32
Kant’s Philosophy of Mind Colin McLear University of Nebraska–Lincoln [email protected] September 16, 2015 Introduction Immanuel Kant (1724-1804) was one of the most important philosophers of the “Enlighten- ment” period (ca. 1650-1800) in western European history. Born in Königsberg, Prussia (now Kaliningrad, Russia) to poor and religiously devout parents, Kant’s intellectual promise was ap- parent at an early age. He attended college at the University of Königsberg (Albertus-Universität Königsberg) and eventually taught as a professor there (1770-1796). Kant wrote his most significant philosophical works relatively late in his professional life, having only achieved a position as full professor in 1770, at the age of forty-six. From 1781 to 1798 Kant published a series of tremendously influential writings, including the Critique of Pure Reason (1781/7), the Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals (1785), the Metaphysical Foundations of Natural Science (1786), the Critique of Practical Reason (1788), and the Critique of the Power of Judgment (1790). This body of work had a transformative impact on virtually all parts of philosophy including aesthetics, epistemology, ethics, logic, metaphysics, philosophy of religion, and philosophy of science. This encyclopedia entry focuses on Kant’s views in the philosophy of mind, which undergird much of his epistemology and metaphysics. In particular, we’ll be focusing on metaphysical and epistemological doctrines forming the core of Kant’s mature philosophy, as presented in the Critique of Pure Reason (CPR) of 1781/87 and elsewhere. There are certain aspects of Kant’s project in the CPR that should be very familiar to anyone versed in the debates of seventeenth century European philosophy. For example, Kant argues, like Locke and Hume before him, that the boundaries of substantive human knowledge stop at experience, and thus that we must be extraordinarily circumspect concerning any claim made about what reality is like independent of all possible human experience. But, like Descartes and Leibniz, Kant thinks that central parts of human knowledge nevertheless exhibit characteristics of necessity and universality, and that, contrary to Hume’s skeptical arguments, we can have good reason to think that they do. Kant carries out a ‘critique’ of pure reason in order to show its nature and limits, and thereby curb the pretensions of various metaphysical systems articulated on the basis of a firm faith that reason alone allows us to scrutinize the very depths of reality. But Kant also argues that the legitimate domain of reason is more extensive and more substantive than previous empiri- cist critiques had allowed. In this way Kant salvages (or attempts to) much of the prevailing Enlightenment conception of reason as an organ for knowledge of the world. Below I discuss Kant’s theory of cognition, including his views of the various mental faculties that make cognition possible. I distinguish between different conceptions of consciousness at the basis of this theory of cognition and explain and discuss Kant’s criticisms of the prevailing rationalist conception of mind, popular in Germany at the time. 1

Kant's Philosophy of Mind

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    10

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Kant’sPhilosophyofMindColinMcLearUniversityofNebraska–[email protected]

September16, 2015

Introduction

ImmanuelKant (1724-1804)wasoneof themost important philosophers of the “Enlighten-ment”period(ca. 1650-1800)inwesternEuropeanhistory. BorninKönigsberg, Prussia(nowKaliningrad, Russia)topoorandreligiouslydevoutparents, Kant’sintellectualpromisewasap-parentatanearlyage. HeattendedcollegeattheUniversityofKönigsberg(Albertus-UniversitätKönigsberg)andeventuallytaughtasaprofessorthere(1770-1796).

Kantwrotehismostsignificantphilosophicalworksrelativelylateinhisprofessionallife,havingonlyachievedapositionasfullprofessorin1770, attheageofforty-six. From1781to1798Kantpublishedaseriesoftremendouslyinfluentialwritings, includingthe CritiqueofPureReason (1781/7), the GroundworkoftheMetaphysicsofMorals (1785), theMetaphysicalFoundationsofNaturalScience (1786), the CritiqueofPracticalReason (1788), andthe CritiqueofthePowerofJudgment (1790). Thisbodyofworkhadatransformativeimpactonvirtuallyallpartsofphilosophyincludingaesthetics, epistemology, ethics, logic, metaphysics, philosophyofreligion, andphilosophyofscience. ThisencyclopediaentryfocusesonKant’sviewsinthephilosophyofmind, whichundergirdmuchofhisepistemologyandmetaphysics. Inparticular,we’llbe focusingonmetaphysicalandepistemologicaldoctrines forming thecoreofKant’smaturephilosophy, aspresentedinthe CritiqueofPureReason (CPR) of1781/87andelsewhere.

TherearecertainaspectsofKant’sprojectinthe CPR thatshouldbeveryfamiliartoanyoneversedinthedebatesofseventeenthcenturyEuropeanphilosophy. Forexample, Kantargues,like Locke and Hume beforehim, thattheboundariesofsubstantivehumanknowledgestopatexperience, andthusthatwemustbeextraordinarilycircumspectconcerninganyclaimmadeaboutwhatrealityislikeindependentofallpossiblehumanexperience. But, like Descartes andLeibniz, Kantthinksthatcentralpartsofhumanknowledgeneverthelessexhibitcharacteristicsofnecessityanduniversality, andthat, contrarytoHume’sskepticalarguments, wecanhavegoodreasontothinkthattheydo.

Kantcarriesouta‘critique’ofpurereasoninordertoshowitsnatureandlimits, andtherebycurb thepretensionsofvariousmetaphysical systemsarticulatedon thebasisofafirm faiththatreasonaloneallowsustoscrutinizetheverydepthsofreality. ButKantalsoarguesthatthelegitimatedomainofreasonismoreextensiveandmoresubstantivethanpreviousempiri-cistcritiqueshadallowed. InthiswayKantsalvages(orattemptsto)muchoftheprevailingEnlightenmentconceptionofreasonasanorganforknowledgeoftheworld.

BelowI discussKant’stheoryofcognition, includinghisviewsofthevariousmentalfacultiesthatmakecognitionpossible. I distinguishbetweendifferentconceptionsofconsciousnessatthebasisofthistheoryofcognitionandexplainanddiscussKant’scriticismsoftheprevailingrationalistconceptionofmind, popularinGermanyatthetime.

