8
Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud Malavika Nair Received: 6 November 2013 / Accepted: 10 April 2014 Ó Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014 Abstract This paper traces the recent debate over the legitimacy of maturity mismatching and fractional reserve banking. It shows that there is common ground between Bagus and Howden (Journal of Business Ethics, 90(3):399–406, 2009, 106:295–300, 2012) on the one hand and Evans (Journal of Business Ethics, 2013) on the other regarding contractual arrangements that lead to fractional reserve banking, while both agree that fractional reserve banking that arises out of a bailment or storage contract constitutes fraud. Block and Barnett (Journal of Business Ethics, 88(4):711–716, 2009, 100:229–238, 2011) stress the illegitimacy of fractional reserve banking for creating more money substitutes than there is actual money. While it is true that fractional reserve banks are capable of cre- ating money, this activity still cannot be regarded as fraudulent using a common law definition of fraud for it can only take place with requisite client collaboration that makes it impossible to identify a victim. Keywords Fractional reserve banking Á Fraud Á Client collaboration Introduction The recent debate about whether maturity mismatching and fractional reserve banking are fraudulent has brought up several interesting issues relevant to the monetary system (Barnett and Block 2009, 2011, henceforth BB), (Bagus and Howden 2009, 2012 henceforth BH), Evans (2013) and Cachanosky (2011). BB and BH are in agreement over whether fractional reserve banking is fraudulent but dis- agree as to the question of whether maturity mismatching is fraudulent or not. Both agree that fractional reserve bank- ing is fraudulent under any scenario, however BB argue that maturity mismatching also ought to be regarded as fraud because it is a more general case of fractional reserve banking. On the other hand, BH argue that maturity mis- matching is not fraudulent because it arises out of loans and hence is fundamentally different from fractional reserve banking that arises out of deposits. Cachanosky (2011) and Evans (2013) critique both BB and BH by arguing that neither fractional reserve banking nor maturity mismatching are fraudulent while also pointing out practical ways in which businesses can overcome diffi- culties in both. This paper takes its cue from Block and Davidson (2011) that ‘‘the moral argument must always come first’’ and focuses only on the question of ethics. In the first section of the paper, it is argued that the views of Evans (2013) and BH regarding fractional reserve banking are not mutually exclusive. On the other hand, there is one limiting case where fractional reserve banking would indeed be fraudulent, the case of a bailment or storage contract. However, BH’s description of an ‘‘aleatory contract’’ (2009, 2012, 2013) that is permissible in a free market is the same ‘‘callable loan’’ or demandable debt contract defended by Evans (2013) and others (White 2003). Hence, the first sec- tion shows that there is more agreement in this debate than meets the eye. Both sides (BH on the one hand and Evans on the other) agree that under certain contractual arrangements, fractional reserve banking is permissible. Hence the point of contention is no longer one about ethics, rather one of whether fractional reserve banking would survive and flourish in a free society. The next section of the paper turns to the issue of maturity mismatching. BB argue that maturity mismatching is but a M. Nair (&) Troy University, Troy, AL, USA e-mail: [email protected] 123 J Bus Ethics DOI 10.1007/s10551-014-2176-x

Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

Malavika Nair

Received: 6 November 2013 / Accepted: 10 April 2014

� Springer Science+Business Media Dordrecht 2014

Abstract This paper traces the recent debate over the

legitimacy of maturity mismatching and fractional reserve

banking. It shows that there is common ground between

Bagus and Howden (Journal of Business Ethics,

90(3):399–406, 2009, 106:295–300, 2012) on the one hand

and Evans (Journal of Business Ethics, 2013) on the other

regarding contractual arrangements that lead to fractional

reserve banking, while both agree that fractional reserve

banking that arises out of a bailment or storage contract

constitutes fraud. Block and Barnett (Journal of Business

Ethics, 88(4):711–716, 2009, 100:229–238, 2011) stress

the illegitimacy of fractional reserve banking for creating

more money substitutes than there is actual money. While

it is true that fractional reserve banks are capable of cre-

ating money, this activity still cannot be regarded as

fraudulent using a common law definition of fraud for it

can only take place with requisite client collaboration that

makes it impossible to identify a victim.

Keywords Fractional reserve banking � Fraud � Client

collaboration

Introduction

The recent debate about whether maturity mismatching and

fractional reserve banking are fraudulent has brought up

several interesting issues relevant to the monetary system

(Barnett and Block 2009, 2011, henceforth BB), (Bagus

and Howden 2009, 2012 henceforth BH), Evans (2013) and

Cachanosky (2011). BB and BH are in agreement over

whether fractional reserve banking is fraudulent but dis-

agree as to the question of whether maturity mismatching is

fraudulent or not. Both agree that fractional reserve bank-

ing is fraudulent under any scenario, however BB argue

that maturity mismatching also ought to be regarded as

fraud because it is a more general case of fractional reserve

banking. On the other hand, BH argue that maturity mis-

matching is not fraudulent because it arises out of loans and

hence is fundamentally different from fractional reserve

banking that arises out of deposits.

Cachanosky (2011) and Evans (2013) critique both BB

and BH by arguing that neither fractional reserve banking

nor maturity mismatching are fraudulent while also pointing

out practical ways in which businesses can overcome diffi-

culties in both. This paper takes its cue from Block and

Davidson (2011) that ‘‘the moral argument must always

come first’’ and focuses only on the question of ethics. In the

first section of the paper, it is argued that the views of Evans

(2013) and BH regarding fractional reserve banking are not

mutually exclusive. On the other hand, there is one limiting

case where fractional reserve banking would indeed be

fraudulent, the case of a bailment or storage contract.

However, BH’s description of an ‘‘aleatory contract’’ (2009,

2012, 2013) that is permissible in a free market is the same

‘‘callable loan’’ or demandable debt contract defended by

Evans (2013) and others (White 2003). Hence, the first sec-

tion shows that there is more agreement in this debate than

meets the eye. Both sides (BH on the one hand and Evans on

the other) agree that under certain contractual arrangements,

fractional reserve banking is permissible. Hence the point of

contention is no longer one about ethics, rather one of

whether fractional reserve banking would survive and

flourish in a free society.

The next section of the paper turns to the issue of maturity

mismatching. BB argue that maturity mismatching is but a

M. Nair (&)

Troy University, Troy, AL, USA

e-mail: [email protected]

123

J Bus Ethics

DOI 10.1007/s10551-014-2176-x

Page 2: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

more general case of fractional reserve banking and hence

must be regarded as illegitimate for it involves the over-issue

of more property titles than there is actual property. First, it is

problematic to theorize that more property titles, than there is

property, are being issued because maturity mismatching

arises out of loan contracts. Property titles or warehouse

receipts would be issued only in the case of bailments or

storage contracts, debt claims or bonds would be issued in the

case of loans.

On the other hand, it is true that maturity mismatching

can be seen as a more general case of legitimate fractional

reserve banking that arises out of redeemable demand

deposits. Hence fractional reserve banks can indeed ‘‘create

money’’ or put into circulation more banknotes or money

substitutes than there is actual money. However, this

practice cannot be categorized as fraud using a common

law definition, which requires an intention to misrepresent

(scienter) as well as a clear victim and aggressor. This is

because in a free market, no bank can force customers to

use its money substitutes as money and the extent of money

creation by fractional reserve banks directly depends on

how much its clients use substitutes in place of money.

Hence, it is impossible to identify a victim (as long as

clients are aware the bank lends their money) due to the

inbuilt problem of requisite client collaboration (both

depositors and borrowers) that is required for fractional

reserve banking to exist in the first place.

The remainder of the section then tries to provide a

theoretical answer as to why fractional reserve banking

may come to play a legitimate non-trivial role in a free

society using Mises’ (1953) typology of money. This is

because money substitutes or redeemable claims to money

are technologically capable of performing all the functions

of money itself. This is unlike any consumption good

where a claim to the good can never satisfy the demand for

the good itself. The final section then concludes.

All Demand Deposits are Not Storage Contracts

BH claim that while loan maturity mismatching is not

problematic, fractional reserve banking is indeed fraudu-

lent. As pointed out by Evans (2013), this distinction relies

heavily on the meaning of the terms ‘‘deposit’’ and ‘‘loan’’.

A deposit is defined as a contract where ‘‘the depositors

deposit goods with the depositary because they wish for the

depositary to safe-guard the goods, while retaining at all

time the availability of their use’’, while a ‘‘loan’’ involves

‘‘the borrower relinquishing the availability of the car,

olive oil, or money for a specified time period.’’ (Bagus and

Howden 2009, p. 400, Emphasis mine) Hence, fractional

reserve banking that involves the loaning out of money

placed in a redeemable checking account violates the initial

terms of the contract (safe-keeping and availability). On

the other hand, the fungibility of money makes possible

borrowing short-term loans and lending them for longer

periods. Since a loan contract does not promise the con-

stant availability of money, but only that the money be

repaid when the loan is due, such maturity transformation

is not illegitimate, argue BH.

As alluded to in Evans (2013), BH’s strongest case

arises if the deposit was one of only pure safe-keeping or a

storage contract.1 It is only this limiting case that would

require a 100 % reserve. This coincides with BH’s

description of a ‘‘deposit’’ as shown above. Fractional

reserve banking that arises out of lending money placed

with the banker for the explicit purpose of safe-keeping and

nothing else (a storage contract) amounts to fraud. There

seems to be implicit agreement on this point. However, the

implicit agreement does not end there. As shown below,

the type of fractional reserve banking contract defended by

Evans and others of the Free Banking School has the same

essential features of the ‘‘aleatory contract’’ so named by

BH to be permissible in a free society. Hence, both sides of

this debate actually agree that under certain contractual

arrangements, fractional reserve banking is not fraudulent.

The disagreement is thus no longer one of ethics, rather one

of whether fractional reserve banking would flourish in a

free society.

To be clear, it is only when the original intention was

one of safe-keeping in the form of a storage contract, that

there is a necessity for the banker to hold 100 % reserves.

This amounts to saying that the bank or warehouse keeper

must not appropriate the funds for personal use, he must

safe-guard them. For this, the depositor must pay a fee to

the banker. However, if it is not a pure safe-keeping con-

tract, and if the banker promised availability but never to

keep the depositor’s money in a safe deposit box, then all

he must do is return the money whenever it is asked for.

This may come from a reserve fund at first, if that runs out

in a contingency; the banker must supply the money by

liquidating assets or borrowing. In the latter case, the

waiting time may increase to a few hours or days, bankers

may include such a stipulation in the original contract via

an option clause. Demand deposits that pay interest would

be an example of such a contract. For how could a bank

pay interest on a redeemable deposit if it were not lending

it out?2

For it is perfectly possible to have contracts that provide

redeemable or checkable deposits (available at all times)

1 Evans (forthcoming) writes ‘‘Obviously, it would be considered

either fraud or outright theft for the warehouse to use or lend out your

property to another person without your permission.’’2 Selgin (2012a) provides such an example about Goldsmith banks in

seventeenth century England.

M. Nair

123

Page 3: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

that do not involve any safe-keeping, rather the bank

openly discloses the fact that the money will be lent out

further or invested. Evans (2013) calls this type of contract

a ‘‘callable loan’’. Fractional reserve banking that results

from these types of contracts does not involve any fraud-

ulent activity. In other words, it is the violation of the safe-

keeping or storage function alone that can lead to fraudu-

lent fractional reserve banking. On the other hand, deposits

that promise redeemability of money while openly lending

it out further do not involve a violation of any contract or

fraud. Evans (2013) describes this type of redeemable

deposit contract as ‘‘a loan may be callable, and be repaid

upon the lender’s demand.’’ For a more substantial expla-

nation from the point of view of the Free Banking School,

White (2003, p 427) writes of legitimate fractional reserve

banking contracts: ‘‘As the term to maturity goes to zero,

such a contract becomes a demandable debt that gives the

customer the legal right to reclaim (and transfer, if it is a

checking account) any part of the deposited sum on any

date, but that also allows the bank to continue using the

sum until the date the depositor actually reclaims it…The

customer who holds a banknote or a demand deposit has a

debt claim payable on demand.’’

Evidence that BH actually agree that this type of con-

tract is not fraudulent comes from their description of what

they name an ‘‘aleatory contract’’ (Bagus and Howden

2009, 2012, 2013). They write that ‘‘we classify a frac-

tional reserve demand deposit contract showing that it may

be considered, at best, an aleatory contract—0 a contract

contingent on an uncertain event. Such a contract contra-

dicts the reason individuals deposit money—the mitigation

of uncertainty’’ (Bagus and Howden 2013, p. 627). While

BH are skeptical about why someone might patronize a

bank that offers them such a contract, this question is not

relevant to whether an ‘‘aleatory contract’’ is fraudulent.

They further describe this contract as:

Both parties are aware of the fact that the bank uses the

money for its own purposes. The ‘‘depositor’’ would

not have the availability of the money but the right to

ask for the money and the bank would try its best to give

it to the ‘‘depositor’’ (citation suppressed). The

‘‘depositors’’ motivation for entering the contract

would not be to maintain full availability of the money,

but rather to invest it. Hence, the purposes of the two

parties to the aleatory contract are compatible and

possible to carry out. It then becomes a question of

probabilistic forecasting if the bank will have the

money and be willing to return the money when the

‘‘depositor’’ asks for it. Many members of the Rothbard

School (Huerta de Soto; Hulsmann) have acknowl-

edged the possibility of aleatory contracts.

They go on to state ‘‘Hulsmann (2003) does not use the

term ‘‘aleatory contract’’ but calls the contract an IOU with

a redemption promise. Hulsmann (2003) sees these types of

redeemable debt contracts as not fraudulent and legally

permissible in a free society. He too, however, remains

skeptical about the extent to how much these types of

contracts would exist in a free society. He describes these

contracts as ‘‘It can so happen that a person who

‘‘deposits’’ a sum of money with his banker really means

to buy an IOU plus redemption promise. Indeed, it is not

difficult to see that a free market might exist in IOUs plus

redemption promise (IOUs ?RP). Although these IOUs

yield lower returns than other investments, they are more

liquid; and although they are not always as liquid as money

titles, they are costless or even promise some return.’’

(2003, p. 402).

The evidence presented above allows us to acknowledge

that there is some agreement as to whether certain con-

tractual arrangements that allow for fractional reserve

banking are legitimate or not. Both sides of the debate

acknowledge that a certain type of deposit that allows for

redemption and pays interest is legitimate. While different

sides of the debate may have different names for the same

contract, the agreement over whether they are legitimate

remains. The relevant point of contention then becomes

whether these contracts would survive and proliferate in a

free society. For example, insurance contracts too are

widely accepted to be ‘‘aleatory’’ in nature, and insurance

companies play an important and prominent role in society

(with or without government support). Could not it be that

fractional reserve banking, even if we were to accept the

‘‘aleatory’’ label, could have a prominent role to play in a

free society? While BH and Hulsmann (2003) argue that it

would not and Evans (2013), White (2003), and other

members of the Free Banking School argue that it would,

this is no longer a question of ethics. It is rather a question

of practice and institution-specific analysis.

Client Collaboration and the Question of Fraud

The paper now turns to an analysis of BB’s arguments.

BB’s argument for fraudulent fractional reserve banking

differs from BH’s argument. BH stress legal arguments for

fraudulent fractional reserve banking that they see as

applying only to demand deposits, not time deposits. Hence

BH see fractional reserve banking as fraudulent but not

maturity mismatching. BB stress the over issuance of titles

or claims, unbacked by actual money to be the main cause

of fraud. They see the ‘‘over determination of property

titles’’ (Barnett and Block 2009, p. 713) as representing an

inherent conflict of rights. BB argue that this applies in the

Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration and Fraud

123

Page 4: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

case of both fractional reserve banking and borrowing short

and lending long and hence see both these practices as

fraudulent, contra BH.

Barnett and Block (2009) argument goes as follows. If

a bank borrows money from A for 1 year and lends

money to B for 2 years, it is committing fraud for cre-

ating credit or more claims to money than money exists.

For on the day that A’s loan comes due, there are two

people with an equally valid claim to only one amount of

money. First off, this argument is problematic on its own

terms. If the bank has promised to pay back A when his

payment comes due, then this logically and necessarily

requires the bank to borrow before the payment is due in

order to honor its contract. This is not an ‘‘extra-con-

tractual’’ maneuver as (Barnett and Block 2011, p. 236)

term it, it is very much a contractual requirement on the

part of the bank. There is no conflict of rights, neither are

there more claims to money than there is money. The

bank must borrow money from let us say C and hence

increase its liabilities by a corresponding amount to pay

back A, while at the same time removing from circulation

the amount of money he owes A. When B’s loan comes

due, the bank uses it to pay off C and makes money off

the interest differential. If the bank fails to borrow in the

short term, then debt holder A has a preferential claim to

the bank’s assets. Even now, there is no case of more

claims than money, as long as the bank is able to increase

liabilities by borrowing or liquidate assets; every liability

is ‘‘backed up’’ by money. In the extreme event that the

bank fails to do so, it must declare bankruptcy, which is

not the same thing as fraud.

Further, using the distinction laid out above between

pure safe-keeping deposits and demandable debt, it is

possible to distinguish two distinct types of claims that

come into existence. When a depositor puts money into a

safety deposit box, he receives a ‘‘warehouse receipt’’ that

may be redeemed at any time. That receipt represents a

property title. The depositor owns the bailment and may

transfer ownership of his property by transferring the title.

If a depositor puts his money into a demandable deposit

that pays interest (demandable debt), then he receives a

redeemable debt claim.3 This claim represents a debt that

the bank owes the depositor and that may be redeemed at

any time (unspecified maturity). In this sense, it resembles

a bond.

As an illustration of how a debt claim or IOU is distinct

from a property title or warehouse receipt, consider the

following example. Because the two are conceptually dis-

tinct, it is perfectly possible to have a property title and a

debt claim or bond on one asset at the same time. If Mr.

Jones buys a house, then he receives and holds the property

title to that house, and it represents his ownership of the

house. Now Mr. Jones can lend or rent out the house to Mr.

Smith for one year. Mr. Smith signs a rental contract saying

that he must return the house to Mr. Jones at the end of one

year. That rental contract is a debt claim or IOU that Mr.

Jones holds onto. At the end of one year, Mr. Smith owes

Mr. Jones the exact same house. If it were true that there is

no difference between property titles and debt claims, BB

would have to claim that all rental contracts are fraudulent

as well for there has been an ‘‘over determination of

property titles’’ (Barnett and Block 2009, p173). This

would be an absurd conclusion. Just the same way, in the

case of a monetary loan or a redeemable deposit contract,

debt claims or IOUs are issued, not property titles. The

fungibility of money is only an added feature that allows

for the banker to return an equivalent amount of money as

well as lets him engage in borrowing short and lending

long. It would indeed be fraudulent to borrow a house for

1 year and lend it for two, but not because of the over

determination of property titles (for property titles are not

involved in rental contracts), rather because houses are not

fungible.

Applying this analysis to BB’s description of what

causes fraud in the case of borrowing short and lending

long reveals the same problem. For borrowing short and

lending long and legitimate fractional reserve banking of

the type described above is always a debt transaction.

Money substitutes that are issued as a result of a debt

transaction are not property titles. Property title or ware-

house receipts would only be issued if the initial deposit

was a safe-keeping or storage contract. In every other case,

the bank note or checking account represents a debt claim.

Hence money creation by banks in this sense does not

amount to more titles to property than there is property in

the same way if there were more titles to houses than actual

houses. What does exist however is more debt claims than

there is money to redeem all of them simultaneously.

Mises (1953) himself never uses the term ‘‘property

title’’, rather he uses the more general ‘‘claim’’ when

writing about money substitutes, a term that could

encompass both a debt claim and a property title. The

practice of using ‘‘property title’’ only starts with Rothbard

(1993), however this is understandable given the fact that

he only envisions warehouse deposits and warehouse

receipts when talking about demand deposits. The concept

of ‘‘over-issue of property titles’’ does not exist in the case

of fractional reserve banking that arises from redeemable

debt.

Now, I turn to an analysis of what can be seen as the

strongest case for the fraudulent fractional reserve banking

being made by BB. BB are right in pointing out the affinity

between fractional reserve banking and maturity

3 Selgin (2012b) uses historical samples to show the differences

between warehouse receipts and bank notes (debt claims).

M. Nair

123

Page 5: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

mismatching. As BB (2011, p. 236) point out: ‘‘FRB, in

addition to being a special, limiting, case of BSLL, is

unique in another way. BSLL always, i.e., whether or not

of the FRB type, involves an increase in credit. But only

FRB also and always involves an increase in money,

something that BSLL of the non-FRB type never does.’’

Fractional reserve banking can indeed be seen as a special

case of borrowing short and lending long; however, there is

one crucial difference. Credit is not being created; it is

merely being allocated in the case of borrowing short and

lending long. However, it is possible that money be created

in fractional reserve banking by the creation of more

money substitutes in circulation than there is money.

The analysis in the earlier part of the paper argued that

fractional reserve banking cannot be regarded as fraudulent

on account of the underlying contract for it is possible to

construct contracts that allow for it legitimately. If there is

full disclosure between the bank and the depositors that the

bank will lend the money while depositors have use of the

money through money substitutes, then the bank cannot be

charged with fraud. Only if the bank misappropriates funds

placed with it for safe-keeping or storage will fraud have

taken place. However, can we deem the practice of frac-

tional reserve banking fraudulent solely on account of this

money creation?

Before answering that question, a brief detour to set up a

clear understanding of what is meant by fraud at least under

current law is helpful. Using a common law definition of

fraud as understood in the American law system, fraud is

defined to be ‘‘a knowing misrepresentation of the truth or

concealment of a material fact to induce another to act to

his or her detriment’’ (Garner 2001). It is ‘‘defined to

include intentional wrongdoing and usually also includes

scienter, an intention to deceive and induce reliance by the

other party’’ (Rohwer and Skrocki 2006, p 290). Another

legal source defines fraud as consisting of five elements:

‘‘(1) a material misrepresentation; (2) the defendant acted

with the requisite scienter: she knew the statement was

false or made it with reckless disregard as to its truth or

falsity; (3) the defendant intended to induce reliance; (4)

the misrepresentation caused plaintiff’s justifiable reliance;

(5) pecuniary damages resulted to the plaintiff.’’ (Diamond

et al. 2010, p. 332).

Using the above definitions of fraud as a guide, we must

conclude that it is not possible to classify fractional reserve

banking as fraud on account of money creation for two

reasons. The first reason is that one cannot blame the bank

for deception if it discloses all the facts to its clients at the

outset, and they still choose to engage in placing their

money with the bank. The second more important reason is

that there is no clear victim. One cannot tell who is

defrauding whom for voluntary actions of the bank’s cli-

ents (depositors and borrowers) are required for the bank to

engage in fractional reserve banking in the first place. The

extent to which a bank can engage in fractional reserve

banking is also determined by its clients’ collaboration.4

The following two examples help to illustrate this point of

how the clients’ actions directly determine the extent to

which a bank can engage in fractional reserve banking. The

first example illustrates the simple case where a bank

engages in fractional reserve banking by lending out

money proper (not money substitutes). The second exam-

ple then moves to the more complex yet realistic case,

where like today, banks engage in fractional reserve

banking by issuing money substitutes, not lending money

proper. While the extent of money creation can be much

greater in the second case, the limits faced by the bank are

the same.

Consider the following simple example of fractional

reserve banking. Depositor A deposits $1000 cash in

checkable deposit account at Bank B. Bank B issues a

checking deposit with a balance of $1,000 and gives A a

check book, debit card, and ATM card. A is free to with-

draw cash at any time; he may write checks or even pay for

goods using his debit card. In this scenario, the checking

deposit with a book balance (equivalent to contemporary

online balances) is the money substitute. The actual cash or

money is with the bank. Now the bank has disclosed the

fact that it will lend the money out further. So far, there is

$1,000 worth of claims or money substitutes that A can

redeem for actual cash at any time, and there is $1,000 of

actual cash in this system. Let us say that over a few weeks

Bank B learns of A’s spending and redemption habits.

Every week A only withdraws $50 in cash while making

payments worth $100 using her debit card. Bank B makes

the call that if it were to keep and maintain $100 in reserves

and lend out the rest, it will be able to satisfy redemption

demand as well as meet contingency redemption for A with

ease. So it proceeds to lend out $900 in cash (for simplicity

sake let us assume it lends out the actual cash rather than

4 It is important to point out how this differs from fraud in a Ponzi

scheme. For one could argue that voluntary client collaboration is

required even in that case. Bernard Madoff could not have done what

he did without clients voluntarily giving him money. The Ponzi

scheme case is different for two reasons. It is regarded as fraud

because of misrepresentation of the facts, clients are made to believe

that they can earn unusually high returns from a real investment

opportunity accessible to the manager, while in reality their returns

are coming from new entrants’ contributions into the scheme, and

there is no actual investment opportunity. The second reason is that it

is very easy to identify a victim; those people who unknowingly

invested money into the scheme and stood to lose from it. Neither of

these is the case with fractional reserve banking that arises from

legitimate contracts. On the other hand, similar schemes where clients

are fully aware of the business model and there is a legitimate product

or investment involved are considered legal and thrive, for example:

multi-level marketing schemes.

Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration and Fraud

123

Page 6: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

by issuing more money substitutes). So far, the Bank B’s

balance sheet is illustrated by Fig. 1.

At this point, BB would claim that the Bank has com-

mitted fraud, for the bank has managed to nearly double the

money supply in this economy. So while the borrowers

have a valid claim to the use of the $900 loan they have just

got from Bank B, so does Depositor A have a valid claim to

the entire $1,000 at the same time, only one tenth of which

lies in the bank’s vault. Hence, there has been an over-issue

of claims, and fraud has been committed.

However, let us closely examine what allows this bank

to ‘‘create money’’ in the first place. If Depositor A with-

drew the whole $1,000 cash out of her account over the

course of every week, while re-depositing every Monday,

then Bank B would be unable to lend out anything for it

would not have any cash in its possession. On the other end

of the spectrum, if A only withdrew $5 worth of cash and

was content to make use of her account the rest of the time

by simply drawing down the book balance by using her

debit card or check book, then Bank B would now be in a

position to loan out the cash. Of course, another crucial

step here is whether or not others in the economy to whom

A makes payments demand cash redemption from Bank B

or whether they too are happy with an increase in their

checking account book balance.

Let us assume A buys a television worth $800 from

Store C and pays with a check. Store C does not have a

bank account, so he goes to Bank B and cashes out the

check for a whole $800. Again Bank B is legally bound to

make the cash payment on demand. It is now however

unable to loan out the initial deposit of A since it is once

again cash poor. On the other hand, if Store C was a client

of Bank B and was content holding a higher checking

account balance rather than the actual cash, all Bank B

would have to do is draw down A’s balance in favor of C’s.

No cash would change hands at all and Bank B would once

again be in a position to loan it out.

It appears that Bank B has a strict limitation in its ability

to ‘‘create money’’ by loaning out the money in checking

accounts. It is entirely dependent on its clients and others in

the economy making use of the money substitutes instead

of the money proper. For if its clients and non-clients ask

for cash redemption constantly, as made clear in the

example above, the bank is unable to make loans and hence

‘‘create money’’. The key, it appears then, is that the bank’s

money substitutes must first circulate as though they were

money. Now, it is important to stress that a bank in a free

market and in the absence of a central bank or legal tender

laws, cannot force its clients to use money substitutes. It is

entirely up to the people in the economy whether or not

they hold a particular bank’s money substitutes as though

they were money or whether they ask for redemption for

real money.

This brings us back to the question of fraud as described

by BB. If the clients of the bank choose to use money

substitutes rather than money, then the bank is able to

‘‘create money’’ and not if they do not. Who is defrauding

whom here? Can we accuse the bank of defrauding the

clients? If we do, then we would have to accept that the

clients are also equally culpable in this act. For their own

free actions are crucial for the bank to engage in fractional

reserve banking in the first place. If they freely choose to

make use of money substitutes and not ask for frequent

redemption, are they defrauding themselves? The questions

itself is absurd. As long as the bank discloses the fact that it

will lend out money deposited in checking accounts and

promises to pay back depositors whenever they ask for

redemption (it may have to liquidate assets if its reserves

run out as described previously), no fraud has been

committed.

What if the bank understands this process and engages

in coaxing its customers to use money substitutes by

making it easier and more convenient to do so than car-

rying cash? The bank may invest in many ATM machines

or tie up with other banks so that they mutually accept each

other’s money substitutes. Such efforts would indeed make

it easier to use money substitutes for clients could be

assured of being able to purchase goods at more places

without having to carry cash. Does this activity on the

bank’s part imply fraud? Again, in a free market for

money, there would be no compulsion for any client to use

money substitutes instead of money. Furthermore, every

bank has to honor its contract to redeem substitutes for

money at any time. How much ever the bank tries to cajole

its clients, the ultimate choice and responsibility for

understanding this process lies with the client. You can

take a horse to water, but you cannot make it drink. Again,

no fraud is being committed.

Now, let us turn to another case of fractional reserve

banking, one where the bank does not loan out cash, rather

it makes loans by issuing money substitutes or by opening

a checking account for the borrower. Let us keep the ori-

ginal scenario where Depositor A deposits $1,000 in Bank

B. This time Bank B keeps $1,000 as cash reserves and

makes loans worth an additional $1,000 to Borrower C, this

time by creating a checking deposit for that amount and

thereby increasing its liabilities along with its assets.

Assets Liabilities

Cash Reserves: $100 Checking Deposits: $1000Loans in cash: $900

Fig. 1 Bank B’s balance sheet

M. Nair

123

Page 7: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

Hence, the bank has made loans this time by issuing more

money substitutes. Now the Bank’s balance sheet is illus-

trated by Fig. 2.

Again, it is clear to see that the bank has effectively

‘‘created money’’, since now there is $2,000 worth of

checking deposits backed by only $1,000 cash. However,

the same caveat as before applies. If A constantly redeems

cash or others in the economy do not value Bank B’s

money substitutes highly, then this practice would be

impossible. The extent of money creation again is com-

pletely contingent on clients’ actions, even more so than in

the previous case. Again, it is impossible to identify a

victim. It is also important to note that C’s relationship to

the bank is very different from A’s relationship. C is the

bank’s debtor; it owes the bank money and not the other

way around. The bank only promises to redeem cash to C if

he may want it to make payments. C is the one who owes

the bank money when the loan comes due. When C pays

back his loan, the bank reduces its liabilities and assets for

$1,000 simultaneously, and the money creation is reversed.

On the other hand, the bank is A’s debtor, it owes A

money. Only if others value the bank’s money substitutes

highly enough that neither C nor the people C pays with the

loan money regularly redeem for cash, can the bank engage

in this type of fractional reserve banking.

An often overlooked feature of Mises’ (1953) monetary

thought helps provide us with an understanding as to why

such a practice may well lead a prominent role in a free

society. Mises (1953) is to be attributed for creating and

elaborating upon the distinction between money proper on

the one hand and money substitutes as valid redeemable

claims to money on the other.5 Mises writes about the

ability of money substitutes to replace money proper in

people’s cash balances: ‘‘A claim to money may be

transferred over and over again in an indefinite number of

indirect exchanges without the person by whom it is pay-

able ever being called upon to settle it. This is obviously

not true as far as other economic goods are concerned, for

these are always destined for ultimate consumption’’ (1953,

p. 50).

This is because money is a medium of exchange, it is

held or demanded only to be given away in exchange

again. Hence, a perfectly secure claim to money (like a

checkable deposit balance or a bank note) is technically

capable of performing this function just as well. This is

not the case with consumption goods or capital goods. A

claim (whether a property title or an IOU) to a car, house

or carton of apples can never perform the function of the

underlying good for the underlying goods only provide

utility in consumption. This means that consuming or

using a title to a house as though it could render the

services of a house itself would necessarily prove to be

fruitless. On the other hand, money provides utility pri-

marily as a medium of exchange, which is when it can be

used to exchange and acquire those goods that people do

wish to actually consume. Hence in a technological sense,

a liquid redeemable claim to money can take the place of

actual money while performing all the functions of

money. Mises stressed that this feature is distinct from the

fungibility of money.6

Of course, it is an empirical question as to the extent that

such claims may circulate in place of money proper.

However, it provides an answer to the question of how

fractional reserve banking may exist and even proliferate in

an ethical way. If people or banks’ clients find it more

convenient to use and hold bank notes or checking balances

instead of the actual money, then banks will be able to

engage in fractional reserve banking and hence ‘‘create’’

more money. If clients choose to redeem money often, then

that will place a natural limit on the extent of money cre-

ation. BB might argue that no person would knowingly

Assets Liabilities

Cash Reserves: $1000 A’s Checking Deposit: $1000 Loans: $1000 C’s Checking Deposit: $1000

Fig. 2 Bank B’s balance sheet

5 Mises (1953) takes this distinction between claims to and goods

themselves from Bohm-Bawerk (1962). Bohm-Bawerk (1962) theo-

rizes that issuing claims to goods does not double the amount of

actual goods in existence because claims do not give one power of

disposal over the good in question. Mises (1953) takes this idea and

applies it to money and money substitutes. Yet, Mises (1953)

recognizes and stresses the fact that money is unique and that claims

to money can technically give one all the benefits (power of disposal)

of holding money itself. Yet, he remains steadfast to Bohm-Bawerk’s

(1962) distinction between claims and goods and thus sticks to his

terminology of money and money substitutes, rather than just money.

For more on this, see Nair (2012).

6 Here we find Mises (1953) distinguishing between fungibility and

the ability of claims to be used in place of money proper.

In the first place, money is especially well adapted to constitute

the substance of a generic obligation. Whereas the fungibility

of nearly all other economic goods is more or less circum-

scribed and is often only a fiction based on an artificial com-

mercial terminology, that of money is almost unlimited… A

still more important circumstance is involved in the nature of

the function that money performs. A claim to money may be

transferred over and over again in an indefinite number of

indirect exchanges without the person by whom it is payable

ever being called upon to settle it. This is obviously not true as

far as other economic goods are concerned, for these are

always destined for ultimate consumption. (Mises 1953, p. 50

Emphasis mine).

Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration and Fraud

123

Page 8: Fractional Reserve Banking, Client Collaboration, and Fraud

patronize such a bank and hence in a free society, banks’

ability to create money will be seriously circumscribed.

This might be true, but what if certain people still know-

ingly choose to patronize such banks? At that point still, no

fraud would have been committed. For as long as people

choose not to redeem for cash, the ability of banks to create

money is enlarged. Why would people willingly and

knowingly choose not to redeem for cash even if they knew

their bank was effectively creating money if they did not?

