

Suppose that we offer the decision maker

a choice between the two lotteries shown in Figure

3.10.

Page 82: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This shows that lottery 1 offers a reward of B

for certain while lottery 2 offers a reward of A, with

probability p and a reward of C with probability

1 − p. Reward A is preferable to reward B, and

B in turn is preferred to reward C.

Page 83: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The continuity axiom states that there must be some

value of p at which the decision maker will be

indifferent between the two lotteries. We obviously

assumed that this axiom applied when we elicited the

conference organizer’s utility for $30, 000 earlier in the

chapter.

Page 84: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 4: The substitution axiom

Page 85: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 86: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose that a decision maker indicates that

he is indifferent between the lotteries shown

in Figure 3.11, where X , Y and Z are rewards and

p is a probability. According to the substitution axiom,

if reward X appears as a reward in another lottery

it can always be substituted by lottery 2 because

the decision maker regards X and lottery 2 as being

equally preferable.

Page 87: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, the conference organizer indicated that

she was indifferent between the lotteries shown

in Figure 3.12(a). If the substitution axiom applies,

she will also be indifferent between lotteries 3 and 4,

which are shown in Figure 3.12(b).

Note that these lotteries are identical, except that

in lottery 4 we have substituted lottery 2

for the $30, 000. Lottery 4 offers a 0.6 chance of

winning a ticket in another lottery and is therefore

referred to as a compound lottery.

Page 88: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 5: Unequal probability axiom

Suppose that a decision maker prefers reward A

to reward B. Then, according to this axiom, if he is

offered two lotteries which only offer rewards A and B

as possible outcomes he will prefer the lottery offering

the highest probability of reward A.

Page 89: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We used this axiom in our explanation of utility

earlier, where we reduced the conference organizer’s

decision to a comparison of the two lotteries shown in

Figure 3.13. Clearly, if the conference organizer’s

preferences conform to this axiom then she will prefer

lottery 1.

Page 90: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 91: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Axiom 6: Compound lottery axiom

If this axiom applies then a decision maker will

be indifferent between a compound lottery and

a simple lottery which offers the same rewards with

the same probabilities.

Page 92: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, suppose that the conference organizer

is offered the compound lottery shown in

Figure 3.14(a). Note that this lottery offers

a 0.28 (i.e. 0.4 × 0.7) probability of $60, 000 and

a 0.72 (i.e. 0.4× 0.3+0.6) probability of −$10, 000.

Page 93: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

According to this axiom she will also be indifferent

between the compound lottery and the simple lottery

shown in Figure 3.13(b).

Page 94: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 95: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It can be shown (see, for example,

French [11]) that if the decision maker accepts

these six axioms then a utility function exists

which represents his preferences.

Page 96: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Moreover, if the decision maker behaves in a manner

which is consistent with the axioms (i.e. rationally),

then he will choose the course of action which has the

highest expected utility. Of course, it may be possible

to demonstrate that a particular decision maker does

not act according to the axioms of utility theory.

However, this does not necessarily imply that the

theory is inappropriate in his case.

Page 97: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

All that is required is that he wishes to behave

consistently according to the axioms.

Applying decision analysis helps a decision maker to

formulate preferences, assess uncertainty and make

judgments in a coherent fashion. Thus coherence is

the result of decision analysis, not a prerequisite.

Page 98: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.5 More on utility elicitation

So far, we have only considered utility assessment

based on the probability-equivalence approach.

A disadvantage of this approach is that the decision

maker may have difficulty in thinking in terms of

probabilities like 0.90 or 0.95.

Page 99: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Because of this, a number of alternative approaches

have been developed (for example, Farquahar [10]

reviews 24 different methods). Perhaps

the most widely used of these is the

certainty-equivalence approach, which, in its most

common form, only requires the decision maker to

think in terms of 50 : 50 gambles.

Page 100: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To illustrate the approach, let us suppose that

we wish to elicit a decision maker’s utility function for

monetary values in the range $0 − 40,000

(so that u($0) = 0 and u($40, 000) = 1).

An elicitation session might proceed as follows:

Page 101: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Analyst : If I offered you a hypothetical lottery

ticket which gave a 50% chance of $0 and a 50%

chance of $40, 000, how much would you be prepared

to pay for it? Obviously, its expected monetary value is

$20, 000, but I want to know the minimum amount of

money you would just be willing to pay for the ticket.

Page 102: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Decision maker : (after some thought) $10, 000.

Hence u($10, 000) = 0.5u($0) + 0.5u($40, 000) =

0.5(0) + 0.5(1) = 0.5

The analyst would now use the $10, 000 as the worst

payoff in a new hypothetical lottery.

Page 103: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Analyst : If I now offered you a hypothetical

lottery ticket which gave you a 50% chance of

$40, 000 and a 50% chance of $10, 000 how much

would you be prepared to pay for it?

Page 104: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Decision maker : About $18, 000.

Hence u($18, 000) = 0.5u($10, 000) +

0.5u($40, 000) = 0.5(0.5) + 0.5(1) =0.75

The $40, 000 is also used as the best payoff in

a lottery which will also offer a chance of $0.

Page 105: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Analyst : What would you be prepared to pay

for a ticket offering a 50% chance of $10, 000 and

a 50% chance of $0?

Decision maker : $3, 000.

Thus u($3, 000) = 0.5u($0) + 0.5u($10, 000) =

0.5(0) + 0.5(0.5) = 0.25.

Page 106: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It can be seen that the effect of this procedure is

to elicit the monetary values which have utilities of 0,

0.25, 0.5, 0.75 and 1. Thus we have:

Page 107: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If we plotted this utility function on a graph

it would be seen that the decision maker is risk averse

for this range of monetary values. The curve could,

of course, also be used to estimate the utilities of other

sums of money.

Page 108: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

While the certainty-equivalence method we have

just demonstrated frees the decision maker from the

need to think about awkward probabilities it is not

without its dangers. You will have noted that the

decision makers first response ($10, 000) was used

by the analyst in subsequent lotteries, both as a best

and worst outcome. This process is known as

chaining, and the effect of this can be to propagate

earlier judgmental errors.

Page 109: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The obvious question is, do these two

approaches to utility elicitation produce consistent

responses? Unfortunately, the evidence is that they do

not. Indeed, utilities appear to be extremely sensitive to

the elicitation method which is adopted.

Certainty-equivalence methods were found to yield

greater risk seeking than probability-equivalence

methods.

Page 110: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The payoffs and probabilities used in the lotteries and,

in particular, whether or not they included possible

losses also led to different utility functions. Moreover,

it was found that responses differed depending upon

whether the choice offered involved risk being

assumed or transferred away.

Page 111: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, in the certainty-equivalence method we

could either ask the decision maker how much he

would be prepared to pay to buy the lottery ticket or,

assuming that he already owns the ticket, how much he

would accept to sell it.

Page 112: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Research suggests that people tend to offer a lower

price to buy the ticket than they would accept to sell it.

There is thus a propensity to prefer the status quo,

so that people are generally happier to retain a given

risk than to take the same risk on. Finally, the context

in which the questions were framed was found to have

an effect on responses.

Page 113: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, Hershey et al.[13] refer to an earlier

experiment when the same choice was posed in

different ways, the first involving an insurance decision

and the second a gamble as shown below:

Page 114: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Insurance formulation

Situation A: You stand a one out of a thousand chance

of losing $1000.

