English Complement at Ion

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    1/77

    ENGLISH COMPLEMENTATION

    Spring 2011

    INTRODUCING THE MINIMALIST FRAMEWORK

    1.1. Aim of the course. Topics covered

    A presentation of theEnglish complementation system, within the general framework of Chomsky'sMinimalist Program (Chomsky 1995, 1998, 1999).

    Range of description: the domain ofcomplementclauses point of view

    Complement clauses (informal definition): subordinate clauses which function as arguments ofpredicates (subjects, objects).

    Complement clauses: a) that-clausesb) infinitive clausesc) ing-complements (gerunds, participial

    constructions).

    (1) a. He considered that it was a mistake.b. He considered it to be a mistake.

    c. He considered accepting their offer.

    1. 2. Classification of subordinate clauses

    A) The structural criterion ( informally , the nature of the introductoryelement: acomplementizer, a relative/interrogative pronoun, a subordinative conjunction). If (most) subordinateclauses are CPs, the structural criterion concerns the type of constituents that fills the CP projection).Three types o subordinates may be identified:1) Complement clauses: the introducer is a complementizer (C0), an abstract element whose role is to

    partly nominalize a clause, turning it into an argument of a predicate.

    (2) a. It is spring. CPb. ...that it is spring

    c. I can feel that it is string C IPd. Everybody is aware that it is spring. | DP Ithat I

    C0that, for, whether, ifC0 --[IP I

    0 [+finite] ] thatC0 --[IP I

    0 [-finite] ] for

    C0 --[IP I0 [ finite] ] whether

    Complement clauses are clauses introduced by complementizers, which function as arguments ofpredicates.Predicates (verbs, adjectives, nouns, prepositions) c-select and s-select complements, and theirsubcategorial properties are listed in the lexicon.

    A) The structural criterion2) Wh-complements are subordinate clauses introduced by relative or interrogative phrases(pronouns, determiners, adverbs) which move to Spec, C.

    a. relative clauses (nominal modifiers)Wh- complements b. interrogative complements

    c. cleft-sentences c1) pseudo-clefts orwh-cleftsc2) it-clefts

    (3) a. the man on whom people have pinned their hopes/

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    2/77

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    3/77

    Goals

    a. an explanatory account

    b. a descriptively complete account, even if surely not exhaustive

    Practical skills

    a. identifying the complex sentence patterns of English

    b. a good command of the distribution of these patterns.

    c. understanding the relation between meaning and structure for the patterns studied

    d. skills a), b), c) are required in any form ofmanipulating these patterns:paraphrasing, translating, editing, etc.

    2. 1 Plato's problem and the GB program

    Distinctive features of the GB model

    1. GB is modular (Modules of GB: X' Theory, - theory, Binding and Control, Case Theory, Move

    )

    2. Through its Move module, GB, contains a very unconstrained transformational component,

    because, in principle, Move allows any category to move anywhere at any time. Possible problem:overgeneration, hence the need of filtering away incorrect representations3. GB has four levels of representation at which various conditions are applied to filter out illicitstructures: D-Structure (DS), S -Structures (SS), Logical Form (LF), and Phonological Form (PF).4. The central grammatical relation in GB isgovernment. This relation is what lends formal unity tootherwise rather diverse subcomponents.

    Aim of GB: finding a suitable answer toPlato's problem; its success deoends on proposingplausible accounts oflanguage variation and language acquisition.

    New problem: Which of the conceivable PP modelsis best, and the issue is in part addressed,using conventional (not uniquely linguistic) criteria of theory evaluation.

    2.2 General design of the Minimalist Program (MP)

    Chomsky currently considers the following questions: How well is FL designed ? How close doeslanguage come to optimal design ? More narrowly, the MP seeks to discover to what extent minimal

    conditions of adequacy (=success at the interfaces) suffice to determine the nature of the right theory.The program addresses the question of what conditions are imposed on the linguistic system by virtueof its interaction with theperformance systems.

    a) The Articulatory-Perceptual System (A-P)b) the Conceptual-Intentional System (C-I).

    In so far as we can discover the properties of these systems, we can ask how well the language organsatisfies the design specifications they impose, providing legible representation at the interface.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    4/77

    (8) Strong Minimalist Thesis

    Language is an optimal answer to legibility conditions (cf. Chomsky 1998)

    2.3. Design of the MP Bare output conditions

    An expression converges at an interface level, if it consists solely of elements that provide instructionsto that external level, thus being legible for the respective external level. The presence of objectswhich are not interpretable at an interface causes a derivation to crash.

    There are two linguistic levels which interface with performance modules, i.e, A-P and C-I: these arePF and LF respectively. PF and LF can be conceived of as those parts of the linguistic system which

    provide instructions to the performance systems.

    (9)The organization of a GB Grammar

    Lexicon

    D-Structure

    Move (Affect )

    S-Structure

    Logical Form Phonological Form

    (10)The organization of an MP Grammar

    Lexicon

    (Spell-out)

    Logical Form Phonological Form

    Grammar still associatesstructural descriptions with each sentence /expression. But instead ofassociating a sentence/ expression with four representation (D-Structure, S-Structure, Logical Form,Phonological Form), the structural descriptions of a sentence / expression is now a pair of

    representations ( , ). is a PF representation interpreted at the articulatory perceptual (A-P)interface. is an LF representation interpreted at the conceptual-intentional (C-I) interface.

    Conclusions

    1. The MP seeks a maximally simple design for language. Given this view, the linguistic levels aretaken to be only those conceptually necessary -namely PF and LF - meaning that that there are no(intermediate levels of D-Structure or S-Structure.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    5/77

    2. Each expression is associated with a structural representation, a pair ( , ), where is a PF

    representation interpreted at the articulatory perceptual (A-P) interface, and is an LF representationinterpreted at the conceptual-intentional (C-I) interface.

    3. Structure of an (I)-language: A lexicon and a computational procedure

    3.1 The components of a language are a lexicon and a computational procedure for humanlanguages CHL, that is, a procedure for constructing or generating linguistic expressions using theitems in the lexicon. Linguistic items fall into two main categories: substantive ( N, V, A, P) andfunctional (C, T D, etc.).

    The following procedures are involved in building expressions:

    (12) (i) Select lexical items from the lexicon ( a Lexical Array, aNumeration)

    (ii) Map lexical items to expression.

    The computational system (narrow syntax) consists of a few trivial operations Select, Merge, Move,and (more recently)Agree.

    Selectis involved in the initial choice of the Numeration, as well as in providing pairs of objects thatundergo Merge.

    Merge operates on pairs of elements chosen by Select and maps them from a pair into a single elementwith a more complex structure. Merge is the basic combinatorial device for obtaining complex objectsout of simpler or basic ones.

    4.Merge. From X'-Theory to Bare Phrase Structure

    Defining Merge

    Merge takes two syntactic objects ( , ) and forms the new object (K ( , )) from them.(14) Input Output

    , , K

    Since the possibility of Merge depends on the c-selectional/ s-selectional possibilities of thecombining lexical items, Merge is obviously the analogue of X'-Theory.The principle ofendocentricity is still present in as much as, of the two items that combine, one, thehead, is that which projects and transmits its lable.The relations ofhead-complement( sister) and head-specifiercontinue to be available.

    Conclusions1. The bare phrase structure theory adopted by the MP is represented by the operation Merge.

    Merge takes two syntactic objects ( , ) and forms the new object K(( , )) from them.2. Endocentricity continues to function given that, of the two elements that merge, only one, namely,the head projects.3. The relations of head-complement and head-specifier are available, as before.

    5. Spell-Out

    Elements interpretable at the A-P interface (e.g. phonologic features) are not interpretable at the C-Iinterface, and vice versa. At some point in the derivation, the computational system must then split

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    6/77

    into two parts, one forming , and the other forming , which do not interact any further after thebifurcation.S-structure was the point of this split in pre-minimalist versions of the PP theory. From a minimalist

    perspective, the problem with there being a distinct level feeding PF and LF, such as S-structure, isthat, since it does not interface with any performance system , it is not conceptually necessary. Thusevery substantive property attributed to S-Structure should be restated within the minimalist

    framework in either LF or PF terms.The only thing required under minimalist assumptions is a rule which splits the computation to form

    the distinct objects and . Chomsky (1993:22) dubs this operation Spell-Out.After Spell-Out the lexicon will no longer be accessed, and the items in the Numeration have beenused up.The computation from Spell-Out to PF is referred to as thePhonological Component.The computation from Spell-Out to LF is referred to as the covertcomponent, and the computationthat obtains before Spell-Out is referred to as overt syntax. PF contains, in addition to phonologicalrules proper, a morphological subcomponentand it also deals with linearization.

    6.Types of features and feature checking

    Why check?

    The items combined by Merge group features of different types: phonological, semantic, but also

    formal (grammatical features) (Person, Number, Gender,(= -features), Case, Tense, etc.). Theformal features of the lexical items must be checked during the derivation. Intuitively, one has toverify that each item is suitably placed in an expression. Thus *We goes to schoolis ungrammatical

    because the Number feature on the subject does not match the number feature of the verbal inflection.Feature checking is thus an essential aspect of a derivation.

    6.1 Strong/Weak features (Chomsky, 1993, 1995)

    Strong features illegible at PF, so they must be eliminated in the overt componentof Syntax by overtmovement.

    A strong feature must enter into a checking relation as soon aspossible, causing movement orinsertion.

    The analysis of strong (formal) features, formalizes the intuition that a strong feature is checkedimmediately and that it has visible effect (displacement).