1

Contents

Introduction 1

1. Kant’sTheoryofCognition 3

a. MentalFaculties&MentalRepresentation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3i. Sensibility, Understanding, andReason . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 3ii. ImaginationandJudgment . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 6

b. MentalProcessing . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 8

2. Consciousness 9

a. PhenomenalConsciousness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 9b. Discrimination&Differentiation . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 10c. Self-Consciousness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11

i. InnerSense . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 11ii. Apperception . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12

d. UnityofConsciousness&theCategories . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 12

3. Concepts&Perception 16

a. Content&Correctness . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 16b. ConceptualContent . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 17c. Conceptualism&Synthesis . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 18d. ObjectionstoConceptualism . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 19

4. RationalPsychology&Self-Knowledge 21

a. Substantiality(A348-51/B410-11) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 21b. Simplicity(A351-61/B407-8) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 23c. NumericalIdentity(A361-66/B408) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24d. RelationtoObjectsinSpace(A366-80/B409) . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 24

i. TheImmediacyArgument . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 25ii. TheArgumentfromImagination . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 26

e. LessonsoftheParalogisms . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 27

5. Summary 28

6. ReferencesandFurtherReading 28

a. Kant’sWorksinEnglish . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 28b. SecondarySources . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 29

2| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

1. Kant’sTheoryofCognition

Kantisprimarilyinterestedininvestigatingthemindforepistemologicalreasons. Oneofthegoalsofhismature“critical”philosophyisarticulatingtheconditionsunderwhichourscien-tificknowledge, includingmathematicsandnaturalscience, ispossible. Achievingthisgoalre-quires, inKant’sestimation, a critique ofthemannerinwhichrationalbeingslikeourselvesgainsuchknowledge, sothatwemightdistinguishthoseformsofinquiry(suchasnaturalscience),whicharelegitimate, fromthose(suchasrationalistmetaphysics), whichareillegitimate. Thiscritiqueproceedsviaanexaminationofthosefeaturesofthemindrelevanttotheacquisitionofknowledge. Thisamountstoanexaminationoftheconditionsfor“cognition”[Erkenntnis],orthemind’srelationtoanobject(thereissomecontroversyaboutthebestwaytounderstandKant’suseofthisterm, butherewe’llunderstanditasinvolvingrelationtoapossibleobjectofexperience, andasbeinganecessaryconditionforpositivesubstantiveknowledge[Wissen]).ThustounderstandKant’scriticalphilosophyweneedtounderstandhisconceptionofthemind.

a. MentalFaculties&MentalRepresentation

Kantcharacterizesthemindalongtwofundamentalaxes–first, thevariouskindsofpowerswhichitpossesses; second, theresultsofexercisingthosepowers. We’lltaketheseinturn.

Atthemostbasicexplanatorylevel, Kantconceivesofthemindasconstitutedbytwofun-damentalcapacities[Fähigkeiten], orpowers, whichhelabels“receptivity”[Receptivität]and“spontaneity”[Spontaneität]. Receptivity, asthenamesuggests, constitutesthemind’scapacitytobeaffectedbysomething, whetheritselforsomethingelse. Kant’sbasicideahereisthatthemind’sreceptivepoweressentiallyrequiressomeexternalpromptinginordertoengageintheproductionofrepresentations. Incontrast, thepowerofspontaneityneedsnosuchprompting.Itisabletoinitiateitsactivityfromitself, withoutanyexternaltrigger.

Thesetwocapacitiesofthemindarethebasisforall(human)mentalbehavior. Kantthusconstruesallmentalactivityeitherintermsofitsresultingfromaffection(receptivity)orfromthemind’s self-promptedactivity (spontaneity). From these twovery general aspects of themindKantthenderivesthreefurtherbasicfacultiesor“powers”[Vermögen], termedbyKant“sensibility”[Sinnlichkeit], “understanding”[Verstand], and“reason”[Vernunft]. Thesefacultiescharacterizespecificcognitivepowers, noneofwhichisreducibletoanyoftheothers, andtoeachofwhichisassignedaparticularcognitivetask. We’lldiscusstheseinturn.

i. Sensibility, Understanding, andReason

Kantdistinguishesthethreefundamentalmentalfacultiesfromoneanotherintwoways. First,heconstruessensibilityasthespecificmannerinwhichhumanbeings, aswellasotheranimals,are receptive. This is incontrastwith the facultiesofunderstandingand reason, whichareformsofhuman(orofallrationalbeings, shouldthatclassextendmorewidely)spontaneity.Second, Kantdistinguishes the facultiesby theiroutput. Allof themental facultiesproduce“representations”[Vorstellungen], whicharebestthoughtofasdiscretementaleventsorstates,ofwhichthemindisaware, or invirtueofwhichthemindisawareofsomethingelse(it issomewhatcontroversialwhetherrepresentationsaretheultimateobjectsofawarenessormerelythevehiclesofsuchawareness). Wecanseethesedistinctionsatworkinwhatisgenerallycalled

September16, 2015 3| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

the“stepladder”[Stufenleiter]passagefromtheTranscendentalDialecticofKant’smajorwork,the CritiqueofPureReason (1781/7). ThisisoneofthefewplacesintheentireKantiancorpuswhereKantexplicitlydiscussesthemeaningsofandrelationsbetweenhistechnicalterms, anddefinesandclassifiesvarietiesofrepresentation.

Thegenusisrepresentation(representatio)ingeneral. Underitstandrepresenta-tionswithconsciousness(perceptio). A perception[Wahrnehmung], thatrelatessolelytoasubjectasamodificationofitsstate, issensation(sensatio). Anobjec-tiveperceptioniscognition(cognitio). Thisiseitherintuitionorconcept(intuitusvelconceptus). Thefirstrelatesimmediatelytotheobjectandissingular; thesec-ondismediate, conveyedbyamark, whichcanbecommontomanythings. Aconceptiseitheranempiricalorapureconcept, andthepureconcept, insofarasithasitsoriginsolelyintheunderstanding(notinapureimageofsensibility), iscalled notio. A conceptmadeupofnotions, whichgoesbeyondthepossibilityofexperience, isanideaoraconceptofreason. (A320/B376–7).

AsKant’sdiscussionhereindicates, thecategoryofrepresentationcontainssensations[Empfind-ungen], intuitions[Anschauungen], andconcepts[Begriffe]. Sensibilityisthefacultythatpro-vides sensory representations. Sensibility generates representationsbasedonbeingaffectedeitherbyentitiesdistinctfromthesubjectorbythesubjectherself. Thisisincontrasttothefac-ultyofunderstanding, whichgeneratesconceptualrepresentationsspontaneously–i.e. withoutadvertencetoaffection. Reasonisthatspontaneousfacultybywhichspecialsortsofconcepts,whichKantcalls“ideas”or“notions”, maybegenerated, andwhoseobjectscouldneverbemetwithinexperience. SuchideasincludethoseconcerningGodandthesoul.

Kantclaimsthatalltherepresentationsgeneratedviasensibilityarestructuredbytwo“forms”ofintuition—spaceandtime—andthatallsensoryaspectsofourexperiencearetheir“matter”(A20/B34). ThesimplestwayofunderstandingwhatKantmeansby“form”hereisthatanythingofwhichonemighthaveexperiencewillbesuchastoeitherhavespatialfeatures(e.g. extension,shape, location), ortemporalfeatures(e.g. beingsuccessiveorsimultaneous). Sotheformalelementofanempiricalintuition, orsenseperception, willalwaysbeeitherspatialortemporal,whilethematerialelementisalwayssensory(inthesenseofdeterminingthephenomenalor“whatitislike”characterofexperience), andtiedeithertooneormoreofthefivesenses, orthefeelingsofpleasureanddispleasure.

Kanttiesthetwoformsofintuitiontotwodistinctspheresordomains, the“inner”andthe“outer”. Thedomainofouter intuitionconcerns the spatialworldofmaterialobjectswhilethedomainofinnerintuitionconcernstemporallyorderedstatesofmind. Spaceisthustheformof“outersense”whiletimeistheformof“innersense”(A22/B37; cf. An7:154). IntheTranscendentalAesthetic, Kantisprimarilyconcernedwith“pure”[rein]intuition, orintuitionabsentanysensation, andoftenonlyspeaksinpassingofthesenseperceptionofphysicalbodies(e.g. A20–1/B35). However, Kantmoreclearlylinksthefivesenseswithintuitioninhis1798work AnthropologyfromaPragmaticPointofView, inthesectionentitled“OntheFiveSenses”.

Sensibility inthecognitivefaculty(thefacultyofintuitiverepresentations)containstwoparts: sense andthe imagination…Butthesenses, ontheotherhand, aredi-videdinto outer and inner sense(sensusinternus); thefirstiswherethehumanbodyisaffectedbyphysicalthings, thesecondiswherethehumanbodyisaffectedbythemind(An7:153).

September16, 2015 4| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

Kantcharacterizesintuitiongenerallyintermsoftwocharacteristics—viz. immediacy [Unmit-telbarkeit]and particularity [Einzelheit](cf. A19/B33, A68/B93; JL 9:91). Thisisincontrasttothemediacyandgenerality[Allgemeinheit]characteristicofconceptualrepresentation(A68/B93;JL 9:91).

Kantcontraststheparticularityofintuitionwiththegeneralityofconceptsinthe“stepladder”passage(seethefirstquoteabove). Butthespecificremarkhemakesisthataconceptisrelatedtoitsobjectvia“amark, whichcanbecommontomanythings”(A320/B377)andthissuggeststhatintuition, incontrasttoconcepts, putsasubjectincognitivecontactwithfeaturesofanobjectthatareuniquetoparticularobjectsandarenothadbyotherobjects(thereissomedebateastowhether the immediacyof intuitioniscompatiblewithanintuition’srelatingtoanobjectbymeansofmarksorwhetherrelationbymeansofmarksentailsmediacy, andthusthatonlyconceptsrelatetoobjectsbymeansofmarks. SeeSmit(2000)fordiscussion.) Spatio-temporalpropertiesseemlikeexcellentcandidatesforsuchfeatures, asnotwoobjectsofexperiencecanhavetheverysamespatio-temporallocation(B327-8). Butperhapsanynon-repeatable, non-universalfeatureofaperceivedobjectwilldo(forrelevantdiscussionseeSmit(2000); Grüne(2009), 50, 66-70).

ThoughKant’sdiscussionof intuition suggests that it is a formofperceptual experience,thismightseemtoclashwithhisdistinctionbetween“experience”[Erfahrung]and“intuition”[Anschauung]. Inpart, thisisaterminologicalissue. Kant’snotionofan“experience”istypicallyquiteabitnarrowerthanourcontemporaryEnglishusageoftheterm. Kantactuallyequates, atseveralpoints, “experience”with“empiricalcognition”(B166, A176/B218, A189/B234), whichis incompatiblewithexperiencebeing falsidical inanyway. Healsogives indications thatexperience, inhissense, isnotsomethinghadbyasinglesubject. See, forexample, hisclaimthatthereisonlyoneexperience(A230/B282-3).

Kantalsodistinguishesintuitionfrom“perception”[Wahrnehmung], whichhecharacterizesastheconsciousapprehensionofthecontentofanintuition(Pr4:300; cf. A99, A119-20, B162,andB202-3). “Experience”, inKant’ssense, isthenconstruedasasetofperceptionsthatareconnectedviafundamentalconceptsthatKantentitlesthe“categories”. Asheputsit, “Experi-enceiscognitionthroughconnectedperceptions[durchverknüpfteWahrnehmungen]”(B161;cf. B218; Pr4:300).

Empiricalintuition, perception, andexperience, inKant’susageoftheseterms, alldenotekindsof“experience”asweusethetermincontemporaryEnglish. Atitsmostprimitivelevel,empiricalintuitionpresents, inasensorymanner, somefeatureoftheworldtothemind, andinsuchawaythatthesubjectoftheintuitionistherebyinapositiontodistinguishthatfeaturefromothers. A perception, inKant’ssense, involvestheawarenessofthebasisorgroundbywhichthefeatureoftheworldthatoneisawareofinanintuitionissuchastobedifferentfromotherthings(Kanttendstousethisterminavarietyofways, however—e.g. JL 9:64-5—sothereissomecontroversysurroundingtheproperunderstandingofthisterm). Soonehasaperception,inKant’ssense, whenoneisinapositiontonotonlydiscriminateonethingfromanother(orbetweenthepartsofasinglething)basedonasensoryapprehensionofit, butalsocanarticulateexactlywhatfeaturesofone’ssensoryapprehensionoftheobjectorobjectsthatdistinguishitfromothers(e.g. thatitisgreenratherthanred, orthatitoccupiesthisspatiallocationratherthanthatone). Intuitionthusallowsforthediscriminationofdistinctobjects, viaanawarenessoftheirfeatures, whileperceptionallowsforanawarenessofwhatitisspecificallyaboutthefeaturesofanobject thatdistinguishesit fromothers. “Experience”, inKant’ssense, iseven

September16, 2015 5| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

furtherupthecognitiveladder(cf. JL 9:64-5), insofarasitindicatesanawarenessoffeaturessuchasthesubstantialityofathing, itcausalrelationswithotherbeings, anditsmereologicalfeatures(i.e. part-wholedependencerelations).