Situation B: You can buy insurance for $10 to protect

you from this loss.

Page 115: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Gamble formulation

Situation A: You stand a one out of a thousand chance

of losing $1000.

Situation B: You will lose $10 with certainty.

Page 116: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It was found that 81% of subjects preferred B in

the insurance formulation, while only 56% preferred B

in the gamble formulation.

Page 117: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Tversky and Kahneman [24] provide further

evidence that the way in which the choice is framed

affects the decision maker’s response. They found

that choices involving statements about gains tend to

produce risk-averse responses, while those involving

losses are often risk seeking.

Page 118: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, in an experiment subjects were asked to

choose a program to combat a disease which was

otherwise expected to kill 600 people.

One group was told that Program A would certainly

save 200 lives while Program B offered

a 1/3 probability of saving all 600 people and

a 2/3 probability of saving nobody.

Most subjects preferred A.

Page 119: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

A second group were offered the equivalent choice,

but this time the statements referred to the number of

deaths, rather than lives saved. They were therefore

told that the first program would lead to 400 deaths

while the second would offer a 1/3 probability of

no deaths and a 2/3 probability of 600 deaths.

Most subjects in this group preferred the second

program, which clearly carries the higher risk.

Page 120: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Further experimental evidence that different

assessment methods lead to different utilities can be

found in a paper by Johnson and Schkade [16].

Page 121: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

What are the implications of this research for

utility assessment? First, it is clear that utility

assessment requires effort and commitment from the

decision maker. This suggests that, before the actual

elicitation takes place, there should be a pre-analysis

phase in which the importance of the task is explained

to the decision maker so that he will feel motivated to

think carefully about his responses to the questions

posed.

Page 122: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Second, the fact that different elicitation

methods are likely to generate different assessments

means that the use of several methods is advisable.

By posing questions in new ways the consistency of

the original utilities can be checked and any

inconsistencies between the assessments can be

explored and reconciled.

Page 123: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Third, since the utility assessments appear to be

very sensitive to both the values used and the context

in which the questions are framed it is a good idea to

phrase the actual utility questions in terms which are

closely related to the values which appear in the

original decision problem.

Page 124: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, if there is no chance of losses being

incurred in the original problem then the lotteries used

in the utility elicitation should not involve the chances

of incurring a loss. Similarly, if the decision problem

involves only very high or low probabilities then the

use of lotteries involving 50 : 50 chances should be

avoided.

Page 125: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.6 Attitudes Towards Risk

Consider the following situation. You own

a ”lottery” ticket with the following properties.

Tomorrow, a fair coin will be flipped.

If it lands heads up, you will receive $1 million.

If it lands tails up, you will receive nothing.

Page 126: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The ticket is transferable; that is, you can give or sell it

to another person, in which case this other person is

entitled to the winnings from the lottery ticket (if any).

Between today and tomorrow, people may approach

you about buying your ticket. What is the smallest

price that you would accept in exchange for your

ticket?

Page 127: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

A possible answer is $500, 000 because that is

the expected value of this lottery. Many people,

however, would be willing to accept less than

$500, 000. You, for instance, might be willing to sell

the ticket for as little as $400, 000, under the view that

a certain $400, 000 was worth the same as a half

chance at $1 million. Moreover, even if you are

unwilling to sell your ticket for $400, 000, many people

in your situation would be.

Page 128: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Selling your ticket for less than $500, 000 is,

however, inconsistent with being an expected-value

maximizer, because you wouldn’t be choosing the

alternative that yielded you the greatest expected

value. So, if you would, in fact, accept $400, 000, then

you are not an expected-value maximizer.

Page 129: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Moreover, even if you are (i.e., you wouldn’t sell for

less than $500, 000), others definitely aren’t. As

this discussion makes clear, we need to pay some

attention to decision makers who aren’t

expected-value maximizers. This is the task of this

section.

Page 130: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Risk aversion: A distate for risk.

Page 131: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

One reason that someone is not

an expected-value maximizer is that he is concerned

with the riskiness of the gambles he faces.

For instance, a critical difference between

an expected payoff of $500, 000 and a certain payoff

of $400, 000 is that there is considerable risk with the

former you might win $1 million, but you also might

end up with nothing but no risk with the latter.

Page 132: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Most people don’t like risk, and they are willing, in fact,

to pay to avoid it. Such people are called risk averse.

By accepting less than $500, 000 for the ticket,

you are effectively paying to avoid risk; that is, you are

behaving in a risk-averse fashion.

Page 133: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

When you buy insurance, thereby reducing or

eliminating your risk of loss, you are behaving in

a risk-averse fashion. When you put some of your

wealth in low-risk assets, such as government-insured

deposit accounts, rather than investing it all in

high-risk stocks with greater expected returns,

you are behaving in a risk-averse fashion.

Page 134: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To define risk aversion more formally, we give the

formal definition of a certainty equivalent value :

Definition 1 The certainty-equivalent value of

a gamble is the minimum payment a decision maker

would accept, if paid with certainty, rather than face

a gamble. The certainty-equivalent value is often

abbreviated CE.

Page 135: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, if $400, 000 is the smallest

amount that you would accept in exchange for

the lottery ticket discussed previously, then your

certainty- equivalent value for the gamble is $400, 000

(i.e., CE = $400, 000).

Page 136: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We can now define risk aversion formally:

Definition 2 A decision maker is risk averse if his or

her certainty value for any given gamble is less than

the expected value of that gamble. That is, we say

an individual is risk averse if CE ≤ EV for all gambles

and CE < EV for at least some gambles.

Risk neutral:

Unaffected by risk.

Page 137: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In contrast, an expected-value maximizer is

risk neutral – his or her decisions are unaffected by

risk. Formally,

Definition 3 A decision maker is risk neutral if

the certainty-equivalent value for any gamble is equal

to the expected value of that gamble; that is, he or she

is risk neutral if CE = EV for all gambles.

Page 138: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

At this point you might ask: When is it

appropriate (i.e., reasonably accurate) to assume

a decision maker is risk neutral and when is it

appropriate to assume he is risk averse?

Some answers:

Page 139: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Small stakes versus large stakes: If the amounts

of money involved in the gamble are small relative to

the decision maker’s wealth or income, then his

behavior will tend to be approximately risk neutral.

Page 140: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, for gambles involving sums less than

$10, most peoples behavior is approximately risk

neutral. On the other hand, if the amounts of money

involved are large relative to the decision maker’s

wealth or income, then his behavior will tend to be risk

averse. For example, for gambles involving sums of

more than $10, 000, most people’s behavior exhibits

risk aversion.

Page 141: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Small risks versus large risks: If the possible

payoffs (or at least the most likely to be realized

payoffs) are close to the expected value, then the risk

is small and the decision maker’s behavior will be

approximately risk neutral.

Page 142: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For instance, if the gamble is heads you win

$500,001, but tails you win $499,999, then

your behavior will be close to risk neutral since both

payoffs are close to the expected value

(i.e., $500,000). On the other hand, if the possible

payoffs are far from the expected value, then the risk

is greater and the decision maker’s behavior will tend

to be risk averse. For instance, we saw that we should

expect risk-averse behavior when the gamble was

heads you win $1 million, but tails you win $0.

Page 143: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Diversification: So far the question of whether

someone takes a gamble has been presented as

an all-or-nothing proposition. In many instances,

however, a person purchases a portion of a gamble.

Page 144: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, investing in General Motors

(or any other company) is a gamble, but you don’t

have to buy all of General Motors to participate in that

gamble. Moreover, at the same time you buy stock in

General Motors, you can purchase other securities,

giving you a portfolio of investments.

Page 145: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If you choose your portfolio wisely, you can diversify

away much of the risk that is unique to a given

company. That is, the risk that is unique to a given

company in your portfolio no longer concerns you you

are risk neutral with respect to it. Consequently,

you would like your firm to act as an expected-value

maximizer.

Page 146: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

As we discuss in the next section, diversified decision

makers are risk neutral (or approximately so),

while undiversified decision makers are more likely to

be risk averse.

Page 147: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Diversification

To clarify the issue of diversification, consider

the following example. There are two companies

in which you can invest. One sells ice cream.

The other sells umbrellas. Ice cream sales are greater

on sunny days than on rainy days, while umbrella

sales are greater on rainy days than on sunny days.

Page 148: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose that, on average, one out of four days is

rainy; that is, the probability of rain is 1/4.

On a rainy day, the umbrella company makes a profit

of $100 and the ice cream company makes

a profit of $0. On a sunny day, the umbrella company

makes a profit of $0 and the ice cream factory makes

a profit of $200.

Page 149: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose you invest in the umbrella company only;

specifically, suppose you own all of it. Then you face

a gamble: on rainy days you receive $100 and

on sunny days you receive nothing. Your expected

value is

Page 150: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose, in contrast, that you sell three quarters

of your holdings in the umbrella company and

use some of the proceeds to buy one eighth of

the ice cream factory. Now on rainy days you receive

$25 from the umbrella company (since you can claim

one quarter of the $100 profit), but nothing from the

ice cream company (since there are no profits).

Page 151: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

On sunny days you receive $25 from the ice cream

company (since you can claim one eighth of the

$200 profit), but nothing from the umbrella company

(since there are no profits). That is, rain or shine,

you receive $25 - your risk has disappeared!

Your expected value, however, has remained

the same (i.e., $25). This is the magic of

diversification.

Page 152: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Moreover, once you can diversify, you want

your companies to make expected - value -

maximizing decisions. Suppose, for instance, that

the umbrella company could change its strategy

so that it made a profit of $150 on rainy days, but

lost $10 on sunny days. This would increase its daily

expected profit by $5 - the new EV calculation is

Page 153: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It would also, arguably, increase the riskiness of

its profits by changing its strategy in this way.

Suppose, for convenience, that 100% of a company

trades on the stock exchange for 100 times

its expected daily earnings. The entire ice cream

company would, then, be worth

and the entire umbrella company would, then, be

worth $3, 000.

Page 154: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To return to your position of complete diversification

and earning $25 a day, you would have to reduce

your position in the umbrella company to hold one

sixth of the company and you would have to increase

your holdings of the ice cream company to th of

the company:

215

Page 155: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Earnings on a rainy day:

Earnings on a sunny day:

and

Page 156: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Going from holding one fourth of the umbrella

company to owning one sixth of the umbrella company

means selling th of the umbrella company, which

would yield you

112

Page 157: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Going from holding one eighth of the ice cream

company to owning ths means buying

an additional th of the ice cream company,

which would cost you

112

1120

Page 158: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Your profit from these stock market trades would be

$125. Moreover, you would still receive a riskless

$25 per day. So because you can diversify, you benefit

by having your umbrella company do something that

increases its expected value, even if it is riskier.

Page 159: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.7 Risk

Basing decisions on expected monetary values

(EMVs) is convenient, but it can lead to decisions that

may not seem intuitively appealing.

For example, consider the following two games.

Imagine that you have the opportunity to play one

game or the other, but only one time. Which one

would you prefer to play? Your choice also is drawn in

decision-tree form in Figure 3.15

Page 160: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 161: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Game 1 has an expected value of $14.50.

Game 2, on the other hand, has an expected value of

$50.00. If you were to make your choice on the basis

of expected value, then you would choose Game 2.

Most of us, however, would consider Game 2 to be

riskier than Game 1, and it seems reasonable

to suspect that most people actually would prefer

Game 1.

Page 162: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Using expected values to make decisions

means that the decision maker is considering only the

average or expected payoff. If we take

a long-run frequency approach, the expected value is

the average amount we would be likely to win over

many plays of the game. But this ignores the range of

possible values.

Page 163: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

After all, if we play each game 10 times, the worst we

could do in game 1 is to lose $10. On the other hand,

the worst we could do in Game 2 is lose $19, 000!

Page 164: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Many of the examples and problems that

we have considered so far have been analyzed

in terms of expected monetary value (EMV).

EMV, however, does not capture risk attitudes.

Page 165: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Individuals who are afraid of risk or are sensitive

to risk are called risk- averse. We could explain

risk aversion if we think in terms of a utility function

(Figure 3.16 ) that is curved and concave. This utility

function represents a way to translate dollars into

”utility units.”

Page 166: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

That is, if we take some dollar amount (x ), we can

locate that amount on the horizontal axis. Read up

to the curve and then horizontally across to the

vertical axis. From that point we can read off the utility

value U (x) for the dollars we started with.

Page 167: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

A utility function might be specified in terms of

a graph, as in Figure 3.16, or given as a table, as

in Table 3.4. A third form is a mathematical

expression. If graphed, for example, all of

the following expressions would have the same

general concave shape as the utility function graphed

in Figure 3.16:

Page 168: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 169: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 170: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Of course, the utility and dollar values

in Table 3.4 also could be graphed, as could

the functional forms shown above. Likewise, the graph

in Figure 3.16 could be converted into a table of

values. The point is that the utility function makes the

translation from dollars to utility regardless of

its displayed form.

Page 171: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.8 Risk Attitudes

We think of a typical utility curve as (1) convex and

(2) concave. A convex utility curve makes fine sense;

it means that more wealth is better than less wealth,

everything else being equal. Few people will argue

with this. Concavity in a utility curve implies that

an individual is risk-averse.

Page 172: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Imagine that you are forced to play the following game:

Win $500 with probability 0.5

Lose $500 with probability 0.5.

Page 173: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Would you pay to get out of this situation? How

much? The game has a zero expected value, so

if you would pay something to get out, you are

avoiding a risky situation with zero expected value.

Page 174: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Generally, if you would trade a gamble for

a sure amount that is less than the expected value

of the gamble, you are risk-averse.

Purchasing insurance is an example of risk-averse

behavior. Insurance companies analyze a lot of data

in order to understand the probability distributions

associated with claims for different kinds of policies.

Page 175: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Of course, this work is costly. To make up

these costs and still have an expected profit,

an insurance company must charge more for

its insurance policy than the policy can be expected to

produce in claims.

Page 176: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus, unless you have some reason to believe that

you are more likely than others in your risk group

to make a claim, you probably are paying more

in insurance premiums than the expected amount

you would claim.

Page 177: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Not everyone displays risk-averse behavior

all the time, and so utility curves need not be concave.

A convex utility curve indicates risk-seeking behavior

(Figure 3.7).

Page 178: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The risk seeker might be eager to enter into a gamble;

for example, he or she might pay to play the game just

described. An individual who plays a state lottery

exhibits risk-seeking behavior. State lottery tickets

typically cost $1.00 and have an expected value of

approximately 50 cents.

Page 179: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Finally, an individual can be risk-neutral.

Risk neutrality is reflected by a utility curve that is

simply a straight line. For this type of person,

maximizing EMV is the same as maximizing expected

utility. This makes sense; someone who is risk-neutral

does not care about risk and can ignore risk aspects of

the alternatives that he or she faces. Thus, EMV is

a fine criterion for choosing among alternatives,

because it also ignores risk.

Page 180: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.9 Expected Utility, Certainty Equivalents,

and Risk Premiums

Two concepts are closely linked to the idea of expected

utility. One is that of a certainty equivalent, or

the amount of money that is equivalent in your mind to

a given situation that involves uncertainty.

Page 181: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, suppose you face the following gamble:

Win $2000 with probability 0.5

Lose $20 with probability 0.5.

Page 182: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now imagine that one of your friends is interested in

taking your place. ”Sure,” you reply, ”I’ll sell it to you.”

After thought and discussion, you conclude that

the least you would sell your position for is $300.

If your friend cannot pay that much, then you would

rather keep the gamble. (Of course, if your friend were

to offer more, you would take it!)

Page 183: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Your certain equivalent for the gamble is $300.

This is a sure thing; no risk is involved.

From this, the meaning of certainty equivalent

becomes clear.

Page 184: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If $300 is the least that you would accept for

the gamble, then the gamble must be equivalent in

your mind to a sure $300.

Page 185: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Closely related to the idea of a certainty

equivalent is the notion of risk premium.

The risk premium is defined as the difference between

the EMV and the certainty equivalent:

Risk Premium = EMV – Certainty Equivalent

Page 186: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Consider the gamble between winning $2000 and

losing $20, each with probability 0.50.

The EMV of this gamble is $990. On reflection,

you assessed your certainty equivalent to be $300,

and so your risk premium is

Risk Premium = $990 − $300 = $690

Page 187: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Because you were willing to trade the gamble for

$300, you were willing to ”give up” $690 in expected

value in order to avoid the risk inherent in the gamble.

You can think of the risk premium as the premium you

pay (in the sense of a lost opportunity) to avoid

the risk.

Page 188: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 189: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Figure 3.17 graphically ties together

utility functions, certainty equivalents, and

risk premiums. Notice that the certainty equivalent

and the expected utility of a gamble are points

that are ”matched up” by the utility function. That is,

EU(Gamble) = U(Certainty Equivalent)

Page 190: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In words, the utility of the certainty equivalent is

equal to the expected utility of the gamble.

Because these two quantities are equal, the decision

maker must be indifferent to the choice between

them. After all, that is the meaning of certainty

equivalent.

Page 191: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For a risk-averse individual, the horizontal

EU line reaches the concave utility curve before

it reaches the vertical line that corresponds to the

expected value. Thus, for a risk-averse individual

the risk premium must be positive.

Page 192: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If the utility function were convex, the horizontal

EU line would reach the expected value before the

utility curve. The certainty equivalent would be

greater than the expected value, and so

the risk premium would be negative. This would imply

that the decision maker would have to be paid to give

up an opportunity to gamble.

Page 193: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In any given situation, the certainty equivalent,

expected value, and risk premium all depend on two

factors: the decision maker’s utility function and

the probability distributions for the payoffs. The values

that the payoff can take combine with the probabilities

to determine the EMV.

Page 194: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The utility function, coupled with the probability

distribution, determines the expected utility and hence

the certainty equivalent. The degree to which the

utility curve is nonlinear determines the distance

between the certainty equivalent and the expected

payoff.

Page 195: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.10 Risk Tolerance and the Exponential

Utility function

The assessment process described above works well

for assessing a utility function subjectively, and it can

be used in any situation, although it can involve a fair

number of assessments.

Page 196: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

An alternative approach is to base the assessment

on a particular mathematical function. In particular,

let us consider the exponential utility function:

U (x) = 1 − e−x/R .

Page 197: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This utility function is based on the constant

e = 2.71828..., the base of natural logarithm.

This function is concave and thus can be used to

interpret risk-averse preferences. As x becomes large,

U (x) approaches 1. The utility of zero, U (0), is

equal to 0, and the utility for negative x (being in debt)

is negative.

Page 198: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In the exponential utility function, R is

a parameter that determines how risk-averse

the utility function is. In particular, R is called the

risk tolerance. Larger values of R make

the exponential function flatter, while smaller values

make it more concave or more risk-averse.

Page 199: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus, if you are less risk-averse – if you can tolerate

more risk – you would assess a larger value for R

to obtain a flatter utility function. If you are

less tolerant of risk, then you would assess

a smaller R and have a more curved utility function.

Page 200: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

How can R be determined? A variety of ways

exist, but it turns out that R has a very intuitive

interpretation that makes its assessment relatively

easy. Consider the gamble

Win $Y with probability 0.5

Lose $Y /2 with probability 0.5.

Page 201: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Would you be willing to take this gamble if

Y were $100? $2000? $35000? Or, framing it as

an investment, how much would you be willing to risk

($Y/2) in order to have a 50% chance of tripling your

money (winning $Y and keeping your $Y/2) ? At what

point would the risk become intolerable?

Page 202: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The largest value of Y for which you would

prefer to take the gamble rather than not take it is

approximately equal to your risk tolerance. This is

the value that you can use for R in your exponential

utility function.

Page 203: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, suppose that after considering this lottery

you conclude that the largest Y for which you would

take the gamble is Y = $900. Hence, R = $900.

Using this assessment in the exponential utility function

would result in the utility function

U (x) = 1 − e−x / 900

This exponential utility function provides the translation

from dollars to utility units.

Page 204: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Once you have your R value and your

exponential utility function, it is fairly easy to find

certainty equivalents. For example, suppose that you

face the following gamble:

Win $2000 with probability 0.4

Win $1000 with probability 0.4

Win $500 with probability 0.2

Page 205: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The expected utility for this gamble is

EU = 0.4U ($2000) + 0.4U ($1000) + 0.2U ($500)

= 0.4(0.8916) + 0.4(0.6708) + 0.2(0.4262) = 0.7102.

Page 206: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To find the CE we must work backward through

the utility function. We want to find the value x such

that U (x) = 0.7102. Set up the equation

0.7102 = 1 − e−x/900 .

Page 207: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Subtract 1 from each side to get

−0.2898 = −e−x/900 .

Multiply through to eliminate the minus signs:

0.2898 = e−x/900 .

Page 208: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now we can take natural logs of both sides to

eliminate the exponential term:

ln(0.2898) = ln(e−x/900 ) = −x/900.

Now we simply solve for x :

x = −900[ln(0.2898)] = $1114.71

Page 209: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The procedure above requires that you use

the exponential utility function to translate the dollar

outcomes into utilities, find the expected utility, and

finally convert to dollars to find the exact certainty

equivalent. That can be a lot of work, especially

if there are many outcomes to consider. Fortunately,

an approximation is available from [18] and also

discussed in [17].

Page 210: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose you can figure out the expected value and

variance of the payoffs. Then the CE is approximately

where µ and σ2 are the expected value and variance,

respectively.

Page 211: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, in the gamble above, the expected value

(EMV or µ) equals $1300, and the standard deviation

(σ) equals $600. Thus, the approximation gives

Page 212: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The approximation is within $15. That’s pretty good!