    6.2Interpretable/Uninterpretable features

    A feature is interpretable if it is legible at LF.

    A feature like Case is always uninterpretable Number or Gender are interpretable on Nouns, butuninterpretable on verbs, adjectives.

    Uninterpretable features are not legible at LF, therefore they must be erased before LF. Following thesame intuition, uninterpretable features must be eliminated as soon as possible, therefore they inducestrict cyclicity. If uninterpretable features are also "strong", they are checked by overt movement anderased after checking. (A slightly different description of strong uninterpretable features will be givenin the next chapters). Interpretable features survive to LF and may be used several times in aderivation.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    7/77

    7. Move and Agree

    7.1 MoveWhile, Merge forms a new object by concatenating two objects that are separate phrase markers,Move forms a new object by concatenating two objects that are in asingle phrase marker. Move isdefined as follows. It is possible to decompose Move into the simple operations of Copy and(re)merge.

    (18) Move (from Kitahara (1997)Applied to the category and , Move forms ' by concatenating and .

    Input: containing .

    Concatenate and , forming '

    Output: '(19) a.

    b.

    '

    t( )

    7.1 Move

    Chomsky (1993) incorporates the copy theory of movement. According to the copy theory, a trace is acopy of the moved element which is deleted in the phonological component, but is available forinterpretation at LF. A chain thus becomes a set of occurrences of a constituent in a constructedsyntactic object.

    Summarising, Move appears to be a complex operation comprised of copy, merge, chain formation,and finally, chain reduction. Chain reduction is the deletion at PF of all the copies in the chain, but thehighest ( the head of the chain).

    Move observes the following two requirements:(i) Constituents always move ( to the left) to c-commanding positions, of the same

    type. Therefore heads move to head positions, phrases move to phrasal positions (A or A).(ii)Locality The closest constituent that has the appropriate checkable feature is the

    one that moves.

    Locality becomes a built-in condition, stated as the Minimal Link Condition or the Minimize ChainLinksCondition, which specifies that a constituent always travels the shortest possible distance, orequivalently, that if two candidates could check the same feature, it is the closest that actually checksit.

    7.2.Agree

    Agree is a relation between two items, the probe, which is the agreeing item and which is a head thatpossesses uninterpretable features and the goala phrase or a head, possessed of a feature that matches

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    8/77

    the feature of the agreeing head. In the case of Agree, matching of the features of the probe underidentity with features of the goal is sufficient to delete the strong uninterpretable features on the probe,rendering movement unnecessary. Agree allows the checking and erasure of an uninterpretablefeature, by matching it with an identical feature of another item, in a sufficiently local domain. Theconditions governing Agree are summarized below (cf. Carstens (2000:149)). According to thisconception , Agree is driven by uninterpetable features of the probe, which must be deleted for

    legibility.

    (24) Agree operates between a probe and a goal iff

    a. has uninterpretable features.

    b. has identical interpretable features.

    c. c-commands

    d. There is no closer potential goal such that -commands and c-commands b(25)

    [-interpretable](probe)

    [+interpretable](goal)

    ConclusionMove and Agree are alternative mechanisms of deleting uninterpretable features, so as to meet thelegibility conditions of LF.

    8. Economy Principles

    Economy of representation is nothing other than the principle of Full Interpretation:every object at the interface must receive an "external" interpretation, i.e., must be interpretable by theexternal performance systems. Full Interpretation thus determines the set of convergent derivations fora language.

    Economy of derivation requires fewer steps than in another permissible derivation.

    (27) Shortest derivation ConditionMinimize the number of operations necessary for convergence.

    Instead of Conclusions

    The novelty of the MP lies in its addressing the question of the optimal design of language,the answer to which is the Strong Minimalist Thesis stated in (28)

    (28) Language is an optimal answer to legibility conditions (cf. Chomsky (1998))

    Adopting the strong thesis has proved to have the following consequences:1. The only linguistically significant levels are the interface levels (PF, LF)

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    9/77

    2. The interpretability condition: Linguistic items have no features other than those interpreted at theinterface, properties of sound and meaning.3. The inclusiveness condition: No new features or symbols are introduce by CHL.4. Relations that enter into CHL either (i) are imposed by legibility conditions, (ii) or fall out in somenatural way from the computational process

    THE STRUCTURE OF THE ENGLISH CLAUSE

    1. The endocentricity of sentences

    1.1 Inflection as the head of the sentence.

    (1) S NP ^ VP

    (2) a. I0 Tense [ Agr] ^( Mood).

    b. I' I0 ^ VP

    c. IP DP ^ VP

    Inflection (I0) is considered the head of the sentence, since it c-selects the VP and agrees with the

    subject DP, thus entertaining formal relations with the predicate (the head - complement relation) andwith the subject (the head-specifier relation).

    Tense[+Agr] s/ed

    The Stranded Affix FilterTense is an affix which must be supported by a verbal root. The present orpast form of a verb is derivationally produced, by combining the verbal stem and Tense affix duringthe derivation.

    Modal auxiliaries

    In English, Inflection includes in addition to Tense and Agr , the modal verbs: can, may, shall, will,must, need, dare.

    Justification modals are defective, having only finite Tense froms, i.e., Tense plus agreement features.When modals are present, they support Tense, and the tensed modals may further raise to C0. A clearindication that modals move to C0 is that I0-to-C0 takes place only in root clauses, i.e., only when theC0 position is not filled by a complementizer, as is apparent in the complementary distribution in (3)

    below, where either the complementizerwhether, or the modal auxiliary, occupies the position beforethe subject (C0):

    (3) a. Could [IP he ta be a fool]?b. I asked you [CP whether [IP he could be a fool]]c. *I asked you [CP whether could [IP he be a fool]]

    Aspectual auxiliaries

    (4) Aux Tense (Modal ) ( have -en) (be-ing)

    Definition: An auxiliary is a verb that subcategorizes a VP, and cannot assign -roles.

    1.2. The projection of auxiliaries

    Similarties between modals and auxiliaries (the NICE properties)a)Negation

    He should not go.He has not gone.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    10/77

    b)InterrogationShould he read this?Has he read this?

    c) Contracted sentences (tag-questions, etc.)He should do it, shouldnt he?He has read this, hasnt he.

    d)Emphatic stress (in emphatic assertions)Bob should not go there. Yes, he should go there.Bob has not read this. Yes, he HAS read this, Im sure.

    Dissimilarties between modals and auxiliaries

    a) Auxiliaries have a complete paradigm, with finite and non-finite forms, modals are defectiveto be, having

    b) Auxiliaries still have lexical uses, unlike modals which are always functional.He has a nice house.He has bought a nice house.He has had a nice house

    There are several manners of projecting auxiliaries.

    a) One may treat them as lexical verbs, under the VP, which c-select a VP(5) VP V0 ^ VP(6) have [ V[EN]]

    be [V [ING] ](7) IP

    I'I0 VP

    [+Past] V0 VPV'

    ed have V0+en

    b) Alternatively, one might stress their functional nature and project them as heads of suitably labelled

    functional projections: Auxiliary Phrase, Aspect P, etc.

    (8) IPI'

    I0 AuxP[+Past] Aux'ed Aux0 VP

    have

    The syntax of auxiliariesa) V-to-IIn sentences where there are no modals, the highest auxiliary raises to Tense, to support the Tenseaffix, and then it may further move to C0. Example (9b) shows that the auxiliary have has raised out

    of the VP to T0, past the adverb often, adjoined to the VP, as shown in (9c).(9) a. She often visited the city.

    b. She has often visited the city.c.

    IPDP I'She I0 VP

    V0 I0 AdvP VP

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    11/77

    have s often V0 VPta visited

    the city

    b)I-to-C

    An auxiliary that has moved to I0

    can further continue to C0

    , as shown in (10):

    (10) a. Has she often visited the city ?

    b.CPC'

    C0 IPI0 DP I'

    V0 I0 I0 VPhave+s she ta AdvP VPHas often V0 VP

    ta V'V0 DPvisited him

    Extended Projections

    An extended projection defines a domain of movement for the head (i.e., the verb).a. English, auxiliaries raise all the way up to C0,

    b. English lexical verbs remain in the VP.

    (11) French vs. English

    a. Il embrasse souvent Marie.b. *He kisses often Mary.c. He often kisses Mary.d. Embrasse-t-il souvent Marie ?e *Kisses he often Mary ?f. Does he often kiss Mary?

    Conclusion

    The English clause has the following functional structure:

    (12) CP> IP >Vaux0 > VP

    I0 Tense[+Agr]^(Modal)

    2.Main verbs and auxiliary verbs again. 2.1. Verb Movement and Verbal Morphology

    The lexicalist analysis: Verbs enter the derivation fully inflected, and merely check their inflectionalfeatures against the functional heads.If the inflectional features are strong, the verb raises to Inflection (or the Inflectional heads) to checkits features.(The case of French). If the inflectional features are weak, the verb does not raise overtly.There is covert movement at LF English.

    The derivational account(bare stems +affixes)

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    12/77

    (13) TP TPT0 VPed V T0 VP

    walk V0

    V0 ed

    The lexicalist account(inflected forms)

    (14) TP TPT0 VP[+Past] V T0 VP

    walked V0 T0

    walked [Past]

    The difference between English and French can be stated as follows (cf. Lasnik (1995)):(15) a. In French, the V-features, i.e., those that check features of V, are strong.

    b. In English the V-features are weak.(16) Strong features surviving at PF cause the derivation to crash.

    (17) Delay an operation until LF whenever possible, that is, whenever delaying would not causethe derivation to crash.