Kantthusbelievesthatthecapacitytocognitivelyascendfrommerediscriminatoryaware-nessofone’senvironment(intuition), toanawarenessofthosefeaturesbymeansofwhichonediscriminates(perception), andfinallytoanawarenessoftheobjectswhichgroundthesefea-tures(experience), dependsonthekindsofmentalprocessesofwhichthesubjectiscapable.

Beforeweturntotheissueofmentalprocessing, whichfigurescentrallyinKant’soverallcriticalproject, therearetwofurtherfacultiesofthemindthatareworthdiscussion—viz. thefacultyofjudgmentandthefacultyofimagination. Thesefacultiesarenotobviouslyasfun-damentalasthefacultiesofsensibility, understanding, andreason, buttheyneverthelessplayacentral role inKant’s thinkingabout thestructureof themindand itscontributions toourexperienceoftheworld.

ii. ImaginationandJudgment

Kantlinksthefacultyofimaginationcloselytosensibility. Forexample, inhis Anthropology hesays,

Sensibility inthecognitivefaculty(thefacultyofintuitiverepresentations)containstwoparts: sense andthe powerofimagination. -Thefirstisthefacultyofintuitioninthepresenceofanobject, thesecondisintuitioneven without thepresenceofanobject. (An7:153; cf. 7:167; B151; LM 29:881; LM 28:449, 673)

ThecontrastKantmakeshereisnotentirelyobvious, butmustincludeatleastthedifferencebetweencasesofoccurrentsensoryexperienceofaperceivedobject—e.g. seeing thebrowntablebeforeyou—andcasesofsensoryrecollectionofapreviouslyperceivedobject—e.g. vi-suallyimagining thebrowntablethatwasonceinfrontofyou. Kantmakesthisclearerintheprocessoffurtherdistinguishingbetweendifferentkindsofimagination.

Thepowerofimagination(facultasimaginandi), asafacultyofintuitionwithoutthepresenceof theobject, iseitherproductive, that is, a facultyof theoriginalpresentation[Darstellung]oftheobject(exhibitio originaria), whichthusprecedesexperience; orreproductive, afacultyofthederivativepresentationoftheobject(exhibitioderivativa), whichbringsbacktomindanempiricalintuitionthatithadpreviously(An7:167).

So, intheoperationofproductiveimagination, onebringstomindasensoryexperiencethatisnotitselfbasedonanyobjectpreviouslysoexperienced. Thisisnottosaytheproductiveimaginationistotally creative. Kantexplicitlydenies(An7:167)thattheproductiveimaginationhasthepowertogeneratewhollynovelsensoryexperience(e.g. itcouldnot, inapersonbornblind, producethephenomenalqualityassociatedwiththeexperienceofseeingaredobject).If theproductive imagination is instrumental inproducingsensoryfictions, the reproductiveimaginationisinstrumentalinproducingsensoryexperiencesofpreviouslyperceivedobjects.

Theimaginationthusplaysacentralroleinempiricalcognitionbyservingasthebasisforbothmemoryand thecreativearts (for furtherdiscussionseeMatherne). Inaddition italso

September16, 2015 6| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

playsakindofmediating rolebetween the facultiesof sensibilityandunderstanding. Kantcallsthismediatingrolea“transcendentalfunction”oftheimagination(A124). Itaccomplishesthisbybeingtiedinitsfunctioningtobothfaculties. Ontheonehand, itproducessensiblerepresentations, andisthusconnectedtosensibility. Ontheotherhand, itisnotapurelypassivefacultybutratherengagesintheactivityofbringingtogethervariousrepresentations(memoryisacentralexamplehere)andthiskindofactivementalprocessingKantexplicitlyconnectswiththeunderstanding.

Kantalsogoessofarastoclaimthattheactivityoftheimaginationisanecessarypartofwhatmakesperception(inhistechnicalsenseofastringofconnectedandconscioussensoryexperiences)possible(A120, note). ThoughKant’sviewconcerningtheexactroleofimagina-tioninsensoryexperienceiscontested, twopointsemergeascentral. First, Kantregardstheimaginationasplayingacrucialroleinthegenerationofcomplexsensoryrepresentationsofanobject(seeSellars(1978)forainfluentialexampleofthisinterpretation). Itistheimaginationthatmakesitpossibleto, e.g. haveasensoryexperience(inone’s“mind’seye”asitwere)ofacomplex, three-dimensional, geometricfigurewhoseidentityremainsconstantasitissubjecttotranslationsandrotationsinspace. Second, Kantregardstheimagination’smediatingrolebetweensensibilityandunderstandingascrucialforatleastsomekindsofconceptapplication(seeGuyer(1987)andPendlebury(1995)forfurtherdiscussion). ThismediatingroleinvolveswhatKantcalls the“schematization”ofaconceptandanadditionalmental faculty, thatofjudgment, towhichwe’llnowturn.

