Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eighteenth-Century Origins of the Concept of Scientific Revolution

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    1/33

    The Eighteenth-Century Origins of the Concept of Scientific RevolutionAuthor(s): I. Bernard CohenSource: Journal of the History of Ideas, Vol. 37, No. 2 (Apr. - Jun., 1976), pp. 257-288Published by: University of Pennsylvania PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2708824.

    Accessed: 21/06/2014 02:26

    Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at.http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

    .JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of

    content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms

    of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

    .

    University of Pennsylvania Pressis collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to

    Journal of the History of Ideas.

    http://www.jstor.org

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upennhttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2708824?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/stable/2708824?origin=JSTOR-pdfhttp://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=upenn
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    2/33

    THE EIGHTEENTH-CENTURY

    ORIGINS

    OF THE CONCEPT

    OF SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION1

    BY I. BERNARD OHEN

    Many

    historians of

    science,

    like their fellow

    general

    historians,

    believe that

    the

    concept

    of revolution

    in

    science

    is of

    fairly

    recent

    origin,

    and that

    it

    has

    been

    superimposed

    anachronously-and

    even

    harshly-on

    events

    of

    the

    past.2

    In

    fact,

    however,

    for

    some

    three

    centuries there

    has been a more

    or less unbroken tradition

    of

    viewing

    scientific change as a sequence of revolutions. In the eighteenth century,

    when this tradition

    appears

    to

    have

    taken

    its first

    rise,

    there was

    still

    some confusion

    and

    ambiguity

    about

    the sense

    of the word "revolution":

    in

    relation

    not

    only

    to science

    but to

    political

    events.

    Although

    "revolu-

    tion"

    came

    into

    general

    usage during

    the

    eighteenth

    century

    to

    denote a

    breach

    of

    continuity

    or a secular

    change

    of real

    magnitude,

    there also

    remained

    current

    the older sense

    of "revolution" as

    a

    cyclical

    phenomenon,

    a

    continuous

    sequence

    of ebb

    and

    flow,

    a

    kind of circula-

    'This

    article,

    based

    on

    research

    supported by

    a

    grant

    from the

    Spencer

    Foundation,

    is

    taken

    from a

    larger

    and

    more

    general

    survey

    of

    the

    origins

    and

    development

    of the

    concept

    and

    name,

    "scientific

    revolution,"

    presented

    at the

    semicentennial

    meeting

    of

    the

    History

    of Science

    Society

    (Oct.

    1974)

    and-in

    a somewhat altered

    version-at the

    Boston

    Colloquium

    for the

    Philosophy

    of Science

    (Feb. 1975).

    2

    In the

    past

    decade or

    more,

    the

    discussions

    of

    revolutions

    in

    science have

    pivoted

    on

    Thomas

    S. Kuhn's bold

    and

    challenging

    tract,

    The Structure

    of

    Scientific

    Revolutions

    (Chicago,

    1962;

    also issued as vol.

    2 of the

    International

    Encyclopedia

    of

    Unified

    Science;

    2nd

    ed.,

    enlarged,

    1970).

    For a

    response

    to Kuhn's

    analysis,

    see Imre Lakatos

    and Alan

    Musgrave

    (eds.),

    Criticism and

    the Growth

    of

    Knowledge

    (Cambridge,

    1970),

    comprising

    a

    primary

    paper by

    T.

    S.

    Kuhn,

    followed

    by

    critical discussions

    by

    J.

    W.

    N.

    Watkins,

    S. E.

    Toulmin,

    L. Pearce

    Williams,

    K.

    R.

    Popper,

    Margaret

    Masterman,

    I.

    Lakatos,

    P.

    K.

    Feyerabend,

    plus

    a final

    "Reflections on

    my

    Critics"

    by

    Kuhn.

    Among

    many

    reviews

    and

    review

    articles,

    particular

    attention

    may

    be called to those

    by

    Gerd

    Buchdahl,

    Dudley

    Shapere,

    and Israel

    Scheffler. The

    propriety

    of

    using

    the word and

    concept

    of

    "revolution"

    in relation

    to science

    is

    discussed

    by Stephen

    E.

    Toulmin,

    in the

    course

    of a

    lengthy

    historical

    narrative

    of,

    and

    critique

    upon,

    Kuhn's

    views,

    in

    Human

    Understanding

    (Princeton,

    1972),

    I, 100-30,

    esp.

    117-18.

    The reaction to

    Kuhn's thesis

    of social dynamics of scientific change in terms of a sequence of revolutions (alternating

    with what he calls

    "normal

    science")

    has

    been either

    to

    apply

    or

    to

    challenge

    some fea-

    tures of

    his

    analysis,

    or to

    question

    the

    meaning

    (or

    meanings)

    of the technical terms

    he

    uses,

    or

    to

    raise

    doubts as

    to the

    propriety

    of

    using

    the

    concept

    of revolution

    in relation

    to scientific

    change.

    Thus

    the

    secondary

    literature on the

    philosophy

    and

    history

    of

    science

    has

    become saturated

    with books and articles

    using

    the word "revolution" in

    al-

    most

    every possible

    context,

    and

    dealing

    with

    almost

    every aspect

    of

    scientific

    revolu-

    tions,

    save one:

    there has been

    no

    adequate study

    of what the

    particular

    uses

    of this

    word and

    concept may

    have

    been

    in

    successive

    past ages.

    (But

    see

    note

    19

    infra.)

    257

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    3/33

    258

    I.

    BERNARD

    COHEN

    tion

    and

    return,

    or

    a

    repetition.3

    After

    1789,

    the new

    meaning

    came

    to

    predominate

    and,

    ever

    since,

    "revolution"

    has

    commonly implied

    a

    radical change and a departure from traditional or accepted modes of

    thought,

    belief,

    action,

    social

    behavior,

    or

    political

    or social

    organiza-

    tion.

    Thus

    in

    early

    modern

    times there

    occurred a double transforma-

    tion of "revolution"

    and

    the

    concept

    for

    which it is the name.

    First,

    a

    scientific term,

    taken

    from

    astronomy

    and

    geometry,

    came to be

    ap-

    plied

    to

    a

    general

    range

    of

    social,

    political,

    economic,

    and

    intellectual or

    cultural

    activities;

    and, second,

    in

    this

    usage

    the term

    gained

    a

    new

    meaning

    that was

    radically

    different

    from-if not

    diametrically opposite

    to-the original and strict etymological sense of "revolution" (revolu-

    tion,

    revoluzione),

    which is

    derived

    from

    the mediaeval Latin

    revolutio,

    a

    rolling

    back or

    a

    return,

    usually

    with

    an

    implied

    sense

    of

    revolving

    in

    time.4

    During

    the

    eighteenth

    century,

    the

    point

    of

    view

    emerged

    that

    scientific

    change

    is

    characterized

    by

    an

    analog

    of

    the

    revolutions

    that

    alter

    the

    forms

    of

    society

    and

    the

    political

    affairs of the state. Whereas

    earlier,

    science had contributed

    "revolution" to the discourse

    of

    social

    3An

    example

    is Colin Maclaurin:

    An Account

    of

    Isaac

    Newton's

    Philosophical

    Dis-

    coveries

    (London, 1748);

    a facsimile

    edition,

    with an introduction

    by

    L. L. Laudan

    (New

    York,

    1968).

    Here

    it

    is said

    (39)

    to be "not worth

    while

    ... to

    trace

    the

    history

    of

    learn-

    ing

    thro' its various

    revolutions

    in

    the later

    ages."

    Maclaurin also referred

    to

    a

    com-

    parison

    made

    by

    Aristotle of the

    "revolutions

    of

    learning"

    and

    "the

    rising

    and

    setting

    of

    the

    stars."

    Maclaurin

    obviously

    had

    in

    mind a

    cyclical

    phenomenon,

    or

    ebb and flow. In

    another

    passage

    (ibid.,

    42),

    he referred to

    the

    return

    of

    learning

    to the "western

    parts

    of

    Europe,"

    observing

    that "the

    period

    which commenced

    upon

    the revolution we

    have

    mentioned,

    has

    already

    continued some hundred

    years."

    He also wrote that with

    the

    dis-

    pelling

    of the

    cloud of mediaeval

    darkness,

    "the liberal arts

    and sciences

    were

    restored,

    and none of them has

    gained

    more

    by

    this

    happy

    revolution

    than natural

    philosophy"

    (ibid., 41).

    4Some

    historical studies of the

    concept

    and name

    of

    "revolution" are: Felix

    Gilbert,

    "Revolution,"

    Dictionary of

    the

    History of

    Ideas,

    ed.

    Philip

    P.

    Wiener,

    5

    vols.

    (New

    York,

    1973),

    IV,

    152-67;

    Karl

    Griewank,

    Der

    neuzeitliche

    Revolutionsbegriff

    En-

    stehung

    und

    Entwicklung

    (Weimar, 1955);

    Arthur

    Hatto,

    "Revolution:

    An

    Enquiry

    into

    the Usefulness

    of an

    Historical

    Term,"

    Mind,

    58

    (1949),

    495-517;

    Melvin J.