    The parametric difference between English and French is now expressed in a different manner,namely the strong/weak difference between inflectional V-features. Strong features trigger overtmovement, weak features do not.

    Auxiliaries

    One problem for this analysis of English is that English auxiliaries do raise to Tense0 and then to C0,as is apparent in the following types of well-known contrasts.

    (18) a. He often goes to movies.b. He has often gone to movies.c. Does he often go to movies ?d. Has he often gone to movies ?

    2.2. A Hybrid Approach (Lasnik 1995, 1998)

    In the hybrid approach, the fundamental difference between English auxiliary and main verbs lies inthe choice ofthe checking mechanism, a difference that correlates with different types of lexicalrepresentations. Lasnik re-states the difference between English auxiliaries and main verbs, and

    between English and French as follows:

    (20) a.Have and Be are fully inflected in the lexicon (possibly correlating with

    the fact that they are highly suppletive, allowing for person /number variation).b. All other English verbs are bare in the lexicon.

    (21) a. Inflection is freely either an affix or a set of abstract features.b. Finite featural Inflection isstrongin both French and English.

    The choice of Inflection type (featural, affixal) is predictable from the type of lexical representation. Ifthe lexicon lists inflected forms separately, Inflection will be featural, if the lexicon contains the bareform of the verb, Inflection is affixal. The final necessary mechanism is Affix Hopping. AH is

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    13/77

    morphophonemic; it will be aPF rule, since from the point of view of semantic interpretation, it isdesirable that Tense should c-command the VP on which it operates.

    (22) Afix Hopping : Affixal Inflection must merge with a V, a PF process (distinct from headmovement) demanding adjacency.

    Possible configurations

    a.(23) ...Infl...V...

    +F +FThis configuration is well-formed. V raises (overtly) to Infl, and all relevant features are checked. Thisis the situation ofbe/ have/ do/ (modals) and all French verbs.

    b.(24) ...Infl......V....

    Af bareThis is the case of a bare verb and an affixal Inflection (English main verbs). In this configuration PFmerger takes place as long as adjacency obtains, and the PF affixal requirement of Inflection issatisfied.Two more configurations (25c, d) will arise, but will lead to a crash, as can be seen below:c.

    (25) c. ...Infl....V.... *at LF. +F of Infl will not be checked;+F bare *at PF as well, since +F is strong

    d. Infl V *at LF. +F of V will not be checkedAf +F *at PF also, if merger fails

    In sum, the gist of Lasnik's analysis is that lexical representation determines the type of Inflection, andthe strength of features then determines whether feature checking takes place overtly or covertly.

    2.3. Evidence for the hybrid approach : Verb Phrase Deletion (VPD)

    VPD is a rule which deletes the second of two presumably identical lexicalVPs, leaving an auxiliary

    behind.

    (26) a. Peter should [buy the text book] and Mary should [e] too.b. Peter willgo to London and Mary will [e] too.

    Main Verbs VP ellipsis can ignore certain inflectional differences between the antecedent and theelided verb (cf. Quirk e.a. (1972), Warner (1986)):

    (27) a. John slept, and Mary will too.b. John slept and Mary will slept too.c. John slept, and Mary will sleep too.

    In (27a) the past tense formsleptserves as antecedent for the deletion of the bare formsleep. Thepresent tense form can also antecede the bare form, as in (28a).(28) a. John sleeps every afternoon, and Mary should too.

    b. *Johnsleeps every afternoon, and Mary should sleeps too.c. John sleeps, and Mary shouldsleep too.

    Similarly the progressive and perfect forms can antecede the bare form. It appears that a sort of sloppyidentity is at work here, permitting tense and aspectual differences to be ignored.(29) a. ?John was sleeping, and Mary will too.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    14/77

    b. *John was sleeping, and Mary willsleepingtoo.c. John wassleeping, and Mary willsleep too.

    (30) a. John has slept, and Mary will too.b. *John hasslept, and Mary willslepttoo.c. John has sleptand Mary willsleep too.

    Auxiliary Verbs Ellipsis with auxiliaries is markedly different, requiringstrict identity. Thus, (31a),though seemingly parallel to (27), is unacceptable, because was cannot antecede be; nor can isantecede be, as shown in (49):

    (31) a. * John was here, and Mary will too.b. *John was here and Mary will was here too.c. John was here and Mary will be here too.

    (32) *John is here, and Mary will too.

    Similar effects obtain with the auxiliary have. Ellipsis is markedly better in (33) with identical formsofhave than in (34) with distinct ones:(33) a. John should have left, but Mary shouldn't (have left).

    b. ?John should have left, but Mary shouldn't

    (34) a. * John has left, but Mary shouldn't-(have left).b. John has left, but Mary shouldn't have left.

    (35) Results on VPEThe bare form of a verb V other than be or auxiliary have can be deleted under identity with any otherform of V.Be or auxiliary have can only be deleted under identity with the very same form.

    As Warner (1986) observes, this difference does not follow directly from the degree of suppletion.The paradigm ofgo is highly suppletive, yet the verb patterns with all the other main verbs consideredabove, allowing deletion under sloppy identity (cf. (36))

    (36) John went, and now Mary will go.

    John went and now Mary will.

    Thus, the relevant differences is that between main verbs and auxiliaries. Sag (1976) notices that allthese cases could be accounted for by ordering VP deletion before Affix Hopping, i.e., by allowingdeletion to take place at a point in the derivation where the inflected form of the main verb has not

    been created, so that deletion actually operates on identical forms.

    On a strictly lexicalist view, such as that of Chomsky (1993), described in (14) above, there is no suchpoint in a derivation. Sag's insight is, however, convergent with the hybrid approach, whereby Englishmain verbs come from the lexicon as bare uninflected forms. Identical occurrences may be deleted insyntax, while inflected forms are produced at PF by Affix Hopping: Schematically, (some of) theexamples above are analysed as follows:

    (37) John slept, and Mary will too.John Inflsleep, and Mary willsleep too

    (38) a. John was sleeping, and Mary will.b. John was ingsleep, and now Mary willsleep.

    (39) a. John has slept, and now Mary will.b. John has ensleep, and now Mary willsleep.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    15/77

    On the other hand, if auxiliaries come from the lexicon fully inflected, and if deletion requires strictlyidentical forms, was oris will never be identical to be, since they are not formed in syntax out of Infl +

    be.

    (40) a. *John was here and Mary will, toob. John was here and Mary will be here, too

    Summing up:(41) a. A form of a verb V can only be deleted under identity with the very same form.

    b. Forms ofbe and auxiliary have are introduced into syntactic structures alreadyfully inflected. Forms of "main" verbs are created out of lexically introduced bare forms and

    independent affixes.

    VP Deletion facts provide strong empirical support for the hybrid approach to English verbmorphology. We will adopt it, and use it in the analysis of negation in English.

    Conclusion.1. English verbal morphology can best be described by assigning different lexical representations tomain verb and to auxiliary verbs.

    2. Main verbs are represented with one bare form. They come uninflected into the derivation, and willmerge with inflectional affixes during the derivation (Affix Hopping at PF).3. Auxiliary verbs are represented with all their inflected forms in the lexicon. They come fullyinflected into the derivation, and will simply check their inflectional features during the derivation.(Overt movement to functional heads).4. The lexical representation of the verbs determines the representation of Inflection, either as a bundleof abstract features or as an affix.ENGLISH COMPLEMENTATION

    Spring 2010

    3. Negative sentences

    3.1 Negation may affect different types of constituents in a sentence, and it is useful todistinguish between the following types ofscope of negation:a) word negation - realized by means of negative affixes, mostly prefixes: unhappy, infelicitous,dislike,displease.

    b) phrasal negation: the negation notmay adjoin to any phrase, taking scope over it.

    (42) He came to the party not long ago, didn't he?Not far away, it was still raining, wasn't it ?

    c) Sentence negation - cases where nothas sentence scope. A sentence is negative when its predicateis negated, in other words, when its Inflection, which is the head of the sentence, is negative.

    3.2 The concept of negative sentence. Types of negative sentences A sentences is negative, notonly by virtue of its meaning, but also because of its syntactic properties. Negative sentences have

    particular distributional properties, which identify them as such. It is instructive to compare pairsmade of a negative sentence, and a nearly synonymous sentence, where negation is expressed bymeans of a negative word. There are several tests, due to Klima (1964), which distinguish betweennegative sentences and sentences with negative constituents.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    16/77

    a. Tag questions. Under falling intonation on the tag question, negative sentences

    take affirmative tags, and vice versa:(43) a. Mary is happy/unhappy about her job, isnt she/* is she?

    b. Mary is not happy/unhappy about her job, is she/* isnt she? b. Not -even tag sentences require a negative host sentence:(44) a. George doesnt like smart girls, not even pretty ones.

    b. George dislikes smart girls even pretty ones /*not even pretty ones. c.Eitherconjoining. Two co-ordinated sentences can have the form S1 and S2 only if the

    second is negative.

    (45) a. Jack stayed at home all day and Mary didnt go any place either.b *Jack didnt go anywhere all day and Mary stayed at home either.c. John isnt happy and Mary isnt happy either.d. *John is unhappy and Mary isnt happy either.

    d. Neithertags require negative hosts. Affirmative sntences are followed byso-tags

    (46) a. Jack doesn't like lingusitics and neither does Mary / *and so does Maryb. Jack dislikes linguistics and so does Mary/ and neither does Mary.