Kantdefinesthefacultyofjudgmentas“thecapacitytosubsumeunderrules, thatis, todis-tinguishwhethersomethingfallsunderagivenrule”(A132/B171). However, hespendscom-parativelylittletimediscussingthisfacultyinthefirst Critique. There, itseemstobediscussedasanextensionoftheactivityoftheunderstandinginapplyingconceptstoempiricalobjects(orourintuitiverepresentationsthereof). Itisnotuntilthethird Critique—Kant’s1790 CritiqueofJudgment—thatKantdistinguishesitasanindependentfacultywithaspecialrole. ThereKantspecifiestwodifferentwaysthefacultymightfunction(CJ 5:179; cf. CJ (FirstIntroduction)20:211)

Accordingtothefirst, judgmentsubsumesgivenobjectsunderconcepts, whicharethem-selvesalreadygiven. Thisroleappearsidenticaltotheroleheassignstothefacultyofjudgmentinthe CritiqueofPureReason. Thebasicideaisthatjudgmentfunctionstoassigntosomeintu-itedobject—e.g. aparticulardog—thecorrectconcept(e.g. <dog>). Thisconceptispresumedtobeone already possessedbythesubject. InthisactivitythefacultyoverlapswiththeroleKantsinglesoutfortheimaginationinthesectionofthefirst Critique entitled“OntheSchematismofthePureConceptsoftheUnderstanding”. Bothareconceivedofhereintermsoftheultimatefunctioningoftheunderstanding, sinceitistheunderstandingthatgeneratesconcepts.

Thesecondroleforthefacultyofjudgment, andwhatseemstomakeitadistinctivefacultyinitsownright, isthatof finding aconceptunderwhichto“subsume”someexperiencedobject.This iscalled judgment’s “reflecting” role (CJ 5:179). Here the subject ismeant toexercisethefacultyofjudgmentin generating anappropriateconceptforwhatisgiveninintuition(CJ(FirstIntroduction)20:211-13; JL 9:94–95; fordiscussionseeLonguenesse(1998), 163–166and195–197; Ginsborg(2006)).

Inadditiontothegenerationof(empirical)concepts, Kantalsodescribesreflectivejudgmentas responsible for scientific inquiry, in that itmust sortandclassifyobjects innature intoahierarchicaltaxonomyofgenus/speciesrelationships. Kantalsoutilizesthenotionofreflective

September16, 2015 7| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

judgmenttounifytheotherwiseseeminglyunrelatedtopicsofthe CritiqueofJudgment—viz.aestheticjudgmentsandteleologicaljudgmentsconcerningtheorderofnature.

Thusfar, thediscussionofKant’sviewofthemindhasfocusedprimarilyonthevariousmen-talfacultiesandtheircorrespondingrepresentationaloutput. Boththefacultyofimaginationandthatofjudgmentoperateonrepresentationsgivenfromsensibilityandtheunderstanding.Ingeneral, Kantconceivesoftheactivityofthemindintermsofkindsof“processing”ofrepre-sentations. Inthenextsub-sectionwe’llexaminethisnotionofmentalprocessingmoreclosely.

b. MentalProcessing

Kant’stermformentalprocessingis“combination”[Verbindung], andtheformofcombinationwithwhichheisprimarilyconcernediswhathecalls“synthesis”. Kantcharacterizessynthesisasthatactivitybywhichtheunderstanding“runsthrough”and“gatherstogether”representationsgiventoitbysensibilityinordertoformconcepts, judgments, andultimately, foranycognitiontotakeplaceatall(A77-8/B102-3). Synthesisisnotsomethingwearetypicallyawareofdoing.AsKantsays, itisa“ablindthoughindispensablefunctionofthesoul…ofwhichweareonlyseldomevenconscious(A78/B103)”.

Synthesisiscarriedoutbytheunitarysubjectofrepresentationonrepresentationsthatareeithergiven to it in sensibility (i.e. intuition)orproducedby it in thought (e.g. inanactofstipulativeconceptualdefinition). Whensynthesis iscarriedouton representations formingthecontentofaconceptorjudgment, itiscalled“intellectual”synthesis; whencarriedoutbytheimaginationonmaterialprovidedbysensibility(i.e. onintuitionandsensation), itiscalled“figurative”synthesis(B150-1). Inthe CritiqueofPureReason Kantisprimarilyconcernedwithsynthesisperformedonrepresentationsprovidedbysensibility, anddiscussesthreecentralkindsofsynthesis–viz. apprehension, reproduction(orimagination), andrecognition(orconceptu-alization)(A98-110/B159-61). ThoughKantdiscussestheseformsofsynthesisasiftheywerediscretetypesofmentalacts, itseemsthatatleastthefirsttwoformsmustalwaysoccurtogether,whilethethirdmayormaynotalwaysoccuraswell(cf. Brook(1997); Allais(2009)).

Oneof thecentral topicsofdebate in theinterpretationofKant’sviewsonsynthesishasbeenwhetherKant endorses a position concerning thenatureof sensory experience called“conceptualism.” Roughly, conceptualismaboutexperienceistheclaimthatthecapacityforconscioussensoryexperienceoftheobjectiveworlddepends, atleastinpart, ontherepertoireofconceptspossessedbytheexperiencingsubject, insofarasthoseconceptsareexercisedinactsofsynthesisbytheunderstanding. I discussthisfurtherbelow, insection3.

Kanttypicallycontrastssynthesiswithotherwaysinwhichrepresentationsmightberelated,mostimportantly, byassociation(e.g. B139-40). Associationisprimarilya passive processbywhichthemindcomestoconnectrepresentationsduetotherepeatedexposureofthesubjecttocertainkindsofregularities. Onemightcome, forexampletoassociatethoughtsofchickensoupwiththoughtsofbeingill, becauseoneonlyeverhadchickensoupwhenonewasill. Incontrast, synthesisisafundamentally active process, dependentuponthemind’sspontaneity,andisthemeansbywhichgenuinejudgmentispossible.

Consider, forexample, thedifferencebetween themerelyassociative transitionbetweenholdingastoneandthefeelingofitsweight, ascomparedtothejudgmentthatthestoneisheavy(B142). Theassociationoftheholdingofthestonewithafeelingofweightisnotyetajudgmentaboutthestone, butmerelyakindofinvoluntaryconnectionbetweentwostatesofoneself. In

September16, 2015 8| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

contrast, inthinkingofthestone, thatitisheavy, onemovesbeyondmerelyassociatingtwofeelingstoathoughtabouthowthingsareobjectively, i.e. independentlyofone’sownmentalstates(Pereboom(1995), Pereboom(2006)). OneofKant’smostimportantpointsconcerningmentalprocessingisthatassociationcannotexplainthepossibilityofobjectivejudgment, andthatwhatisrequiredisatheoryofmentalprocessingbyanactive(or“spontaneous”)subjectcapableofactsofsynthesis.

Wecansummarizeseveraloftheimportantdifferencesbetweensynthesisandassociationasfollows(Pereboom(1995), 4-7):

1. Thesourceofsynthesis is tobefoundinasubjectandthissubject isdistinct fromitsstates.

2. Synthesiscanemployaprioriconceptsasmodesofprocessingrepresentations, whereasassociationneverdoes.

3. Synthesisistheproductofacausallyactivesubject-itisproducedbyacausethatisrealizedinafacultyofthesubject(eithertheimaginationortheunderstanding).

Kant’sconceptionofsynthesisandjudgmentistiedupwithhisconceptionof“consciousness”[Bewußtsein]and“self-consciousness”[Selbstbewußtsein]. However, thesetwonotionsrequiresomesignificantunpacking, sowe’lllookattheminthenextsection.

2. Consciousness

Thenotionofconsciousness[Bewußtsein]playsanimportantroleinKant’sphilosophy. Thereare, however, severaldifferentsensesof“consciousness”inplayinKant’swork, notallofwhichlineupwith contemporaryphilosophicalusage. BelowI detailseveralofKant’smostcentralnotionsandtheirdifferencesfromandrelationstocontemporaryusage.

a. PhenomenalConsciousness

Contemporaryphilosophicaldiscussionsofconsciousnesstypicallyfocusonphenomenalcon-sciousness, or“whatitislike”tohaveaconsciousexperienceofaparticularkind(e.gseeingthecolorred, smellingarose, etc.). Such qualitativefeaturesofconsciousness havebeenofmajorconcerntophilosophersinthelastseveraldecades. However, themetaphysicalissueofphe-nomenalconsciousnessisalmostentirelyignoredbyKant, perhapsbecauseheisunconcernedwithproblemsstemmingfromcommitmentstonaturalismorphysicalism. Heseemstoattributeallqualitativecharacteristicsofconsciousnesstosensationandwhathecalls“feeling”[Gefühl](CJ 5:206). Kantdistinguishesbetweensensationandfeelingintermsofanobjective/subjectivedistinction. Sensationsindicateorpresentfeaturesofobjects, distinctfromthesubjectofexpe-rience. Feelings, incontrast, presentonlystatesofthesubjecttoconsciousness. Kant’stypicalexamplesofsuchfeelingsincludepainandpleasure(B66-7; CJ 5:189, 203-6).

Thus, whileKantclearlyassignsacognitiveroletosensation, andallowsthatitis“throughsensation”thatwecognitivelyrelatetoobjectsgiveninsensibility(A20/B34), hedoesnotfocusinanysubstantiveorsystematicwayonthephenomenalaspectsofsensoryconsciousness, orhowitisexactlythattheyaidincognitionoftheempiricalworld.

September16, 2015 9| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

b. Discrimination&Differentiation

Thecentralnotionof“consciousness”withwhichKantisconcernedisthatofdiscriminationordifferentiation. ThisistheconceptionofconsciousnessthatwasmostlyinuseinKant’stime,particularlybyhismajorpredecessors GottfriedWilhelmLeibniz (1646–1716)andChristianWolff(1679-1754), andhegiveslittleindicationthathedepartsfromtheirgeneralpractice.

AccordingtoKant, anythingwhichasubjectcandiscriminatefromotherthingsisathingofwhichasubjectisorcanbeconscious(An7:136-8). Representationswhichallowfordis-criminationanddifferentiationare“clear”[klar]. Representationswhichallownotonlyforthedifferentiationofonethingfromothers(e.g. differentiatingoneperson’sfacefromanother’s),butalsothedifferentiationofpartsofthethingsodiscriminated(e.g. differentiatingthedifferentpartsofaperson’sface)arecalled“distinct”[deutlich].

Kantdoesseemtodeny, asagainsttheLeibniz-Wolfftradition, thatclaritycansimplybeequated withconsciousness(B414-15, note). Hisprimarymotivationforthispositionseemstobethatheallowsthatone’sdiscriminatorycapacitiesmayoutrunone’scapacityformemoryoreventheexplicitarticulationofwhatissodiscriminated. Insuchcasesonedoesnothaveafullyclearrepresentation.

Kant’sconceptionof“obscure”[dunkel]representationasthatwhichallowsthesubjectofthe representation todiscriminatedifferentiallybetweenaspectsofherenvironmentwithoutanyexplicitawarenessofthebasisbywhichsheisdoingso, connectshimwiththeLeibniz-Wolfftraditionofrecognizingtheexistenceof unconscious representations(An7:135-7). Kantconceivesofthemajorityofrepresentationsthatweappealtoinordertoexplainthecomplexdiscriminatorybehaviorsoflivingorganismsasbeing“obscure”inhistechnicalsense. LikeningthemindtoamapKantgoessofarastosaythat

Thefieldof sensuous intuitionsand sensationsofwhichwearenot conscious,eventhoughwecanundoubtedlyconcludethatwehavethem; thatis, obscurerepresentationsinthehumanbeing(andthusalsoinanimals), isimmense. Clearrepresentations, ontheotherhand, containonlyinfinitelyfewpointsofthisfieldwhichlieopentoconsciousness; sothatasitwereonlyafewplacesonthevastmapofourmindare illuminated. (An7:135)

Thus, obscurerepresentations, i.e. representationsofwhichwehavenodirectornon-inferentialawareness, butwhichmustbeposited toexplainour (and thoseofother livingbeings)finegraineddifferentialdiscriminatorycapacities, constitutethemajorityofthementalrepresenta-tionswithwhichthemindbusiesitself.

ThoughKantdoesnotmakethispointexplicitinhisdiscussionofdiscriminationandcon-sciousness, itisclearthathetakesourcapacitytodiscriminatebetweenobjectsandpartsofobjectstobeultimatelybasedonoursensoryrepresentationofthoseobjects. Thismeansthathisviewsonconsciousnessasdifferentialdiscriminationintersectwithhisviewsonphenom-enalconsciousnessinthefollowingmanner. Sincewearereceptivebeings, andtheformofourreceptivityissensibility, theultimatebasisonwhichwedifferentiallydiscriminatebetweenobjectsmustbesensory, andhenceonwhatitisliketoperceivethoseobjects. Thus, thoughKantseemstotakeforgrantedthefactthatconsciousbeingsareinstateswithaparticularphe-nomenalcharacter, itmustbetheclarityanddistinctnessofthisphenomenalcharacterwhichallowsaconscioussubjecttodifferentiallydiscriminatebetweenthevariouselementsofherenvironment(seeKant’sdiscussionofaestheticperfectioninthe1801 JäscheLogic, 9:33-9forrelevantdiscussion).