    Lasky,

    "The

    Birth of a

    Metaphor.

    On the

    Origins

    of

    Utopia

    &

    Revolution,"

    Encounter,

    34

    (Feb. 1970), 35-45, 34 (Mar. 1970), 30-42; Eugen Rosenstock [=Rosenstock-Huessy],

    "Revolution

    als

    politische Begriff

    in

    der

    Neuzeit,"

    Abhandlungen

    der Schlesischen

    Gesellschaft fur

    vaterlandische

    Cultur

    (Geisteswissenschaftliche Reihe),

    5. Heft:

    "Festgabe

    der rechts-

    und

    staatswissenschaftlichen

    Fakultat

    in

    Breslau

    fur

    Paul Heil-

    born

    zum 70.

    Geburtstag

    6. Februar 1931"

    (Breslau,

    1931),

    83-124,

    of which the main

    points

    are

    given

    in

    summary

    in Hatto's

    article;

    Vernon

    F.

    Snow,

    "The

    Concept

    of

    Revolution

    in

    Seventeenth-Century England,"

    The Historical

    Journal,

    5

    (1962),

    167-74.

    Useful as

    first

    guides

    to the

    history

    and successive

    meanings

    of

    "revolution"

    are E.

    Lit-

    tr6,

    Dictionnaire

    de

    la

    languefrancaise,

    4

    vols.

    and

    suppl.

    (Paris, 1881-83),

    and A

    New

    English Dictionary

    on Historical

    Principles,

    ed. James A. H.

    Murray,

    Henry Bradley,

    W. A.

    Craigie,

    C. T.

    Onions,

    and reissued as The

    Oxford English Dictionary,

    12 vols.

    and

    suppl.

    (Oxford,

    1933).

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    4/33

    CONCEPT OF SCIENTIFIC

    REVOLUTION

    259

    and

    political

    change,

    now

    social and

    political thought

    gave

    back to

    science the

    concept

    of revolution

    in the

    newly

    established

    sense,

    no

    longer as a term serving in the scientific explanation of natural

    phenomena,

    but

    rather an

    expression

    to

    be used

    in

    the

    social

    or

    in-

    tellectual

    explanation

    of scientific

    change

    itself-now visualized as a

    series

    of secular

    discontinuities of

    such

    magnitude

    as

    to

    constitute defi-

    nite breaks with the

    past.

    The

    rejection

    of

    the

    older and more traditional

    opinions

    in

    which

    scientific

    change

    was seen as a

    cyclical

    continuous

    process,

    and

    the

    rise of the

    doctrine that science

    progresses by

    radical

    revolutions

    has

    occurred

    by degrees

    ever since

    the

    opening

    years

    of

    the

    eighteenth century, and has been continuously influenced by the

    development

    of

    concepts

    and theories of

    political

    and social

    (and

    cultural)

    revolution.

    Accordingly,

    an

    understanding

    of the

    rise of the

    idea of

    revolutions

    in

    science

    (and

    of

    the existence of

    the Scientific

    Revolution)

    requires

    some

    knowledge

    of the

    general

    history

    of the con-

    cept

    and name

    "revolution."6

    The

    history

    of the

    idea

    of

    revolution

    in

    the sciences

    is of

    real

    im-

    portance

    for

    our

    understanding

    of

    the

    development

    of the sciences. For

    example,

    we

    today

    conceive

    Galileo

    to have been a

    revolutionary

    figure

    and

    write

    about

    the "intellectual revolution" that he

    wrought;

    but did he

    consider

    himself to have been a

    revolutionary?7

    Did Newton? When

    did

    the value

    of

    progress

    become linked

    to the

    concept

    of

    change

    by

    revolu-

    tion? Such

    questions

    illuminate the nature

    of scientific

    change

    by

    mak-

    5

    An

    example

    of the

    ways

    in which

    political

    and social

    events

    may

    affect the

    image

    of

    revolution

    in

    science

    occurs in the

    acceptance

    by

    today's

    scholars

    of the

    conception

    that

    the Scientific

    Revolution was

    not

    an

    event or a set of events that occurred

    in

    a narrow

    compass

    of

    time

    (as

    was the case for the American

    and French

    Revolutions),

    but

    may

    have lasted

    through

    two or even three centuries. Such a notion of a continuing revolution

    appears

    to have been one

    of the innovative features

    of the Russian

    Revolution,

    which

    went so far as

    to reckon the calendar

    in

    years

    of

    the

    Revolution,

    rather than

    years

    since

    the

    Revolution;

    so that the

    revolution itself became an

    era. Students of

    revolution

    point

    out that all

    previous

    revolutions had been

    (or

    had been conceived

    as)

    events in a

    limited

    time-span

    that

    produced

    a

    change-violent,

    dramatic,

    even

    cataclysmic-or

    a

    rapid

    series

    of such

    events.

    The

    acceptable

    title

    of

    a

    book such

    as A. R.

    Hall's

    The

    Scientific

    Revolution

    1500-1800

    (London, 1954),

    thus reflects

    a

    general

    point

    of view

    concerning

    revolutions that

    has become

    common-place

    in recent

    decades,

    but would

    itself have been

    revolutionary a century ago. Eugen Rosenstock has discussed the ways in which such

    phrases

    used

    in

    Russia

    as

    "the next two

    decades

    of the Revolution"

    imply

    an

    institu-

    tionalizing

    of the

    revolution;

    cf.

    loc.

    cit.,

    84.

    6This relation

    of the

    changing

    concept

    of revolution

    (in

    the

    political,

    social,

    and

    eco-

    nomic

    domains)

    to the successive

    ways

    in which

    scientists,

    philosophers,

    and

    historians

    of science have

    conceived the so-called

    Scientific Revolution

    (and

    revolutions

    in

    science)

    is

    one

    of the main themes

    of

    a

    more

    general inquiry

    I

    have undertaken

    into the

    origins

    and

    history

    of

    the

    concept

    of revolution in science. The results shall

    eventually

    be

    published

    in

    book

    form

    by

    Science

    History

    Publications,

    a

    division

    of

    Neale Watson

    Academic

    Publications,

    New York.

    7Such a question has both historical and philosophical components. Historical re-

    search tells us that

    the noun

    "revolutionary"

    had

    not

    yet

    come into

    being,

    and that

    at

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    5/33

    260

    I.

    BERNARD COHEN

    ing precise

    the scientist's

    image

    of

    himself,

    which is

    directly

    related to

    the

    public

    image

    of the

    scientist,

    a factor

    in

    the

    type

    of

    creative indi-

    vidual attracted to the pursuit of science.8 In some of his scientific work,

    notably

    in

    physics,

    Newton saw

    himself

    as

    only

    rediscovering

    some of

    the

    knowledge

    of

    nature

    and

    of her laws

    that had

    been current

    among

    certain

    ancient

    sages;9

    but

    in

    mathematics he was so

    jealous

    of

    his

    pro-

    prietary rights

    in

    the invention of

    the

    calculus

    that

    he

    concluded that

    Leibniz could have

    produced

    similar

    results

    only by plagiarism

    from

    the

    Newton

    mathematical

    manuscripts

    then

    in

    circulation.

    Furthermore,

    the

    present enquiry

    clarifies

    such

    fundamental historical issues as the

    special defining features of the Newtonian revolution in science by

    enabling

    us

    to

    distinguish

    between

    what

    Newton's

    contemporaries

    and

    immediate successors held

    to

    be his

    signal

    achievement

    and

    what seems

    to

    us-some two

    and

    a half centuries

    later-to have been

    so remarkable

    and

    innovatory

    in

    Newtonian science.10

    In

    recent

    discussions,

    historians

    and

    philosophers

    have

    expressed

    doubts as to whether

    it

    is

    proper

    to

    use

    "revolution"

    to

    describe

    scientific

    change,

    and whether in

    any

    event

    there

    ever

    was a Scientific

    Revolution;l1

    yet

    in

    all

    writings

    on this

    sub-

    ject

    with

    which

    I

    am

    familiar,

    the

    question

    is

    never

    raised as

    to

    whether

    the

    scientists

    allegedly participating

    in

    such

    supposed

    revolutions

    may

    or

    may

    not

    have

    considered themselves to be

    active

    in

    a

    revolution or to

    have

    been

    immediate

    heirs to

    a revolution.

    For

    these and other

    reasons,

    the

    present

    enquiry may

    transcend the value of

    a

    mere

    chronicle

    of

    an

    idea,

    and

    shed some illumination on

    the

    nature

    of science

    and

    of

    scienti-

    fic

    change

    in

    the

    age

    of

    Newton.

    that time

    the

    word

    "revolution" had not

    yet

    been

    applied

    to

    the

    description

    of scientific

    change.

