28
Epistemic Modality in Greek: Towards a Constructional and Typological Approach Accepting language as in some way a result of cognitive processes, understanding any language necessarily involves accounting for the ways in which these processes are instantiated in that language. The present study represents a tentative and initiatory explanation to lay the groundwork for understanding the conceptualization and construal of epistemic modality in ancient Greek. A constructional approach can best account for the primary methods through which epistemic stance is expressed in Greek texts, and a typology by which a superior organization and understanding of primary epistemic constructions is possible. However, before a typology of epistemic constructions is possible, basic components of these constructions, basic constructions, and some understanding of their interaction must be analyzed. The purpose of the present study is to do just this. 1. Epistemic Modality It is impossible to proceed with a description of how epistemic modality is conceptualized in ancient Greek without first understanding what epistemic modality is: Epistemic modality is defined here as (the linguistic expression of) an evaluation of the chances that a certain hypothetical state of affairs under consideration (or some aspect of it) will occur, is occurring, or has occurred in a possible world which serves as the universe of interpretation for the evaluation process… In other words, epistemic modality concerns

Epistemic Modality in Greek- Towards a Constructional and Typological Approach

  • Upload
    50bmg

  • View
    12

  • Download
    1

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • Epistemic Modality in Greek:

    Towards a Constructional and Typological Approach

    Accepting language as in some way a result of cognitive processes, understanding

    any language necessarily involves accounting for the ways in which these processes are

    instantiated in that language. The present study represents a tentative and initiatory

    explanation to lay the groundwork for understanding the conceptualization and construal

    of epistemic modality in ancient Greek. A constructional approach can best account for

    the primary methods through which epistemic stance is expressed in Greek texts, and a

    typology by which a superior organization and understanding of primary epistemic

    constructions is possible. However, before a typology of epistemic constructions is

    possible, basic components of these constructions, basic constructions, and some

    understanding of their interaction must be analyzed. The purpose of the present study is

    to do just this.

    1. Epistemic Modality

    It is impossible to proceed with a description of how epistemic modality is

    conceptualized in ancient Greek without first understanding what epistemic modality is:

    Epistemic modality is defined here as (the linguistic expression of) an

    evaluation of the chances that a certain hypothetical state of affairs under

    consideration (or some aspect of it) will occur, is occurring, or has

    occurred in a possible world which serves as the universe of interpretation

    for the evaluation process In other words, epistemic modality concerns

  • an estimation of the likelihood that (some aspect of) a certain state of

    affairs is/has been/will be true (or false) in the context of the possible

    world under consideration. And this estimation of likelihood is situated on

    a scale (henceforth called the epistemic scale) going from certainty that

    the state of affairs applies, via a neutral or agnostic stance towards its

    occurrence, to certainty that it does not apply, with intermediary positions

    on the positive and the negative sides of the scale.D1

    Epistemic modality is, then, includes a very large category of possible statements. There

    are any number of methods through which a speaker can construeD2D their place on the

    epistemic scale. From a pragmatic perspectiveD3D, this is not even limited to word choice.

    Intonation, the context of utterance, and other factors make it possible to turn a simple

    indicative statement into a construal of the likelihood of a situation. For example, the

    statement

    (1) He was at home.

    is, in and of itself, not an expression or construal of epistemic modality. There is nothing

    present in (1) itself to indicate the speakers stance on the likelihood of the situation

    under consideration. It is presented as simple fact. However, when placed in a specific

    context, the same statement can represent the speakers epistemic stance.

    (2) Speaker 1: Theres no possible way he could have been studying,

    because I swear I saw him at the club last night.

    Speaker 2: He was at home.

    In (2), the statement made in (1) is set in the context of discourse. A base spaceD4D is

    present in which the act of studying by unnamed individual is under consideration. From

  • this base space a possibility space is constructed by the Speaker 1 in which the unnamed

    individual is in fact not studying, but is at a club. Speaker 2, in making the same

    statement present in (1) is now emphatically denying the state of affairsD5D described in the

    possibility space constructed by Speaker 1. In this context, He was at home is certainly

    a construal of epistemic modality because it is now concerned with the likelihood of a

    particular state of affairs. In fact, the very aspects of the statement in (1) which it

    excluded it from the realm of epistemic modality are in (2) the indication of the speakers

    stance on the epistemic scale. In (1), no part of the statement indicates the possibility that

    the state of affairs described did not happen. In (2), this lack of such indications places

    the speaker at the far end (at certainty) on the epistemic scale, completely rejecting the

    possibility of the state of affairs set up by the possibility space constructed by Speaker 1.

