20
7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 1/20 10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 1/20 Print Window The Independent Institute Contest Essay Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation  By Philipp Bagus | Posted: Mon. October 13, 2008 Junior Faculty Winner. Second Prize ($5,000) Abstract Property rights are human rights grounded in human nature. In fact, all human rights can be formulated as a variation of property rights. Nevertheless, many authors have advanced alleged human rights that confront and violate property rights. In this paper, the differences between property rights and these alleged rights, or pseudo human rights, are analyzed. The differences regarding the concomitant political systems explain why there have been more defenders of pseudo human rights than of property rights. There is no such dichotomy as “human rights” versus “property rights.” No human rights can exist without property rights. [1] —Ayn Rand The program of liberalism, therefore, if condensed into a single word, would have to read: property... All the other demands of liberalism result from this fundamental demand.[2] —Ludwig von Mises 1. Introduction We need not look very long to find unsettling news. Haitians scavenge for food in a garbage dump in Port-au-Prince, a city that has witnessed recent food riots. As food prices spiral, those in places like Egypt, India, Malaysia, Senegal, and sub-Saharan Africa face similar unrest to that of Haiti. [3] In addition to widespread hunger, violence has erupted in Tibet as Chinese security forces attempt to subdue protests by Buddhist monks and other ethnic Tibetans. [4] In Zimbabwe, police gather up election monitors and opposition members as the election process continues in disarray.[5] In Dafur, estimates suggest that as many as 300,000 people have died as a result of the five-year conflict in the region, a situation that some have labeled as genocide.[6] Though recent news is not new  news, hunger, stifling of dissent, military conflict, and claims of genocide are characteristic of the times, often invoking calls to respect and enforce human rights. Over the last 60 years, human rights have become the moral currency of our times, as efforts

Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 1/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 1/20

Print Window 

The Independent Institute 

Contest Essay

Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights

Devaluation 

By Philipp Bagus | Posted: Mon. October 13, 2008

Junior Faculty Winner. Second Prize ($5,000)

Abstract

Property rights are human rights grounded in human nature. In fact, all human rights can be

formulated as a variation of property rights. Nevertheless, many authors have advanced

alleged human rights that confront and violate property rights. In this paper, the differences

between property rights and these alleged rights, or pseudo human rights, are analyzed. The

differences regarding the concomitant political systems explain why there have been more

defenders of pseudo human rights than of property rights.

There is no such dichotomy as “human rights” versus “property rights.” No human

rights can exist without property rights.[1]

—Ayn Rand

The program of liberalism, therefore, if condensed into a single word, would have to

read: property... All the other demands of liberalism result from this fundamental

demand.[2]

—Ludwig von Mises

1. Introduction

We need not look very long to find unsettling news. Haitians scavenge for food in a garbage

dump in Port-au-Prince, a city that has witnessed recent food r iots. As food prices spiral, those

in places like Egypt, India, Malaysia, Senegal, and sub-Saharan Africa face similar unrest to

that of Haiti.[3] In addition to widespread hunger, violence has erupted in Tibet as Chinese

security forces attempt to subdue protests by Buddhist monks and other ethnic Tibetans.[4] In

Zimbabwe, police gather up election monitors and opposition members as the election process

continues in disarray.[5] In Dafur, estimates suggest that as many as 300,000 people have died

as a result of the five-year conflict in the region, a situation that some have labeled as

genocide.[6] Though recent news is not new  news, hunger, stifling of dissent, military conflict,and claims of genocide are characteristic of the times, often invoking calls to respect and

enforce human rights.

Over the last 60 years, human rights have become the moral currency of our times, as efforts

Page 2: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 2/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 2/20

are made to address social injustices. Such efforts are reflected in the positing and stipulating

of human rights. In fact, the number of human rights treaties in international law over the last 60

years has substantially increased. Marking the beginning of this expansion, the Declaration of 

Human Rights (1948) has been followed by the European Convention on Human Rights (1950),

the International Covenant on Civil and Political Rights (1966), the International Covenant on

Economic, Social and Cultural Rights (1966), and the British Human Rights Act (1998) among

others. This growing industry of human rights is also evidenced by the number of alleged

human rights discussed in academic discourse. Human rights language permeates a vast array

of social life and is found in discussions of health care, education, wages, welfare, culture, and

the environment. In fact, Nickel (2006) has described this as a “human rights inflation.”

The continuously expanding list of human rights is especially alarming from a classical liberal

perspective as represented by Smith (1776), Bastiat (1850), Mises (1927) and Hayek (1960), in

that it causes a devaluing of important human rights. More precisely, these more recent human

rights deal mainly with social welfare, entailing positive duties for the government, requiring its

expansion. These more recent human rights stand in contrast to individual liberty and

progressively undermine property rights and freedom.

This paper has two goals. The first is to examine the relationship between property rights and

human rights. Starting from a Lockean natural law perspective, I investigate which human rights

can be considered natural rights. I find that only property rights, and rights derivable from them,

are natural rights. Subsequently, the unbridgeable differences between property rights and

what I call pseudo human rights, i.e. alleged human rights that are not natural rights, will be

analyzed.

The paper’s second goal is to investigate why property rights have found fewer intellectualchampions than pseudo human rights. I will show that the reason lies in the abysmal

differences between the two types of rights. A capitalist society is grounded in property rights

while pseudo human rights are a vehicle to promote socialist ideals. Consequently, I explore the

reasons why intellectuals tend to be socialists and therefore why property rights have rarely

found staunch defenders while the defense of expansive human rights continues to be en

vogue among intellectuals.

2. Property Rights as (Natural) Human Rights

 According to natural law theorists, what is just and unjust does not depend on human

arbitrariness but is objective. Natural law theorists argue further that the norms of justice are

grounded in human nature and can be found by human reason. One of the most important

modern natural law theorists, John Locke, developed his natural law theory in his famous Two

Treatises on Government , inspiring American revolutionaries and the Declaration of 

Independence. John Locke (1824, ch. II, § 6) maintains that

The state of nature has a law of nature to govern it, which obliges every one: and reason, which

is that law, teaches all mankind, who will but consult it, that being all equal and independent, noone ought to harm another in his life, health, liberty, or possessions.

The r ight to life, health, liberty or possessions is a central point for classical liberal

and libertarian political philosophy and is closely connected to property rights.[7]

Page 3: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 3/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 3/20

Property rights can be deduced from two basic twin axioms (Rothbard, 1982): the

axiom of self-ownership and the homesteading principle. The self-evident principle

of self-ownership (Machan 2002) signifies that every human being has the absolute

 jurisdiction over his own body.[8] The principle of self-ownership points to the

homesteading principle, also known as first-use-first-own or finder-keeper principle.