    But there is an

    open

    philosophical question

    as to whether the

    foregoing

    his-

    torical

    fact

    would

    actually

    have

    inhibited Galileo from so

    considering

    himself.

    8This

    topic

    is

    explored

    in

    the

    work

    cited

    in

    note

    6

    supra.

    90n this

    aspect

    of

    Newton's

    thought

    see J.

    E.

    McGuire

    and P. M.

    Rattansi,

    "Newton

    and

    the

    'Pipes

    of

    Pan',"

    Notes

    and

    Records

    of

    the

    Royal Society of

    London,

    21

    (1966),

    108-43;

    I. B.

    Cohen,

    "'Quantum

    in

    se

    est': Newton's

    Concept

    of

    Inertia

    in

    Relation to

    Descartes

    and

    Lucretius,"

    ibid.,

    19

    (1964),

    131-55.

    "?This

    question

    is discussed

    in

    my

    forthcoming

    book,

    The Newtonian Revolution in

    Science,

    with

    Illustrations

    of

    the

    Transformation of

    Scientific

    Ideas

    (Cambridge:

    at

    the

    University Press, to be publishedin 1977).

    11The Scientific

    Revolution

    is the

    name

    commonly

    given

    today

    to

    the

    particular

    scientific

    revolution

    (or

    set

    of

    revolutions)

    of

    the

    sixteenth

    and seventeenth

    centuries,

    by

    means

    of

    which our modern

    science

    was

    established,

    associated

    with such

    figures

    as

    Copernicus

    and

    Vesalius,

    Bacon and

    Descartes,

    Galileo

    and

    Kepler,

    Harvey, Huygens,

    and

    Newton.

    In

    the

    eighteenth century,

    and

    in

    the

    seventeenth

    century,

    a

    revolution was

    conceived

    as a

    single

    event

    (e.g.,

    the

    Glorious

    Revolution)

    or

    a

    composite

    event

    (e.g.,

    the

    French

    Revolution).

    Thus

    it

    is

    hardly

    likely

    that

    any analyst

    would then

    have

    thought

    of

    a

    revolution

    in

    science

    extending

    over

    more

    than

    a

    century

    of

    time,

    say

    from

    Copernicus

    (1543)

    to

    Newton

    (1687).

    The

    writers on science

    in

    the

    eighteenth

    century developed

    the

    notion of revolutionary scientific events, comparable to political events and usually

    associated with

    the

    work

    of

    a

    single

    individual:

    Copernicus,

    Descartes,

    Newton. Never-

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    6/33

    CONCEPT

    OF

    SCIENTIFIC

    REVOLUTION

    261

    During

    most

    of

    the

    eighteenth

    century-as

    in the

    preceding

    centuries-the

    primary signification

    of "revolution"

    was

    astronomical,

    and thus-associatively or derivatively-astrological. The revolutions

    observed

    in

    the diurnal

    motion

    of the heavens12and

    the

    apparent

    diurnal

    and orbital

    motions of

    the

    "planetary"

    bodies

    (or

    of their

    spheres)

    had

    been recorded

    over centuries

    in the

    works

    of

    Chaucer,

    Dante,

    Alfra-

    ganus

    (who

    was

    a

    major

    source of astronomical

    knowledge

    for

    Dante),

    Messahala,

    Sacrobosco,

    and countless

    others.

    This term

    appears boldly

    in

    the title of

    Copernicus's

    celebrated

    book,

    De revolutionibus

    orbium

    coelestium

    (1543),

    and

    it occurs

    not

    infrequently

    in

    Galileo's

    Dialogue

    concerning

    the Two

    Chief

    World

    Systems.13

    It

    may

    be found

    in

    almanacs and

    in

    such

    popular

    works as Leurechon's

    La Recreation

    mathematique

    (which

    was

    Englished

    by

    William

    Oughtred),

    and

    in

    Vincent

    Wing's

    popular

    compendiums

    of

    astronomy

    and

    astrology

    theless,

    there

    are also

    some

    implications

    of

    larger-scale

    revolutions

    in

    science

    than

    would

    be

    represented by

    any

    one treatise

    or a

    single

    discovery

    or

    invention,

    however

    monumental.

    The historian

    of

    mathematics,

    Montucla,

    thus wrote of

    "l'heureuse revo-

    lution"

    that,

    soon

    after

    Copernicus,

    "6prouva

    la

    philosophie."

    Bailly,

    in his

    history

    of

    astronomy, though asserting that Newton's Principia was to create a "revolution dans

    l'astronomie,"

    observed

    that this revolution

    "ne

    se

    fit

    pas

    tout-a-coup."

    Bailly,

    as

    we

    shall see

    below,

    extended

    the

    revolutionary concept

    to

    a

    series

    of

    events

    that could

    extend

    over the

    greater

    part

    of a

    century, including

    the

    stage

    of destruction

    of a

    received

    system

    as a

    necessary prior

    condition

    for the

    construction

    and

    acceptance

    of a new one.

    For him Descartes did

    not achieve

    revolutionary

    status,

    although

    he was

    of the

    utmost

    importance

    in

    preparing

    the

    Newtonian revolution

    to come.

    Furthermore,

    in

    the

    eighteenth

    century,

    there

    seems to have been

    a

    widely

    held

    opinion

    that

    the

    special

    fea-

    tures of the

    science that

    emerged

    between

    Copernicus

    and

    Newton

    did not

    merely

    constitute an

    "improvement"

    of ancient

    knowledge,

    but were

    revolutionary,

    in the

    sense

    of being new and unprecedented. The inaugural century of modern science, in other

    words,

    had

    produced

    the foundation

    for the

    future scientific

    revolutions

    and

    for those

    that had

    occurred

    in

    the

    eighteenth

    century.

    In the

    post-Principia

    decades,

    the events

    of

    the

    primary

    century

    of

    revolution

    were not

    called

    "the

    Scientific

    Revolution,"

    as

    is

    done

    today,

    but this distinction

    between

    the

    conceptions

    of that era

    and of

    ours

    may

    have less

    real fundamental

    difference

    than

    may

    at

    first

    sight appear.

    12Throughout

    most of

    modern times

    there has

    not been a clear distinction

    between

    revolution and

    rotation,

    such as is

    generally

    made

    today:

    rotation

    being

    the

    turning

    of a

    body

    about an axis and

    revolution

    the

    motion

    of a

    body

    in an orbit. In the case of

    the

    heavenly bodies,

    the

    planets

    revolve about

    the

    sun while

    rotating

    on their axes. But

    their

    revolutions

    would

    actually

    be rotations

    if

    the

    planets

    were conceived

    to

    be

    attached

    to

    large

    rotating

    spheres.

    Hence

    there

    is a lack

    of

    clarity

    in the

    title

    of

    Copernicus's

    De

    revolutionibus

    orbium

    coelestium

    (1543),

    since the

    heavenly spheres

    in

    question

    are

    presumably

    not the

    planets

    but the

    rotating

    spheres

    that

    carry

    the

    planets

    around

    the

    sun

    in

    their revolutions.

    The

    two

    words are used somewhat

    interchangeably

    in

    Newton's

    Principia

    (1687).

    And even

    today

    we still refer

    to

    a solid

    generated

    by

    the rotation

    of a

    plane

    figure

    about

    an axis

    in that

    plane

    as a

    "solid

    of revolution."

    '3The

    Dialogo

    sopra

    i

    due

    massimi

    sistemi

    (Florence,

    1632),

    was

    published

    in an

    English

    version in 1661.

    A

    facsimile

    of the latter was

    published

    in 1967

    by

    Dawsons

    of

    Pall Mall (London) and Zeitlin and Ver Brugge (Los Angeles), with an introduction by

    Stillman Drake.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    7/33

    262

    I. BERNARD

    COHEN

    (1651,

    1669)

    and Streete's

    Astronomia

    Carolina

    (1661,

    1663,

    1710),

    from

    which the

    youthful

    Newton

    recorded

    Kepler's

    third law.

    In the late Middle Ages, "revolution" came to signify not only the

    moving

    of

    a

    celestial

    body throughout

    a

    complete

    closed orbit

    (or

    the

    time in which the

    circuit of

    the

    orbit

    is

    completed),

    but also

    any turning

    or

    rolling

    back or

    around-ranging

    from

    the

    circular

    turning

    of

    a

    wheel

    to

    the

    figurative

    sense

    of

    turning

    over

    in the

    mind

    or

    considering.

    By

    the

    time of

    the

    Renaissance,

    "revolutions"

    had a

    wider

    significa-

    tion-including

    any

    periodical

    (or quasiperiodical)

    occurrences,

    and

    eventually

    any

    group

    of

    phenomena

    that

    went

    through

    an ordered set

    of

    stages-a cycle (in the sense of "coming full circle").14Even the rise and

    fall of

    civilizations,

    or of

    culture,

    as a kind

    of tidal ebb

    and

    flow,

    was

    called

    a revolution.