    Types of negative sentences.

    a) Sentences where negation is in the Auxiliary

    (47) a. Bob has lost my respect.b. Bob has not lost my respect.c. Bob abandoned his pet cat.d. Bob did not abandon his pet cat.

    b) Sentences where negation is expressed by negative quantifiers, like nobody, never, nothing.Syntactically, these negative quantifiers are determiners (no), pronouns (nobody, nothing) or adverbs (never, nowhere).

    (48) a. He saw no rose-bush in the garden.b. He saw nobody in the garden.

    c. He had never visited that city.

    c)Emphatic negative sentences are sentences where the negative constituent appears to theleft of the subject, triggering inversion.

    (49) Never before had he seen such pretty girls.

    Polarity items

    One other famous problem that relates to negation is that ofpolarity items (items sensitive to thepolarity of the sentence).Affirmative polarity items require assertive, non-negative contexts(sentences).Negative polarity items require negative sentences. Here are a few examples.

    Positive Polarity Items

    (50) a. It isstillraining.b. He has already arrived.c. Mary is here, too.d. Mary was looking forsome old pair of shoes.

    Negative Polarity Items

    a'. It is not raining anymore.b'. He hasn't arrivedyet.c.' Mary isn't here, either.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    17/77

    d'. Mary wasn't looking forany old pair of shoes.

    Remark

    Negative polarity items occur in several contexts related by their semantic properties. Klima (1964)labels them contexts that contain [+affective] triggers. Here is the list of contexts which license NPIs:a) Negative sentences Negation is the strongest [affective] trigger. Use of an API instead of a NPI may

    lead to ungrammaticality. Most of the other contexts permit both NPIs and APIs, but the interpretationassociated with the sentences are critically different:

    (i) He didnt lift a finger to help.*He lifted a finger to help.

    b) Questions are also sensitive to polarity. NPIs are used when a negative answer is expected. APIs areneutral or expect a positive answer.

    (ii) a. Are you expecting anyone this afternoonb. Are you expecting someone in particular?a Do you want any more beans, perhaps?

    b. Do you want some more beans, perhaps?

    c) Comparative clauses allow both NPIs and APIs, but the interpretations are very different:

    (iii) a. She was more beautiful than any princess that he had seen.b. She was more beautiful than some princess that he head seen.a. He is smarter than any student I everhad.

    b. He is smarter than some student I once had.

    d) Relative clauses headed by indefinite determiners like no, any, every, few, little etc., as opposed tothe definite article, demonstratives, each, several,

    (iv) I know no politician who has everdone anythingfor this country.He had every reason to refuse any help they offered.

    e) If-clauses are also NPIs triggers, but they license APIs as well, roughly, under the samecircumstances as questions:

    (v) If anyone comes, tell them to wait.Ifsomeone comes, invite him in the office.

    4. Negation in the Auxiliary.

    4.1 The Negative Projection

    English sentential negation can show up in two different shapes: the contracted n'tor the full form not.It is generally assumed that the two formatives spell out the content of a Negative Projection, NegP,one of the functional categories of the verb. The examination of sentences with negative operator willoffer evidence for projecting NegP as an independent phrase.

    The Negative Parameter(Laka, 1990)

    (51) a. Mary isnotin the kitchen

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    18/77

    b. Maria nueste in bucatarie.

    (52) The Negative Parameterdistinguishes between:a. languages where Negation is above Tense; (Romanian)

    b. languages where Negation is below Tense. (English)

    (55) a. Not to accept this proposal (seems foolish)Neg>TP

    b. He has not accepted this proposal.TP> NegP

    A more restrictive hypothesis regarding functional structure:(56) Hypothesis.1) The hierarchy of functional categories is invariant. The only thing that varies is the properties of thefunctional nodes (Borer 1984).2) Functional categories are projected as a last resort.

    4.2 The Split Inflection Hypothesis. (Chomsky 1993)

    (57) AgrSP > TP > AgrOP > VPs ed ?

    The analysis may be more detailed and extended by detailing the verbal features of Inflection.

    (58) AgrSP> TP(M) > AspP > AspP> (AgrOP)> VPs ed, may have be ?

    The position of NegP Following Lopez (1995), we will assume that NegP is above TP in English aswell as in UG:(59) AgrSP> NegP> TP > AspP AspP> (AgrOP) VP

    s nt ed have be ?It is necessary to analyse the two items that may fill the NegP: not, and n't.

    4.3. n'tand not.English sentential negation can show up in two different shapes: the contracted n'tor the full form not.In this section we will pay attention to their syntactic distribution, particularly to the problem of howthe orderauxiliary verb + negation obtains.

    4.3.1. NtN'tis an affix to the auxiliary; it is a bound morpheme, incorporated into a modal or an auxiliary.Forms, such as, can't, aren'tare pulled from the lexicon as fully inflected, and they will have to checktheir features during the derivation:Hasn'tfor instance must check [+Present, 3d Person, +Negative].

    The hypothesis that n'tis incorporated into the auxiliary explains the following:

    a)N'tand the auxiliary raise together as in (60).

    b) N'tattaches to the highest verbal projection of the sentence, (61).c) There can't be two formatives nt, (62):

    (60) Couldn't you give me that book /(61) a. He couldn't have been fooling around so much.

    b. *He could haven't been fooling around so much/(62) **He couldn't haven't been so careful

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    19/77

    The sentences in (61) confirm the hypothesis that there is a functional category,NegPwith an abstract head carrying a strong feature, Neg [+neg], against which n'tchecks its ownfeature. This hypothesis explains the fixed position ofn't, which must show up on the highestauxiliary, the one that raises. Ifn'tattached to the lower auxiliary verbs, as in (61b), the features ofn'tcould not be checked. In the same way, there can't be two n'ts as in (62), because there is only onefunctional head against which the two n'ts could check features and, as a result, the features of the

    lowern'twould go to PF unchecked, causing the derivation to crash. The assumption adopted here (following Lopez (1995), Haegeman (1996)) is that theinflected auxiliary is projected under Tense ( do and the modals) or under Aspect (have, be), therefore,under a category whose content it lexiclizes, and then successively raises to check its inflectionalfeatures, ultimately getting to the AgrS0 head where it checks its [Person] features.

    (63) a. Mary hasn't come.b.AgrSP

    AgrS'

    AgrS

    0

    NegP[+person]Neg'

    Neg0 TP[+neg] T'

    T0 AspP

    Asp"

    Asp0 VPhasn't

    DP V'+present V0

    +3d pers+neg come

    Negated modals are subject to the same analysis, except that they are generated under Tense.(64) a. He shouldn't go.

    4.3.2.NotConsider now the syntax ofnot. It differs from ntin the following ways:

    a. It is not cliticized or affixed to auxiliary verbs.b. When auxiliaries raise to C0 past the subject, notmust be left behind (cf. (65)).This suggests thatnotis not a head that checks features through head to head movement the way n'tdoes.c. In sharp contrast to n't, notcan appear in lower positions, as in (66a-c), where notmay be adjoinedto any of the verbal functional projections.d. There can be two nots, as in (66d).e. Finally the two negatives not, n'tco-occur, suggesting that they occupy different positions.

    (65) a. Could you not stay home tonight for a change?b. *Could not you stay home tonight for a change?

    (66) a. He could not have been fooling around so much.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    20/77

    b. He could have not been fooling around so much.c. He could have been not fooling around so much.d. He could not have not been fooling around so much.e. He couldn't not do his homework

    The following result has been obtained:1)N'tis an affixal head that checks features with an abstract functional category.2)Notdoes not have to check features and does not have to be associated to sentence negation.Actually, notcan be adjoined to verbal as well as to non-verbal projections as well, so that anadjunction configuration like (67c) below is generally available.

    (67) a. Not everyone can swim.b. He came here not long ago.

    c.XP

    Neg XPnot

    In sentences which are negative and pass the tests for negativity above, there is a NegP whose strong[+neg] feature must be checked. It can be checked by head to head movement, as already shown, or itcan be checked by specifier -head agreement with a negative specifier. We may analyse notas aspecifier of the NegP. The presence ofnotchecks the feature [+neg] of the negative head "making thesentence negative" (i.e., negation has scope above tense).Notis a functional element. An alternativethat comes to mind is to regard notas a negative adverb, in the lexical class not, never, hardly,scarcely, etc. The analysis ofnotas an adverb is undermined by the fact that, nottriggers do-support,while the other negative adverbs do not.

    (68) a .* I did hardly buy Nixon's book.b. I did not buy Nixon's book.c. I hardly bought Nixon's book.d. *I not bought Nixon's book.

    It is also likely that notshould not be analysed as a head (contra Laka (1990), Chomsky (1993)). Thusexamples like the ones below, show a clear difference between n'twhich is affected by head to headmovement, and not, which is not. Ifn'tis a head and notis a Spec, it is predictable that auxiliaries canskip not, but cannot skip n't.(69) a. He should not have done it.

    b. Should he not have done it ?c. He shouldn't have done it.d. Shouldn't he have done it ?

    Conclusions

    1. Neg sentences contain a NegP headed by a strong negative feature [+neg].

    2. The NegP is uniformly projected above the TP. Tense and negation are conceptually related, sincewhat sentence negation denies is that the event holds at a particular time interval.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    21/77

    3. The Auxiliary verb + negation word order is due to the existence of a higher AgrS phrase,where theAuxiliary verb checks its [Person , Number] features.

    4. Sentential Neg is a functional head whose content is retrieved in two ways, by checking with theaffix n't, or by specifier- head agreement with not. Move is involved in both checking operations. Thederivation of a negative sentence relies on the mechanisms presented in (71), and (72)

    (71) [AgrSP [NegP NEG [TP [ PAST ] [AuxP hasn't]]]

    [AgrSP [NegP not [Neg' NEG [TP [ PAST ] [AuxP has]]]

    (72) [AgrSP hasn't [NegP t [TP t [AuxP t]]][AgrSP has [NegP not [TP t [AuxP t]]]

    5.Do-Support

    (73) He did not come.(74) (a)

    NegP

    Neg Neg'

    not Neg0 TP[+neg]

    DPsubj T'

    T0 VP-ed

    DP V'tsubj

    V0 ...

    come

    5.Do-Support

    (b)AgrSP

    AgrS'AgrS0

    [+ 3d person] NegP

    Neg Neg'not

    Neg0 TP[+neg] T

    T0 VPdid/*ed V'[+past][+ 3d person] V0

    come

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    22/77

    (75) He didn't come.

    (76) AgrSP

    AgrS'

    AgrS0

    NegP[3d person]

    Neg'

    Neg0 TP[+neg]

    T'

    T0 VPdidn't

    V'

    [3d person] V0

    [+past] come

    [+neg]

    5.1. Extending the analysis. Emphatic assertion

    The analysis can be extended to other contexts where do appears, namely: questions, emphaticassertions, short answers and VP-ellipsis:

    (77) a. Do you know this man ?b. Of course, I DO know the truth.c. Of course, I do.

    In all of the cases do supports an abstract morpheme that is not phonetically overt, and which is above

    T: the question morpheme in (77a), the emphatic assertion morpheme in (77b). Consider emphaticassertions first, by examining the following paradigm:

    (78) a. Mary left.b. Mary didn't leave.c. *Mary did leave.

    (79) d. Mary DID leave

    (80)AgrSP

    AgrS

    AgrS0 AffP[3d person]

    Aff'

    Aff0 TP[+aff]

    T'T0 VP

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    23/77

    DID V'[3rd person] V0

    [+past] leave[+aff]

    5.2. Questionsand short answers:

    (84) a. Did she go ?b. What did she sell ?c. Yes, she did.

    Questions are CPs, containing a question feature and a wh feature in C0. The question feature carriesthe interrogative meaning, the wh feature is the syntactic marker of a family of related constructionsall of which involve wh-Movement (questions, relative clauses, cleft sentences). The question featureis strong in root questions and must be checked by moving an auxiliary verb to C0. This is the familiarrule T/Agr0-to- C0 (I0 -to -C0). Since the question feature is checked by moving a verb, it has to beconceived as some sort of verbal feature, and since only finite auxiliaries undergo movement to C0,the Q feature may be viewed as an uninterpretable Tense feature, finite Tense being the common

    property of modals, have, be, do. We will accept that root questions contain a Tense feature in C0, afeature which must attract an appropriate verb. In (85a), the aspectual auxiliary have will raise all theway up to C0, finally checking the Tense and wh features.

    (85) a. Has she come ?b. Is she still working with that company ?c. Could he still go there ?

    (86)CP

    C'

    C0 T/AgrPuTenseuwh DP T/Agr'

    sheT/Agr0 AspP[+Present]

    Asp'

    Asp0 VP

    has come

    5.3 Licensing NPIs: NPIs are always in the command domain of overt negation:

    (87) a. Bill didnt buy any books.b. Bill is not sure that anyone will lift a finger to help.

    (*Anyone will lift a finger to help.)c. *Anyone didnt come.d. Didnt anyone come?

    Conclusions

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    24/77

    1.Do Support occurs in a variety of environments. In all of them do supports an abstractmorpheme (e.g. +neg, +aff, +uTense, +Agr) which appears above Tense, therefore above the

    position of the affixess/ed, and which would remain invisible, unchecked.2. The presence of these abstract heads bearing strong features forces Inflection to be featural, andforces the use of an auxiliary which can successively raise to check all the features.3. Given its morphology, do is inserted under Tense and must raise further at least as far as

    Agreement, possibly to C0

    .4. The requirement that these abstract features should be supported by do is a PF not an LFrequirement5. To claim that there is only one negation in an English sentence is to claim that the abstract Neghead licenses only one negative constituent.

    6. Other types of negative sentences

    6.1. Sentences with negative quantifiers

    Consider the following sets of examples, containing negative quantifiers.

    (90) a. Nobody came to the party, did they ?b. Nobody came to the party, not even her brother.c. Few people showed up for the lecture, and no one showed up for the party either.d. Nobody likes him, neither do I.

    (91) a. They found nothing in the garden. did they?b. They found nothing in the attic, not even old coins.c. They found nothing in the first room and they didn't find much in the second room,

    either.

    These examples point out to two things:a) Sentences with negative quantifiers are syntactically negative and pass all the tests for sentence

    negation.b) These sentences must be "marked" as negative by Spell-Out, because they overtly show thebehaviour of negative sentences.

    The standard analysis of examples like these relies on the insight that sentences with Neg quantifierscontain a NegP, headed by a [+neg] feature, and it is this Neg head which licenses the negativequantifier, if it has sentence scope. Such a view is strengthened by the existence of negative concordlanguages (e.g., Romanian), where the sentence negator must appears on the verb, in order to licensethe negative QPs. Thus in Romanian, nu always shows up in sentences with nimeni, nimic.(92) a. Nimeni nu a venit

    b. *Nimeni a venitc. N-au gasit nimic.d. *Au gasit nimic.

    As to the specific licensing strategy, a frequently invoked solution is the Neg Criterion:(93) a. A negative operator (QP) must be in a Spec head relation with an [+negative] X0 head.

    b. A negative head X0 must be in a spec-head agreement configuration with anegative operator.A negative operatoris a negative phrase in a scope A' position.

    (94) a. No one has come yet.b.AgrsP

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    25/77

    DP AgrS'No one

    AgrS0 NegPhas

    Neg

    Neg0 TPta

    T'

    T0 AspPta

    Asp

    Asp0 VP

    ta come yet

    (96) a. Nobody came

    b.NegP

    DP Neg'Nobody[+neg] Neg0 T/AgrP

    [+neg]DP T/Agr'tnobody

    T/Agr0 VPed come

    (98) a. Mary bought nothingb.NegP

    Op Neg'[+neg]

    Neg0 T/AgrP

    DP T/Agr'Mary

    T/Agr0 VPed

    V'

    V0 DP buy nothing

    [+neg]

    (99) a. Mary has heard nothing.b.

    AgrSP

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    26/77

    DP Agrs'Mary

    Agrs0 NegPhas

    Op Neg'

    [+neg]Neg0 TP[+neg]

    T'

    T0 AspP

    Asp'Asp0 VP

    V'V0 DP

    nothing

    [+neg]

    Conclusions

    1. Neg QPs may have sentence scope, so that sentences containing them pass al the tests for sentencenegation.

    2. When they have sentence scope, negative QPs are licensed by vebal negation, therefore by theNegP.

    3. Negative Quantifiers are licensed by the Neg Criterion.

    6.2.Emphatic negative sentences.The last type of negative sentences considered are emphatic negative sentences.(100) a. Not often did he digress from the topic.

    b. Not until yesterday did he change his mind.c. Seldom do I see him nowadays.d. Never before had he seen such a crowd.

    (101) a. Not long ago it rained.b. Not unreasonably, one may expect results from him.c. In no small measure. it is his attitude that is blocking progress.d. Not far away, it was raining very hard.

    It is easy to prove that sentences in (100) exhibit sentence negation, while those in (101) exhibitconstituent negation, using the familiar tests. Instances of sentence negation admit neithertags, butinstances of constituent negation do not.(102) Not often does Jack attend parties and neither does Jill.

    *Not long ago, Jack attended a party and neither did Jill.Secondly, instances of sentence negation most naturally take affirmative tags, while instances ofconstituent negation take negative tags.

    (103) Not often does Jack attend parties, does he?

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    27/77

    Not long ago Jack attended a party, didn't he ?

    When there is sentence negation, negative polarity items ( any, ever, etc.) are licensed, whileotherwise they are not :(104) Not often does Jack attend any party.

    *Not long ago, Jack attended any parties.

    According to Rudanko (1980), phrases which trigger inversion all "seem to be principally composedof adverbials with an overt or inherent quantifier and motivational adverbs"(1980:356): notoften, notalways, not until, not even then, not because, not for any reason, not under any circumstances, etc.The attempt to give a sharp semantic characterization of the inversion-triggering phrases isundermined by the fact that the same element may or may not cause inversion:(105) With no job, John would be happy.

    With no job would John be happy.(106) In no clothes, Mary looks attractive

    In no clothes does Mary look attractive.This shows that it is the syntax of the sentence rather than the semantics of the phrase which isessential in the description of the contrast between examples (100) and (101)The contrast (100), (101) can be accounted for assuming that the negative constituents which triggerinversion are operators, i.e., sentence negators which have moved to a scope position satisfying the

    Negative Criterion. Accordingly, they will be licensed in a configuration of specifier-head agreementwith a negative head.When an ordinary negated constituent is preposed, which does not qualify as an operator, it does nottrigger inversion since it will not require to be in a Spec-head relation with a negative head. Inversionsignals the presence of the abstract negative head.