 As Locke (1824, Ch. V, § 27) writes famously on mixing one’s labor with natural

resources:

Every man has a property in his own person . . . The labor of his body and the work of his

hands we may say are properly his. Whatsoever then he removes out of the state that nature

hath provided, and left it in, he hath mixed his labour with, and joined to it something that is his

own, and thereby makes it his property.

Kirzner (1974) renders this more accurately, that our entrepreneurial actions make

us the rightful owner of our findings. When we discover an unowned resource and

form a use for it, we are the rightful owners. We have used our entrepreneurial

capacities to create an economic means. Parting from the self-ownership andhomesteading principles it is then a small step to deduce the rights to one’s

production and the right to exchange one’s property. As we are owners of ourselves

and especially of our own minds, everything that we do with our homesteaded

resources without harming the property of others is just. Consequently, whatever we

produce with our resources and mind is ours. Furthermore, we can transfer or 

exchange our property and enter into contract with other people freely. Property

rights also answer the question of when the use force in society is justified. Force is

 justified in order to defend one’s property and any initiation of an attack on anyone’s

property is unjustifiable.

I have thus shown that property rights are natural rights stemming from natural law theory. In

fact, property rights form a core element of natural law. However, property rights are not only

natural rights, they are also and foremost human rights. Property rights are human rights for 

two main reasons. First, property rights can be found by human reason and are implied in

human nature. Second, property rights only accrue to human beings. Every human being owns

these rights by virtue of his human nature (Machan 1997). Things, in contrast, cannot possess

a property right.

 After demonstrating that property rights are human rights, I now take on the more difficult task

of analyzing Murray N. Rothbard´s (1977; 1998) bold claim that human rights are dependent on

property rights. In other words, no human rights exist which cannot be formulated in terms of 

property rights. From this point of view, property rights are a cardinal restraint for what may

else be considered a human right. While doing so, I formulate human rights in terms of property

rights and define a means of sorting human rights from pseudo human rights.

3. Human Rights Contained in Property Rights Vs. Pseudo Human Rights

Rothbard (1998) claims that any right can be summarized or formulated as a variant of property

rights. Following Rothbard, I will now use a property rights approach to sort through the mass of 

alleged human rights in order to distinguish human rights from pseudo human rights.

Page 4: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 4/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 4/20

The Universal Declaration of Human Rights (1948) alone provides a list of over two-dozen

human rights. These rights can be grouped into six families (Nickel 2006): security rights, due

process rights, liberty rights, political rights, equality rights, and social (or “welfare”) rights. The

first five groups are commonly called first-generation rights. Social rights are called second-

generation rights. More recently, a third group encompassing collective or group rights has

been added. In the following section, the legitimacy of these alleged human rights will be

analyzed individually.

3.1. First-Generation Rights

The first set of first-generation human rights concerns security rights which protect against

crimes like murder, torture and rape. As human rights are commonly seen as restraints on

governments, security rights protect against infringement of the government on the lives of its

own citizens. Clearly, security rights are implied in property rights, namely to the principle of 

self-ownership. Yet, these rights not only restrain governments from the use of unjustified force,

they restrain the use of unjustified force by individuals. If I own my body, no one has the right todo harm to my body without my consent.

The second set of first-generation human rights concerns due process rights, which protect

against unfair trials. Due process rights are also entailed in property rights. Property rights imply

that an innocent person cannot be arrested arbitrarily nor punished by an arbitrary trial. Any

use of force against innocent persons violates the self-ownership principle.

However, due process rights do not obligate the person whose property rights are violated to

go through a burdensome trial.[9] For instance, applying natural rights theory, if someone

steals my car and I happen to see it one day in a street, I have the right to take it back

immediately. The criminal does not have a right to force me to go through a burdensome trial.

In spite of this right to self-defense it is probable that in a libertarian society people would

almost universally make use of due process. There is, after all, a higher risk of error and costly

restitution of that error without due process (Rothbard 1998). Without due process we might

 just not have found the criminal but an innocent person. Moreover, we can expect a stronger or 

even violent resistance of the accused person when we do not make use of due process.

The third set of first-generation human rights encompasses the so-called liberty rights which

protect freedom of belief, expression, and association. These rights are to a great extent

included in property rights as well. As each is the owner of one’s own mind, he is free to believe

whatever he wants. Moreover, each individual has the right to express his beliefs with his own

property. Anyone can speak on his own property or use his means to produce or buy media in

order to express his opinion. One could, for instance, rent a hall or a yard and speak to an

audience, buy air-time on radio and television, acquire and blog on an internet domain or print

his opinions in acquired space in newspapers, pamphlets, and books.

 All the freedom contained in liberty rights is necessarily limited by property rights and

inseparable from them. As Rothbard (1977, 238-39) states regarding the right to free speech:

...He has the right only on his own property or on the property of someone who has

agreed, as a gift or in a rental contract, to allow him on / the premises. In fact, then

there is no such thing as a separate “right to free speech;” there is only a man’s

Page 5: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 5/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 5/20

 property  right: the right to do as he wills with his own or to make voluntary

agreements with other property owners. (Italics in the original)

The same is true for the right of association. There is no separate right of association but only

the possibility to use one’s own property to form with others voluntarily associations, clubs,

groups or parties.

The right of association is related to the r ight to assembly, which brings us to the fourth set of first-generation of human rights, which concerns political rights. Political rights protect freedoms

to participate in politics and assemblies, vote, protest, and communicate. Rightly understood,

political rights can also be inferred from property rights. Everyone may use his property to

protest, assemble, and speak freely. For example, I can call for a demonstration in my yard or I

can buy ads in a newspaper to express my political views. I can use my car to drive to the ballot

box, make an x with my pencil and cast the vote. Or I can participate in government by using

my property. A different assessment arises when it comes to the actions of government itself.

For instance, people can use their property to vote on the question of whether an individual’s

house and land should be expropriated to build a new highway. The vote in favor of theexpropriation itself does not violate property rights. Only at that moment the government

expropriates the property, does it violate property rights. For each person has the complete

authority over the use of her own property. Similarly, participation in a government itself is

legitimate. Participation only becomes illegitimate in the moment when the government violates

property rights.[10]

Before turning to second-generation human rights, we can state that property rights do imply

many of the first-generation human rights, like security of life, freedom of association, and

freedom of speech. In fact, these rights are not separable from property rights. Furthermore,when property rights are infringed upon, these human rights disappear along with them. For 

instance, when TV channels are licensed or state owned, the freedom of speech is inhibited as

opinion in the TV is controlled. The same happen when newspapers are licensed or owned by

the government. As Mises (2006, 33) points out “free press can only exist where there is private

control of the means of production.” The same curtailment of human rights occurs when private

property is violated to the extent that demonstrations, assemblies, or the formation of certain

groups are forbidden. Moreover, by prohibiting the use of private property for certain spiritual

meetings, religious rights are violated.