    All

    of these

    usages

    are

    obviously

    linked

    to the

    primary

    sense

    in

    which

    this word occurs

    in

    astronomy

    and

    geometry.

    It

    shall

    be seen

    below how these several

    meanings

    were

    applied

    to science

    and the sciences

    during

    the Scientific Revolution.

    One

    possible

    link between the

    original

    cyclical

    meaning

    and

    today's

    common

    usage

    of "revolution"-for

    a

    "complete change

    of

    affairs"

    or

    a

    "reversal

    of

    conditions,"

    an

    overthrowing (usually accompanied by

    vio-

    lence)

    of established

    government

    or

    society

    or institutions-lies

    in

    the

    close

    association

    of a

    cyclical "turning-over"

    and a secular

    "overturn-

    ing."

    Today,

    the associated

    verb

    used

    to denote

    cyclical phenomena

    is

    "revolve";

    whereas

    the

    verb "revolt"

    implies

    an

    uprising against

    the

    political

    state

    or social

    order.

    Both "revolve" and "revolt"

    come

    from

    the same

    verb:

    revolvere,

    revolutus.

    In

    the

    eighteenth

    century, prior

    to

    1789,

    these two

    distinct

    and

    very

    different senses

    of "revolution"

    are

    apt

    to occur

    together

    in

    discussions of

    history

    and

    politics

    as

    well as the

    course

    of

    development

    in

    literature,

    the

    arts,

    and

    the sciences.

    It

    is,

    ac-

    cordingly,

    not

    always

    a

    simple

    task to discover

    whether a

    given

    eighteenth-century

    author

    may

    have had

    in

    mind a

    cyclical

    return

    (an

    ebb

    and

    flow)

    or a secular

    change

    of a

    significant

    magnitude

    (often,

    but

    not

    necessarily,

    accompanied

    by violence).

    This

    ambiguity

    was

    particu-

    larly

    a

    feature of the

    years

    between

    the

    English

    revolutions

    of the

    seventeenth

    century

    and the American

    and

    French revolutions-the

    era

    '4See

    Arthur

    Hatto,

    "Revolution

    . ."

    (1949,

    cited

    in note 4

    supra).

    A

    cyclical

    view

    of

    history

    was

    propounded

    in

    antiquity by

    Plato and

    Polybius,

    and

    discussed

    by

    Cicero.

    A

    major

    modern

    cyclical

    concept

    of

    history

    occurs

    in Giambattista

    Vico's

    Scienza

    nuova

    (1725);

    see

    The

    New Science

    of

    Giambattista

    Vico,

    revised

    translation

    of the

    third

    edi-

    tion

    (1744) by

    Thomas

    G.

    Bergin

    and Max

    H. Fisch

    (Ithaca, 1968). Among

    the

    many

    works on

    cycles, particular

    attention

    may

    be

    called

    to Mircea

    Eliade,

    The

    Myth of

    the

    Eternal

    Return,

    trans. from

    the French

    by

    Willard R. Trask

    (Princeton,

    1954,

    1965);

    Stephen

    G.

    Brush,

    "The

    Development

    of

    the

    Kinetic

    Theory

    of Gases.

    VIII.

    Random-

    ness and

    Irreversibility,"

    Archive

    for

    History of

    Exact

    Sciences,

    12

    (1974),

    1-88,

    esp.

    ?

    7, "The Recurrence Paradox," 67-77; Abel Rey, Le retour eternel et la philosophie de

    la

    physique

    (Paris, 1927).

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    8/33

    CONCEPT

    OF SCIENTIFIC

    REVOLUTION

    263

    of the Newtonian

    revolution

    in science

    and

    of the

    emergence

    of the

    con-

    cept

    of revolution

    as a mode

    of scientific

    change.

    There is one term, however, whose usage generally enables

    the

    modern

    (i.e.,

    post-1789)

    reader to

    distinguish

    between

    the two

    senses of

    "revolution,"

    that

    is,

    the use

    of the word

    "epoch."

    Thus

    there

    is no am-

    biguity

    whatsoever

    in

    Alexis

    Clairaut's

    blunt

    assertion

    in 1747:

    "Le

    fameux

    livre des

    Principes

    mathematiques

    de la

    Philosophie

    naturelle

    [de

    Newton]

    a ete

    l'epoque

    d'une

    grande

    revolution

    dans la

    Physique."15

    Here

    "epoch"

    is

    not

    used

    in

    the

    presently

    current

    meaning

    of an

    era

    or

    an

    age

    (the

    primary

    sense in American

    English),

    but

    rather

    signifies

    an

    event that

    inaugurates

    an

    age

    or

    that

    is

    the initial

    or

    major

    occurrence

    of or

    in

    a

    revolution:

    the

    beginning

    of a new

    era.

    Often,

    in the

    late

    seventeenth

    and

    in the

    eighteenth

    century,

    this word

    appears

    in its

    late

    Latin form

    as

    epocha,

    in

    historical

    and

    political

    writings

    and

    in

    scientific

    works.16

    The sixteenth

    century

    knew no

    full-scale or national

    revolutions

    in

    the

    sense

    in which

    we use

    the

    word

    today

    in

    social

    and

    political

    contexts;

    but the seventeenth

    century

    was

    witness to the Glorious

    Revolution

    (1688)17

    and to an

    earlier series

    of

    events and

    political

    and social

    move-

    15Alexis-Claude

    Clairaut:

    "Du

    systeme

    du

    monde,

    dans

    les

    principes

    de la

    gravitation

    universelle,"

    Suite

    des

    memoires

    de

    mathematique,

    et

    dephysique,

    tires des

    registres

    de

    l'Academie

    Royale

    des Sciences

    de l'annee

    M.DCCXL

    V

    (Amsterdam,

    1754),

    II,

    465;

    Clairaut's

    paper

    was

    read

    "a

    l'Assemble

    publique

    du 15

    Nov.

    1747."

    16This is

    still the

    first definition

    of

    "epoch"

    in British

    and French

    dictionaries:

    an

    event that

    begins

    an

    era

    in

    history,

    in

    life,

    or in science.

    It is thus

    closely

    akin to

    "epoch-

    making."

    On

    "epoch,"

    see

    Bossuet's

    Discours

    sur l'histoire

    universelle,

    "Dessein

    general

    de

    cet

    ouvrage"

    (Edition

    augmentee

    des nouvelles

    additions

    et des variantes

    de

    texte, Paris,

    1823),

    I,

    5-6.

    '7The primary image of revolution in the eighteenth century was The Glorious Revo-

    lution,

    cited in

    the

    general

    article

    on

    "Revolution"

    in the Diderot-d'Alembert

    Ency-

    clopedie,

    and

    in fact the chief

    example

    there

    given.

    The

    Glorious

    Revolution

    grew

    greater

    and

    greater

    in

    importance

    in the

    development

    of the

    concept

    of revolution

    up

    to

    1789,

    as

    it

    gradually

    became

    evident to

    both

    Englishmen

    and Continentals

    that

    there

    had

    been

    a

    revolution

    in

    England,

    possibly

    the first true

    revolution

    in the

    modern era.

    In

    Samuel

    Johnson's

    Dictionary

    of

    the

    English

    Language

    (1755),

    this revolution

    appears

    in

    the third definition

    of

    "revolution":

    "Change

    in

    the state of a

    government

    or

    country.

    It

    is

    used

    among

    us .

    .

    . for the

    change

    produced

    by

    the admission

    of

    king

    William

    and

    queen Mary."

    The Glorious

    Revolution

    may

    not seem as

    revolutionary

    to us-with

    our

    outlook

    so determined

    by

    such

    greater

    cataclysms

    as the

    French,

    Russian,

    and

    Chinese

    revolutions-as

    it

    did

    to the men

    and women

    of the

    eighteenth

    century.

    But to thinkers

    of so different

    a

    political

    stripe

    as

    Joseph

    Priestley

    and

    David

    Hume,

    it was indeed

    a

    revolution,

    and

    a rather

    glorious

    one

    at that. In

    Priestley's judgment,

    "the most

    im-

    portant period

    in our

    history

    is that of the revolution

    under

    king

    William.

    Then

    it was

    that

    our

    constitution,

    after

    many

    fluctuations,

    and

    frequent

    struggles

    for

    power by

    the

    different

    members

    of it

    (several

    of them

    attended

    with

    vast effusion of

    blood),

    was

    finally

    settled.