    The derivation of emphatic negative sentences

    (107) Seldom do I see him nowadays

    CPAdvP C'

    Seldom[+neg] C0

    T/AgrSP[+neg] DP T/AgrS'[+Tense] I T/Agrs0 VP

    ta AdvP VPtseldom V' AdvP

    V0 DPnowadays

    see himConclusions

    In the following description of English complementation, the finite clause will be assumed to have (atleast) the following structure:

    CP>AgrSP> NegP> TP> AspP1> AspP2 > VPENGLISH COMPLEMENTATION

    Spring 2010

    THATCOMPLEMENTSSYNTACTIC PROPERTIES OF THAT COMPLEMENTS

    1. Similarities and differences between DPs and CPs

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    28/77

    1.1. DPs and CPs share several properties:

    a. Both DPs and CPs occur as arguments of predicates. Thus the Longman Grammar (1999) states that"Complement clauses are sometimes called nominal clauses, because they typically occupy a noun

    phrase slot, such as subject, object, or predicative."

    b. DPs and CPs merge in - positions and are - markedby predicates that c-select and s-select

    them. Predicates, (V, A, or N) which combine with thatcomplements have characteristic s-selectionalproperties. They accept an abstract argument, a Proposition/Theme, and more often thannot, they also s-select a human role,

    Experiencer, orAgent. These two -roles appear in various syntactic functions.(1) a.Ithought that it looked good.

    b. It surprised me that he was right.c.He is aware that he is mistaken.d. It seems to me that he is right.e. It is important (for all of us) that he is still here.f.Iclaim that he is right.

    Similarities (continued)

    c. DPs and CPs accept (some of) the same pronominal substitutes: it, this, that. This is because clauses

    too have default -features, selecting a clause substitute which is [+Neuter, +Singular].

    (2) a. I believe that God is good.b. I believe this/ that / it.c. [That he knows the truth] is not sure.

    Differences between DPs and CPs:

    DPs must be case-licensed, i.e, DPs have case features which must be checked during the derivation.The Case Filter bars the occurrence of DPs which lack Case.

    CPs do no have to be case-licensed. The absence of Case is the main syntactic difference between DPs

    and CPs, from which all the other differences between DP and CP syntax can be derived. Thedistribution of CPs is not determined by the Case Filter. As a result, the distribution of CPs is lessconstrained by syntactic factors and more dependent on discourse factors. Through their syntactic

    position, that-clauses often code discourse function, like focus or topic.

    1.2 Introducing Extraposition

    In this pattern regardless of its syntactic role ((Su(bject), D(irect) O(bject), Prepositional O(bject)),the complement clause appears at the right periphery of the sentence, while the pronoun itappears inthe position which ought to have been occupied by the clause, thus indicating its syntactic function.

    (3) Subjecta. That Pauline moved to Kansas surprised me indeed.

    b. It surprises me indeed [that Pauline moved to Kansas].

    (4) Direct objecta. The engineer wrongly figured out [that the bridge would hold ].

    b. The engineer wrongly figured it out [ that the bridge would hold ].

    (5) Prepositional objecta. Can you swear [ that the accused man was at your house all Friday evening? ].

    b. Can you swear to it [ that the accused man was at your house all Friday evening?].

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    29/77

    The extraposed clause is adjoined to the VP, as in (6) . In (6), the pronoun itoccupies the Nom caseposition, the transitive verb checks the Acc feature of the object, so the CP must be devoid of case.

    (6) IP

    DP I'

    I0 VP

    VP CP

    V0 DPIt surprises me that he didn't come

    The term extraposition is due to Jespersen, MEG. The pronoun it is the so-called introductory-anticipatory it, since it introduces and anticipates the real object of the sentence. The introductory-anticiptory itis regarded as a type of formal subject or object, a "meaningless" or expletive pronoun.

    2. The Case Resistance Principle

    2.1. The difference between DPs and CPs with respect to case has noticeable empirical consequences.(7) a. I am happy that he left.

    b* I am happy his leaving.c. I am happy about his leaving.

    (8) a. I insisted that Mary should depart in the morning.b. *I insisted Mary's departure.c. I insisted on Mary's departure.

    The first attempt to precisely state this difference between CPs and DPs is Stowell's 1981 Case

    Resistance Principle, stated in (9).[ According to Stowell, the case difference between CPs and DPsfollows from a dfference between categories which assign case and categories which are case-marked.

    (9) The Case-Resistance Principle ( CRP)

    Case must not be assigned to a category bearing a case-assigning feature.

    According to Stowell, the case assigning feature that CPs bear is [+Tense], which is involved in theassignment of Nom case in finite clauses. CPs, unlike DPs, bear [+Tense], a verbal case assigningfeature, and cannot be assigned case as a consequence.

    Assuming that there is a difference between -positions and case positions, the consequence of theCRP is that CPs will be banned from positions of case-checking.English supports the CRP to a considerable extent, since in English CPs are excluded from the

    following three basic (structural) case-checking positions:

    a) the position after prepositions;b) the structural Accusative position;c) the Nominative position.

    a) Theprepositionalcontext: In English, CPs cannot be sisters to prepositions.(10) a. I insisted that Mary should depart in the morning

    b.*I insited on that Mary should depart in the morning.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    30/77

    b) Structural Acc: the Acc+ Inf construction. The Acc (in italics in (11)) is -marked by the infinitive

    verb, but gets case from the main verb, (consider). Since the Case source is not the -assigner, the

    Acc is structural. The example in (11b) is analogous. The CP is -marked by the subordinateinfinitive predicate, and would get case from the main verb (consider). The CP is in a structural Acc

    position, this leading to ill-formedness.

    (11) a. I consider [ this statement] to be a big mistake].b *I consider[ [CP that Mary left] to be a big mistake].

    c) The Nominative positionSentence (13a), with the subject clause in preverbal position, may be taken to show that the subjectclause is in SpecT, i.e. in a position where it has been assigned Nom. On the other hand, sentence(13e). where the Auxiliary has moved to Comp is ungrammatical. Given the ungrammaticality of(13e), it is likely that in the well-formed (13a) the clause is in topic, rather than subject position. Assuggested by examples like (13b), there is more than one preverbal position in English. In (13b), lastnightand in London are topicalized phrases.(13) a. That John hates Mary could be true.

    a' [[ TP That John hates Mary] [TP tCP [T'could be true]]].b. Last night, in London, the killer struck again.c. Could this be true ?d.*Did last night, in London, the killer strike again ?e. * Could [that he hates her] be true ?

    2.2. CPs may have to pass through case-marked positions

    Stowell's insight that DPs and CPs differ in terms of case is correct. Nevertheless, as stated in (9), theCRP is too strong and there are empirical facts which disprove it, since they involve CPs that havemoved through case-positions, even if they do not remain there.One example is that of operator-variable constructions, movement constructions, where what moves isthe CP, acting as a syntactic operator. It is well known that an operator's trace, (=a variable), must bein a case-marked position. Such operator-variable constructions include relativization, question

    formation, tough-movement, topicalization, a.o. Simple examples with DP operators show thatvariables are case-marked:

    (15) a. What are you so happy about tDPb*What are you so happy tDP

    (16) a. Who tDP wrote it?b. * Who was it written tDP ?c. Who was it written by tDP ?

    Examples (15b, (16b) are ill-formed since the trace is not case marked. The adjective happy in (15b)cannot case-mark the DP-trace. The passive verb in (16b) cannot case-mark the DP trace either, so the

    preposition by is necessary to case-license the trace, as in (16c)

    Safir(1985) investigates the behaviour of clauses in operator-variable constructions, systematicallycomparing extraposed and unextraposed clauses. Extraposed clauses are in caseless position, and

    predictably, they cannot participate in operator-variable constructions. The essential observationis that only unextraposed clauses participate in operator-variable constructions. Therefore, they leave

    behind case-marked traces.The operator-variable construction considered below is Topicalization. This rule moves a DP/CP tothe left periphery, leaving behind a case-marked trace.(17) a. That Susan would be late John didn't think [ tCP was very likely]

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    31/77

    b. *That Susan would be late John didn't think [ it was very likely tCP](18) a. That he had solved the problem we didn't really find [tCP to be very surprising]

    b.* That he had solved the problem we didn't really find [it to be verysurprising tCP]

    (19) a. That we won't abandon him you may definitely depend on tCP.b. *That we won't abandon him you may definitely depend on it tCP.

    In every pair, only the unextraposed clause can be topicalized, while the extraposed clause cannot.The chains in examples (17a)-(19a) are correctly formed, containing the operator, that is, thetopicalized CP, which binds a variable, i.e., a trace in a case-marked position. In contrast the trace ofthe extraposed clause is not in a case-marked position. The operator does not bind a variable in (17b)-(19b), the chains are incorrectly formed, so severe ungrammaticality results.

    Conclusions

    1. At least sometimes, CPs mustpass through positions where case is licensed, against the CRP.

    2. One might interpret this as a sign that a CP may be used to check the strong case feature of somehead. Thus, one might claim that in (17), the CP moves from Spec VP to SpecTP, and perhaps furtheron in order to check the strong features of Tense in English. The principle at work is Lasnik's 1995Enlightened self interest: a constituent, in this case the CP, moves to satisfy the needs of another

    constituent, in this case Tense (Inflection). Tense may attract the CP, because the latter possesses features. Thus Case may not be the right way of eliminating the ungramamtical sentences in (10-13)above.

    3.Given the data in (17-19), the CRP cannot be maintained in the strong form initially proposed byStowell.

    2.3. More recently, Stowell's CRP has been reinterpreted as a categorial filter. The proposal is that theCP category is categorially unsuited in certain configurations. This forces clauses to move out of these

    positions. This interpretation is based on the intuition that predicates/heads should be categoriallydistinct from their arguments or, more generally from the constituents they govern. Evidence for acategorial filter comes from the fact that sequences of type *N NP (*destruction the city vsdestruction of the city), *I ^IP, etc are usually unacceptable.