3.2. Second-Generation Rights

Whereas first-generation human rights are mainly negative rights, i.e., rights to be left alone,

second generation rights are mainly positive in that they generally obligate governments to

provide for the socio-economic welfare of others.[11] In this sense, these second-generation

rights are sometimes called welfare rights. I will now look at some of these socio-economic or 

second-generation r ights in detail. First, I quote two articles of the Universal Declaration of 

Human Rights to provide an impression of the nature of second-generation rights. Then, I

proceed to present and critique the main argument in for why welfare rights should be

considered human rights.

 Article 25 (1) of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights states that

Page 6: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 6/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 6/20

Everyone has the right to a standard of living adequate for the health and well-being

of himself and of his family, including food, clothing, housing, and medical care and

necessary social services, and the r ight to security in the event of unemployment,

sickness, disability, widowhood, old age or other lack of livelihood in circumstances

beyond his control.

 Article 26 (1) reads:

Everyone has the right to education. Education shall be free, at least in the

elementary and fundamental stages. Elementary education shall be compulsory.

Technical and professional education shall be made generally available and higher 

education shall be equally accessible to all on the basis of merit.

Three main kinds of arguments are brought forward in favor of the alleged human social right to

a minimum adequate standard of living, health care, social services, or education. The first kind

of argument is egalitarian (Singh 2001). Although various egalitarian arguments differ in their 

account of equality, these arguments use equality as a norm to justify the claims of welfare

rights. For example, James Sterba (2001, 325) takes an egalitarian approach when he

maintains that there is a positive right, or “liberty not to be interfered with in taking the surplus

resources of the rich what is required to meet one’s basic needs.” He continues (326) asking:

“Isn’t it clearly unreasonable to require the poor to sacrifice the liberty to meet their basic needs

so that the rich can have the liberty to meet their luxury demands?”

 A second line of reasoning promotes human dignity as the norm for justifying the redistribution

of resources. For example, Schachter (1983) and Otto (1997) regard human dignity – a term

widespread in human rights treatises - as a foundation for human rights. According to this

rationale, human dignity or the intrinsic worth of human beings demands, that everyone be

provided an adequate means of subsistence or an opportunity to work. Human dignity would

also imply, for instance, that every one gets a basic education and a minimum of “distributive

 justice”.

The third argument made in favor of social rights is based in T. H. Marshall’s influential work:

Citizenship and Social Class: And other Essays (1950). Marshall argues that the possession of 

civil, political and social rights is a principal element of citizenship. If one element were missing,

citizenship would be incomplete. Similarly, Beetham (1995) argues that social rights are a

necessary condition of human agency. In this tradition, social rights are seen as a precondition

of first generation rights. Swan (2001) argues that education is a precondition for liberty and

political choice. Likewise, Almquist (2005) maintains a right of suitable cultural equipment[12] as

precondition for cultural participation and other individual rights.

The central critique to all three lines of arguments is that to a large extent, second-generation

rights violate property rights, i.e., real human rights. Second-generation rights require providing

a service to those who cannot afford that service. If no one is willing to voluntarily finance these

services, second-generation rights imply the use of coercion in order to provide such services.

In such cases, second-generation rights violate property rights, as it is impossible to honor bothof them at the same time.

It should be added, that property rights are not prima facie rights that can be restricted or 

balanced at discretion against some important goal, be it equality, “dignity,” or citizenship.

Page 7: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 7/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 7/20

Property rights are natural rights. They restrain the justifiable use of force in society. Their 

infringement would violate the self-ownership or the homesteading principle and as such stand

against human nature. These violations are unjustifiable independent of any noble goals sought

to be achieved by them. In addition to this central critique, every one of the three arguments is

also susceptible to complementary criticisms.

The egalitarian argument fails, as it requires coercion to make men equal. As Erich von

Kühnelt-Leddihn (1952) has cogently pointed out, there is always a dichotomy between equalityand liberty. Sterba's (2001) argument that the poor have the right to violate the liberty of the

rich in order to satisfy their basic needs, shows the conflict between liberty and equality most

clearly. In order to argue for his goal of a more equal distribution of resources, Sterba

presupposes that there is no such thing as absolute property rights. Moreover, as a general

critique to egalitarian approaches, Rothbard (1974; 1995) points out that there is no scientific

argument that all men should be equal. Why should all men be equal? Naturally, humans have

different characteristics; everyone is unique. These natural differences obviously imply a

varying use of resources. Even efforts to create a more equal distribution of resources would

not be successful in creating more equality. Nor would it be successful in remaining that way as

human beings will continue to use the redistributed resources according to their own

inclinations and talents.

The dignity argument resembles to some extent natural right philosophy by using reason to

determine the intrinsic worth of a human being. Yet, the argument fails because it implicitly

demands that private property rights be violated in order to secure, for instance, free education

for everyone. In addition, the argumentation is problematic as no clear definition of human

dignity is provided. In respect to this reasoning, one wonders above all: Would it not be against

human dignity to violate property rights?

The argument that social rights are a precondition of other rights also fails as in order to secure

citizenship state intervention is advised. The state is to provide public education, cultural

equipment, regulate working conditions and payments. Beside the implication of coercion,

social rights are no precondition for human rights. There is no need for universal free education

or health care to enjoy property rights. I must not even be literate to enjoy the property in my

body or possessions. The only condition is that no one violates my property. On the contrary,

universal free education requires the violation of property rights.

3.3. Third-Generation Rights

Even though the list of second-generation rights already seems to be quite long, a new

category of human rights has been promoted. In a response to the argument that human rights

are too individualistic (Campbell 2004), collective or group rights have been suggested. Among

these are the rights to peace (Jones 2006), to a safe and healthy environment (Nickel 1993),

the right to development (Rich 1988) or the right to national self-determination (Seel 2001).

Third-generation rights are susceptible to the same central criticism as second-generationrights. Their application requires the violation of property rights. Moreover, third-generation

rights are rights of groups. Yet groups cannot have rights, only individuals have rights. Of 

course, individuals have the right to use their property to form groups or acquire joint ownership

Page 8: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 8/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 8/20

of resources. However, it is simply impossible to establish an independent right of collective or 

group ownership from natural law. This attempt would require that parts of persons are

collectively owned by a group, which would in turn violate the principle of self-ownership.

Consequently, there is no group right to peace. Only individuals have the right that their 

property and persons not be attacked. Yet, property rights address these environmental

concerns implicitly. No one has the right to pollute someone else’s property.