September16, 2015 10| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

c. Self-Consciousness

Asthediscussionofunconsciousrepresentationindicates, Kantbelievesthatmostofourrepre-sentationsareonesofwhichwearenotdirectlyaware. Theyareneverthelesstosomedegreeconscious, sincetheyallowdifferentialdiscriminationofelementsofthesubject’senvironment.Kantseemstothinkthattheprocessofmakingarepresentationclear, orfullyconscious, requiresahigher-orderrepresentationoftherelevantrepresentation. AsKantsays, “consciousnessisre-allytherepresentationthatanotherrepresentationisinme”(JL 9:33). Sincethishigher-orderrepresentationisoneofanotherrepresentation inme, Kant’spositionheresuggeststhatcon-sciousnessrequiresatleastthecapacityforself-consciousness. ThispositionisreinforcedbyKant’sfamousclaimintheTranscendentalDeductionofthe CritiqueofPureReason that

The I thinkmust beable toaccompanyallmyrepresentations; forotherwisesome-thingwouldberepresented inmethatcouldnotbe thoughtatall, which isasmuchastosaythattherepresentationwouldeitherbeimpossibleorelseatleastwouldbenothingforme. (B131-2; emphasisintheoriginal)

Kantmightgivetheimpressionhereofsayingthatforrepresentationtobepossibleforasubject,thatsubjectmustpossessthecapacityforself-ascribingherrepresentations. IfKantreallydidendorsethisself-ascriptioncondition, thenrepresentation, andthusthecapacityforconsciousrepresentation, ineitherofthephenomenalordiscriminatorysensesoutlinedabove, wouldde-pendonthecapacityforself-consciousness. SinceKanttiesthecapacityforself-consciousnesstospontaneity(B132, 137, 423), andrestrictsspontaneitytotheclassofrationalbeings, thedemandforself-ascriptionwouldseemtodenythatanynon-rationalanimal(e.g. dogs, cats,birds, etc.), atleastaccordingtoKant’sconceptionofsuchanimalsaslackingunderstandingandreason, couldhavephenomenalordiscriminatoryconsciousness!

However, thereislittleevidencetoshowthatKantendorsestheself-ascriptioncondition.Instead, hedistinguishesbetweentwodistinctmodesinwhichoneisawareofoneselfandone’srepresentations, via“inner sense”andvia“apperception” (SeeAmeriks (2000) forextensivediscussion). Onlythelatterformofawarenessseemstodemandacapacityforself-ascription.We’lltakethesetwonotionsinturn.

i. InnerSense

Innersenseis, accordingtoKant, themeansbywhichweareawareofalterationsinourownstate. Henceallsensations, includingsuchbasicalterationsaspleasureandpain, aswellasmoodsandfeelings, areallthepropersubjectmatterofinnersense. Ultimately, Kantarguesthatnotonlyallsensationsandfeelings, butallrepresentationsattributabletoasubjectwhatsoevermustultimatelyoccurininnersenseandconformtoitsform, time(A22-3/B37; A34/B51).

Thus, tobeawareofsomethingininnersenseisminimally, atleastinthecaseoftheaware-nessofsensationsandfeelings, tobephenomenallyconscious. Tosaythatasubjectisawareofherownstatesviainnersenseistosaythatshehas(atleast)atemporallyorderedseriesofmentalstates, eachofwhichsheisphenomenallyconscious, thoughshemaynotbeconsciousoftheseriesasawhole. Thiscouldstillcountasakindofself-awareness, aswhenananimalsisawareofbeinginpain. Butitisnotanawarenessofsubjectasa self. KanthimselfindicatessuchapositioninalettertohisfriendandformerstudentMarcusHerzin1789.

September16, 2015 11| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

[representations]couldstill(I considermyselfasananimal)carryontheirplayinanorderlyfashion, asconnectedaccordingtoempiricallawsofassociation, andthustheycouldevenhaveinfluenceonmyfeelinganddesire, withoutmybeingawareofmyownexistence[meinesDaseinsunbewußt](assumingthatI amevenconsciousofeachindividualrepresentation, butnotoftheirrelationtotheunityofrepresentationoftheirobject, bymeansofthesyntheticunityoftheirapperception).Thismightbesowithoutmycognizingtheslightestthingthereby, notevenwhatmyownconditionis(C 11:52, May26, 1789).

Hence, accordingtoKant, onemaybeawareofone’srepresentationsviainnersense, butoneisnotandcannotviainnersensealoneawareofoneselfasthe subject ofthoserepresentations.ThatrequireswhatKant, followingLeibniz(1996)calls“apperception”.

ii. Apperception

Kantusestheterm“apperception”todenotethecapacityfortheawarenessofsomestateormodificationofone’sselfasjustsuchastate. Forabeingcapableofapperception, thereisadifferencebetweenfeelingapain, andthusbeingawareofitininnersense, andapperceivingthatoneisinpain, andthusascribing, orbeinginapositiontoascribe, acertainpropertyorstateofmindtoone’sself. Intheexampleabove, ofanon-apperceptiveanimalasbeingawareofitsownpain, whilethereissomething(inthiscaseratherunpleasant)itisliketobetheanimal,andtheanimalisitselfawareofthis–thepain, anditsawarenessispartiallyexplanatoryofitsbehavior(e.g. avoidance), Kantconstruestheanimalasincapableofmakinganyself-attributionofitspain. Kantseemstothinkofsuchamindasincapableofconstruingitselfasasubjectofstates, andthusasunabletoconstrueitselfaspersistingthroughchangesofthosestates. Thisisnotnecessarilytosaythatananimalincapableofapperceptionlacksanysubjectorself. But,attheveryleast, suchananimalwouldbeincapableofconceivingorrepresentingitselfinthisway(SeeNaragon(1990); McLear(2011)).