    (20) A head and its complement must be distinct in terms of their categorial features.

    This categorial filter is sufficient to eliminate sequences of type *P^CP. Categorially speaking, CPsare surely [-N], which is why they do not need case. They may also be viewed as [-V], this allows

    them the possibiity to be -marked arguments. IF CPs are [-N,-V], they are non-distinct from

    prepositions and subordinating conjunctions, which are also traditionally described as [-N, -V]. Wederive the unacceptability of (22)

    (22) a. *They complained about [ that salaries were too low].b. *Although [that she had done her work], the master was displeased.

    Conclusions

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    32/77

    1.Unlike DPs, CPs do not have to be Case-licensed.

    2. Nevertheless, CPs can be attracted to case positions, at least when they are antecedents inoperator-variable cosntructions.

    3. As they pass through positions of case checking, they will be case-marked, this allowingthem to appear in operator variable constructions. This property is not available to clauses inextraposed position precisly because they do not acquire a case feature.

    4. By virtue of their categorial properties CPs are filtered away from certain environments,such as the position of sister to a preposition.

    3. The Extraposition Structure

    (26) Subject

    a. That Pauline moved to Kansas surprised me indeed.b. It surprises me indeed [ that Pauline moved to Kansas ].

    Direct object

    a. The engineer wrongly figured out [ that the bridge would hold ].b. The engineer wrongly figured it out [ that the bridge would hold ].

    Prepositional object

    a. Can you swear [ that the accused man was at your house all Friday

    evening? ].b. Can you swear to it [ that the accused man was at your house all Fridayevening? ].

    2.2Establishing a link between itand the CP

    The it+CP configuration does not represent a chain of type expletive +associate, for the followingreasons:

    a) CPs do not have to be in a case-marked -chain.b) CPs do not inherit case form it. The CP is caseless when extraposed.

    Let us turn to claims a) and b), under the standard assumption that Case is inherited along the

    members of a chain. For example, whom in SpecCP in (30) is Acc-marked and so is its trace in DOposition. Consider then the examples in (31):

    (30) Whom did you see t ?(31) a. *It was bizarre Mary's departure.

    b. It was bizarre that Mary left.c. *It was noticed Mary's departure.d. It was noticed that Mary left.e.There seems to be a man under your bed.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    33/77

    Examples (31a-d) prove that DPs cannot occur in the position of the extraposed clause, because that isa caseless position and DPs need case. Evidence that extraposed clauses do not inherit Case from theexpletive it comes from operator-variable constructions.

    Evidence that extraposed clauses do not inherit Case from the expletive it comes from operator-

    variable constructions.

    a) Topicalization The topicalized clause moves to the CP field, and it should leave behind a trace in acase-assigned position. If it were true that extraposed clauses inherit case from the expletive it, itwould not matter, in operator variable constructions, whether the (unextraposed )clause is itself in acase position or whether the (extraposed) clause merely inherits case from the expletive it. However,this expectation is no confirmed. Only the unextraposed clause can be topicalized, while theextraposed clause cannot. This is because the trace of the unextraposed clause is in a case marked

    position (a subject trace in (32), a direct object trace in (33), while the trace of the extraposed clause isin a non-case marked position.

    (32) a. That Susan would be late John didn't think [ tCP was very likely]

    b. *That Susan would be late John didn't think [ it was very likely tCP](33) a. That he had solved the problem we didn't really find [tCP to be very surprising]

    b. *That he had solved the problem we didn't really find [it to be very surprising tCP]

    b)Appositive relative clauses. A that-complement can serve as the antecedent of an appositive clauseonly if the trace it ultimately binds through the mediation of the relative pronoun is in a case position.Since the relative pronoun itself is a DP, rather than a CP, the requirement that the relative pronounshould check case is natural.

    (34) a.[ That Mary was leaving]i , whichi ti was noticed at once, upset Joe.

    b.[That Mary was leaving]i , whichi iti was noticed at once ti upset Joe.

    Thus the evidence from operator-variable constructions shows that there is no case transmissionbetween itand the CP, so that it +CPare not members of a chain.

    Conclusions

    1. The evidence argues both against Case-transmission from it to the CP

    2. Safir (1985) proposes that itand the CPare simply related as members of a configuration. Thesemantic relation between itand the CPis that the CP is an adjunct which specifies the content of the

    pronoun, very much like an appositive clause, which specifies the content of the antecedent (e.g., thefact that he has abandoned his former love).

    4. The subject-object asymmetry in Extraposition constructions

    On the motivaton of extraposition A fundamental remark regarding Extraposition in English, is thatthis structure is extremely frequent if not quasi-obligatory for subject clauses and marginal for DO andPO clauses. This asymmetry is motivated by structuralas well as byfunctionalconsiderations. The

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    34/77

    examination of the motivation for extraposition will help us choose among the various proposals onhow to analyse Extraposition syntactically.

    Cullicover and Rochemont (1990), in work on Focus constructions, include Extraposition in a largeclass of constructions which are motivated by functional considerations. Quirk e.a. (1972) mention thetwo discourse principles of End-Focus and End-Weight, which play a major role in determining word-

    order in English. According to these two principles, other things being equal, constituents which arefocussed and constituents which are "long" and heavy tend to occur towards the end of the sentence.

    4.1 More on End-focus and End-weight.

    Structural FocusEnglish disposes of two syntactic structures specifically designed to place a constitiuent in focus.These are the cleft sentence, in (39)&(40), and the pseudo-cleft sentence, in (41). In both instances theconstituent which occurs afterbe is focussed, while the rest of the sentence contains presuppostionalinformation.

    (39) a. What did he purchase for his wife?b. It was [ a brand new fur coat ] that John purchased for his wife.

    c. Focus: A brand new fur coat.d. Presupposition: He purchased something for his wife.

    (40) a. Who purchased a brand new fur coat for his wife?b. It was [ John] who purchased a brand new fur coat for his wifec. Focus. John (purchased a new fur coat for his wife).d. Presupposition: Someone bought a brand new fur coat for his wife.

    (41) a. What does Mary want ?b. What Mary wants is a rich husband.c. Assertion: (Mary wants) a rich husband.d. Presupposition. Mary wants something.

    4.1 More on End-focus and End-weight.

    Topicalization is a syntactic rule designed to indicate the topic of discourse or a link, the constituentwhich bridges between the given sentence and the preceding discourse. The topic is thus aninformationally given element.

    (42) A: They would like to offer you roses.B: Roses I heartily dislike t.

    Topicalization is possible only if there is a case-marked trace in the initial position of the topic.

    4.2. The functional perspective

    Extraposition of a Su clause is functional, since it enables a Su clause, which is a heavy constituent,often containing new information, to occur in final position.

    S clause V O => itV O S clause

    (43) a. He kept complaining. It annoyed him that inflation was running so high.b. ?That inflation was running so high annoyed him.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    35/77

    c. He kept complaining. He had found out that inflation was running high.

    Extraposition from object position is not motivated by the same considerations, since object clausesalready satisfy the principles of End-Focus and End-Weight. In a simple declarative transitive SVOsenetnce with neutral intonation, the O is the expected focus. Hence, DO/PO extraposition isfunctionally superfluous and therefore, infrequent. On the other hand, when DO/PO extraposition does

    occur, the resulting structure has characterstic semantic and pragmatic properties. (see below).SV O clause => SV it O

    (46) a. John regretted [that he had abandoned the race].b. John regretted itthat he had abandoned the race.

    4.3. The structural perspectiveStructurally, the motivation for extraposition+itinsertion comes from the Extended ProjectionPrinciple and from Case Theory (see next section).English is a SVO language that requires an overt subject in preverbal position. Reinterpreting the EPPin feature-checking terms, the fact that a subject in SpecT is always required in English means that theT head has strong features, features which require checking by moving an (appropriate) constituent toSpecT. When there are reasons for the semantic "real" subject to be post-verbal, as is the case with

    extraposed subject clauses, a formal, 'meaningless' itsubject is needed tocheck the strong feature of Tand satisfy the EPP.While for the reasons explained, the Nom Su position must be lexically filled , there is no requirement

    to lexically realize the Acc DO position. If an object clause does not appear in its -position, thelatter may remain empty, as in (46a) or it may be filled by the introductory anticipatory pronoun it, asin (46b).

    (46) a. John has known it for a long time that Mary will leave him.b. John has known tCP for a long time that Mary will leave him.

    Conclusions.1. Extraposition is a discourse-related rule, which places a clausal constituent in Focus position and atthe right periphery, satisfying End Focus and End Weight.

    2. Extraposition is quasi-obligatory for Su clauses, but infrequent for DO/PO clauses.3. The subject /object asymmetry is important enough to be looked upon as a structural phenomenon,therefore as a matter of syntax, rather than a matter of stylistic preference.

    5. On the English expletives

    A central claim about expletives is that they occur only in subject position. The Su receives its -rolein SpecVP. It follows that the Su position, Spect TP, is projected for purely syntactic reasons, havingto do with the strong features of Tense and must therefore be filled even when it has no semanticrelevance. Consider the passives below. The passive is an ergative configuration which lacks athematic subject, but where the syntactic subject SpecT position must be filled nevertheless. It may befilled by the clause itself, or it may be filled by an expletive pronoun:

    (47) a. That the earth was flat was widely believed in ancient times.b. It was widely believed that the earth was flat in ancient times.