    If (1), which contains nothing to indicate the speakers epistemic stance, can be an

    expression of epistemic modality, then the number of ways in which epistemic modality

    can be construed are limitless and form a complex and open class. Additionally, just as

    the lack of any epistemic components can indicate a speakers epistemic stance, there are

    a wide range of epistemic components which may be present in a statement to locate the

    speakers statement somewhere on the epistemic scale: Epistemic modality can be

    expressed by a variety of linguistic forms,such as epistemic phrases, adverbs, adjectives,

    nouns, lexical verbs and participial forms.D6D The complexity and open-ended nature of

    the linguistic construal of epistemic modality make it impossible to capture the infinite

    number of ways epistemic statements can be made.

    What is possible, however, and what the present study is concerned with, is the

    following:

  • 1. What are the typical or proto-typical components involved in the

    general construal of epistemic modality in any given language (in this

    case ancient Greek)?

    2. Are these components typically structured in ways which make possible

    meaningful generalizations concerning the nature of epistemic

    constructionsD7D in that language?

    3. If it is possible to identify the basic components and constructions

    generally used, is it possible to construct a typology of the methods in

    which the simpler components and structures are used to indicate the

    speakers epistemic stance?

    In other words, simply identifying that any number of words, types of words, and

    combinations of words can express epistemic modality does not aid in understanding how

    speakers in a given language use lexical and syntactical features in that language in

    conceptualizing and construing the likelihood involved in any given situation. On the

    other hand, identifying patterns of lexical and syntactical constructions, and their

    components, used by speakers to express epistemic modality enables a better

    understanding of how speakers use their language to express a vital aspect of

    communication.

    In order to lay the groundwork for understanding epistemic modality in ancient

    Greek, several texts of Greek oratory were examinedD8D. From these texts, a corpus of

    epistemic statements were extracted and examined. The typical components used in these

    statements were identified, including lexical items and simple constructions. From this

    examination, the present study constructs a tentative typology of basic epistemic

  • constructions and identifies not only some important aspects on the construal of epistemic

    stance in complex epistemic constructions, but also notes areas where further

    investigation is necessary.

    2. Basic Components

    As was already noted, no epistemic markers are necessary in the construction of

    epistemic statements. It is possible for context alone to transform a statement which lacks

    all such markers into an epistemic construction. However, in the corpus examined, many

    common components were used as epistemic markers in epistemic constructions. Three

    of the most important classes of epistemic markers are outlined below. Excluded are any

    components which alone are capable of consideration as epistemic constructions.

    1. Grammatical Mood

    Greek grammarsD9D traditionally recognize a number of moods any Greek word can take,

    including indicative, subjunctive, and optative, which were the most common in

    epistemic constructions. While the indicative mood was the most common mood used in

    epistemic constructions, this likely due to the fact that it was also the most common mood

    used throughout the texts. The optative mood, on the other hand, while not being enough

    by itself to construe epistemic stance, was the only mood capable of being the primary

    component in an epistemic construction in determining epistemic stance, but even here it

    was often combined with an - clause:

    (3)

    , .

  • For it would be a great stroke of good fortune for the youth, if one alone

    corrupts them, but the others aid. (Plat. Apol. 25b)

    (4) ,

    .

    For if they mean this, I would admit I am an orator, [though] not in a class

    with these. (Plat. Apol. 17b)

    Both of the above lines contain a potential optative construction used as an epistemic

    construction. However, the contrast between the two uses shows the ability of the

    potential optative construction to be both the primary component in an epistemic

    construction, as well as a more secondary one. In (3), the potential optative is the primary

    component which is used to construe Socrates epistemic stance. In (4), the -clause sets

    up a possibility space to consider, and the potential optative construction constructs a

    resultative space from the possibility space. The -clause already indicates that the state

    of affairs under consideration is non-actual, and therefore even before the potential

    optative construction Socrates indicates that he doesnt believe his opponents mean what

    he suggests as possible in the possibility space. However, in (3), the potential optative is

    the component of the epistemic construction which initially construes the non-actuality of

    the state of affairs under consideration, and the -clause is secondary. So while in neither

    case, as found in the corpus in general, does the potential optative construction

    encapsulate the epistemic construction, (3) show that it is quite possible for this

    construction to be primary.

    2. Tense

  • Various studies have shown the importance of tense in English in construing the

    speakers epistemic stanceD10D. The present study found tense was also a primary

    component in epistemic modality in Greek. Epistemic constructions in the corpus used all

    tenses, and often more than one in the same construction. However, two general

    observations are important. First, future tense indicative epistemic constructions were less

    present. Most epistemic statements used moods as a primary indicator of the possibility

    of future states of affairs. Second, the use of the future tense indicative tended to place

    the speakers epistemic stance towards the certainty end of the epistemic scale:

    (5)

    Being cleared of all forms of the charge, neither going into the holy places

    will I profane the sanctity of the gods(Antiph. 2.2.11)

    The very fact that the state of affairs under consideration is a future one makes it

    unrealized. However, rather than distancing himself from the certainty that this

    hypothetical state of affairs will be as described (e.g. by using words such as I think or

    by using a different mood/tense of the verb to be) the use of the future indicative

    construes the state of affairs as a certainty..