    A revolution

    so

    remarkable,

    and attended

    with such

    happy

    consequences,

    had

    perhaps

    no

    parallel

    in the

    history

    of the

    world,

    till the still more

    remarkable

    revolutions

    that have lately taken place in America and France. This it was, as Mr. Hume says, that

    cut off all

    pretensions

    to

    power

    founded on

    hereditary

    right;

    when a

    prince

    was chosen

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    9/33

    264 I.

    BERNARD

    COHEN

    ments

    that

    we have

    lately

    come to

    call

    the

    English

    Revolution.18There

    were thus

    no

    political

    or

    social

    events

    of

    the sixteenth

    century,

    or

    of

    the

    seventeenth century before 1688, that could provide examples or con-

    ceptual

    models for

    revolution

    (in

    the sense

    of

    a drastic

    or

    even

    a sudden

    secular

    change)

    in

    the areas of human

    creative

    effort;

    this

    fact

    is

    mir-

    rored

    in

    the failure to find an

    example

    of

    a

    coupling

    of "science"

    and

    "revolution"

    dating

    earlier than

    about

    1700.19

    About a

    half-century

    after

    the

    Glorious

    Revolution, however,

    just

    at

    the time when the full-

    ness

    of Newton's achievement had become

    recognized,

    the new

    concept

    of

    revolution

    was

    being applied

    to

    science,

    and

    specifically

    to Newton's

    Principia.20 And even earlier, the new infinitesimal calculus of Newton

    and

    of

    Leibniz

    had

    been

    judged

    to have constituted a

    revolution

    in

    mathematics.

    Those who wrote

    of

    "revolutions"

    in

    political

    affairs

    in

    the late

    seventeenth

    century

    most

    often had

    in

    mind

    some

    kind of

    restoration,

    a

    form

    of

    return to

    a former or

    original

    state,

    or

    at

    least

    the

    completion

    of

    a

    cycle.

    If

    this

    meant

    the

    end of a condition

    that

    was

    found

    to

    be

    in-

    tolerable,

    then the

    act

    of

    completing

    that

    cycle

    could be a

    kind of revo-

    lution

    in

    the

    post-1789

    sense. In

    this way the concept of a revolutionas a

    who

    received

    the crown on

    express

    conditions,

    and found his

    authority

    established on the

    same

    bottom

    with

    the

    privileges

    of

    the

    people

    .. ." Hume referred

    specifically

    to

    "that

    famous

    revolution,

    which

    has

    had such a

    happy

    influence on

    our

    constitution,

    and

    has

    been

    attended

    with

    such

    mightly consequences."

    See

    Joseph

    Priestley,

    Lectures

    on

    His-

    tory

    and

    General

    Policy

    (London,

    1826),

    Lect.

    36,

    286-87;

    David

    Hume,

    A

    Treatise

    of

    Human

    Nature,

    ed. L. A.

    Selby-Bigge

    (Oxford,

    1967,

    reprint;

    first

    ed.,

    1888),

    563;

    Book

    III,

    "Of

    Morals,"

    part

    2,

    sect. 10.

    Guizot,

    calling

    for a

    new

    attitude

    toward

    British

    eighteenth-century

    history,

    observed that

    Hume

    had

    "formed

    ... the

    opinion

    of

    Europe"

    but that his "narrative and

    opinions

    . . . had ceased to

    satisfy

    the

    imagination

    and reason

    of the

    public."

    See his

    History

    of

    the

    English

    Revolution

    from

    the Accession

    of

    Charles

    I,

    trans. Louise

    H. R.

    Coutier

    (Oxford, 1838),

    "Author's

    Preface,"

    xxi-xxii.

    '8The

    so-called

    English

    Revolution

    was

    not

    generally

    conceived to have

    been

    a revo-

    lution until the twentieth

    century,

    although

    a few

    historians

    of the

    nineteenth

    century

    (notably

    F. P. G. Guizot and Samuel R.

    Gardiner)

    had

    supposed

    the

    events of the 1640's

    to have

    been

    a revolution.

    (Gardiner

    wrote

    of a Puritan

    Revolution.)

    See,

    on this

    topic,

    J. R.

    Jones,

    The Revolution

    of

    1688

    in

    England

    (London, 1972),

    9;

    R.

    C.

    Latham,

    "English

    Revolutionary Thought,

    1640-60,"

    History,

    30

    (1945),

    38-59.

    "9Theearliest such instance that I have found cited in the secondary literature is Di-

    derot's

    essay, "Encyclopedie"

    (1755),

    in the

    great

    encyclopaedia

    associated

    with his

    name;

    this occurs in Lewis

    S.

    Feuer,

    Einstein and the Generations

    of

    Science

    (New

    York,

    1974),

    241. But Diderot was

    preceded

    in this

    usage

    by

    Fontenelle, Clairaut,

    and

    d'Alembert

    (and

    perhaps

    others),

    as

    shall

    be seen below. Feuer's

    book,

    which

    appeared

    as

    I

    was

    completing

    this

    study,

    contains

    some

    notes on

    the

    history

    of

    "The Idea

    of

    Scientific

    Revolution"

    (239-52),

    as a section

    of

    part

    3

    dealing

    with

    "Generational Move-

    ments

    and

    'Scientific

    Revolutions',"

    in which

    the

    main

    topic appears

    to be "The Dis-

    analogy

    of Scientific Revolution: The Absence

    of

    Revolutionary

    Situations"

    (252-68).

    Feuer's

    brief historical r6sum6

    of this

    topic

    is

    impaired by

    errors

    of

    fact and

    omissions;

    e.g., he mistakenly states that William Whewell did not refer to revolutions in science.

    20See note 15

    supra.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    10/33

    CONCEPT

    OF SCIENTIFIC

    REVOLUTION

    265

    radical

    change

    could

    be

    compatible

    with the ancient

    cyclical

    view

    of

    his-

    tory,

    and did

    not

    necessarily imply

    a secular

    (non-cyclical)

    or linear con-

    cept of historical change-even in the political sphere. Revolution thus

    could and did mean

    a

    dynastic change

    or

    a

    dynastic

    restoration or

    a

    change

    in

    the

    actual form or

    system

    of

    government

    or

    rule,

    as well as a

    cyclical change,

    "in

    administration,

    economics and

    the social

    life of a

    people."21

    The

    ordinary

    usage

    at the end of the

    seventeenth

    century may

    be

    illustrated

    by

    the

    writings

    of Hobbes

    and Locke.

    Hobbes

    was

    perfectly

    familiar with

    the traditional scientific

    sense of "revolution"

    and he used

    this expression in his writings on geometry and on natural philosophy.

    He

    wrote of "a

    contrary

    revolution,"

    of

    "epicycles,"

    and of

    revolutions

    in the

    sense

    of

    completed

    circular motions.

    But

    apparently

    he

    did not

    transfer

    this scientific term to

    politics,

    where

    to "describe

    a sudden

    political

    change

    Hobbes-like

    Bacon, Coke,

    Greville and

    Seldon-used

    such

    words as

    'revolt',

    'rebellion'

    and

    'overturning'."22

    Locke,

    in

    both

    his

    Elements

    of

    Natural

    Philosophy

    and

    Some

    Thoughts

    Concerning

    Education,

    used "revolution"

    in

    reference to

    the

    Earth's annual

    motion about

    the Sun

    (her

    "annual

    revolutions")

    and

    referred to the

    Sun as

    the

    "Center"

    of

    our

    planet's

    "Revolutions."23

    In the

    political

    sphere,

    Locke

    followed

    Francois

    Bernier

    (whose

    Histoire de la

    derniere

    revolution des

    etats du Grand

    Mongol

    he had studied

    in

    close

    detail)

    in

    his use of "revolution"

    in

    the sense

    of

    completed dynastic change.24

    In

    his famous

    Second

    Treatise,

    notable

    for

    its defense

    of the Glorious

    Revolution and

    for its

    presentation

    of the

    theory

    of

    government

    based

    on

    compact,

    Locke used

    "revolution"

    only

    twice-each

    time

    referring

    to

    a

    political cycle

    in which there

    was a return to

    a

    previous

    state

    with

    regard

    to some constitutional

    points.

    Thus he mentioned

    the "slowness

    and aversion

    in the

    people

    to

    quit

    their old

    constitutions,"

    which "has

    in

    the

    many

    revolutions

    that

    have been

    seen in this

    kingdom,

    in this

    and

    former

    ages,

    still

    kept

    us

    to,

    or

    after some

    interval of

    fruitless

    attempts,

    still

    brought

    us back

    again

    to

    our

    old

    legislative

    of

    king,

    lord,

    and com-

    mons."25

    Rather

    early

    in

    the

    eighteenth

    century,

    when

    "revolution"

    began

    to

    gain

    currency

    in the

    meaning

    of

    a radical or

    significant

    change,

    there

    were seen to have been revolutions in

    many

    domains of human

    activity.

    21V.

    F.

    Snow,

    "The

    Concept

    of

    Revolution,"

    op.

    cit.,

    172.

    22Ibid.,

    169.

    23Ibid.,

    172. Cf. Peter

    Laslett,

    "The

    English

    Revolution and

    Locke's'Two

    Treatises

    of

    Government',"

    The

    Cambridge

    Historical

    Journal,

    12

    (1956),

    40-55;

    esp.

    55.