This approximation is especially useful for continuous

random variables or problems where the expected

value and variance are relatively easy to estimate or

assess compared to assessing the entire probability

distribution. The approximation will be closest to

the actual value when the outcome’s probability

distribution is a symmetric, bell-shaped curve.

Page 213: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

What are reasonable R values?

For an individual’s utility function, the appropriate

value for R clearly depends on the individual’s risk

attitude. As indicated, the less risk-averse a person is,

the larger R is.

Page 214: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose, however, that an individual or a group

(a board of directors, say) has to make a decision

on behalf of a corporation. It is important that

these decision makers adopt a decision-making

attitude based on corporate goals and acceptable

risk levels for the corporation. This can be quite

different from an individual’s personal risk attitude; the

individual director may be unwilling to risk $10

million, even though the corporation can afford such a

loss.

Page 215: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Howard [15] suggests certain guidelines for

determining a corporation’s risk tolerance in terms of

total sales, net income, or equity. Reasonable values

of R appear to be approximately 6.4% of total sales,

1.24 times net income, or 15.7% of equity.

Page 216: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

These figures are based on observations that Howard

has made in the course of consulting with various

companies. More research may refine these figures,

and it may turn out that different industries have

different ratios for determining reasonable R′s.

Page 217: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Using the exponential utility function seems like

magic, doesn’t it? One assessment, and we are

finished! Why bother with all of those certainty

equivalents that we discussed above? You know,

however that you never get something for nothing,

and that definitely is the case here.

Page 218: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The exponential utility function has a specific kind of

curvature and implies a certain kind of risk attitude.

This risk attitude is called constant risk aversion.

Essentially it means that no matter how much wealth

you have – how much money in your pocket or

bank account – you would view a particular gamble

in the same way.

Page 219: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The gamble’s risk premium

(Risk Premium = EMV – Certainty Equivalent) would

be the same no matter how much money you have.

Is constant risk aversion reasonable? May be it is

for some people. Many individuals might be less

risk-averse if they had more wealth.

Page 220: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In later sections we will study the exponential

utility function in more detail, especially with regard to

constant risk aversion. The message here is that the

exponential utility function is most appropriate for

people who really believe that they would view

gambles the same way regardless of their wealth

level. But even if this is not true for you, the

exponential utility function can be a useful tool for

modeling preferences.

Page 221: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.11 Decreasing and Constant Risk Aversion

In this section we will consider how individuals might

deal with risky invesments. Suppose you had $1000

to invest. How would you feel about investing $500

in an extremely risky venture in which you might lose

the entire $500?

Page 222: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now suppose you have saved more money and have

$20,000. How would you feel about that extremely

risky venture? Is it more or less attractive to you?

How do you think a person’s degree of risk aversion

changes with wealth?

Page 223: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If an individual’s preferences show decreasing

risk aversion, then the risk premium

(Risk Premium = EMV – Certainty Equivalent)

decreases if a constant amount is added to all payoffs

in a gamble. Expressed informally, decreasing risk

aversion means the more money you have, the less

nervous you are about a particular bet.

Decreasing Risk Aversion

Page 224: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

For example, suppose an individual’s utility

curve can be described by a logarithmic function:

U (x) = ln(x)

where x is the wealth or payoff and ln(x) is the natural

logarithm of x.

Page 225: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Using this logarithmic utility function, consider the

gamble

Win $10 with probability 0.5

Win $40 with probability 0.5

Page 226: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To find the certainty equivalent, we first find

the expected utility. The utility values for $10 and $40

are

U ($10) = ln(10) = 2.3026

U ($40) = ln(40) = 3.6889.

Page 227: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Calculating expected utility:

EU = 0.5(2.3026) + 0.5(3.6889) = 2.9957.

Page 228: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To find the certainty equivalent, you must find the

certain value x that has U (x) = 2.9957; thus, set

the utility function equal to 2.9957:

2.9957 = ln(x).

Page 229: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now solve for x. To remove the logarithm, we take

antilogs:

e2.9957 = eln(x) = x.

Finally, we simply calculate

x = e2.9957 = $20 = CE.

Page 230: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

To find the risk premium, we need the expected

payoff, which is

EMV = 0.5($10) + 0.5($40) = $25.

Thus, the risk premium is

EMV - CE = $25 − $20 = $5.

Page 231: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Using the same procedure, we can find risk

premiums for the lotteries as shown in Table 3.5.

Page 232: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Notice that the sequence of lotteries is

constructed so that each is like having

the previous one plus $10. For example, the

$20 − $50 lottery is like having the $10 − $40 lottery

plus a $10 bill. The risk premium decreases with each

$10 addition. The decreasing risk premium reflects

decreasing risk aversion, which is a property of the

logarithmic utility function.

Page 233: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

An Investment Example

For another example, suppose that

an entrepreneur is considering a new business

investment. To participate, the entrepreneur must

invest $5000. There is a 25% chance that the

investment will earn back the $5000 leaving her just

as well off as if she had not made investment.

Page 234: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

But there is also a 45% chance that she will lose the

$5000 altogether, although this is counter-balanced

by a 30% chance that the investment will return

the original $5000 plus an additional $10, 000.

Page 235: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We will assume that this entrepreneur’s preferences

can be modeled with the logarithmic utility function

U (x) = ln(x), where x is interpreted as total wealth.

Suppose that the investor now has $10, 000.

Should she make the investment or avoid it?

Page 236: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The easiest way to solve this problem is

to calculate the expected utility of the investment and

compare it with the expected utility of the alternative,

which is to do nothing. The expected utility of doing

nothing simply is the utility of the current wealth, or

U (10, 000), which is

U (10, 000) = ln(10, 000) = 9.2103

Page 237: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The expected utility of the investment is easy to

calculate:

EU = 0.30U (20, 000) + 0.25U (10, 000) + 0.45U (5000)

= 0.30(9.9035) + 0.25(9.2103) + 0.45(8.5172) = 9.1064

Page 238: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 239: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Because the expected utility of the investment is

less than the utility of not investing, the investment

should not be made.

Page 240: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now, suppose that several years have passed.

The utility function has not changed, but

other investments have paid off handsomely, and

she currently has $70, 000. Should she undertake the

project now?

Page 241: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Recalculating with a base wealth of $70, 000 rather

than $10, 000, we find that the utility of doing nothing

is U(70, 000) = 11.1563, and the EU for the

investment is 11.1630. Now the expected utility of the

investment is greater than the utility of doing nothing,

and so she should invest.

Page 242: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The point of these examples is to show how

decreasing risk aversion determines the way in which

a decision maker views risky prospects. As indicated,

the wealthier a decreasingly risk-averse decision

maker is, the less anxious he or she will be about

taking a particular gamble.

Page 243: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Generally speaking, decreasing risk aversion makes

sense when we think about risk attitudes and the way

that many people appear to deal with risky situations.

Many would feel better about investing money in the

stock market if they were wealthier to begin with. For

such reasons, the logarithmic utility function is

commonly used by economists and decision theorists

as a model of typical risk attitudes.

Page 244: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Constant Risk Aversion

An individual displays constant risk aversion if

the risk premium for a gamble does not depend on

the initial amount of wealth held by the decision

maker. Intuitively, the idea is that a constantly risk-

averse person would be just as anxious about taking a

bet regardless of the amount of money available.