    3. Particles

    Greek particles are numerous and are found throughout Greek literature, used in

    all manner of ways. In the corpus examined, the most common use of particles which

    contributed to the construal of epistemic stance were emphatic (e.g. and )D11D.

    However, other particles were often used as epistemic markers in interesting ways. For

    example, in (4) above, the use of in the -clause without a corresponding may

  • suggest that some sort of clause to the effect of but they dont after Socrates states if

    they mean this.D12D The therefore is an epistemic marker in that construction,

    although this was not a common occurrence in the corpus.

    One particle in particular, however, was of paramount importance in epistemic

    constructions. The particle was used in a variety of epistemic constructions. Just how

    this particle should be understood will be discussed in the section below devoted to .

    4. Adjectives/Adverbs

    A common element in epistemic constructions in the corpus were qualifying

    words used as secondary components to further determine exactly where the speakers

    epistemic stance was on the epistemic scale. For example, two common adverbs, and

    , were commonly used as components in Simple Epistemic Verbal Constructions

    (SEVCs), but also in Complex Epistemic Constructions (CECs):

    (6) ,

    If we all were shown to be clever speakers, I know well that your own

    situation would not be in anyway better. (Dem. Ex. 7.2)

    (7)

    For we know clearly that all of the city is being stained by him

    (Antiph. 2.1.3)

  • In (7), a more complex form of an SEVC (by virtue of other components being present in

    the construction), the adverb simply adds force to the speakers construal of his

    epistemic stance (as does the use of the first person plural, which serves to pull the jury

    into the speakers epistemic construal). In (6), the adverb serves the exact same

    purpose, even though the epistemic construction is far more complex, using many

    elements to construe the speakers epistemic stance.

    3. The particle

    Any comprehensive grammar of Greek will invariably list a number of

    constructions in which either can or must be used. The variety of these constructions

    make it difficult to define in any meaningful way. Smyth states explicitly that its

    force varies as it modifies the meaning of the moods.D13D Goodwin argues that has, in

    general, two separate main uses. In the first of these two it denotes that the action of

    the verb to which it is joined is dependent upon some condition, expressed or implied.D14D

    In the second is joined with relative and temporal words, and sometimes final

    particlesD15D rather than verbs. Similarly, Basset divides an into its appearance in protasis

    and apodosis: En grec ancient, la particule avait deux employs principaux

    doublement divergents. Dans un protase, aprs ou , dans une relative, une

    temporelle ou une finale, cest--dire dans des propositions subordonnes, elle

    accompagnait un subjunctive et se liait au mot subordonnantDans une apodose de

    systme hypothtique ou dans une proposition indpendante ou assimilable une

  • independente, elle accompagnait un optatif ou un temps secondaire de lindicatif.FiFD16D As

    a lexical item, what is it possible to say about the meaning of , not just in terms of

    epistemic modality but in ancient Greek as a whole, given such diverse usage? First, any

    lexical item used with any frequency is almost invariably polysemous: it has multiple

    related meanings that have all been conventionalized to some degree and therefore there

    is no single abstract meaning from which all its uses can be predicted.D17D Rather, an

    encyclopedic viewD18D of the various meanings of will more fully explain its uses,

    and likely enable definitions of the particle that are avoided in descriptive grammarsD19D.

    Second, as noted by Smyth, Goodwin, Schwyzer & Debrunner, and so forth, the particle

    is invariably linked to other words in constructions. As constructions are not merely

    an unstructured list but rather form a structured inventory of a speakers knowledge of

    the conventions of their language.D20D These constructions are represented in a taxonomic

    network. In other words, does have meaning, and can be viewed like any other

    lexical item in Greek. It simply is more closely linked with a limited number of

    constructions than other lexical items. To understand the meaning of , each

    construction in which the meaning differs must be understood as a separate node in the

    network of constructions in which is used. Although such an exercise is beyond the

    scope of this study, it would enable an encyclopedic definition of , and better account

    for its use.

    i In ancient Greek, the particle has two principle uses for two different reasons. In a protasis, after or , in a relative, a temporal or a final, that is to say, in subordinate clauses, it accompanies a subjunctive and it links itself to a subordinate word. In an apodosis of [the Greek] hypothetical system or in a independent clause or something comparable to an independent clause, it accompanies an optative or a secondary tense of the indicative.