    A

    similar

    expression

    occurs

    in

    the

    Essay

    Concerning

    Human

    Understanding.

    24Snow,

    op.

    cit.,

    173.

    25Ibid.,

    173. Cf.

    Peter Laslett's

    critical

    edition

    of

    Locke's

    Two

    Treatises

    of

    Govern-

    ment

    (2nd

    ed.,

    Cambridge,

    1967),

    432

    (II,

    ?

    223).

    Locke also wrote

    that

    "such

    Revolu-

    tions happen not upon every little mismanagement in publick affairs"; ibid., 433 (II, ?

    225).

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    11/33

    266

    I. BERNARD COHEN

    It

    was

    then

    that an

    interest became

    expressed

    n

    two

    aspects

    of

    possible

    revolutions

    n

    science:

    the scientific revolutions

    hat

    might

    have

    occur-

    redin the past (associatedwithCopernicus,Bacon,Descartes,Galileo)

    and

    those

    that were

    actually

    in

    progress.

    In

    the

    extreme,

    in

    the

    decade

    or so before

    the

    French

    Revolution,

    possibly

    two

    scientists

    concluded

    that

    theirown

    workwas

    revolutionary.2

    I

    have

    not

    been able

    to

    find

    any

    references

    to revolutions

    n the

    sciences

    earlier

    than

    1700.27One

    source that had held

    promise

    of

    possi-

    ble

    usage

    of

    "revolution"

    was

    the

    literature

    concerning

    he Battle

    of

    the Books

    (the

    Quarrel

    between

    the

    Ancients

    and the

    Moderns),

    since

    in

    the sciencesthe superiority f the modernsmightseem to haveimplied

    an

    order-of-magnitude

    reak withthe

    past.28

    But

    a close examination

    f

    26They

    were

    Antoine-Laurent

    Lavoisier

    and

    (possibly)

    Jean-Paul

    Marat;

    see notes

    78-82

    infra.

    27Should

    any

    reader

    have encountered

    a

    pre-1700

    occurrence

    of "revolution"

    in

    rela-

    tion to the

    growth

    of

    science,

    I should

    be

    grateful

    for

    the reference.

    I

    myself

    have

    not

    found

    any

    in the

    writings

    of

    Galileo,

    Kepler,

    Descartes,

    Bacon,

    Leibniz,

    Huygens,

    Wallis,

    Newton,

    Halley,

    Flamsteed,

    Hooke,

    or Duhamel

    (although

    there

    may

    be one

    that I have missed); nor have I had any better luck in perusing the seventeenth-century

    volumes of

    the

    Journal des

    Scavans,

    or

    the

    Philosophical

    Transactions,

    or the volumes

    of

    Histoire

    (and

    Memoires)

    of the Paris

    Academy

    of

    Sciences;

    and a

    variety

    of other

    works

    by

    seventeenth-century

    authors.

    I

    have

    kept

    on

    the

    look-out for

    such an occur-

    rence for

    many

    years

    and

    I

    have

    asked

    more

    colleagues

    than

    I would care

    to

    mention

    as

    to whether

    they

    have ever encountered

    the use

    of

    the term

    "revolution"

    in

    relation

    to

    scientific

    change.

    Accordingly,

    may

    I be allowed to

    presume

    that

    such a

    usage

    (should

    any

    ever

    turn

    up)

    would

    probably

    be rather

    obscure

    or

    uncommon?

    28For this

    purpose

    I

    have

    carefully

    examined-in vain-the

    writings

    of

    Fontenelle,

    Glanvill,

    Perrault, Swift,

    Temple,

    and Wotton.

    On this

    topic

    see

    Ferdinand

    Brunetiere,

    Etudes critiques sur l'histoire de la litterature francaise, cinquieme sdrie (Paris, 1893),

    183-250,

    "La formation de l'idee de

    progres

    au

    XVIIIe

    siecle,"

    and

    also Richard Foster

    Jones,

    Ancients and

    Moderns:

    A

    Study

    of

    the Rise

    of

    the

    Scientific

    Movement

    in

    Seventeenth-Century

    England

    (2nd.

    ed.,

    St.

    Louis,

    1961);

    the first

    edition

    (Washington

    University

    Studies,

    New

    Series,

    Language

    and

    Literature,

    No.

    6,

    St.

    Louis,

    1936)

    was

    entitled:

    Ancients and

    Moderns:

    A

    Study

    of

    the

    Background

    of

    the

    Battle

    of

    the Books.

    One of the reasons

    why

    the

    Quarrel

    between

    the Ancients and the

    Moderns seemed

    so

    promising

    is

    that one

    of the late books

    (possibly

    the

    latest)

    in

    this

    controversy

    has a

    postil

    to

    its second

    paragraph,

    reading:

    "Revolution dans les sciences."

    This

    work

    is

    Louis Dutens: Recherches

    sur

    l'origine

    des decouvertes

    attributes aux

    modernes,

    oiu.

    I'on

    demontre

    que

    nos

    plus

    celebres

    philosophes

    ont

    puise

    les

    ouvrages

    des

    anciens...,

    2

    vols.

    (Paris, 1766).

    A

    second edition

    was

    published

    in Paris in

    1776,

    a third in London

    in

    1796,

    and

    a fourth

    in Paris

    in

    1812.

    This

    phrase

    occurs also

    in the index

    to the

    second

    edition

    (and

    the later

    editions)

    in

    the

    "Table des

    matieres,"

    where

    we find: "Revolution

    dans les

    sciences, 1.3;

    des

    astres;

    v.

    Proportion;

    des

    planetes

    sur

    elles-memes,

    1,228,

    v.

    Rotation. Revolution

    particuliere

    &

    gnedrale

    des

    astres,

    1.231:

    des

    cometes, 1.241;

    v.

    Seneque."

    There

    is no other occurrence

    of

    the

    phrase

    "Revolution

    dans les sciences"

    in

    Dutens'

    book,

    and

    in

    context

    it is evident

    that he

    was

    referring

    to

    a

    return,

    a

    finding

    again

    of the truths

    known-at least

    in

    principle-in

    antiquity.

    Some of the

    major

    publications in the Battle of the Books, or the Quarrel between the Ancients and the

    Moderns,

    in

    modern

    editions,

    are:

    Bernard Le

    Bouyer

    (or

    Bovier)

    de

    Fontenelle,

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    12/33

    CONCEPT OF

    SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION 267

    the main writers disclosed

    that

    apparently they

    never used the term

    "revolution"29 and rather tended

    to invoke

    "improvement"

    of

    knowledge, although

    two of the

    protagonists (Fontenelle

    and

    Swift)

    did

    write of "revolutions"

    in

    other contexts and one

    of them

    (Fontenelle)

    applied

    this

    very

    word to the

    development

    of mathematics.

    Nor did I

    find

    any explicit

    reference to

    a

    revolution

    in

    Thomas

    Sprat's

    defence

    of

    the

    Royal Society

    of 1667.30The fact

    that the term "revolution" does

    not

    appear

    in

    relation to

    scientific

    change

    prior

    to

    the

    eighteenth

    century

    is

    not

    unexpected,

    since "revolution" did not

    begin

    to

    come

    into

    general

    use-even

    in

    the discourse

    of

    politics-until

    after the Glorious

    Revolution of 1688.31

    An

    unambiguous

    reference to a

    revolution

    in

    the sciences as a

    radical

    change

    occurs

    in

    Bernard Le

    Bouyer

    (or

    Bovier)

    de

    Fontenelle's

    preface

    to his

    Elements

    de la

    geometric

    de 'in

    fini

    (1727).

    Fontenelle

    has

    been

    discussing

    the

    newly

    discovered

    (or

    invented)

    infinitesimal cal-

    culus

    (le

    calcul

    de

    l'infini)

    of

    Newton

    and

    Leibniz,

    and the several

    ways

    in which

    "Bernoulli,

    le

    marquis

    de

    l'Hopital,

    Varignon,

    tous les

    grands

    geometres"

    carried

    the

    subject

    forward

    "a

    pas

    de

    geant."

    Then

    he

    said:

    L'infinieleva tout a une.. facilitd,dont on n'eutos6 auparavant oncevoir

    l'esperance;

    t c'est

    la

    l'epoque

    d'une rdvolution

    resque

    otale

    arrivee

    dans la

    geometrie.32

    Digression

    sur les

    anciens et les

    modernes,

    edited

    together

    with

    Fontenelle's

    Entretiens

    sur la

    pluralite

    des

    mondes,

    by

    Robert Shackleton

    (Oxford,

    1955);

    Joseph

    Glanvill,

    Plus

    Ultra:

    or,

    the

    Progress

    and

    Advancement

    of

    Knowledge

    since the

    Days

    of

    Aristotle. In

    an

    Account

    of

    Some

    of

    the

    Most

    Remarkable Late

    Improvements

    of

    Practical,

    Useful

    Learning

    (London,

    1668;

    facsimile

    reprint

    with

    an intro.

    by

    Jackson

    I.