Mises’ (1953) insight about how money substitutes can

play the same function of money helps shed light on how

fractional reserve banking can play a legitimate role in a

free society. Hence Mises (1953) stresses the utilitarian

argument as well as the ability of free banking to keep

excessive monetary creation in check.

Conclusion

The debate over the legitimacy of fractional reserve

banking has been through several iterations and the latest

installment brings up important issues about the linkages

between fractional reserves and maturity mismatching.

This paper showed that there is more common ground

between the views of BH and Evans than meets the eye

regarding the possibility of contractual arrangements that

lead to legitimate fractional reserve banking. It was shown

that both BH and Evans would agree that there is one type

of contract under which fractional reserve banking may be

rightfully seen as fraudulent, the storage or bailment con-

tract. On the other hand, demand deposits of the type

defended by the free bankers have the same essential fea-

tures as the ‘‘aleatory contract’’ described by BH. The

disagreement between can thus be seen no longer to be on

the question of ethics, rather one of practice as to how

much such contractual arrangements may proliferate in a

free society.

On the other hand, BB’s argument regarding fraud as

arising from an ‘‘over determination of property titles’’ was

shown to be inapplicable to the case of debt contracts

(whether borrowing short and lending long or fractional

reserve banking arising from demandable debt). This is

because property titles are only issued in the case of bail-

ments or storage contracts, whereas IOUs or debt claims

are issued in the case of debt contracts. Nevertheless, even

contractual fractional reserve banks are capable of creating

money de novo and the question of whether they should be

regarded as fraudulent on account of this still remains and

represents BB’s the strongest case argument for fraud. It

was shown that even in this case, one cannot classify

fractional reserve banking as fraudulent on account of

money creation alone for it is impossible for the bank to

pull it off without requisite client collaboration. This along

with a lack of misrepresentation (which would be the case

if the bank discloses the money is being lent) makes it

impossible to identify a clear victim. Hence, at least using

current common law definition of fraud, one cannot clas-

sify contractual fractional reserve banking as fraudulent on

the charge of its ability to create money. The paper then

points to an underappreciated theoretical point in Mises

(1953) that helps explain why fractional reserve banking

may well flourish in a free society.

References

Bagus, P., & Howden, D. (2009). The legitimacy of loan maturity

mismatching: A risky, but not fraudulent undertaking. Journal of

Business Ethics, 90(3), 399–406.

Bagus, P., & Howden, D. (2012). The continuing continuum problem

of deposits and loans. Journal of Business Ethics, 106, 295–300.

Bagus, P., & Howden, D. (2013). Deposits, loans and banking:

Clarifying the debate. American Journal of Economics and

Sociology, 72(3), 627.

Barnett, W., & Block, W. E. (2009). Time deposits, dimensions and

fraud. Journal of Business Ethics, 88(4), 711–716.

Barnett, W., & Block, W. E. (2011). Rejoinder to Bagus and Howden

on borrowing short and lending long. Journal of Business Ethics,

100, 229–238.

Block, W. E., & Davidson, L. (2011). The case against Fiduciary

Media: Ethics is the key. Journal of Business Ethics, 98,

505–511.

Bohm-Bawerk, E. V. (1962). Whether legal rights and relationships

are economic goods. Grove City: Penn, Libertarian Books.

Cachanosky, N. (2011). A comment on Barnett and Block on time

deposit and Bagus and Howden on loan maturity mismatching.

Journal of Business Ethics, 104, 219–221.

Diamond, J., Levine, L., & Bernstein, A. (2010). Understanding torts.

Charlotte, NC: Lexis Nexis.

Evans, A. J. (2013). Defense of demand deposits: Contractual

solutions to the Bagus and Howden and Block and Barnett

Debate. Journal of Business Ethics, 22, 1.

Garner, B. (Ed.). (2001). Black’s law dictionary (7th ed.). Eagan:

West Group.

Hulsmann, J. G. (2003). Has fractional reserve banking really passed

the market test? The Independent Review, 7(3), 399–422.

Mises, L. (1953). The theory of money and credit. New Haven: Yale

University Press.

Nair, M. (2012). Bohm-Bawerk’s influence on Mises’ typology of

money. In J. G. Hulsmann (Ed.), Theory of money and fiduciary

media. Essays in celebration of the centennial. Auburn: Ludwig

von Mises Institute.

Rohwer, C., & Skrocki, A. (2006). Contracts. Eagan: Thomson West.

Rothbard, M. N. (1993). Man, economy, and state. Auburn, AL:

Ludwig von Mises Institute.

Selgin, G. (2012a). Those dishonest goldsmiths. Financial History

Review, 19(3), 269–288.

Selgin, G. (2012b). Banknotes are not, and have never pretended to

be, warehouse receipts. http://www.freebanking.org/2012/07/17/

banknotes-are-not-and-have-never-pretended-to-be-warehouse-

receipts/.

White, L. H. (2003). Accounting for fractional-reserve banknotes and

deposits- or, what’s twenty quid to the bloody midland bank?

The Independent Review, 7(3), 423.

M. Nair

123