  • 4. The Particle

    In addition to being a common component in a variety of epistemic constructions, the

    particle can make a statement an epistemic construction by itself:

    (8)

    For I do not suppose those plotting the deaths of their neighbors devise

    and prepare in front of witnesses (Antiph. 1.28)

    (8) is an epistemic construction, but is so solely due to the particle , which alone

    acts as an epistemic marker, and which expresses the epistemic stance of the speaker by

    adding at least some doubt to the evaluation of the likelihood of the state of affairs under

    consideration. In this way, functions in a similar fashion to a SVEC (see below)

    with a verb of thinking or supposing.

    5. Compositionally Complex Epistemic Words

    The fundamental hypothesis of construction grammars is the continuum between

    syntax and lexicon. At the extreme of the lexical side are atomic morphemes. Although

    these can be words, they are often not, and this is particularly true of Greek, a highly

    flectional language. Morphology allows a single word to express more complexity, and

    cannot therefore be considered atomic. Consider the word . From a constructional

    perspective, this word is complex, consisting of an atomic componential (semantic)

    aspect (-) and the morphological aspect which creates componential complexity by

    adding syntactical elements such as number, tense, mood, and voice. In other words,

    can be considered to consist of the atomic component loose whose morphological

  • properties add the components to form the complex construction I loose (actively and

    indicatively) at this time. Additionally, it is also possible for a construction composed of

    several words to be closer to the atomic side of the syntax-lexicon continuum by virtue of

    be representing a single component. For example, although the idiom kick the bucket is

    composed of several words, it is in fact noncompositional, in that it the entire expression

    is mapped onto die.D21

    Most words in ancient Greek exist at the level of complex but boundD22D by virtue

    being morphologically complex. However, some words exist further to the syntactic side

    of the continuum by way of being schematically conceptualized as representing,

    semantically, more than can be predicted by it morphology. Simply put, a particular

    adverb in Greek, despite its morphological expression and grammatical class, may be

    better interpreted as phrasal: So kann auch ein Adverb statt eines kausalen oder finalen

    oder auch eines anderen Nebensatzes stehenFiiF.D23

    Among the many possible other Nebenstze and adverb and other Greek words

    are subordinate clauses which construe epistemic stance. These may be called

    Compositionally Complex Epistemic Words (CCEWs). An excellent example of this

    category is the word . Arguably, this word is not typically even at the level of

    complex but bound as it is morphologically invariable (and therefore, as an

    instantiation of a grammatical class it is atomic and schematic). Pragmatic factors

    determine how this word is construed, and often enough it is used as a simple epistemic

    adverb meaning naturally or reasonably. However, at times this fits very

    well into Khners category above, e.g. in Demosthenes speech Olynthiac (1.10):

    ii Thus, an adverb can also stand in place of a causal or final or also another subordinate clause.

  • (9) ,

    Nevertheless, [his] gratitude will be great- as is to be expected. A simpler adverbial reading here is inadequate. It fails to express the phrasal quality of

    the adverb.

    The question then becomes how these CCEWs are used to convey, modify, alter,

    etc, the speakers epistemic stance. In fact, they are quite similar to the next type of

    epistemic construction considered below in that their primary function is distancing. In

    using a word like , the speaker is offering an epistemic evaluation, but is doing

    so impersonally. In (9), a base space is set up containing the blessings the gods have

    given the Athenians. From this space a possibility space is built in which any Athenian

    can consider these blessings compared to the problems the Athenians are experiencing. A

    resultative space is then constructed in which Demosthenes determines that any Athenian

    will be grateful to the gods despite the current misfortunes. This resultative space

    represents a positive epistemic stance formed from a Complex Epistemic Construction,

    and will therefore be considered in full below. Here, what is important is how the CCEW

    functions in the resultative space. This entire space is built from a possibility

    space. In it, is used to construe Demosthenes epistemic stance on the

    probability that any given Athenian, having weighed the blessings of the gods against the

    current problems, will be grateful to the gods. However, does not directly

    connect this stance to Demosthenes. Even though it, in fact, merely expresses

    Demosthenes evaluation of a likelihood, it is designed to appear that this is not an

    opinion of Demosthenes at all. Demosthenes does not say I expect X, in which it

  • would be clear that Demosthenes alone considers X as likely. Instead, he uses

    as a way of construing the hypothetical situation as likely from any perspective.

    The function of CCEWs is to do just that: construe an epistemic stance, a personal

    evaluation of likelihood, as a general truth.

    6. Simple Epistemic Vebal Constructions (SEVCs)

    The simplest of the simple epistemic constructions in Gree, are phrases or clauses which

    use a first person verb (or participle) of thinking, perceiving, believing, etc. Examples

    found in the corpus include ,,, ,,and.