    Cope:

    Gainesville,

    1958);Charles Perrault, Paralelle des anciens et des modernes en ce qui regarde les arts

    et les

    sciences,

    4

    vols.

    (Paris,

    1688-97;

    facsimile

    reprint

    "mit einer einleitenden Abhand-

    lung

    von

    H.

    R. Jauss

    und

    kunstgeschichtlichen

    Exkursen

    von M.

    Imdahl," Miinchen,

    1964);

    Jonathan

    Swift,

    A

    Full

    and

    True Account

    of

    the

    Battel

    fought

    last

    Friday

    between

    the Antient and the Modern Books in St. James's

    Library

    (1704),

    available in

    Herbert

    Davis

    (ed.),

    The Prose Works

    of

    Jonathan

    Swift

    (Oxford, 1939),

    I, 137-65;

    Sir

    William

    Temple,

    Five

    Miscellaneous

    Essays,

    ed. Samuel

    H. Monk

    (Ann

    Arbor,

    1963);

    William

    Wotton,

    Reflections

    upon

    Ancient

    and Modern

    Learning

    (London,

    1694;

    a

    "third

    edition,

    corrected"

    was

    printed

    1705).

    The

    only

    one

    of

    these

    authors

    cited

    by

    Dutens

    in his

    "liste

    des

    principaux

    Auteurs cites dans cet

    Ouvrage

    ..

    ."

    is

    Wotton.

    29Again,I should be grateful to any reader who may know of such an occurrence that

    I

    may

    have

    missed.

    30Thomas

    Sprat,

    The

    History

    of

    the

    Royal

    Society of

    London,

    for

    the

    Improving

    of

    Natural

    Knowledge

    (London,

    1667;

    facsimile

    reprint

    with a critical

    apparatus

    by

    Jackson

    I.

    Cope

    and Harold W.

    Jones,

    Saint

    Louis,

    1958).

    31

    ee

    note 17

    supra.

    32Elements de la

    geometrie

    de

    l'infini.

    Suite

    des

    memoires de L'Academie

    Royale

    des Sciences

    (Paris,

    1727),

    "pr6face,"

    a4

    verso;

    a variant edition

    or issue

    differs

    in title

    only

    in

    the

    first word

    (ELEMENS

    for

    ELEMENTS),

    and has the

    same

    publisher

    and

    date

    (although

    it

    was

    apparently published

    some

    decades

    later).

    The

    preface

    is

    included

    in the

    CEuvres

    e Fontenelle

    (nouvelle

    edition,

    1790),

    VI,

    43.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    13/33

    268

    I. BERNARD

    COHEN

    The

    conjunction

    of words

    "epoque"

    and "revolution" leaves

    no

    doubt

    that

    Fontenelle had

    in mind

    a

    change

    of such an

    order of

    magnitude

    as

    to alter completely the state of mathematics. And Fontenelle went on at

    once

    to

    emphasize

    that

    this

    revolution was

    progressive

    or beneficial

    to

    mathematical

    science,

    although

    not

    unaccompanied by

    several

    prob-

    lems.33

    Fontenelle

    used

    the

    term

    "revolution"

    in the

    eloge

    of

    the mathema-

    tician,

    Michel

    Rolle,

    which he wrote in

    his

    capacity ofsecretaireperpe-

    tuel of the

    Royal

    Academy

    of Sciences. But "revolution" does

    not here

    occur

    in relation

    to the work

    of Rolle

    himself,

    but rather

    in an

    aside;

    on

    the Analyse des infiniment petits (Paris, 1696; later eds., 1715, 1720,

    1768)

    of

    the

    Marquis

    de

    l'H6pital,

    the first textbook

    on

    the

    new infini-

    tesimal calculus:

    En ce

    temps-la

    e

    livre du

    marquis

    de

    l'H6pital

    avoit

    paru,

    et

    presque

    ous les

    mathematiciens

    ommengoient

    se tournerdu c6te de

    la nouvelle

    g6ometrie

    de

    l'infini,

    usques-la

    peu

    connue.

    L'universalite

    urprenante

    des

    methodes,

    1'ele-

    gante

    brievete

    des

    demonstrations,

    a

    finesse

    et la

    promptitude

    es solutions es

    plus

    difficiles,

    une nouveaute

    inguliere

    t

    imprevue,

    out attiroit

    es

    esprits,

    et

    il se faisoitdans e mondegeometreune revolution ienmarquee.34

    Fontenelle

    also used

    "revolution"

    in

    the

    eloge

    of

    l'H6pital

    (d. 1704),

    again

    in relation

    to his

    textbook,

    and

    the

    avidity

    with which

    "I'Analyse

    des

    infiniment

    petits

    a

    ete

    saisie

    par

    tous

    les

    G6ometres

    naissans."

    L'Hopital's

    aim

    had

    been

    "principalement

    de

    faire

    des

    Mathe-

    maticiens,"

    Fontenelle

    wrote,

    and

    he had

    the satisfaction

    of

    seeing

    that

    "des

    Problemes

    reservez

    autrefois a

    ceux

    qui

    avoient

    vieilli dans

    les

    epines

    des

    Mathematiques,

    devenoient

    des

    coups

    d'essai

    de

    jeunes

    gens":

    Apparemment

    a

    revolution

    eviendra ncore

    plus

    grande,

    & il

    se seroit

    trouve

    avec

    le

    temps

    autantde

    Disciples,

    qu'il

    y

    eut eu de

    Mathematiciens.35

    These latter

    two uses of "revolution"

    in

    relation

    to

    l'Hopital's

    textbook

    33Ibid.;

    "Cette

    revolution,

    quelque

    heureuse

    qu'elle

    ffit,

    a

    pourtant

    ete

    accompagnee

    de

    quelques

    troubles."

    A

    succinct

    appraisal

    of this work of Fontenelle's

    is

    given by

    Su-

    zanne Delorme in the

    Dictionary of Scientific Biography,

    ed.

    Charles C.

    Gillispie

    (New

    York, 1972), V, 61b; a review by the Abbe Terrasson appeared in Journal des scavans,

    July-Oct.

    1728, 387-403,

    608-25.

    34"Eloge

    de

    Rolle,"

    CEuvres

    de

    Fontenelle

    (nouvelle

    ed., Paris,

    1792),

    VII,

    67.

    This

    eloge

    was first

    published

    in the

    Histoire

    de

    l'Academie

    Royale

    des Sciences

    (1719).

    Fontenelle was the author of

    the

    anonymous preface

    to

    l'Hopital's

    book,

    which was

    writ-

    ten

    in a

    style

    that would

    lead

    the

    unsuspecting

    reader to

    suppose

    it

    had

    been written

    by

    l'Hopital

    himself.

    35"Eloge

    de

    M.

    le

    Marquis

    de

    l'H6pital,"

    Histoire

    du renouvellement

    de

    l'Academie

    Royale

    des

    Sciences

    en M. DC.XCIX. et les

    eloges historiques

    de

    tous

    les academiciens

    morts

    depuis

    ce renouvellement

    (Amsterdam, 1709),

    105-06. In

    the

    "Eloge

    du

    Marquis

    de l'H6pital," publishedin CEuvres e Fontenelle (Paris, 1790) VI, 131, the word "revo-

    lution" is

    misprinted

    as

    "resolution."

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    14/33

    CONCEPT

    OF

    SCIENTIFIC REVOLUTION

    269

    differ

    from

    the former

    instance,

    in that the calculus

    inaugurated

    a con-

    ceptual

    revolution

    in

    mathematics,

    whereas the

    Analyse

    des

    infiniment

    petits

    consolidated the

    achievements

    of that revolution

    and made its

    methods

    and

    achievements

    so

    readily

    available

    as

    to revolutionize

    the

    profession

    of

    mathematician;

    that

    is,

    I'Hopital

    was

    (according

    to

    Fontenelle) primarily responsible

    for

    attracting

    young

    mathematicians

    ("geometres")

    to the

    new

    analysis

    and

    endowing

    them with

    new

    powers.

    Fontenelle

    would

    thus seem to

    have made

    a distinction

    between

    "une

    revolution

    presque

    totale .

    . . dans

    la

    geometrie"36

    and

    "une revolution

    bien

    marquee,"

    such as

    l'Hopital's

    book

    produced

    "dans

    le

    monde

    geometre."37

    The revolution within the sciences to which Fontenelle referred was

    the

    discovery

    or invention

    of the

    calculus

    by

    Newton

    and

    by

    Leibniz.38

    Another

    eighteenth-century

    reference

    to

    Isaac

    Newton and

    a revolution

    in

    science

    is

    found

    in

    Clairaut's statement of

    1747 that

    Newton's

    Prin-

    cipia

    had marked

    "l'epoque

    d'une

    grande

    revolution dans

    la

    Phy-

    sique."39

    The fact that

    these earliest

    references

    to a

    revolution in

    science

    occur

    in

    relation

    to

    Newton

    is

    worthy

    of

    notice,

    since

    it was

    Newton's

    achievement

    in

    pure

    mathematics

    coupled

    with his

    analysis

    of

    36

    A

    "revolution

    presque

    totale" would seem

    more

    fitting

    an

    expression

    for a

    cyclical

    phenomenon

    than for the kind of revolution Fontenelle had

    in mind.