Similarly, just as a group right to peace does not exist, neither does a collective right to a safeand healthy environment exist. Only individuals have the right that their property not be polluted

and destroyed. Furthermore, a right to clean water or an access to wilderness (Swan 2001)

would be a welfare right and like second-generation rights, would violate private property rights.

 A right to development does not exist either. Every person has the right to develop his own

property and capacities. Yet a nation has no right to foreign aid from another nation based on a

right to development. Lastly, the right to national self-determination is a fictitious right, as well,

because collective entities cannot own rights. Some concession must be made, however,

regarding self-determination. First, individuals have the right not to be exploited by a nationalmajority. Second, every individual owns a natural right to self-determination and can join with

others to disassociate themselves from a state.

4. Differences Between Property Rights and Pseudo Human Rights

In this section I investigate the differences between property rights, i.e., human rights, and

pseudo human rights. These differences will give more weight to my assertion that property

rights and pseudo human rights are irreconcilable. Such dissimilarities concern conceptual

clarity, universality, coherency, specificity, rule of law, finiteness, response to conflicts, and

nature, as well as their influence on governments, moral space, and economic prosperity.

First, the divergence between property rights and pseudo human rights is noted in terms of 

conceptual clarity. The definition of property rights is clear and precise: A property right gives

the exclusive authority of the use of the property. Pseudo human rights, however, are

ambiguous and vague. For instance, the alleged right for free basic education neither defines

what counts as education nor the quantity and quality of the education that every human

allegedly has a right to. Moreover, what is considered basic education and health care might

change. During the passing of time outstanding historical events or new scientific theories might

be included in the canon of basic education. Likewise, with the introduction of new drugs or 

more effective medical treatment, health care alters as well.

The next difference lies in the universality of human rights. Property rights are universal rights.

They lie in human nature and are applicable to any human society. In fact, they are feasible in

any country at any time if people just abstain from the violation of property rights. Yet pseudo

human rights are not universal for two main reasons. First, they are not natural rights and as

such dependent on legal enactment and the provision of the state. Second, as Cranston (1973)

has shown, socio-economic rights are not possessed by virtue of being human but by virtue of being a member of a certain society. If a society is poor, there might not be enough resources

to provide basic free education or health care to everyone.

The coherency of property rights and incoherency of pseudo human rights is another main

Page 9: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 9/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 9/20

distinction between them. Property rights are coherent and pose no self-contradictions. For 

example, the right of free speech on one’s own property does not interfere with the right of 

using one’s property to call for an assembly. Quite to the contrary, pseudo human rights are not

only in conflict with property rights but also with each other. Pseudo human rights stand in

conflict with each other because there is always a limited amount of resources available to

satisfy these rights (Nickel 2006). For example, the right to health care interferes with the right

to free education and with the right to security in the event of unemployment. Logically, the

resources the government dedicates to health care cannot be dedicated to competing pseudo

human rights.

 Another dissimilarity between property rights and pseudo human rights lies in their specificity.

Property rights are general and abstract, implying general rules of conduct as, for instance: it is

never allowed to steal or murder. These rules imply an absence of interference that is difficult to

visualize. Pseudo property rights, however, are not abstract notions. They are specific to a

situation and are subsequently more visible than property rights. Gordon (1998) actually

advocates that human rights should be directly related to concrete life activities. This difference

makes pseudo human rights more visualizable than property rights. The alleged right to free

basic education or a right to clean water is more visualizable than the abstractness of property

rights.

 A related distinction is the rule of law in the Hayekian (1944) sense implied in property rights

and their absence under pseudo human rights. Property rights minimize the discretion left to

government. Property rights entail rules of conduct that are the same for everyone independent

of the specific circumstances. In other words, they point to general rules or formal law.

Consequently, property rights imply equality before the law. In contrast, pseudo human rights

imply certain redistribution from the rich to those who cannot afford the alleged rights. Someonehas to provide a service to those who cannot afford the right. Therefore, pseudo human rights

demand an unequal treatment before the law. Some are taxed in order to pay for the welfare of 

others. The interpretation of the particular situation and person gives the government

discretion. The specific circumstances of a person call for a different treatment. Individuals

make use of the coercive measures of the state to improve their welfare. The particular 

legislation and vague definitions give room for discretion by the government and violates,

consequently, the rule of law. By violating the rule of law, the traditional sense of justice in the

population is perverted. As a consequence, corruption flourishes and the population no longer 

follows universal rules but tries to gain advantages by demanding and interpreting pseudo

human rights.

Furthermore, as another distinction, property rights are few, determinate, and finite. Those

rights can be summarized in the principle of self-ownership and the homesteading principle.

These two principals are similar to a corset which limits the implicit rights in property rights.

Quite to the contrary, pseudo human rights are many, indeterminate and in fact expanding

(Stoilov 2001). We live in an age in which human rights inflation devaluates property rights. The

quantity of pseudo human rights is open and not bound by any principle. Anything that is just

important enough and lies in the alleged dignity of humans is deemed as a precondition for other rights or that which makes humans more equal can in principal be advocated as a human

right.

 A further discrepancy lies in the manner in which property rights and pseudo human rights

Page 10: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 10/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 10/20

 

affect conflicts. Property rights minimize conflicts. By giving each individual exclusive authority

over his body and property, conflicts are reduced.[13] Moreover, pseudo human rights create

conflicts for several reasons. First, welfare rights create conflicts with property right owners.

Property owners who do not want to pay for the welfare rights of their fellow citizens will try to

avoid that infringement of their property. Second, conflicts can occur concerning the quantity

and quality of those services or resources a vaguely defined pseudo human right implies. Third,

conflicts arise between different pseudo human rights when not enough resources are available

to meet them all. Fourth, as pseudo human rights are an open sum, conflicts are possible about

the question of which new human rights are to be added. Everyone could make the claim to

have a certain pseudo human right and use it to justify initiating coercion on another person to

provide the right.

 An additional difference lies in the type of rights that property rights and pseudo human rights

are. Property rights are negative and active rights. They are negative in the sense that they

require restraint from doing certain things (Machan 1997), i.e., the non-interference with the

property of other people. They are active rights in the sense that they imply the right to do

things (Almond 1993). Everyone has the right to do with his body and property what he wants

as long as he does not violate the property of another.

Quite to the contrary, pseudo human rights are positive and passive rights. They are positive

rights in the sense that they point to positive duties (Jones 2006). For instance, the alleged right

of free medical care implies the positive duties of others to provide these medical services.

Pseudo human rights are passive rights in the sense that they are rights to have things done to

the owner of the welfare right (Almond 1993). Thus, this owner is provided with an adequate

living standard and education.

Interestingly, this clear-cut distinction between property rights and pseudo human rights has

been disputed. Beetham (1995) tries to show that property rights are also positive or active

rights, as they require actions to protect them. Government provides the protection of property

rights in the same sense as it would provide welfare rights. As a response, it must first be

pointed out that property rights can in principal, and are in practice, protected without the help

of government. People can defend themselves, put walls around their property or hire private

security guards. Second, it is as Machan (1985, 36) distinctly notes, only the “enjoyment of a

right” that needs protection. Property rights exist prior to and independent of any defense.

Third, and most importantly, property rights do not need active protection if they are respected.In contrast, pseudo human rights in order to be respected need an active intervention in order 

to secure the provision of welfare goods and services.

These differences in the types of rights lead us directly to the divergent influences property

rights and pseudo human rights have upon government. As property rights are negative rights

they restrict the sphere of government. Pseudo human rights, however, give government the

authority and even the duty to provide the population with some services, be it clean water,

cultural equipment, fair wages, or medical care. Pseudo human rights, in this way, expand the

role of government in the economy requiring paternalistic and bureaucratic central agencies.

 Another disparity between property rights and pseudo human rights can be found in their 

effects on human responsibility. As Machan (1992) points out, property rights provide human

beings with a moral space. Inside their moral space as limited by their property rights, human

 

Page 11: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 11/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 11/20

beings can act morally and responsibly. This allows for and promotes courage, honesty,

generosity, and prudence. Pseudo human rights have the opposite effect. They restrict and

violate property rights, consequently restricting the possibility for moral action. Furthermore,

they promote irresponsible behavior with resources that are provided for by the government.

When people receive resources for free, they tend to waste those resources. When the

government guarantees the provision of these resources, the cost of wasting them will be

socialized.

This last difference leads us directly to the unlikely effects that private property rights and

pseudo human rights have upon wealth creation and economic growth. A system of well-

defined and defended private property rights fosters economic growth in several respects. First,

private property in the means of production makes economic calculation possible, as Mises

(1920) lucidly has shown. His argument is as ingenious as it is simple. If there is no private

property in the means of production there are no market prices of the means of production.

Without market prices of the means of production rational economic calculation becomes

impossible. No central planning agency could possibly command the information necessary to

coordinate a complex economy.

Second, private property rights foster economic growth because they provide incentives for 

individual actors to create wealth and take care of their property. When property is privately

owned and not restricted by government, the owner of private property can fully participate in

the benefits that the property provides. A property owner bears the costs of their actions, when

their property or wealth decreases in value. Consequently, the property owner has the incentive

to take care of his property, to prevent waste, and to put it into the most value-productive uses

as determined by the consumers on the free market.

Third, secure property rights enhance incentives to save and accumulate capital, which

enhance productivity and lead to higher economic growth. In addition, secure property rights

create incentives to acquire greater skills in production for the market and earning profits. When

property rights are respected the economy grows thereby raising the standard of living. The

increased standard of living makes the fulfillment of the goals set by second-generation rights

more probable. A higher standard of living gives people the opportunity to provide for health

care, basic education, etc.. Moreover, charity tends to increase with increasing wealth thereby

providing the means for basic needs of the poor without the violation of property rights.

In contrast, pseudo human rights inhibit economic growth. By infringing upon property rights,

they make economic calculation more difficult. By enlarging the role of government and the

burden of taxation they discourage the efficient use of resources. Moreover, in addition to the

higher tax burden they create legal insecurity. Pseudo human rights are not clearly defined, and

also are changeable and augmentable. Therefore, legal insecurity is the result of the inner 

contradictions and conflicts that pseudo human rights face. As a consequence, savings and

capital accumulation are discouraged. Ironically, by curbing economic growth, pseudo human

rights make the fulfillment of their goals more difficult. There are fewer resources available than

with secure property rights and higher economic growth. Thus, satisfying basic needs is moredifficult and less resources available for charity purposes.

Lastly, property rights and pseudo human rights differ in their associated political system and

philosophy. The concomitant political system to property rights is capitalism (Machan 1992).

Page 12: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 12/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 12/20

The concomitant political value is liberty. Indeed, liberty is implied in property rights. In this

sense Hayek (1973, 107) states: “Law, liberty, and property are an inseparable trinity.” We find

this same conclusion in the quote by Ludwig von Mises at the beginning of this essay. The

political program of classical liberalism can be reduced to property rights.

Quite to the contrary, the concomitant political system to pseudo human rights is socialism. The

intervention of the state in human affairs in order to improve society is reflected in such positive

rights as universal health care or public education. In fact, Stoilov (2001) argues that the rise of the welfare state was accompanied by the development of social and economic rights

doctrines.

The differences between property rights and pseudo human rights discussed in this section are

summarized in the following table:

Differences: Property Rights

or Human Rights

Pseudo Human

Rights

Conceptual

Clarity

Clear and precise Vague and ambiguous

Universality Transhistorial Not universal

Coherency Coherent Contradictory

Specifity  Abstract and

general

Specific and problem

oriented

Rule of Law Yes No

Quantity Few and finite Many and infinite

Conflict

Resolution

Minimize Create

Type of right Negative and

active

Positive and passive

Effects on

government

Restrict Expand

Moral Space  Allow Close

Page 13: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 13/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 13/20

Wealth Creation Foster Inhibit and destroy

Basis of social

system

Capitalism Socialism

In sum, property rights (which are human rights) and pseudo human rights contain

unbridgeable differences and are mutually exclusive. In fact, pseudo human rights destroy the

concept of rights by violating property rights and perverting the traditional meaning of justice. If 

pseudo human rights and property rights are artificially set on an equal basis something similar 

to the logic implied in Gresham´s Law occurs. Artificially overvalued rights, i.e. the pseudo

rights, crowd out the undervalued rights, i.e. property rights. Progressively, property rights are

neglected and violated. The inflating pseudo human rights take prevalence in society. In this

sense, Hayek (1976, 105), regards the Universal Declaration of Human Rights as “an

irresponsible game with the concept of ´right´ which could result only in destroying the respect

for it.”

5. The Defenders of Property Rights and Defenders of Pseudo Human Rights

In this section I will investigate why there have been fewer intellectual defenders of property

rights than defenders of pseudo human rights. There are several reasons for this discrepancy.

First, it is much easier to inspire people with practical and visualizable concepts than with

abstract concepts. Property rights are abstract concepts with many implications. They

guarantee the absence of an action, namely the interference with one’s property. Contrary to

property rights, pseudo human rights are more problem-specific and visualizable. Moreover,the goals that pseudo human rights aim at are an adequate living standard for all, or a clean

environment, are perceived as noble and practical. Pseudo human rights seem to provide a

solution to many burdensome problems of mankind by carrying normative weight for the use of 

force.

Second, as we have seen, property rights are the “keystone” of capitalism (DiLorenzo 2004).

Property rights are correctly associated with exchange, trade, and the market economy.

Pseudo human rights, in contrast, are associated with solidarity and the welfare state. They

provide a justification of interventions into society. Logically, defenders of capitalism defendproperty rights and defenders of statism defend pseudo human rights.

Traditionally, there have been few defenders of capitalism and liberty. Lord Acton (1907, ch. 1)

observes that “[a]t all times sincere friends of freedom have been rare, and its triumphs have

been due to minorities...” Indeed, the “hegemony of the Left” over the universities is

overwhelming (Feser 2004). Consequently, the answer to our question is straightforward: As

there have been few friends of liberty among intellectuals there have been also few defenders

of property rights. However, we still have not really answered the question why there have been

fewer defenders of property rights than defenders of pseudo human rights. We just have

moved it to another level. We are now faced with the intriguing question of why the majority of 

intellectuals have socialist leanings, making them advocates of pseudo human rights.

Even if we assume best intentions, like protecting people through welfare rights, it is important

Page 14: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 14/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 14/20

to look at the incentive structure with which intellectuals are confronted. Many intellectuals

receive part or all of their income from the government (Klein 2006). Many intellectuals are

working in the education sector, which is highly regulated and subsidized, if not outright

nationalized, by the government. By subsidizing intellectuals their number increases above the

number that would prevail on a free market. Owing their job to the government, many

intellectuals - consciously or not - tend to justify government interventions. These government

interventions are, in fact, in many cases justified by pseudo human rights. Moreover, as many

intellectuals are part of the government apparatus, they indirectly profit from the application of 

interventions such as those implied in pseudo human rights. With pseudo human rights, the

power of the state increases and many intellectuals form part of the state organization.

 A second reason is brought forward in Hayek's seminal 1949 article “The Intellectuals and

Socialism.” Hayek argues that many intelligent libertarians do not go into academia or other 

intellectual jobs but instead go into business. Therefore, left-leaning intellectuals are over-

represented in academia.

 A third reason denotes human vanity. Everyone likes to feel important. As do most people,intellectuals want to think they do something useful or important. Therefore, intellectuals hired

or subsidized by the state favor social engineering. They think they can fine-tune society and

call for the state in helping them in this noble task. Incidentally, one way to improve society in

the eyes of intellectuals is by fulfilling pseudo human rights. As their quantity, quality, and

extension are vague, someone is needed in order to decide on these delicate questions. This is

where the importance of the intellectuals enters. They help to answer these questions and also

provide justifications for these rights.

 A fourth reason, is the hatred that many intellectuals nourish against capitalism. There areseveral reasons for this hatred. One is the myth of a falling standard of living during the

industrial revolution.[14] Another cause of the resentment is, as Mises (2006) notes, caused by

frustrated ambitions. Many intellectuals, even though they regard themselves as better 

educated, earn much less than many entrepreneurs. They envy[15] the success of the

entrepreneurs and managers that earn more than they do. Subsequently, they look for a

scapegoat for their failure and find it in capitalism. As a result, they resent the system, which

allows uneducated entrepreneurs to earn much more than the well-educated and highly

intelligent intellectuals. Related to Mises´argument is Nozick´s (1986) explanation of the

opposition of intellectuals to capitalism. Nozick maintains that intellectuals have been successfulin their school years and rewarded by the central school authority while they have failed socially

in a spontaneous market environment. Consequently, they tend to favor a central organization

to the market economy.

 A fifth reason is that many intellectuals do not understand the market economy (Hayek 1949).

 As they do not understand it, they see the market economy as something suspicious that must

be controlled and channeled into controllable lines by pseudo human rights. They do not grasp

the importance of the rule of law and property rights for civilization. They are also unaware of 

the consequences that the alternatives to capitalism entail. Moreover, they do not know thedetrimental effects interventionism has on wealth creation. Nor do they comprehend what

adverse effects pseudo human rights have on society.

Sixth, the ideal at which socialists are aiming is more appealing than capitalism. The portrait of 

Page 15: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 15/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 15/20

a socialist ideal with the brush strokes of pseudo human rights is more appealing and promising

than the realistic picture of a capitalistic society. Consequently, in the marketing of ideas,

defenders of socialism have been more successful.

Conclusion

Murray Rothbard makes the daring claim that all human rights can be formulated as a variationof property rights. This analysis affirms this claim. Property rights are natural rights resting on

the twin axioms of self-ownership and the homesteading principle.

 Any human right can be deduced from property rights. In fact, there are no separate human

rights distinct from property rights. Instead, human rights are entailed in and limited by property

rights. Any alleged right that infringes property rights and jumps the boundaries set by them,

cannot be a human right. By violating property rights, the alleged right violates rights firmly

rooted in human nature. These alleged human rights that infringe on human rights are

therefore called pseudo human rights.

The distinction between property rights and pseudo human rights could not be greater.

Property rights are clearly defined, universal, coherent, abstract, general, limited, and stand for 

the rule of law. They are negative and active rights that minimize conflicts, allow for moral

space, restrict government, and foster economic growth. In contrast, pseudo human rights are

vaguely defined, situation-dependent, contradictory, specific, open for augmentation, and

contrast with the rule of law. They are positive and passive rights that breed conflict, restrict

moral responsibility, expand the role of government, and inhibit economic growth.

With regard to these distinctions, we must ask why there have been more defenders of propertyrights than pseudo human rights. The solution lies in the concomitant political systems of these

rights. Property rights are the pillars of a capitalist society. Pseudo human rights promote

socialist measures. Socialism is still the dream of many intellectuals. As such, many intellectuals

use the language of human rights to give moral weight to social welfare goals. Indeed, pseudo

human rights give intellectuals a task to work upon. They must find justifications, refine

definitions, create additional rights, and quarrel about quantity and quality of pseudo human

rights. Consequently, pseudo human rights give intellectuals a role in society. Property rights, in

contrast, are less visualizable and less academically inspiring. They restrict government and

consequently the space for government-employed intellectuals. All this explains why

intellectuals tend to be defenders of pseudo human rights and why these kinds of human rights

are a growing industry. This inflation of the human rights concept is like a cancer in the flesh of 

a capitalistic society devaluating its basis: property rights. Hopefully, this cancer can be treated

by a new inspiring liberal utopia as Hayek (1949) describes: “a liberal Utopia, . . . which seems

neither a mere defense of things as they are nor a diluted kind of socialism, but a truly liberal

radicalism.”