    In a Simple Epistemic Verbal Construction (SEVC),the place of the speakers statement on the epistemic scale, in the indicative mood at least, is determined solely by the

    semantics of the verb selected. This is hardly surprising, as it is fairly obvious that an

    epistemic stance taken with the statement I believe does not have the force of one taken

    with I know. Consider, for example, the difference between the following:

    (9),

    .

    And I know indeed from earlier reports already it has happened that sometimes

    those murdered, and other times those having murdered, have not been found out.

    (Antiph. 5.67)

    (10)

    .

    For you will not, I suppose, deny what you did in front of all the Athenians.

    (Lys. 13.32)

  • It is true that the particle attached to the first person pronoun, as well as the pronoun

    itself, in (9) add emphasis apart from the verb choice itselfD24D. However, even without

    these the use of in (9) versus the use of in (10) are enough to place the

    two statements at different points on the epistemic scale. The former makes a much

    stronger epistemic stance, and the statement is made as if there is no doubt at all, and can

    be no doubt, that the past events in question are as the speaker asserts. Examining the

    second statement from a pragmatic point of view, it is easy to see why the speaker would

    not wish to commit himself as in (9). On the one hand, he is asserting his belief that his

    opponent will do X. However, as doing X would actually be an honest action on the part

    of his opponent, a stronger epistemic stance is undesirable, as it would be the equivalent

    of a commitment to the honest nature of his opponent.

    Pragmatics is a central factor which often dictates the choice of verb in SEVCs.

    What is most important here is that in these simple constructions it is the verb (or verbal

    variant such as a participle) which makes the construction an epistemic one. As such,

    these constructions are actually somewhat rare. Although included in this section for

    contrastive purposes, the statement (9) above is actually a Complex Epistemic Statement

    due to the use of an emphatic pronoun and particle. It uses other components than the

    verb alone to make the statement an epistemic construction. In the corpus examined, this

    was far more the norm than the exception.

    7. Impersonal Epistemic Constructions

    Impersonal Epistemic Constructions (IECs) function similarly to CCEWs

    described above. These constructions can be subdivided into three different types.

    Type 1: Qualifier (Q) + 3rd Person Copula

  • As in English and many other languages, (e.g. French and German) Greek allows

    impersonal constructions by combining a qualifier (adjective, participle, etc) with a form

    of the third person copula. A few such qualifiers are commonly used in IECs, such as

    , , , etc. For example:

    (11)

    It is not [at all] unclear that [the defence] themselves were avoiding clear

    knowledge of the facts(Antiph. 1.13) In (11), as is common in such constructionsD25D, the copula has been omitted and must be

    understood. The epistemic component of the above construction is the adjective (here

    used adverbially) .The pragmatic function of such a construction is again to

    make the epistemic stance of the speaker appear to be fact rather than opinion.

    Type 2: Distanced Epistemic Impersonal Verbs

    Greek has a number of verbs which are commonly used. In the examined corpus,

    one of the most common was deontic modality (e.g. using ). However, possibility

    that a particular action, situation, etc. could be done/would happen/etc. was also common

    (generally using the impersonal verb ).However, this possibility should not be

    confused with epistemic modality, as it concerns the ability of a particular state of affairs

    to occur, rather than likelihood. In fact, there was not a single instance in the entire

    corpus of this type of construction. This was a curious finding, given the prevalence of

    such constructions in other languages (e.g. It is likely that X is Y).

    Type 3. Personalized Impersonal Epistemic Constructions

  • Despite the above, there were numerous examples in the corpus examined of

    impersonal verbs used in epistemic constructions but that brought the speaker himself

    into the evaluation using the first person pronoun in the dative case (). The most

    common verb used in this construction was :

    (12)

    That I speak the truth has been attested, and it appears quite evident to me [that]

    this is the opposite of what the prosecution alleged.

    Although this epistemic construction is formed impersonally, the use of the first person

    pronoun connects the speaker with the evaluation. The purpose of this construction is not

    to distance the speaker from the evaluation, but is rather a matter of construal and

    perspectivization. By using this epistemic construction, rather than stating something to

    the effect of I believe it is quite evident that. a mental space is created in which the

    focal point of attention is on the situation (in which the prosecution is shown to be

    wrong) rather than the epistemic stance of the speaker. In other words, this type of IEC

    allows the speaker to make an epistemic stance, connect themselves with that stance, and

    yet ensure that another facet of the discourse is the focus of attention.