    37

    In

    his

    "Eloge

    du Czar

    Pierre,"

    Fontenelle used

    the word "revolution"

    in two

    ways,

    neither of

    them in relation

    to science. Thus he wrote

    that

    "La

    revolution,

    arriv6e en

    Perse

    par

    la

    revolte de

    Mahmoud,

    attira

    de ce

    cote-la

    les

    armes du

    Czar et du

    grand

    Seigneur." Again,

    he mentioned

    "[la]

    nation

    Moscovite,

    peu

    connue

    que

    de ses

    plus

    proches

    voisins,

    . . .

    presque

    une nation

    a

    part,

    qui

    n'entroit

    point

    dans le

    systeme

    de

    l'Europe,

    . . . et

    dont

    a

    peine

    6toit-on curieux

    d'apprendre

    de tems en tems

    quelques

    revolutions

    importantes."

    This

    eloge

    is

    printed

    in

    CEuvres

    e

    Fontenelle,

    nouvelle ed.

    op.

    cit., VII, 166, 188. This second quotation appears to have cyclical overtones of the ebbs

    and flows

    of

    ordinary

    history,

    and

    as

    such

    may

    resemble a

    statement in Fontenelle's

    "Preface

    sur

    l'utilit6 des

    mathematiques

    et de la

    physique,

    et sur les

    travaux de l'Aca-

    demie des

    Sciences,"

    Histoire de l'Academie

    Royale

    des

    Sciences.

    Annee

    M. DC.XCIX.

    Avec les memoires de

    mathematique

    & de

    physique,

    pour

    la

    meme annee. Tires des

    registres

    de cette Academie. Seconde

    edition, revue,

    corrigee

    &

    augmentee

    (Am-

    sterdam,

    1734),

    I,

    v-xxvi.

    In

    this

    form,

    the

    essay

    is

    merely

    entitled

    "Preface";

    the above

    title

    comes

    from the

    somewhat truncated

    reprint

    in

    CEuvres

    e

    Fontenelle,

    nouvelle 6d.

    op.

    cit.,

    VI,

    59-75.

    An

    English

    version

    was

    published

    in

    Miscellanea

    Curiosa,

    vol.

    1

    (London,

    1705;

    2nd

    ed., London,

    1708;

    3rd

    ed.,

    London,

    1726).

    Here Fontenelle

    says:

    "L'Histoire ne

    fournit

    pas

    dans

    toute

    son

    6tendue,

    des

    examples

    de

    vertu,

    ni des

    regles

    de

    conduite.

    Hors de

    la,

    ce n'est

    qu'un

    spectacle

    de revolutions

    perpetuelles

    dans les

    affaires

    humaines,

    de

    naissances,

    de chuites

    d'empire,

    de

    mceurs,

    de

    coutumes,

    d'opinions, qui

    se

    succedent

    incessament;

    enfin de

    tout

    ce

    mouvement

    rapide,

    quoiqu'insensible, qui

    emporte

    tout,

    et

    change

    continuellement

    la face de

    la terre."

    38In the "Preface"

    to the

    Elements

    de la

    geometrie

    de

    l'infini,

    loc.

    cit.,

    Fontenelle

    said of the calculus: "Newton

    trouva le

    premier

    ce merveilleux

    calcul,

    Leibnitz

    le

    publia

    le

    premier.

    Que

    Leibnitz

    soit inventeur

    aussi bien

    que

    Newton,

    c'est

    une

    question

    dont

    nous avons

    rapport6

    l'histoire

    en

    1716,

    et

    nous ne la

    r6epterons

    pas

    ici."

    39See note 15 supra. This statement was repeated almost verbatim by Joseph-Louis

    Lagrange,

    John

    Playfair,

    and

    Thomas

    Henry

    Huxley.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsphttp://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp
  • 7/21/2019 Journal of the History of Ideas Volume 37 Issue 2 1976 [Doi 10.2307%2F2708824] I. Bernard Cohen -- The Eightee

    15/33

    270 I.

    BERNARD

    COHEN

    the

    system

    of the world

    on

    the

    basis

    of

    gravitational

    dynamics

    that

    actually

    set the seal on

    the "Scientific Revolution" and

    caused scientists

    and philosophers to recognize that a revolutionhad in fact taken place.40

    In this

    sense,

    Newton's

    Principia

    of 1687

    would have

    played

    the same

    r6le

    in the

    recognition

    of the

    occurrence of a scientific revolution that

    the Glorious Revolution

    of 1688

    apparently

    did

    for

    political

    revolution.

    The

    great Encyclopedie

    of Diderot and d'Alembert

    contains a nota-

    ble

    entry

    on

    revolution.

    The

    concept

    of revolution

    was,

    in

    fact,

    in-

    troduced

    at

    the

    very

    start

    of this collective

    work,

    since

    it

    occurs

    in

    a dra-

    matic

    fashion

    in

    d'Alembert's

    Discours

    preliminaire,

    as well as later on

    in his article "Experimental." In the Discours preliminaire (publishedin

    1751),

    d'Alembert introduced

    the

    concept

    of

    revolution

    in a

    thumb-nail

    sketch of the rise of

    modern science

    or, rather,

    of a

    philosophy

    associated

    with modern science. The aim of

    the

    essay

    was to sketch out

    a

    methodological

    and

    philosophical analysis

    of all

    knowledge

    (including

    science which

    occupies

    a central

    place

    in his

    scheme41)

    and not

    to

    portray

    the

    sciences themselves. d'Alembert

    begins

    his historical

    presentation

    with

    "le Chancelier

    Bacon,"

    who

    occupies

    an

    avuncular

    position, and then moves on to a brief resume of Descartes's radical in-

    novations.

    Fully appreciative

    of

    the

    significance

    of

    the

    Newtonian

    natural

    philosophy,

    which

    in fact

    had

    just

    overthrown and

    replaced

    the

    Cartesian,

    d'Alembert

    nevertheless felt the need to

    say

    some kind

    words

    for

    Descartes,

    a

    fellow

    Frenchman

    and fellow mathematician. He

    thus called

    particular

    attention to the

    great

    "revolte"

    of

    Descartes,

    who

    had

    shown

    "intelligent

    minds how to

    throw

    off

    the

    yoke

    of

    scholasticism,

    of

    opinion,

    of

    authority...."

    d'Alembert

    had

    in

    mind

    a clear

    image

    of

    the action of

    political revolutionary forces,

    and

    he

    portrayed

    Descartes

    "as a leader

    of

    conspirators

    who,

    before

    anyone

    else,

    had the

    courage

    to

    rise

    against

    a

    despotic

    and

    arbitrary

    power

    and

    who,

    in

    preparing

    a

    resounding

    revolution,

    laid the foundations of a

    more

    just

    and

    happier

    government,

    which he himself

    was

    not

    able

    to

    see established."42

    Descartes's

    role in thus

    "preparing"

    the

    "revolution" or his "revolt"

    was "a service to

    philosophy

    perhaps

    more difficult

    to

    perform

    than

    all

    40This

    heme

    is

    developed

    in the

    work cited

    in note 10

    supra.

    41Ronald

    Grimsley,

    Jean d'Alembert

    (1717-83)

    (Oxford,

    1963);

    Thomas L.

    Hankins,

    Jean d'Alembert: Science

    and

    Enlightenment

    (Oxford, 1970),

    8.

    42All of the

    following

    references are

    to

    the first

    edition,

    available in

    a

    facsimile

    re-

    print:

    Encyclopedie,

    ou Dictionnaire raisonne des

    sciences,

    des arts et des metiers.

    Nou-

    velle

    impression

    en

    facsimile

    de

    la

    premiere

    edition de

    1751-1780

    (Stuttgart-Bad

    Cannstatt,

    1966).

    See vol.

    1

    (Paris, 1751),

    xxvi.

    Quoted

    from

    the

    English

    translation

    made

    by

    Richard N. Schwab

    (with

    the

    collaboration

    of

    Walter

    E.

    Rex),

    available

    in

    Jean

    LeRond

    d'Alembert,

    Preliminary

    Discourse

    to

    the

    Encyclopedia

    of

    Diderot

    (In-

    dianapolis,

    1963-The

    Library

    of Liberal

    Arts),

    80-81.

    It

    should be observed that

    d'Alembert used the metaphor of political life in describing Descartes' rl6e in the revo-

    lution.

    This content downloaded from 195.34.79.253 on Sat, 21 Jun 2014 02:26:38 AMAll use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions

    http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp