Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    1/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 1

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Topic 4: Fun and GamesTopic 4: Fun and Games

    Economics 21, Summer 2002

    Andreas Bentz

    Based Primarily on Shy Chapter 2

    and Varian Chapter 27, 28

    2

    Review: Choices and OutcomesReview: Choices and Outcomes

    Consumer theory:

    From a given choice set (e.g. budget set), choose

    the option (e.g. bundle of goods) that you most

    prefer.

    Under certainty, the outcome of choice is certain.

    Choose the option that has an outcome that maximizesutility.

    Under uncertainty, the probability distribution over

    possible outcomes is known.

    Choose the action (associated with a number of

    outcomes, where each occurs with given probability) that

    maximizes expected utility.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    2/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 2

    3

    Choices and Outcomes, contdChoices and Outcomes, contd

    Producer theory - two extreme cases: Perfect competition:

    From a range of possible prices, choose the price

    that maximizes profit.

    Under certainty, the outcome of choice is certain:

    p > MC: zero demand,

    p < MC: negative profit,

    p = MC: zero profit.

    Under uncertainty, the probability distribution over

    possible outcomes is known.

    Maximize expected profit (not covered).

    4

    Choices and Outcomes, contdChoices and Outcomes, contd

    Monopolist:

    From the price-quantity pairs given by the demand

    curve, choose the one that maximizes profit.

    Under certainty, the outcome of choice is certain:

    = p x q(p) - c(q(p))

    Under uncertainty, the probability distribution overpossible outcomes is known.

    Maximize expected profit (not covered).

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    3/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 3

    5

    Choices against NatureChoices against Nature

    In these cases, choice is the choice of one agent, froma given set of alternatives that give certain (expected)

    utility (or profit).

    The agents choice is a game against nature:

    The agent chooses an action (associated with a number of

    outcomes). Then nature chooses the outcome that actually

    occurs:

    Under certainty, nature chooses the single outcome for sure.

    Under uncertainty, nature chooses one of the possible

    outcomes (with the probability of that outcome).

    The agent cannot influence natures move in thisgame.

    6

    Modeling InteractionModeling Interaction

    In general, in all social interaction, my choice

    of action influences your choice (because my

    action influences your payoff [utility, profit],

    and your action influences mine).

    Example (duopoly): How I choose my price

    depends on how I expect you to choose your price,which depends on how you expect me to choose

    my price, which depends on how I expect you to

    choose because our profits depend on how we

    both choose prices.

    We call these social encounters games.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    4/38

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    5/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 5

    9

    A Classification of GamesA Classification of Games

    Simultaneous move games (static games): All players make their choices at the same time.

    Method of analysis: (usually) games in normal

    (or, strategic) form.

    Sequential move games (dynamic games):

    Some players make their choices first, then other

    players observe these choices and then make

    theirs, etc.

    Method of analysis: games in extensive form.

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Normal Form GamesNormal Form Games

    Simultaneous Move Games

    in Normal (Strategic) Form

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    6/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 6

    11

    Normal Form GamesNormal Form Games

    Definition: A normal form game (or, strategicform game) is defined by:

    the set ofplayers in the game;

    the strategies (actions) that are available to each

    player;

    each player chooses one of her available strategies; a

    strategy profile is a list of the strategies chosen by each

    player;

    thepayoffs for each player, depending on the

    choice of action of every player; i.e. each players payoff depends on the strategy profile.

    Analogy with parlor games: e.g. Pong.

    12

    Example: The Price War GameExample: The Price War Game

    Duopolists: player 1 (row), player 2 (column)

    Player 2:

    cut price dont cut

    cut price (1, 1) (3, 0)Player 1:

    dont cut (0, 3) (2, 2)

    This normal form (or strategic form) of the

    game captures all the information needed.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    7/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 7

    13

    The Price War Game, contdThe Price War Game, contd

    The normal form captures all the informationthe definition requires:

    Players: {1, 2}

    Available strategies:

    player 1: {cut price, dont cut}

    player 2: {cut price, dont cut}

    Strategy profiles: Payoffs: player 1 - player 2

    (cut price, cut price) 1 1

    (cut price, dont cut) 3 0

    (dont cut, cut price) 0 3

    (dont cut, dont cut) 2 2

    14

    Equilibrium in GamesEquilibrium in Games

    What is our prediction for the play of a game?

    Which strategies will agents choose?

    What is an appropriate definition of equilibrium in

    games?

    What do we want from an equilibrium

    concept?

    Existence: The equilibrium concept should yield a

    prediction for all games.

    Uniqueness: The equilibrium concept should yield a

    unique prediction of equilibrium play in all games.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    8/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 8

    15

    Dominant StrategiesDominant Strategies

    Suggestion 1:If a player has some strategy that gives her a

    higher payoff than any other strategy she

    could choose, regardless of what the other

    players in the game do, she will choose that

    strategy.

    Such a strategy is called a dominant strategy.

    16

    Dominant Strategies, contdDominant Strategies, contd

    Equilibrium prediction: If every player has a

    dominant strategy, every player will choose

    that dominant strategy.

    Definition: An equilibrium in dominant

    strategies (ordominant strategy equilibrium) is

    a strategy profile in which every player

    chooses her dominant strategy.

    This is an intuitively appealing and robust

    equilibrium concept.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    9/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 9

    17

    The Price War Game, contdThe Price War Game, contd

    What is the dominant strategy equilibrium?

    Player 2:

    cut price dont cut

    cut price (1, 1) (3, 0)

    Player 1:dont cut (0, 3) (2, 2)

    The equilibrium strategy profile in dominant strategies

    is (cut price, cut price).

    In this equilibrium the payoffs are: (1, 1).

    18

    Fun: Prisoners Dilemma GameFun: Prisoners Dilemma Game

    Relabelling players and strategies in the price

    war game, we get the prisoners dilemma

    game (political philosophy, politics):

    Prisoner 2:

    confess lie

    confess (1, 1) (3, 0)

    Prisoner 1:lie (0, 3) (2, 2)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    10/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 10

    19

    The Advertising GameThe Advertising Game

    Duopolists 1 and 2 decide on advertisingexpenditure.

    2:

    low med. high

    low (1, 1) (0, 3) (0, 2)

    1: med. (3, 0) (1, 1) (0, 3)

    high (2, 0) (3, 0) (1, 1)

    What is the dominant strategy equilibrium in

    this game?

    20

    The Advertising Game, contdThe Advertising Game, contd

    In this game, no player has a dominant

    strategy.

    There is no dominant strategy equilibrium.

    What should our equilibrium prediction be?

    (Most games do not have a dominant strategyequilibrium.)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    11/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 11

    21

    Nash EquilibriumNash Equilibrium

    Suggestion 2:If there is a (potential equilibrium) strategy

    profile in which no player wishes to deviate

    unilaterally (i.e. choose a different strategy

    while all other players continue playing their

    (potential equilibrium) strategies), this will be

    the equilibrium of the game.

    Definition: An equilibrium in which no player

    wishes to deviate unilaterally is called a Nashequilibrium (John Nash, 1951).

    22

    The Price War Game, contdThe Price War Game, contd

    What is the Nash equilibrium in the price war

    game?

    Player 2:

    cut price dont cut

    cut price (1, 1) (3, 0)Player 1:

    dont cut (0, 3) (2, 2)

    Check each potential equilibrium strategy

    profile.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    12/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 12

    23

    Nash E. and Dominant StrategiesNash E. and Dominant Strategies

    Proposition: Every dominant strategyequilibrium is also a Nash equilibrium.

    Proof: In a dominant strategy equilibrium, each

    player is playing the strategy that gives them

    the highest payoff regardless of what the other

    players do. Therefore, no player would want to

    deviate: all other strategies open to the players

    are worse.

    But: not every Nash equilibrium is a dominantstrategy equilibrium.

    24

    The Advertising Game, contdThe Advertising Game, contd

    What is the Nash equilibrium in the

    advertising game?

    2:

    low med. high

    low (1, 1) (0, 3) (0, 2)1: med. (3, 0) (1, 1) (0, 3)

    high (2, 0) (3, 0) (1, 1)

    The unique Nash equilibrium strategy profile is

    (high, high).

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    13/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 13

    25

    Existence of Nash EquilibriumExistence of Nash Equilibrium

    Proposition (Nash): A Nash equilibrium(possibly in mixed strategies) exists in every

    game.

    Mixed strategies are strategies where players

    randomize over strategies.

    Example (mixed strategy): My advertising

    expenditure is: low with probability 0.3, medium

    with prob. 0.2, high with probability 0.5.

    This course does not cover mixed strategies. Is the Nash equilibrium prediction unique?

    26

    The Standards GameThe Standards Game

    Duopolists decide simultaneously on the

    standard for VCRs.

    Sony (2):

    VHS Beta

    VHS (2, 1) (0, 0)JVC (1):

    Beta (0, 0) (1, 2)

    What is the Nash equilibrium in this game?

    There are two Nash equilibria (in pure strat.).

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    14/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 14

    27

    Fun: Battle of the Sexes GameFun: Battle of the Sexes Game

    Lovers decide where to go on a Friday night:Her:

    boxing ballet

    boxing (2, 1) (0, 0)

    Him:ballet (0, 0) (1, 2)

    Although he prefers boxing, and she prefers

    ballet, each would rather be with the otherthan on their own.

    28

    Nash Equilibrium and UniquenessNash Equilibrium and Uniqueness

    Nash equilibria are not unique.

    Can we somehow trim down the number of

    Nash equilibria?

    Thomas Schelling The Strategy of Conflict:

    Some equilibria in co-ordination games such as the battle

    of the sexes game are salient. For instance, going

    whereverhe prefers has been salient (is no longer?).

    The overall conclusion is negative: there is no

    uncontested way of paring down the number of

    Nash equilibria.

    Are multiple equilibria a feature of the world?

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    15/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 15

    29

    Best ResponsesBest Responses

    Another way of thinking about Nash equilibriais in terms of best responses:

    Definition: A players best response to the

    strategies played by the other players, is the

    strategy that gives her the highest payoff,

    given the strategies played by the other

    players.

    30

    Best Responses, contdBest Responses, contd

    Example: the price war game:

    Player 2:

    cut price dont cut

    cut price (1, 1) (3, 0)

    Player 1:

    dont cut (0, 3) (2, 2)

    1s best response to 2 playing (cut price) is: (cut price).

    1s best response to 2 playing (dont cut) is: (cut price).

    2s best response to 1 playing (cut price) is: (cut price).

    2s best response to 1 playing (dont cut) is: (cut price).

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    16/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 16

    31

    Best Responses, contdBest Responses, contd

    Example: the standards game:Sony (2):

    VHS Beta

    VHS (2, 1) (0, 0)

    JVC (1):Beta (0, 0) (1, 2)

    1s best response to 2 playing (VHS) is: (VHS).

    1s best response to 2 playing (Beta) is: (Beta).

    2s best response to 1 playing (VHS) is: (VHS).

    2s best response to 1 playing (Beta) is: (Beta).

    32

    Nash and Best ResponsesNash and Best Responses

    Proposition: In a Nash equilibrium, every

    players equilibrium strategy is her best

    response to the other players equilibrium

    strategy.

    Proof: In a Nash equilibrium, no player wishes

    to deviate, given the other players continue to

    play their Nash equilibrium strategies.

    Therefore, her strategy must be the best

    response to the other players equilibrium

    strategies.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    17/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 17

    33

    Nash and Best Responses, contdNash and Best Responses, contd

    Example: the price war game: 1s best response to 2 playing (cut price) is: (cut price).

    1s best response to 2 playing (dont cut) is: (cut price).

    2s best response to 1 playing (cut price) is: (cut price).

    2s best response to 1 playing (dont cut) is: (cut price).

    Player 2:

    cut price dont cut

    cut price (1, 1) (3, 0)

    Player 1: dont cut (0, 3) (2, 2)

    34

    Nash and Best Responses, contdNash and Best Responses, contd

    Example: the standards game:

    1s best response to 2 playing (VHS) is: (VHS).

    1s best response to 2 playing (Beta) is: (Beta).

    2s best response to 1 playing (VHS) is: (VHS).

    2s best response to 1 playing (Beta) is: (Beta).

    Sony (2):

    VHS Beta

    VHS (2, 1) (0, 0)

    JVC (1):Beta (0, 0) (1, 2)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    18/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 18

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    ApplicationsApplications

    between monopoly and perfectcompetition ...

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Market Structure III:Market Structure III:

    An ApplicationAn Application

    Simultaneous Price Setting:

    The Bertrand Game (1883)

    (Shy pp. 107-110)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    19/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 19

    37

    The Bertrand GameThe Bertrand Game

    The game: Players:

    two firms (duopolists), 1 and 2

    Strategies:

    players 1 and 2 set prices p1, p2 simultaneously

    Payoffs:

    players 1, 2 produce quantities y1, y2 of the same

    homogeneous product, each at constant marginal cost c

    inverse demand: p = a - bY, where Y = y1 + y2

    assumption: if p1 < p2, then y1 = Y, y2 = 0 and vice versa assumption: if p1 = p2, then y1 = y2 = 1/2 Y

    38

    The Bertrand Game, contdThe Bertrand Game, contd

    Payoffs, contd:

    player is profit: i = piyi - cyi, ori = (pi - c)yi, where i = 1, 2

    for player 1:

    player 1s profit when p1 < p2:

    1 = (p1 - c) Y,

    i.e. 1 = (p1 - c) (a - p1)/b

    player 1s profit when p1 > p2:

    1 = 0

    player 1s profit when p1 = p2:

    1 = (p1 - c) 1/2 Y,

    i.e. 1 = (p1 - c) 1/2 (a - p1)/b

    similarly for player 2.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    20/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 20

    39

    The Bertrand Game, contdThe Bertrand Game, contd

    Solution: When prices can be chosen continuously,there is a simple and intuitive solution to the Bertrand

    game:

    Can a price less than marginal cost be optimal?

    No: profits are negative.

    Can a price greater than marginal cost be optimal?

    Suppose player 1 were to charge a price above marginal cost.

    Then player 2 could just undercut player 1s price and take the

    entire market. Similarly for player 2.

    The only price at which one player does not have to anticipate

    being undercut by the other player is price = marginal cost.

    The Nash equilibrium strategy profile in the Bertrand

    game is for both players (i = 1, 2) to set pi = c.

    40

    The Bertrand Game, contdThe Bertrand Game, contd

    If oligopolists compete in prices (Bertrand

    competition), the outcome will be efficient:

    price = marginal cost.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    21/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 21

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Market Structure IV:Market Structure IV:

    An ApplicationAn Application

    Simultaneous Quantity Setting:

    The Cournot Game (1838)

    (Shy pp. 98-101; Varian Ch 27)

    42

    The Cournot GameThe Cournot Game

    The game:

    Players:

    two firms (duopolists), 1 and 2

    Strategies:

    players 1 and 2 set quantities y1, y2 simultaneously

    Payoffs: players 1, 2 produce quantities y1, y2 of the same

    homogeneous product, each at constant marginal cost c

    inverse demand: p = a - bY, where Y = y1 + y2

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    22/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 22

    43

    The Cournot Game, contdThe Cournot Game, contd

    Payoffs, contd: firm 1s profit when it sets quantity y1 and firm 2 sets

    quantity y2:

    1 (y1, y2) = p y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = (a - b(y1 + y2)) y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = ay1 - by12 - by2y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = - by12 + (a - by2 - c)y1.

    Similarly for firm 2:

    2 (y1, y2) = - by22 + (a - by1 - c)y2.

    44

    The Cournot Game, contdThe Cournot Game, contd

    So:

    Firm 1 profit: 1(y1, y2) = - by12 + (a - by2 - c)y1.

    Firm 2 profit: 2(y1, y2) = - by22 + (a - by1 - c)y2.

    What is firm 1s best response (reaction) when firm 2

    chooses y2?

    Choose y1 to max

    1 (y1, y2): 1(y1, y2) / y1 = - 2by1 + a - by2 - c = 0

    that is: y1 = (a - by2 - c)/2b

    This is firm 1s best response (or reaction) function.

    What is firm 2s best response function?

    y2 = (a - by1 - c)/2b

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    23/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 23

    45

    The Cournot Game, contdThe Cournot Game, contd

    Recall: In a Nash equilibrium, every playersequilibrium strategy is her best response to the other

    players equilibrium strategy.

    So we know that

    y1 = (a - by2 - c)/2b and

    y2 = (a - by1 - c)/2b

    are both true.

    Solve for y1:

    y1 = (a - c)/3b

    y2 = (a - c)/3b

    46

    The Cournot Game, contdThe Cournot Game, contd

    f1(y2) - firm 1s best response

    (or, reaction) function

    f2(y1) - firm 2s

    reaction

    function

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    24/38

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    25/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 25

    49

    The Cournot Game: ComparisonThe Cournot Game: Comparison

    f1(y2) - firm 1s best response

    (or, reaction) function

    f2(y1) - firm 2s

    reaction

    function

    Nash equilibrium in

    the Cournot game

    Monopoly solution(firm 1 is monopolist)

    Perfect Competition (assuming

    linear demand and symmetry)

    50

    The Cournot Game, contdThe Cournot Game, contd

    If oligopolists compete in quantities (Cournot

    competition), the joint quantity is:

    greater than the quantity in a monopoly,

    but less than the quantity under perfect competition

    (or under Bertrand competition).

    Cournot Bertrand

    quantity

    Monopoly P. C.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    26/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 26

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Extensive Form GamesExtensive Form Games

    (Mostly) Sequential Move Games

    in Extensive Form

    52

    Example: The Entry GameExample: The Entry Game

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)(-1, -1)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    27/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 27

    53

    Extensive Form GamesExtensive Form Games

    Definition: An extensive form game is: a game tree (one starting node, other decision

    nodes, terminal nodes, and branches linking each

    decision node to successor nodes);

    the set ofplayers in the game;

    at each decision node, the name of the player

    making a decision at that node;

    the actions available to players at each node;

    a players strategyis a list of actions of that player at each

    decision node where that player can take an action;

    thepayoffs for each player at each terminal node.

    54

    Extensive Form Games, contdExtensive Form Games, contd

    Note:

    We now need to be careful about the distinction:

    action - strategy:

    An action at some decision node is a players decision of

    what to do when that node is reached.

    A strategy is a complete list of actions that a player plansto take at each decision node, whether or not that node is

    actually reached.

    Example (the entry game): if player 1 chooses to stay

    out, player 2s decision node is not reached.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    28/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 28

    55

    The Entry Game and Nash Eq.The Entry Game and Nash Eq.

    What is the Nash equilibrium in the entrygame?

    Recall: In a Nash equilibrium, no player wishes

    to deviate unilaterally.

    56

    The Entry Game, contdThe Entry Game, contd

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)

    possible Nash

    equilibria:

    (enter, fight)

    (enter, share)

    (stay out, fight)

    (stay out, share)

    This game has two Nash

    equilibria (in pure strategies).(-1, -1)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    29/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 29

    57

    The Entry Game, contdThe Entry Game, contd

    We can convert this extensive form game into anormal (strategic) form game:

    normal (strategic) form:potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)(-1, -1)

    enter

    stay out

    sharefight

    (-1, -1) (2, 2)

    (0, 8) (0, 8)

    58

    The Entry Game, contdThe Entry Game, contd

    One of the two Nash equilibria in the entry game is

    unreasonable: (stay out, fight)

    The potential entrant only stays out because, if she were to

    enter, the incumbent threatens to fight.

    But consider what would happen if the entrant did enter: once

    she has entered (i.e. once we are at player 2s decision node),

    the incumbent would want to share the market (i.e. not fight). This Nash equilibrium is based on a non-credible threat.

    This (overall) equilibrium is unreasonable because, once play

    of the game has reached player 2s decision node,

    subsequent play (i.e. play in the subgame that starts at player

    2s decision node) is not an equilibrium.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    30/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 30

    59

    Multiple Nash EquilibriaMultiple Nash Equilibria

    In extensive form games we can sometimeseliminate unreasonable Nash equilibria.

    Remember: we want a unique prediction for the

    play of the game.

    We only admit reasonable Nash equilibria:

    We want equilibrium play in a game to be such that

    each players strategies are an equilibrium not only

    in the overall game, but also at every decision

    node, for the subsequent game (the subgame

    starting at that decision node).

    60

    Subgame Perfect EquilibriumSubgame Perfect Equilibrium

    Definition: A subgame is the game that starts

    at one of the decision nodes of the original

    game; i.e. it is a decision node from the

    original game along with the decision nodes

    and terminal nodes directly following this node.

    Definition: A Nash equilibrium with the

    property that it induces equilibrium play at

    every subgame is called a subgame perfect

    equilibrium.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    31/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 31

    61

    The Entry Game, contdThe Entry Game, contd

    potentialentrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)

    1. What is theequilibrium in the

    subgame starting

    at player 2s

    decision node?

    2. Once we know

    this, what is the

    equilibrium in the

    subgame starting

    at the startingnode?

    (-1, -1)

    62

    The Entry Game, contdThe Entry Game, contd

    There is a unique subgame perfect equilibrium

    in the entry game.

    Subgame perfection may help us trim down

    the number of Nash equilibria in sequential-

    move games in extensive form.

    Subgame perfection is the solution concept we

    will use for sequential-move games in

    extensive form.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    32/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 32

    63

    Backward InductionBackward Induction

    A method for finding subgame perfectequilibria is backward induction.

    A subgame perfect equilibrium is a specification of

    all players strategies such that play in every

    subgame is a (Nash) equilibrium for that subgame.

    In particular, this is true for the final subgame(s).

    So we know what happens in the final subgame:

    we can replace that subgame by the payoff that will

    be reached in that subgame.

    Then proceed similarly in this new reduced game,

    until there is only one subgame left.

    64

    Backward Induction, contdBackward Induction, contd

    potential

    entrant (1)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)incumbent (2)

    fight share

    (-1, -1) (2, 2)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    33/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 33

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Market Structure V:Market Structure V:

    An ApplicationAn Application

    Entry Deterrence

    Dixit (1982)AER

    66

    Entry DeterrenceEntry Deterrence

    Entry deterrence: the incumbent takes an action that

    influences payoffs such that she can commit to the

    threat of fighting a new entrant.

    Remember: in the entry game, the threat to fight was non-

    credible, and was therefore eliminated by subgame perfection.

    Suppose before playing the entry game, the

    incumbent can choose to incur a cost in readiness to

    fight a price war.

    Suppose this cost does not reduce payoffs if there is a price

    war, but does reduce costs if there is no price war.

    (In our example, this cost is 4.)

    What is the subgame perfect equilibrium?

    Solve by backward induction.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    34/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 34

    67

    The Entry Deterrence GameThe Entry Deterrence Game

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 4)

    fight share

    (2, -2)

    incumbent (2)committed passive

    (-1, -1)

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)(-1, -1)

    68

    Entry Deterrence Game, contdEntry Deterrence Game, contd

    The entry deterrence game in our example

    has a unique subgame perfect equilibrium:

    (stay out [at B], enter [at C]; committed [at A],

    fight [at D], share [at E]).

    (Remember: a players strategy lists an action for

    each of that players decision nodes.)