    8. Complex Epistemic Constructions

    1. Conditions

    Unlike epistemic modality, the topic of conditions in ancient Greek has received a

    great deal of attentionD26D. Additionally, the study of the nature of conditionals themselves

    has been a focus of intense study. Even what constitutes a condition is debatedD27D. Given

    all of the above, attempting to go into Greek conditionals in any detail would either be a

  • waste of time, if nothing new was put forward, or would require a study several times the

    size and complexity of the present one, in order to appropriately address the mass of

    literature already published on conditionals in general and Greek conditionals

    specifically.

    What is important to note, however, is that all conditionals in Greek which may

    be considered epistemic constructions are complex, and use a variety of basic epistemic

    components (e.g. verbal mood, the particle , verbal tense, etc). Additionally, most

    grammars of ancient Greek deal with conditionals as relatively fixed combinations of

    these elements. This is largely appropriate, as there are set constructions which for

    specific conditionals (e.g. a so-called irrealis conditional in the present is constructed

    using + the imperfect indicative in the protasis, and aorist or imperfect + in the

    apodosis). What has received no significant attention is the other components usually

    involved in conditions. In the corpus examined, rarely were epistemic conditional

    constructions formed using only the components described in typical grammars of Greek.

    As far as conditionals are concerned, what will be examined below are how components

    not required by particular conditional constructions are used in certain CECs, as well

    as how simpler epistemic constructions are used in conditionals. Two conditionals, one

    using a typical construction described in any Greek grammar, and the other an atypical

    construction, are examined below with these purposes in mind.

    (13),

    If we all were shown to be clever speakers, I know well that your own

    situation would not be in anyway better. (Dem. Ex. 7.2)

  • This type of conditional is often referred to as future less vivid or something similar.

    The central function of this type of condition is to set up an unlikely hypothetical state of

    affairs, and infer from that possibility spaceD28D. What is important to understand is that the

    less vivid aspect is all contained within the protasis. If that hypothetical state of affairs

    is realized, the use of this construction does not make it less likely, in the speakers mind,

    that the apodosis will be realized. Hence, the apodosis of this conditional construction not

    only combines a SVEC into the entire construction, and adverbial epistemic component

    () is also used to make it clear that, in the unlikely event the protasis is realized, the

    apodosis will surely be as well.

    (14),

    .

    If indeed I have entered court [at some point](followed by a number of

    other hypothetical situations) Let the one wishing rise up now and

    refute me! (Andoc. 1.23)

    In (14) Andocides begins by setting up a possibility space in which several states of

    affairs (all having to do with things which might implicate him) are considered. The first

    -clause sets up this possibility space, but there are no epistemic markers in any of the

    various connected clauses which are used in the construal of Andocides epistemic

    stance. In fact, there are no direct epistemic markers (e.g. a word or particle with a

    particular semantic value used to express his epistemic stance, or a verbal mood/tense

    combination which may do the same) anywhere in the entire condition. Andocides

    epistemic stance is made indirectly by a third person imperative (). By issuing

    a command to his audience to refute him, the implication is that there is no possible

  • refutation, because none of the various states of affairs ever happened. Once again, taking

    pragmatics into consideration is necessary to understand the construal of epistemic

    modality.

    These are only two example of ways in which various standard components of

    Greek epistemic constructions (i.e. SEVCs and verbal moods) can interact with Greek

    conditionals in the construal of epistemic modality. Far more methods were found in the

    corpus. In fact, every single component discusses above was found in conditionals in the

    corpus. Although it is beyond the scope of the present study, a more thorough

    investigation of epistemic markers in the various Greek conditionals is necessary.

    2. Other CECs

    Before going on to make some generalizations about CECs in Greek, and some

    points for further investigation, it is useful to look at examples outside of conditionals.

    After all, epistemic modality in Greek is most frequently expressed in CECs, and this is

    hardly limited to conditionals.

    (15),,

    ,

    .

    It would be fitting, gentlemen, whenever someone willingly brings

    themselves into the dangers [of court], for you to have they exact same

    opinion they of them as they themselves have. (Andoc. 1.3)

    In (3), the hypothetical state of affairs (i.e. the unrealized aspect of the situation under

    consideration), is constructed by the use of the optative + in a potential optative

    construction. What is interesting about the above construction is that, despite the phrasal

  • use of to note the suitability of hypothetical state of affairs constructed, as well

    as the use of the particle to add force to the statement, from an epistemic standpoint

    there is little in the construction in which the speaker expresses his epistemic stance. In

    other words, although this is a Complex Epistemic Construction, the epistemic modality

    aspect is secondary. Pragmatic factors explain this secondary aspect. The potential

    optative is used impersonally (like ) to distance the speaker from the state of

    affairs, not only from an epistemic perspective but also from the truth of the statement

    altogether. The likelihood that the state of affairs will actually occur is only realized as

    possible by the potential optative construction, and nothing else in (15) construes the

    speakers view on how possible or likely that state of affairs is. The purpose for the

    distancing in epistemic stance is secondary. The force of the entire statement is not on the

    likelihood that the state of affairs will be realized, but rather to convince the gentlemen

    of the jury that this state of affairs should be conceptualized by all in a particular way (i.e.

    as fitting or perfectly reasonable). By distancing himself from this conceptualization,

    the speaker makes his opinion appear to be fact. If the speaker had made his epistemic

    more personalized, it would have taken away from the illusion that the statement is not

    opinion at all.