    Since the object position is projected only from thematic structure, therefore only if the verb assigns a

    role in object position, expletive pronouns would not be expected to occur as objects.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    36/77

    However, it has been claimed (cf. Postal and Pullum (1988)) that there are many counterexamples tothis claim, such as those in (48) and (49). In each case there seems to be an expletive pronoun in what

    should be a -position, against GB theory.(48) a. I consider it obvious that you should have done that.

    b. I prevented/ kept it from being obvious that we were late.(49) a. I regretted (it) that he was late.

    b. They never mentioned (it) to the candidate that the jog was poorly paid.c. I resent it every time you say that.d. I hate it when you are late.

    The following claims will be defended here, following Rothstein (1995):1) Expletives occur only in subject position and this follows from the distinguished syntactic nature ofthe subject position.2) The examples in (48) are not counterexamples to the theory, since the pronoun is projected as asubject and is (at most) a derived object.3) When the neuter pronoun itis an object (the examples in (49)), it is not an expletive, but an

    ordinary pronoun, which receives a role.4) This leads to a disunitary analysis of textraposition, since only in the case of extraposition from

    subject position will the clause be initially projected in a -position (SpecVP). For the other cases,the neuter pronoun will be projected in the (prepositional or direct) object position, while the clausewill be projected as an adjunct or in some other position. If this analysis is adopted, it is important todefine the semantic relation holding between the pronoun and the clause, when the pronoun is not anexpletive.

    5.1. Licensing subject expletives. The EPP feature of Tense

    The expletive itis a neuter pronoun, whose main property is that it does not receive any role. As aresult it appears in contexts where lexical DPs, which must be thematic, are banned. In (50), the only

    overt) -role of the passive verb goes to the CP, so the lexical DP in (50b) cannot be interpreted and

    violates the - Criterion.

    (50) a. It was widely believed that the world was flat.

    b. *The hypothesis was widely believed that the world was flat.

    Because expletives fail to be -marked, they cannot be questioned.

    (51) a. That he came was a blessing for them.b. Whatwas a blessing for them ?c.Itwas a blessing for them that he came.d.*Whatwas a blessing for them that he came?

    Expletive as quasi-arguments

    Since, in principle, pleonastic elements are devoid of content, it was proposed (cf. Chomsky (1991))

    that these elements are deleted at LF, because they simply satisfy formal features which have nointerpretation.This analysis proved to be problematic for at least two reasons:a) Different expletive elements with the same role, say different formal subjects, do not contribute inthe same way to the interpretation of the sentence (cf. (53))

    b) Secondly, sentences with expletives are not semantically equivalent with sentences withoutexpletives. Thus, in (54), the variant without there, with the phrase some ghosts in SpecT, presupposesthe existence of ghosts, while the sentence witht there in SpecT does not presuppose the existence ofghosts.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    37/77

    (53) a. It was a man. (Who was it ?)b. There was a man. (Was there anyone in the room?)

    (54) a. There were som ghosts in the pantry.b. Some ghosts were in the pantry.

    The position on expletives adopted here is that expletives are legitimate LF objects with 'null'

    reference, since they make no contribution to the truth conditions of the sentence. It then becomesnecessary to specify for it / there how they are licensed (legitimacy) and what interpretativecontribution ( if any) they have.Assuming the principle of Full Interpretation, a natural question is what principles of the grammarlicense pleonastics.

    Currently there are two (convergent) ways of stating the intuition that expletive pronoun occur to fill asynatctic subject position: a) the syntactic predication account; b) the EPP account.

    a) The syntactic predication account(Rothstein (1995) claims that subjects occur to satisfy thecondition that syntactic predicates must have subjects. This idea is stated as a Predicate Condition:

    (59) Predicate Condition

    Every syntactic predicate must be syntactically saturated.A syntactic predicate is an open maximal projection that needs to be saturated by being linked to asyntactic argument, its subject. Crucially, predicates need not have a thematic relation with theirsubjects, though they must have a thematic relation with their objects. It follows that expletiveelements are licensed only as subjects. A pleonastic subject denotes the null element, since it is has no

    -role and, when the predicate takes a pleonastic subject, the truth value of the proposition is fullydetermined by the content of the predicate. The ergative verb + its object represents a complexsyntactic predicate which needs a subject. The subject is licensed only syntactically, to satisfy theneeds of the (non-lexical) syntactic predicate.

    (60) a. It was obvious that we would be late.b. That we'd be late was obvious.

    c. It was obvious.The expletive interpretation is one way of reading an otherwise ordinary pronoun like it, in thosescases where the syntactic predicate is completely responsible for the semantic interpretation of thesentence; therefore, the pleonastic appears as a default reading, made available by the interaction ofthe principles of interpretation and the properties of pronominals.

    b) The EPP account

    The analysis in terms of syntactic predication does not, however, explain the difference betweenEnglish and, say, Romanian, where the semantic process is similar to English, and there are also caseswhen an ergative verb with its object expresses a complete proposition, but no pleonastic element isovertly present. The fact that the Su is overt in English is related to the well-known fact that English is

    non-pro-drop a language, that is a language where the Su is obligatory.

    The presence of the Su is related to the EPP. The obligatory preverbal Su position in SpecT is theeffect of the features of the functional head T. T is assumed to have a strong D/N feature which canonly be satisfied by Merging or Moving a DP/NP in the (lowest) specifier of T.

    5.2. On the English Expletives.There and itbehave differently, at least with respect to agreement.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    38/77

    (61) a. There is a boy in the room.b. There are boys in the room.

    The different agreement pattern follows from the obvious morpho-syntactic difference between itand

    there.There is an adverbialexpletive, so it lacks -features. This is why in there sentences

    agreement features are checked with the lexical subject, which possesses -features

    Itis apronominalexpletive which has -features: it is a [+3d person, +neuter, +singular] pronoun.Subject italways imposes singular agreement on the verb. This is apparent under co-ordination:

    (62) a. That the president will be re-elected and that he will be impeached are both likely at this point.b. It is /*are equally likely at this point [CP that the president will be re-elected and that he

    will be impeached]

    Let us turn to the expletive there. There may be analysed as a DP that checks the case and EPP

    features, but cannot value the -features of Tense. The simplest analysis is to assume that thereoriginates as a small clause subject and agrees with the predicative inside the small clause.

    There is thus a defective DP, lacking the - features of person and number, but bearing a case featurechecked by T. This analysis suggets that Case may be checked without simultneously checking

    Agreement.

    (62) There are monsters

    IP

    DP I

    I VP

    V XP

    DP X

    X NP

    There are tbe tThere monsters

    5.2. Object Expletives

    5.2.1 A real expletive

    The only case of true expletive objects is that ofderived objects, that is, consituents which start out as(expletive) subjects, but are case-marked by the verb above them.

    (63) I find itimpossible to live under these circumstances.

    5.2.2 It is a -marked pronoun in other cases:(64) a. I regretted (it) that he was late.

    b. They never mentioned (it) to the candidate that the job was poorly paid.c. I resent it every time you say that.d. I hate it when you are late.

  • 8/6/2019 English Complement at Ion

    39/77

    In such cases, the extraposed CP/XPs must be independently licensed. There are three types oflicensing such a phrase. One of them does not involve an it+ CPstructure, but it is instrumental inunderstanding the object it +CPconstruction.

    a.Itas an event variable bound by a quantifier over times

    We refer to examples of type (64 c, d) or (65) below, the DO it is followed by a Time AdverbialQuantifier. In (65a-c) the adverbial is a quantified DP (every time I have dinner with John, etc), whilein (65e), it is followed by a when(ever) time clause. It designates an event variable, quantified over bythe adverbial(65) a. I regret it every time I have dinner with John.

    b. The children enjoy it every time you tell them a story.c. They announced it publicly every time they decided to move house.d. He used to like it when(ever) it thundered late.

    In such examples is that it desgnates an event-variable. Sentence (65a) means "for every event ofhaving dinner with John, I regret that event".. It is a variable that ranges over events of having dinnerwith John (example a), or events of deciding to move house ( example c). The pronoun it now has a

    semantic role, it is an e- variable bound by the quantifier of time. The semantic value of it can beappreciated by comparing (65a) with (66) where it is missing:(66) I regretted every time I had dinner with John.

    In (66), the every phrase is the object of the verb. In (65), where the every phrase is an operatorbinding the pronoun, there is a "matching relation" between events named by the every phrase andevents named by the matrix verb. Sentence (65a) asserts that every event of my having dinner withJohn is matched with an event of my regretting having dinner with him. By contrast, (66) asserts that Iregretted all the occasions of having dinner with John, but it makes no claim about how manyregretting events there were. Thus (66), but not (65a) is appropriate in a situation when, after ten yearsof happy dinner occasions, something happens that makes me regret that I ever had dinner with John.

    Selectional restrictions Since it denotes an event, with this interpretation, it is allowed with just thoseverbs that s-select events. Regret is one such verb, but claim is not. Evidence for this comes fromgerunds, which as known, can express events. Expectedly, regret appears with the gerund, claim doesnot:

    (67) He regretted doing it /that he had done it.*He claimed doing it/ that he had done it

    If a verb does not allow its Theme to be an event, then the verb does not occur in bound time adverbialconstructions, like (65). The verb claim, for instance, can only select a proposition for its object, so itdoes not appear in the it+ (quantified) adverbial construction.

    (68) He claimed it, but it wasn't true.He claimed it every time he saw you.

    The important point is that in the it+ quantified time adverbial construction, the pronoun has semanticcontent, designating an event variable, bound by the adverbial quantifier. The pronoun it is not anexpletive.

    b)Itis a specific context known event. It is an ordina