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    35/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 35

    69

    Entry Deterrence Game, contdEntry Deterrence Game, contd

    We can convert this game into a normal (strategic)form game:

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 4)

    fight share

    (2, -2)

    incumbent (2)

    committed passive

    (-1, -1)

    potential

    entrant (1)

    incumbent (2)

    enter stay out

    (0, 8)

    fight share

    (2, 2)(-1, -1)

    A

    B C

    D E

    enter (B), enter (C)

    enter (B), stay out (C)

    stay out (B), enter (C)

    stay out (B), stay out (C)

    player 1: etc.

    Dartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, SummerDartmouth College, Department of Economics: Economics 21, Summer020202

    Market Structure VI:Market Structure VI:

    An ApplicationAn Application

    Sequential Quantity Setting:

    The Stackelberg Game

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    36/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 36

    71

    The Stackelberg GameThe Stackelberg Game

    The game: Players:

    two firms (duopolists), 1 and 2

    Strategies:

    players 1 and 2 set quantities y1, y2

    player 1 moves first (she is the Stackelberg leader)

    player 2 observes 1s choice of y1, and then sets y2.

    Payoffs:

    players 1, 2 produce quantities y1, y2 of the same

    homogeneous product, each at constant marginal cost c inverse demand: p = a - bY, where Y = y1 + y2

    72

    The Stackelberg Game, contdThe Stackelberg Game, contd

    Payoffs, contd:

    firm 1s profit when it sets quantity y1 and firm 2 sets

    quantity y2:

    1 (y1, y2) = p y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = (a - b(y1 + y2)) y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = ay1 - by12 - by2y1 - c y1, or:

    1 (y1, y2) = - by12 + (a - by2 - c)y1.

    The combinations of y1 and y2 for which profit is constant

    are firm 1s isoprofit curves. (Topic 4)

    Similarly for firm 2:

    2 (y1, y2) = - by22 + (a - by1 - c)y2.

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    37/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    Andreas Bentz page 37

    73

    The Stackelberg Game, contdThe Stackelberg Game, contd

    Solution: by backward induction: Player 2 chooses the quantity that is best for her,

    after observing what player 1 has chosen,

    i.e. player 2 plays her best response to player 1s

    choice: player 2 chooses a point on her best

    response function.

    Knowing this, player 1 chooses the quantity that is

    best for her, given that (after she has chosen),

    player 2 will choose a point on her best response

    function, i.e. player 1 chooses the point on player 2s best

    response function that is best for her.

    74

    The Stackelberg Game, contdThe Stackelberg Game, contd

    Firm 2 chooses the quantity that is best, after having

    observed firm 1s choice of quantity y1.

    Firm 2 chooses y2 to:

    max 2 (y1, y2) = - by22 + (a - by1 - c)y2.

    - 2by2 + a - by1 - c = 0, or

    y2 = (a - by1 - c)/2b.

    Knowing this, firm 1 chooses the quantity that is best.

    Firm 1 chooses y1 to:

    max 1 (y1, (a - by1 - c)/2b) =

    = - by12 + (a - b((a - by1 - c)/2b) - c)y1.

    - 2by1 + a - c - 0.5a + 0.5c + by1 = 0, or

    y1 = (a - c) / 2b

  • 8/4/2019 Economcs 21 Bentz X02 Topic4

    38/38

    DARTMOUTH COLLEGE, DEPARTMENT OF ECONOMICS ECONOMICS 21

    75

    The Stackelberg Game, contdThe Stackelberg Game, contd

    So firm 1 chooses y1 = (a - c) / 2b. Therefore firm 2 chooses y2 = (a - by1 - c)/2b,

    or y2 = (a - b((a - c) / 2b) - c)/2b, or:

    y2 = (a - c) / 4b

    The Stackelberg Game, contdThe Stackelberg Game, contd

    f2(y1) - firm 2s

    reaction

    function

    f1(y2) - firm 1s best response

    (or, reaction) function

    Nash equilibrium in

    the Cournot game

    Subgame perfect equilibrium

    in the Stackelberg game