    (16)

    All of those present would have spoken better than but a few of them

    concerning [the poetry] they themselves had made. (Plat. Apol. 22b)

  • Socrates in discussing the failure of the poets to understand their own work, constructs a

    possibility space in which all of those present were also present with him at the time

    when he was addressing the poets. The imperfect tense, combined with the particle , is

    used to construct the speakers epistemic stance: this hypothetical state of affairs will not

    be realized. The potentiality is constructed from the particle , while the speakers

    epistemic stance is construed both by and by the verbal tense both of

    (imperfect) and (pluperfect). In other words, the use of past tense verbs

    places the time of the hypothetical state of affairs in the past. As it is in the past, by

    necessity it either happened or didnt. Because makes the statement one of potential,

    clearly the hypothetical state of affairs did not in fact occur. The past tense makes the

    mental space constructed either hypothetical or not, and if it is hypothetical then it is

    unrealized, and the epistemic stance of the speaker is clear (on the certainty end of the

    epistemic scale that this hypothetical state of affairs will never happen).

    9. General considerations

    From the examination of epistemic constructions in the corpus, a number of

    important general observations were made, as well as several notes of interest where

    further investigation is needed.

    1. As noted above, hypothetical state of affairs constructed from past tense verbs

    almost invariably construed epistemic modality on the certainty end of the

    epistemic scale. Although it is quite possible to speak of past events as possibly

    happening when the speaker is unsure, this rarely happened in the corpus

    examined.

  • 2. Almost all epistemic constructions were complex. That is, quite rarely were

    simple epistemic constructions used to construe epistemic stance. Most epistemic

    constructions were either conditionals or simple epistemic constructions which

    used particles, adverbs, adjectives, and other components to add to the construal

    of epistemic stance.

    3. Particles of emphasis were used everywhere as components in the construal of

    epistemic modality. Additionally, the particles and were of great

    importance in many epistemic constructions. However, particles were present in

    almost all epistemic constructions in the corpus, and of singular difficulty was the

    determination of when these particles were used as epistemic markers, and when

    they were used for other purposes. A focus on particles from a standpoint of

    epistemic modality alone would therefore be uniquely helpful in understanding

    epistemic modality in Greek.

    4. Epistemic constructions in Greek may be broadly divided into impersonal and

    personal categories. Further, the more personalized the epistemic stance was,

    the more it was possible for the speaker to place himself anywhere on the

    epistemic scale. Impersonal epistemic constructions were often used as distancing

    mechanisms.

    5. In general, no singular component or simple epistemic construction stood out as

    the primary method of construal of epistemic modality. However, the importance

    of various components or constructions did stand out when the place on the

    speaker on the epistemic scale is considered. For example, the further from

  • certainty the speaker was on the epistemic scale, the more verbal mood was

    important, and other components played a secondary role and were less prevalent.

    6. Given its prevalence in epistemic constructions, a typology of -constructions

    from an epistemic standpoint would be useful not only in gaining a better

    understanding of the encyclopedic meaning of the particle, but in constructing a

    typology of epistemic constructions in general.

    10. Conclusions

    There is far more to the construal of epistemic modality than is covered above. The

    topic itself is complex, and also forms an open-ended class. The present study was

    concerned only with laying the groundwork towards a typology of epistemic

    constructions. This was accomplished by identifying the components and simple

    epistemic constructions used in the construal of epistemic modality. Additionally, several

    epistemic constructions were analyzed so that points of interest could be identified for

    further study. Furthermore, several Complex Epistemic Constructions were examined,

    and again analyzed to identify points of interest. Finally, some general observations were

    made. From all of the above, it is clear that although a great deal of investigation is

    necessary towards the goal of understanding epistemic modality and creating a typology

    of epistemic constructions in Greek, various regularities in expression appear to make

    this goal possible.

    1 Nyuts (2001), pp. 21-22.

  • 2 The terms construe and construal are used here as they are in research in cognitive

    linguistics: The cover term that has come to be used for different ways of viewing a

    particular situation is construal. (Verhagen, 2007, p. 38). In other words, the construal

    of epistemic modality refers to the ways in which the speaker, expresses, represents,

    captures, etc, her or his particular viewpoint of this modality.

    3 One outcome of research in functionalist linguistics is the importance of the context in

    which speech or language occurs. Pragmatic as used here relates to the observation that,

    in the context of the human behavioral repertoire, language has a specific role to play,

    viz. (primarily) to allow communication with other members of the speciesHence,

    investigating language also unavoidably means accounting for how this system fulfills

    this communicative function (Nyuts, 2001, p. 22)

    4 The term space here, e.g base space, hypothetical space, etc, is borrowed from

    Fauconnier (1985; 2007), who describes mental spaces as a basic and common aspect

    of human language.. The concept is used in a number of different approaches to language

    in cognitive linguistics. It refers to very partial assemblies constructed as we think and

    talk for purposes of local understanding and action (Fauconnier, 2007, 351). In other

    words, during the course of discourse, speakers construct local spaces where important

    elements of the conversation are located and may be expanded upon. It would be helpful

    to condiser and example: Suppose that we are engaged in a conversation about Romeo

    and Juliet and the following statement is made:

    (1) Maybe Romeo is in love with Juliet.

    The English sentence brings in a frame from our prestructured background cultural

    knowledge, X IN LOVE WITH Y, with two roles highlighted (the lover x and the loved

  • one y)The word maybe is a space builder; it sets up a Possibility space relative to the

    discourse Base space at that point. The Base space contains elements a and b associated

    with the names Romeo and Juliet (Fauconnier, 2007, 355). In the construal of

    epistemic modality in Greek, a possibility space is invariably constructed out of the base

    space, and the epistemic stance of the speaker concerns the likelihood of the realization

    of the state of affairs in that possibility space. The term state of affairs is borrowed from

    Functional Grammar and is an all-encompassing term covering the entity to which the

    whole of the predicate with its arguments refers, irrespective of whether this entity is an

    event, an action, a situation, etc (Wakker, 1994, p. 7n14).

    5 See note 4 above.

    6 Krkkinen (2003) p. 32.

    7 The term constructions here refers to constructions as they are conceived of in various

    construction grammars, which posit that there is a uniform representation of all

    grammatical knowledge in the speakers mind in the form of generalized construction

    everything from words to the most general syntactic and semantic rules can be

    represented as constructions (Croft, 2007, p. 471). The most important aspect of

    construction grammars is the idea that syntax and lexicon form a continuum, rather than

    being two separate components (Goldberg, 1995, p. 7, Langacker, 2008, p. 161).

    Additionally, constructions are organized in a taxonomic network (Croft, p. 476-477),

    and vary from very fixed to highly variable and schematic (ibid, pp. 470-471). All of

    speech is formed from combining various constructions (Langacker, 2008, chaps. 1 and

    6).

  • 8 All of the texts were taken from the Perseus Project of Tufts University

    (http://www.perseus.tufts.edu/hopper/collection?collection=Perseus:collection:Greco-

    Roman). These included the speeches of Antiphon, Andocides, Demosthenes, Lysias, and

    the Apology of Plato.

    9 The Greek grammars consulted in the present study include Smyth (1956), Humbert

    (1960), Schwyzer & Debrunner (1966), Goodwin (1889), and Khner & Gerth (1904).

    10 See, e.g. Dancygier & Sweester (2005, sect. 2.4) and Dancygier (2004, chap. 2).

    11 On the usage of particles in general, as well as the emphatic usage of these particles,

    see Denniston (1950).

    12 See Smyth, sect. 2896.

    13 Sect 1762.

    14 p. 64.

    15 Ibid.

    16 p. 27.

    17 Langacker, pp. 37-38.

    18 As opposed to a dictionary view (see Langacker, pp. 38-39). An encyclopedic view of

    lexical semantics, lexical meaning resides in a particular way of accessing an open

    ended body of knowledge pertaining to a cerain type of entity (Langacker, p. 39).

    19 In other words, rather than simply describe a force has, it is possible to describe

    its meanings as if it were any other lexical item. This is true of all particles, and would be

    a superior method of describing them in Greek grammars.

    20 Croft, pp. 476-77.

    21 Croft, pp. 467; Croft and Cruse (2004) p. 253.

  • 22 The levels of the syntax-lexicon continuum may be found in Croft and Cruse, p. 255:

    23 Khner & Gerth, p. 115.

    24 Goodwin pp. 115-116.

    25 Schwyzer & Debrunner p. 623, Smyth sect. 944.

    26 Apart from Greek grammars, see, e.g., Wakker, Seiler (1997), and Greenberg (1986).

    27 Wierzbicka (1997) pp. 15-18.

    28 Goodwin, pp. 168-69.