That being said, we are still confronted daily with disturbing images from around the world that

call for remedy. Though some might interpret a property-rights-based criterion for defininghuman rights as uncaring, we should be reminded that the distress we see in the news is

aggravated because property rights and human rights derived from them have not always been

secured. If anything, a free-market society that protects such rights will most likely flourish and

Page 16: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 16/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 16/20

have more to share with those less fortunate. A clear understanding of property rights simply

does not imply apathy about the plight of others. If anything, such an understanding is pre-

requisite for creating the appropriate social changes to address these misfortunes. Inflating the

moral currency of human rights to include advocacy of welfare rights can only add further 

injustice to those situations in which changes are sought.

References

 Alchian, Armen A. 2008. “Property Rights” In The Concise Encyclopedia of Economics. Ed.

David R. Henderson. Liberty Fund, Inc. Library of Economics and Liberty. Accessed from

http://www.econlib.org/library/Enc/PropertyRights.html> on 2008-04-08.

 Almond, Brenda. 1993. “Rights”. In A Companion to Ethics. Ed. Peter Singer, 259-269. Oxford:

Blackwell.

 Almqvist, Jessica. 2005. Human Rights, Culture and the Rule of Law . Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Bastiat, Frédéric [1850] 1998. The Law. Trans. Dean Russell, introduction by Walter E.

Williams, foreword by Sheldon Richman. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY: Foundation for Economic

Education. Accessed from http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/78 on 2008-04-14

Beetham, David. 1995. “What Future for Economic and Social Rights?” Political Studies, 43: 41-

60.

Berlin, Isaiah. 1969. “Two Concepts of Liberty.” In Four Essays of Liberty . Oxford: Oxford

University Press.

Campbell, Tom. 2004. “Collective Rights and Individual Interests.” In Law, Legal Culture and 

Politics in the Twenty First Century . Ed. Guenther Doeker-Mach and Klaus A. Ziegert, 127-147.

Stuttgart: Franz Steiner.

Charbonneau, Louis. 2008. “U.N. says Darfur dead may be 300,000 as Sudan denies.” April 22,

2008. Washington Post . Accessed from http://www.washingtonpost.com/wp-

dyn/content/article/2008/04/22/AR2008042201310.html on 2008-04-28.

Council of Europe. 1950. Convention for the Protection of Human Rights and Fundamental 

Freedoms. Accessed from http://conventions.coe.int/treaty/en/Treaties/Html/005.htm on 2008-

15-04.

Cranston, Maurice. 1973. What are Human Rights? London: Bodley Head.

DiLorenzo, Thomas J. 2004. How Capitalism Saved America: The Untold History of Our 

Country, from the Pilgrims to the Present . New York: Crown Forum.

Dugger, Celia W. 2008. “Zimbabwe Rounds Up Opposition Members and Election

Monitors.” New York Times. April 26, 2008. Accessed from

http://www.nytimes.com/2008/04/26/world/africa/26zimbabwe.html?

 _r=1&scp=2&sq=zimbabwe%20elections&st=cse&oref=slogin on 2008-04-29.

Page 17: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 17/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 17/20

Feser, Edward. 2004. Why Are Universities Dominated by the Left? Accessed from

http://www.freerepublic.com/focus/f-news/1077342/posts on 2008-04-29.

Gordon, Joy. 1998. “The Concept of Human Rights: The history and Meaning of its Politization.”

Brooklyn Journal of International Law , 23 (3): 689-791.

Hayek, F. A. 1944. The Road to Serfdom. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Hayek, F. A. [1949] 1960. “The Intellectuals and Socialism.” In The Intellectuals: A Controversal 

Portrait . Ed. George B. de Huszar, 371-84. Glencoe, IL: the Free Press.

Hayek, F.A. 1960. The Constitution of Liberty . Chicago: The University of Chicago Press.

Hayek, F.A., ed. 1963. Capitalism and the Historians. Chicago: The University of Chicago

Press.

Hayek, F. A. 1973. Law, Legislation and Liberty, Volume I: Rules and Order . Chicago, The

University of Chicago Press.

Hayek, F.A. 1976. Law, Legislation and Liberty, Volume II: The Mirage of Social Justice.

London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Jacobs, Andrew. 2008. “China Said to Arrest 100 Protesting Monks.” New York Times. April 19,

2008. Accessed from http://www.nytimes.com/2008/04/19/world/asia/19tibet.html?

 _r=3&st=cse&sq=china+tibet+human+rights&scp=3&oref=slogin&oref=slogin&oref=slogin on

2008-04-28.

Jones, Peter. 2006. “Human Rights.” In Routledge Encyclopedia of Philosophy , ed. E. Craig.London: Routledge. Accessed from http://www. Rep.routledge.com/article/S105 on 2008-04-10.

Kirzner, Israel M. 1974. “Producer, Entrepreneur, and the Right to Property.” Reason Papers: A

Journal of Inderdisciplinary Normative Studies, 1: 1-17.

Klein, Peter G. 2006. ”Why Intellectuals Still Support Socialism.” Mises.org daily article,

11/15/2006. Accessed from http://www.mises.org/story/2318 on 2008-04-14.

Kühnelt-Leddihn, Erik M. Ritter von. 1952. Liberty or Equality: The Challenge of Our Time.

Caldwell, ID: Caxton.

Lacey, Marc. 2008. “Across Globe, Empty Bellies Bring Rising Anger.” New York Times. April

18, 2008. Accessed from http://www.nytimes.com/2008/04/18/world/americas/18food.html?

 _r=1&oref=login on 2008-04-28.

Locke, John. 1824. The Works of John Locke in Nine Volumes. 12 th ed. London: Rivington. Vol.

4. Chapter: CHAPTER II.: Of the state of nature. Accessed from

http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/763/65394 on 2008-04-09 and CHAPTER V.: Of property. Accessed

from http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/763/65421 on 2008-04-09

Lord Acton, John Emerich Edward Dalberg. 1907. The History of Freedom and Other Essays,

ed. John Neville Figgis and Reginald Vere Laurence. London: Macmillan. Chapter: I: THE 

HISTORY OF FREEDOM IN ANTIQUITY 1 Accessed from

Page 18: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 18/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 18/20

http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/75/42894 on 2008-04-09.

Machan, Tibor. 1985. “Moral Myths and Basic Positive Rights,” Tulane Studies in Philosophy,

33: 35-41.

Machan, Tibor. 1992. “The Right to Private Property. Reply to Friedman.” Critical Review , 6 (1):

97-106.

Machan, Tibor. 1997. “For Individual Rights,” Modern Age, 41: 133-142.

Machan, Tibor. 2002. “The Right to Private Property. Essays in Public Policy”. Hoover 

Institution. Accessed from http://media.hoover.org/documents/epp_109b.pdf  on 2008-04-13.

Marshall, Thomas H. 1950. Citizenship and Social Class: And Other Essays. Cambridge:

Cambridge University Press.

Mises, Ludwig von. [1920] 1990. Economic Calculation in the Socialist Commonwealth. Auburn:

Ludwig von Mises Institute.

Mises, Ludwig von. [1927] 1985. Liberalism – In The Classical Tradition. 3rd ed. Trans. Ralph

Raico. Irvington-on-Hudson, NY: The Foundation for Economic Education.

Mises, Ludwig von. 2006. The Anti-Capitalist Mentality. 2nd ed. Liberty Fund.

Nickel, James. 1993. “The Human Rights to a Safe Environment,” Yale Journal of International 

Law , 18: 281-295.

Nickel, James. 2006. “Human Rights.” In Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy . Accessed fromhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/rights-human/ on 2008-04-10.

Nozick, Robert. 1986. “Why Do Intellectuals Oppose Capitalism?” In The Future of Private

Enterprise. Ed. Craig Aronoff et al. Georgia State University: Business Press.

Otto, Dianne. 1997. “Rethinking Universals: Opening Transformative Possibilities in

International Human Rights law.” Australian Year Book of International Law, 18: 1-15.

Rand, Ayn. 1964. “The Monument Builder.” In Virtue of Selfishness: A New Concept of Egoism.

New York: New American Library.

Rich, Roland. 1988. “The Rights to Development as an Emerging Human Rights.” Virignia

Journal of International Law , 23 (2): 387-423.

Rothbard, Murray N. 1974. “Egalitarianism as a Revolt Against Nature.” In Egalitarianism as a

Revolt Against Nature and Other Essays. Washington, D.C.: Libertarian Review Press.

Rothbard, Murray N. 1977. Power and Market . 2nd ed. Kansas City: Sheed Andrews and

McMeel.

Rothbard, Murray N. 1982. “Law, Property Rights, and Air Pollution.” Cato Journal , 2 (1): 55-99.

Rothbard, Murray N. 1995. “Egalitarianism and the Elites.” The Review of Austrian Economics,

8 (2): 39-57.

Page 19: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 19/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

http://www.independent.org/printer.asp? page =%2Fstudents%2Fessay%2Fessay%2Easp?id= 2341 19/20

Rothbard, Murray N. 1998. The Ethics of Liberty . 2nd ed. New York: New York University Press.

Schachter, Oscar. 1983. “Human Dignity as a Normative Concept.” American Journal of 

International Law , 77 (4): 848-54.

Schoeck, Helmut. 1987. Envy: A Theory of Social Behaviour . Indianapolis, In: Liberty Fund.

Seel, Gerhard. 2001. “How to Justify the Rights of Political Minorities.” In Human Rights in

Philosophy and Practice. Ed. Burton M. Leiser and Tom D. Campbell, 215-34. Aldershot:

 Ashgate.

Singh, Rabinder. 2001. “The Place of the Human Rights Act in a Democratic Society”.

Understand Human Rights Principles. (The Justice Series: Putting Rights into Practice). Ed.

Peck, Lib. et al. 179-210. Oxford: Hart Publishing.

Smith, Adam. [1776] 1904. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations by 

 Adam Smith, edited with an Introduction, Notes, Marginal Summary and an Enlarged Index by 

Edwin Cannan. London: Methuen. Accessed from http://oll.libertyfund.org/title/171 on 2008-04-

14.

Sterba, James. 2001. “Defending Women´s Rights Internationally.” In Human Rights in

Philosophy and Practice. Ed. Burton M. Leiser and Tom D. Campbell, 317-32. Aldershot:

 Ashgate.

Stoilov, Yanaki B. 2001. “Are Human Rights Universal?” In Human Rights in Philosophy and 

Practice. Ed. Burton M. Leiser and Tom D. Campbell, 87-104. Aldershot: Ashgate.

Swan, Peter D. 2001. “Global Ecological Citizenship and Human Rights.” In Human Rights in

Philosophy and Practice. Ed. Burton M. Leiser and Tom D. Campbell, 459-76. Aldershot:

 Ashgate.

United Kingdom Parliament. 1998. Human Rights Act . Accessed from

http://www.statutelaw.gov.uk/content.aspx?activeTextDocId=1851003 on 2008-04-15.

United Nations General Assembly. 1948. Universal Declaration of Human Rights. Accessed

from http://www.un.org/rights/50/decla.htm on 2008-04-15.

United Nations General Assembly. 1966a. International Convenant on Civil and Political Rights.

 Accessed from http://www.bayefsky.com/treaties/ccpr.php on 2008-04-15.

United Nations General Assembly. 1966b. International Convenant on Economic, Social and 

Cultural Rights. Accessed from http://www.bayefsky.com/treaties/cescr.php on 2008-04-15.

Footnotes

[1] Rand, The Virtue of Selfishness, p. 91.

[2] Mises, Liberalism – In the Classical Tradition, p. 19.

[3] See Lacey (2008).

Page 20: Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

7/27/2019 Human Rights Inflation and Property Rights Devaluation

http://slidepdf.com/reader/full/human-rights-inflation-and-property-rights-devaluation 20/20

10.2.2014 Printer Friendly Version

[4] See Jacobs (2008).

[5] See Dugger (2008).

[6] See Charbonneau (2008). U.N. says Darfur dead may be 300,000 as Sudan denies.

[7] Property rights can be defined as the exclusive authority over an object. They imply a right

to use the object, to its services and the right to transfer it to other persons (Alchian, 2008).

[8] The alternative to self-ownership is slavery. Slavery, however, does not fulfill the

universalization test of an ethical theory. There would be different rules for different people, as

some people would be masters and others would be slaves. Therefore, slavery is unethical and

must be held as a violation of natural law.

[9] For a libertarian account of the natural law meaning of just punishment, see Rothbard

(1998).

[10] Government infringes on private property by regulations, expropriations, forced labor, or 

taxation. Classical liberals maintain that taxation in order to fulfill government’s function of 

protecting private property would be legitimate. Libertarian anarchists regard any taxation as a

violation of property rights.

[11] For the difference between positive and negative liberty see Berlin (1969).

[12] Almqvist defines cultural equipment as skills (e.g. how to write a motion), tools (e.g.

computer) and know-how (e.g. computer literacy).

[13] So called public property rights do not resolve conflicts very well. The existence of publicstreets, jobs or television lead to conflicts about their uses. Shall the streets be used by

immigrants or by a demonstration for animal rights? However, private property rights, which we

mean in this article as general property rights, solve those problems.

[14] For an analysis of this legend see Hayek (1963).

[15] See Schoeck (1987) for the importance of envy for the human race.

Philipp Bagus, is a professor at Rey Juan Carlos University. He is also a past winner of The

Sir John M. Templeton Fellowships Essay Contest .