Page 245: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If an individual is constantly risk-averse,

the utility function is exponential. It would have the

following form:

U (x) = 1 − e−x/R

For example, suppose that the decision maker

has assessed a risk tolerance of $35 :

U (x) = 1 − e−x / 35

Page 246: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We can perform the same kind of analysis that we did

with the logarithmic utility function above.

Consider the gamble

Win $10 with probability 0.5

Win $40 with probability 0.5

Page 247: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

As before, the expected payoff is $25. To find

the CE, we must find the expected utility, which

requires plugging the amounts $10 and $40 into the

utility function:

U (10) = 1 − e−10 / 35 = 0.2485

U (40) = 1 − e−40 / 35 = 0.6811

Page 248: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus, EU = 0.5(0.2485) + 0.5(0.6811) = 0.4648.

To find the certainty equivalent, set the utility function

to 0.4648. The value for x that gives the utility of

0.4648 is the gamble’s CE:

0.4648 = 1 − e−x / 35

Page 249: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now we can solve for x as we did earlier when

working with the exponential utility function:

0.5352 = e−x / 35

ln(0.5352) = −0.6251 = −x/35

x = 0.6251(35) = $21.88 = C E

Page 250: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Finally, the expected payoff (EMV) is $25, and

so the risk premium is

Risk Premium = EMV - CE = $25 − $21.88 = $3.12

Page 251: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Using the same procedure, we can find the risk

premium for each gamble in Table 3.6.

The risk premium stays the same as long as the

difference between the payoffs does not change.

Adding a constant amount to both sides to both sides

of the gamble does not change the decision maker’s

attitude toward the gamble.

Page 252: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 253: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Alternatively, you can think about this as

a function where you have a bet in which you may

win $15 or lose $15. In the first gamble above, you

face this bet with $25 in your pocket.

Page 254: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In the constant-risk-aversion situation, the way

you feel about the bet (as reflected in the risk

premium) is the same regardless of how much money

is added to your pocket. In the decreasing-risk-

aversion situation, adding something to your pocket

made you less risk- averse toward the bet, thus

resulting in a lower risk premium.

Page 255: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Figure 3.19 plots the two utility functions on the

same graph. They have been rescaled so that

U (10) = 0 and U (100) = 1 in each case. Note

their similarity. It does not take a large change in the

utility curve’s shape to alter the nature of the

individual’s risk attitude. Is constant risk aversion

appropriate?

Page 256: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The argument easily can be made that the more

wealth one has, the easier it is to take larger risks.

Thus, decreasing risk aversion appears to provide

a more appropriate model of preferences than does

constant risk aversion. This is an important point to

keep in mind if you decide to use the exponential

utility function and the risk-tolerance parameter;

this utility function displays constant risk aversion.

Page 257: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 258: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

After all is said and done, while the concepts of

decreasing or constant risk aversion may be intriguing

from the point of view of a decision maker who is

interested in modeling his or her risk attitude, precise

determination of a decision maker’s utility function is

not yet possible. Decision theorists still are learning

how to elicit and measure utility functions.

Page 259: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Many unusual effects arise from human nature. It

would be an overstatement to suggest that it is

possible to determine precisely the degree of

an individual’s risk aversion or whether he or she is

decreasingly risk-averse. It is difficult enough problem

just to determine whether someone is risk-averse or

risk-seeking!

Page 260: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Thus, it may be reasonable to use

the exponential utility function as an approximation

in modeling preferences and risk attitudes. A quick

assessment of risk tolerance, and you are in your way.

And if even that seems a bit strained, then it is always

possible to use the sensitivity-analysis approach;

it may be that a precise assessment of the risk

tolerance is not necessary.

Page 261: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Some Caveats

A few things remain to be said about utilities.

These are thoughts to keep in mind as you work

through utility assessments and use utilities

in decision problems.

Page 262: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

1. Utilities do not add up. That is,

This actually is the whole

point of having a nonlinear utility function.U(A+B) U(A) + U(B). ¹

Page 263: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

2. Utility differences do not express strength of

preferences. Suppose that U(A1)−U(A2)>U(A3)−U (A4).

This does not necessarily mean that you would rather

go from A2 to A1 instead of from A4 to A3 . Utility only

provides a numerical scale for ordering preferences,

not a measure of their strengths.

Page 264: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3. Utilities are not comparable from person to

person. A utility function is a subjective personal

statement of an individual’s preferences and so

provides no basis for comparing utilities among

individuals.

Page 265: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.12 How useful is utility in practice?

We have seen that utility theory is designed to provide

guidance on how to choose between alternative

courses of action under conditions of uncertainty, but

how useful is utility in practice?

Page 266: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It is really worth going to the trouble of asking the

decision maker a series of potentially difficult

questions about imaginary lotteries given that, as

we have just seen, there are likely to be errors in the

resulting assessments?

Page 267: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Interestingly, in a survey of published decision

analysis applications over a 20-year period, Corner

and Corner [8] found that 2 / 3 of applications used

expected values as the decision criterion and reported

no assessment of attitudes to risk. We will summarize

here arguments both for and against the application of

utility and then present our own views at the end of

the section.

Page 268: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

First, let us restate that the raison d’etre of utility

is that it allows the attitude to risk of the decision

maker to be taken into account in the decision model.

Consider again the drug research problem which we

discussed earlier.

Page 269: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

We might have approached this in three different

ways. First, we could have simply taken the course of

action which led to the shortest expected

development time. These expected times would have

been calculated as follows:

Page 270: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Expected development time of continuing with

the existing method

= 0.4 × 6 + 0.6 × 4 = 4.8 years.

Expected development time of switching to new

research approach

= 0.2 × 1 + 0.4 × 2 + 0.48 = 4.2 years.

Page 271: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The adoption of this criterion would therefore

suggest that we should switch to the new research

approach. However, this criterion ignores two factors.

First, it assumes that each extra year of development

time is perceived as being equally bad by the decision

maker, whereas it is possible, for example, that an

increase in time from 1 to 2 years is much less serious

than an increase from 7 to 8 years.

Page 272: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This factor could be captured by a value function

(which is not considered in our course). The derivation

of which does not involve any considerations about

probability, and it therefore will not capture the second

omission from the above analysis, which is, of course,

the attitude to risk of the decision maker.

A utility function is therefore designed to allow both of

these factors to be taken into account.

Page 273: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Despite this, there are a number of arguments

against the use of utility. Perhaps the most persuasive

relates to the problems of measuring utility. As Tocher

[23] has argued, the elicitation of utilities takes the

decision maker away from the real world of the

decision to a world of hypothetical lotteries. Because

these lotteries are only imaginary, the decision

maker’s judgments about the relative attractiveness of

the lotteries may not reflect what he would really do.

Page 274: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It is easy to say that you are prepared to accept

a 10% risk of losing $10, 000 in a hypothetical lottery,

but would you take the risk if you were really facing

this decision? Others argue that if utilities can only

be measured approximately then it may not always be

worth taking the trouble to assess them since a value

function, which is more easily assessed, would offer

a good enough approximation. Indeed, even Howard

Raiffa [19], a leading proponent of the utility approach,

argues:

Page 275: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

”Many analysts assume that a value scoring

system-designed for trade-offs under certainty can

also be used for probabilistic choice (using expected

values). Such an assumption is wrong theoretically, but

as I become more experienced I gain more tolerance

for these analytical simplifications. This is, I believe,

a relatively benign mistake in practice.”

Page 276: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Another criticism of utility relates to what is

known as Allais’s paradox. To illustrate this, suppose

that you were offered the choice of options A and B as

shown in Figure 3.20. Which would you choose?

Experiments suggest that most people would

choose A. After all, $1 million for certain is extremely

attractive while option B offers only a small probability

of $5 million and a chance of receiving $0.

Page 277: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 278: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Now consider the two options X and Y which are

shown in Figure 3.21. Which of these would you

choose? The most popular choice in experiments is X.

With both X and Y, the chances of winning are almost

the same, so it would seem to make sense to go for

the option offering the biggest prize.

Page 279: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 280: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

However, if you did choose options A and X your

judgments are in conflict with utility theory, as we will

now show. If we let u($5m) = 1 and u($0) = 0, then

selecting option A suggests that:

Page 281: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

u($1m) is greater than

0.89u($1m) + 0.1u($5m) + 0.01u($0m)

i.e. u($1m) exceeds 0.89u($1m) + 0.1 which implies:

u($1m) exceeds 0.1/0.11.

Page 282: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

However, choosing X implies that:

0.9u($0) + 0.1u($5m) exceeds 0.89u($0) + 0.11u($1m)

i.e. 0.1 exceeds 0.11u($1m)

so that: u($1m) is less than 0.1 / 0.11.

Page 283: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

This paradox has stimulated much debate

since it was put forward in 1953. However, we should

emphasize that utility theory does not attempt to

describe the way in which people make decisions like

those posed above. It is intended as a normative

theory, which indicates what a rational decision maker

should do if he accepts the axioms of the theory.

Page 284: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The fact that people make inconsistent judgments does

not by itself invalidate the theory. Nevertheless,

it seems sensible to take a relaxed view of the problem.

Remember that utility theory is designed as simply

an aid to decision making, and if a decision maker

wants to ignore its indications then that is

his prerogative.

Page 285: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Having summarized some of the main

arguments, what are our views on the practical

usefulness of utility? First, we have doubts about the

practice adopted by some analysts of applying utility

to decisions where risk and uncertainty are not central

to the decision maker’s concerns. Introducing

questions about lotteries and probabilities to these

sorts of problems seems to us to be unnecessary.

Page 286: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In these circumstances the problem of trading off

conflicting objectives is likely to be the main concern,

and we would therefore recommend the approach of

Decision making in multi-criteria environment.

Page 287: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In important problems which do involve a high level of

uncertainty and risk we do feel that utility has

a valuable role to play as long as the decision maker

is familiar with the concept of probability, and has

the time and patience to devote the necessary effort

and thought to the questions required by the elicitation

procedure.

Page 288: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

In these circumstances the derivation of utilities may

lead to valuable insights into the decision problem.

In view of the problems associated with utility

assessment, we should not regard the utilities as

perfect measures and automatically follow the course

of action they prescribe. Instead, it is more sensible to

think of the utility function as a useful tool for gaining

a greater understanding of the problem.

Page 289: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If the decision maker does not have the

characteristics outlined above or only requires rough

guidance on a problem then it may not be worth

eliciting utilities.

Page 290: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Given the errors which are likely to occur in utility

assessment, the derivation of values (as opposed to

utilities) and the identification of the course of action

yielding the highest expected value may offer a robust

enough approach. (Indeed, there is evidence that

linear utility functions are extremely robust

approximations.) Sensitivity analysis would, of course,

reveal just how precise the judgments needed to be.

Page 291: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13 Exercises

3.13.1. An entertainment company is organizing a pop

concert in London. The company has to decide how

much it should spend on publicizing the event and

three options have been identified:

Page 292: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Option 1: Advertise only in the music press;

Option 2: As option 1 but also advertise in the national

press;

Option 3: As options 1 and 2 but also advertise on

commercial radio.

For simplicity, the demand for tickets is categorized as

low, medium or high.

Page 293: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The payoff table below shows how the profit which the

company will earn for each option depends on the

level of demand.

Page 294: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

It is estimated that if option 1 is adopted

the probabilities of low, medium and high demand are

0.4, 0.5 and 0.1, respectively. For option 2 the

respective probabilities are 0.1, 0.3 and 0.6 while for

option 3 they are 0.05, 0.15 and 0.8. Determine the

option which will lead to the highest expected profit.

Would you have any reservations about

recommending this option to the company?

Page 295: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.2. A speculator is considering the purchase

of a commodity which he reckons has a 60% chance

of increasing in value over the next month.

If he purchases the commodity and it does increase in

value the speculator will make a profit of about

$200, 000, otherwise he will lose $60, 000.

Page 296: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) Assuming that the expected monetary value

criterion is applicable, determine whether

the speculator should purchase the commodity.

Page 297: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(b) Perform a sensitivity analysis on the speculators

estimate of the probability of a price increase and

interpret your result.

Page 298: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(c) What reservations would you have about applying

the expected monetary value criterion in this context?

Page 299: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.3. A team of scientists is due to spend six

months in Antarctica carrying out research. One major

piece of equipment they will be taking is subject to

breakdowns caused by the sudden failure of

a particular component. Because a failed component

cannot be repaired the team intend to carry a stock of

spare units of the component, but it will cost them

roughly $3, 000 for each spare unit they take with

them.

Page 300: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

However, if the equipment breaks down and a spare

is not available a new unit will have to be specially

flown in and the team will incur a total cost of $4, 000

for each unit that is delivered in this way.

Page 301: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

An engineer who will be traveling with the team has

estimated that the number of spares that will be

required during the six months follows the probability

distribution shown below:

Page 302: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Determine the number of spares that the team

should carry if their objective is to minimize expected

costs.

Page 303: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.4. You are a contestant on a television

game show and you have won $5, 000 so far. You are

now offered a choice: either you can keep the money

and leave or you can continue into the next round,

where you have a 70% chance of increasing your

winnings to $10, 000 and a 30% chance of losing the

$5, 000 and finishing the game with nothing.

Page 304: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) Which option would you choose?

(b) How does your choice compare with that which

would be prescribed by the expected monetary

value criterion?

Page 305: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.5. A building contractor is submitting

an estimate to a potential customer for carrying out

some construction work at the customer’s premises.

The builder reckons that if he offers to carry out the

work for $150,000 there is a 0.2 probability that

the customer will agree to the price, a 0.5 probability

that a price of $120, 000 would eventually be agreed

and a 0.3 probability that the customer will simply

refuse the offer and give the work to another builder.

Page 306: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If the builder offers to carry out the work for

$100,000 he reckons that there is a 0.3 probability

that the customer will accept this price,

a 0.6 probability that the customer will bargain so that

a price of $80,000 will eventually be agreed and

a 0.1 probability that the customer will refuse the offer

and take the work elsewhere.

Page 307: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) Determine which price the builder should quote in

order to maximize the expected payment he

receives from the customer.

(b) Suppose that, after some questioning, the builder

is able to make the following statements:

Page 308: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

”I am indifferent between receiving $120,000 for

certain or entering a lottery that will give me

a 0.9 probability of $150,000 and a 0.1 probability of

winning $0.”

Page 309: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

”I am indifferent between receiving $100,000 for

certain or entering a lottery that will give me

a 0.85 probability of winning $150,000 and

a 0.15 probability of winning $0.”

Page 310: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

”I am indifferent between receiving $80,000 for

certain or entering a lottery that will give me a 0.75

probability of winning $150,000 and a 0.25 probability

of winning $0.”

Page 311: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(i) Sketch the builder’s utility function and comment on

what it shows.

(ii) In the light of the above statements which price

should the builder now quote to the customer and

why?

Page 312: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.6. (a) Use the following questions to assess

your own utility function for money values between

$0 and $5, 000. You should assume that all sums of

money referred to will be received immediately.

Page 313: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(i) You are offered either a sum of money for certain or

a lottery ticket that will give you a 50% chance of

winning $5,000 and a 50% chance of winning $0.

Write down below the certain sum of money which

would make you indifferent between whether you

received it or the lottery ticket.

$... (we will now refer to this sum of money as X)

The utility of X is 0.5.

Page 314: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(ii) You are now offered a lottery ticket which offers

you a 50% chance of $... (enter X here) and a 50%

chance of $0. Alternatively, you will receive a sum of

money for certain. Write down below the certain sum

of money which would make you indifferent between

whether you received it or the lottery ticket.

$....

The utility of this sum of money is 0.25.

Page 315: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(iii) Finally, you are offered a sum of money for certain

or a lottery ticket which will give you a 50% chance of

$5,000 and a 50% chance of $... (enter X here). Write

down below the certain sum of money which would

make you indifferent between whether you received it

or the lottery ticket.

$...

The utility of this sum of money is 0.75.

Page 316: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(b) Plot your utility function and discuss what it

reveals.

(c) Discuss the strengths and limitations of the

assessment procedure which was used in (a).

Page 317: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

The following exercises are taken from [7].

3.13.7. Why is it important for decision makers to

consider their attitudes toward risk?

Page 318: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13-8. We have not given a specific definition of

risk. How would you define it? Give examples of

lotteries that vary in riskiness in terms of your definition

of risk.

3.13.9. Explain in your own words the idea of

a certainty equivalent.

3.13.10. Explain what is meant by the term risk

premium.

Page 319: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.11. Explain in your own words the idea of

risk tolerance. How would it apply to utility functions

other than the exponential utility function?

Page 320: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.12. Suppose a decision maker has the

utility function shown in Table 3.9. An investment

opportunity has EMV $1236 and expected utility 0.93.

Find the certainty equivalent for his investment and

the risk premium.

Page 321: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.13. A decision maker’s assessed risk

tolerance is $1210. Assume that this individual’s

preferences can be modeled as an exponential

function.

(a) Find U ($1000), U ($800), U ($0), and

U (−$1250).

Page 322: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(b) Find the expected utility for an investment

that has the following payoff distribution:

P ($1000) = 0.33

P ($800) = 0.21

P ($0) = 0.33

P (−$1250) = 0.13

(c) Find the certainty equivalent for the

investment and the risk premium.

Page 323: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.14. Investment D below is said to show

”second order stochastic dominance” over Investment

C. In this problem, it is up to you to explain why D

dominates C.

You are contemplating two alternative uncertain

investments, whose distributions for payoffs are as

below in Table 3.10 .

Page 324: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr
Page 325: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

If your preference function is given by

U (x) = 1 − e−x/100 , calculate EU for both C and D.

Which would you choose?

Page 326: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.15. Utility functions need not relate to dollar

values. Here is a problem in which we know little about

the abstract outcomes. What is important, however, is

that a person who does know what A to E represent

should be able to compare the outcomes using the

lottery procedures we have studied.

Page 327: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

A decision maker faces a risky gamble in which

she may obtain one of five outcomes. Label the

outcomes A, B, C, D, and E. A is the most preferred,

and E is least preferred. She has made the following

three assessments.

Page 328: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) She is indifferent between having C for sure or

a lottery in which she wins A with probability 0.5 or

E with probability 0.5.

(b) She is indifferent between having B for sure or

a lottery in which she wins A with probability 0.4 or

C with probability 0.6.

Page 329: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(c) She is indifferent between these two lotteries:

1: A 50% chance at B and a 50% chance at D

2: A 50% chance at A and a 50% chance at E.

What are U(A), U(B), U(C), U(D), and U(E)?

Page 330: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.16. An investor with assets of $10, 000 has

an opportunity to invest $5000 in a venture that is

equally likely to pay either $15, 000 or nothing. The

investor’s utility function can be described by the

logarithmic utility function U(x) = ln(x), where x is his

total wealth.

(a) What should the investor do?

Page 331: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(b) Suppose the investor places a bet with

a friend before making the investment decision. The

bet is for $1000; if a fair coin lands heads up, the

investor wins $1000, but if it lands tails up, the

investor pays $1000 to his friend. Only after the bet

has been resolved will the investor decide whether or

not to invest in the venture. What is an appropriate

strategy for the investor? If he wins the bet, should he

invest? What if he loses the bet?

Page 332: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.17. ([2]) A bettor with utility function

U(x) = ln(x), where x is total wealth, has a choice

between the following two alternatives:

A Win $10, 000 with probability 0.2

Win $1000 with probability 0.8

B Win $3000 with probability 0.9

Lose $2000 with probability 0.1

Page 333: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) If the bettor has $2500, should he choose A or B?

(b) Repeat (a), assuming the bettor has $5000.

(c) Repeat (a), assuming the bettor has $10, 000.

(d) Do you think that this pattern of choices between A

and B is reasonable?

Why or why not?

Page 334: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.18. Repeat Problem 3.13-17 with

U(x) = 0.0003x − 8.48e−x / 2775 . A utility function of this

form is called linear-plus-exponential, because

it contains both linear (0.0003x) and exponential

terms. It has a number of interesting and useful

properties, including the fact that it only switches once

among any pair of lotteries (such as those

in Problem 16) as wealth increases. (see Bell [3, 4])

Page 335: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.19. Show that the linear-plus-exponential

utility function in Problem 3.13-18 has decreasing risk

aversion. (Hint: You can use this utility function to

evaluate a series of lotteries like those given

in Problem 3.13-18. Show that the risk premium for

a gamble decreases as wealth increases.)

Page 336: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13-20. Buying and selling prices for risky

investments obviously are related to certainty

equivalents. This problem, however, shows that

the prices depend on exactly what is owned in the

first place!

Page 337: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

Suppose that Tugce Gursoy’s utility for total

wealth (A) can be represented by the utility function

U(A) = ln(A). She currently has $1000 in cash.

A business deal of interest to her yields a reward of

$100 with probability 0.5 and $0 with probability 0.5.

If she owns this business deal in addition to the

$1000, what is the smallest amount for which she

would sell the deal?

Page 338: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

3.13.21. ([25]) Suppose that a person’s utility

function for total wealth is U(A) = 200A − A2 for

0 ≤ A ≤ 100 where A represents total wealth in

thousands of dollars.

Page 339: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(a) Graph this preference function. How would

you classify this person with regard to her attitude

toward risk?

(b) If the person’s total assets are currently

$10K, (=$10, 000) should she take a bet in which she

will win $10K with probability 0.6 and lose $10K with

probability 0.4?

Page 340: Decision Theory - eskisehir.edu.tr

(c) If the person’s total assets are currently

$90K, should she take the bet given in part (b) ?

(d) Compare your answers to parts (b) and (c).

Does the person’s betting behavior seem reasonable

to you? How could you intuitively explain such

behavior?