Kantconsidersthecapacityforapperceptionasimportantlytiedtothecapacitytorepresentobjectsascomplexesofpropertiesattributabletoasingleunderlyingentity(e.g. anappleasasubjectofthecomplexoftheproperties red and round). Kant’sargumentforthisconnectionisnotoriousbothforitscomplexityandforitsobscurity. Inthenextsub-sectionI giveanoverview,thoughnotanexhaustivediscussion, ofsomeofKant’smostimportantpointsconcerningthesematters, astheyrelatetotheissueofapperception.

d. UnityofConsciousness&theCategories

InorderthatwemaybetterunderstandKant’sviewsonapperceptionandunityofconsciousness,weneedtostepbackandlookatthewidercontextoftheargumentinwhichhesituatestheseviews. OneofthecoreprojectsofKant’smostfamouswork, the CritiqueofPureReason, istoprovideanargumentforthelegitimacyofaprioriknowledgeofthenaturalworld. ThoughKant’sconceptionof theapriori iscomplex, onecentralaspectofhisview, sharedwithhisGermanrationalistpredecessors(e.g. Leibniz(1996), preface), isthatwehaveknowledgeofuniversalandnecessarytruthsconcerningaspectsoftheempiricalworld(B4-5), including, e.g.,thateveryeventintheempiricalworldhasacause(B231). Thistraditiontendedtoexplainthe

September16, 2015 12| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

possessionofknowledgeofsuchuniversalandnecessarytruthsbyappealtoinnateconceptswhosecontentcouldbeanalyzedtoyieldtherelevantknowledge. Kantimportantlydepartsfromtherationalisttraditionbyarguingthatnotallknowledgeofuniversalandnecessarytruthsisacquiredviatheanalysisofconcepts(B14-18). Therearesome“synthetic”aprioritruthsthatareknownonthebasisofsomethingotherthanconceptualanalysis. Thus, accordingtoKant,theactivityofpurereasonachievesrelativelylittleonitsown. AllofourampliativeknowledgethatisalsonecessaryanduniversalconsistsinwhatKantcalls“syntheticapriori”judgmentsorpropositions. Thecentralquestionhethenpursuesconcernshowknowledgeofsuchsyntheticaprioripropositionsispossible.

Kant’sbasicanswertothequestionofsyntheticaprioriknowledgeinvolveswhathecallsthe“CopernicanTurn”, accordingtowhichtheobjectsofhumanknowledgemust“conform”tothebasicfacultiesofhumanknowledge–viz. theformsofintuition(spaceandtime)andtheformsofthought(thecategories).

Kantthusengagesinatwo-partstrategyforexplainingthepossibilityofsuchsyntheticaprioriknowledge. Thefirstpartconsistsinarguingthatthepureformsofintuitionprovidethebasisforoursyntheticaprioriknowledgeofmathematicaltruths. Mathematicalknowledgeissyntheticbecauseitgoesbeyondmereconceptualanalysistodealwiththestructureof(ourrepresentationof)spaceitself. Itisaprioribecausethestructureof(ourrepresentationof)spaceisaprioriaccessibletous, beingmerelytheformofourintuitionandnotarealmind-independentthing(a“thinginitself”asKantwouldcallit).

However, inadditiontotherepresentationofspaceandtime, Kantalsothinksthatpossessionofaparticularprivilegedsetofaprioriconceptsisnecessaryforknowledgeoftheempiricalworld. Butthisraisesaproblem. Howcouldanaprioriconcept, whichisnotitselfderivedfromanyparticularexperience, beneverthelesslegitimatelyapplicabletoobjectsofexperience?Tomakethingsevenmoredifficult, itisnotthemerepossibilityoftheapplicationofaprioriconceptstoobjectsofexperiencethatworriesKant, forthiscouldjustbeamatterofpureluck.Kantwantsevenmorethanmerepossibility, forhewantstoshowthatwithregardtoaprivilegedsetofaprioriconcepts, theyapplynecessarilyanduniversallytoallobjectsofexperienceanddosoinawaythatweareinapositiontoknowindependentlyofexperience.

ThisbringsustothesecondpartofKant’sargument, whichisdirectlyrelevantforunder-standingKant’sviewsontheimportanceofapperception. Notonlymustobjectsofknowledgeconformtotheformsofintuition, theyalsomustconformtothemostbasicconcepts(or“cate-gories”)governingourcapacityforthought. Kant’sstrategyisthustoshowhowaprioriconceptslegitimatelyapplytotheirobjectsinvirtueofbeingpartlyconstitutiveoftheobjectsofrepresen-tation, ratherthanthetraditionalviewaccordingtowhichtheobjectsofrepresentationwerethesourceorexplanatorygroundofourconcepts(Bxvii-xix). Now, exactlywhatthismeansisdeeplycontested, inpartbecause it is ratherunclearwhatKant intendsus tounderstandbyhisdoctrineofTranscendentalIdealism. Forexample, doesKantintendthattheobjectsofrepresentationare themselves nothingotherthanrepresentations? Thiswouldbeaformofphe-nomenalismsimilar to thatofferedby Berkeley. Kant, however, seems towant todeny thathisviewissimilartoBerkeley’s, assertinginsteadthattheobjectsofrepresentationreallyexistindependentlyofthemind, andthatitisonlythe way thattheyarerepresentedthatismind-dependent(A92/B125; cf. Pr4:288-94).

WhatmakesKant’s“CopernicanTurn”relevantforourdiscussionisthathisstrategyforvali-datingthelegitimacyoftheaprioricategoriesproceedsbywayofa“transcendentalargument”

September16, 2015 13| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

tyingtogethertheconditionsnecessaryforconsciousnessoftheidentityofoneselfasthesub-jectofdifferentself-attributedmentalstateswiththosenecessaryforgroundingthepossibilityofrepresentinganobjectdistinctfromoneself, ofwhichvariouspropertiesmaybepredicated.Inthissense, Kantarguesthattheintellectualrepresentationofsubjectandobjectstandandfalltogether. Kantthusdeniesthepossibilityofaself-conscioussubject, whocouldconceptu-alizeandself-ascribeherrepresentations, butwhoserepresentationscouldnotrepresentlaw-governedobjectsinspace, andthusthematerialworldor“nature”asthesubjectconceivesofit.

ThoughKant’sviewsregardingtheunityofthesubjectarecontested, thereareseveralpointswhichcanbemadefairlyclearly. First, Kantconceivesofallspecificallyintellectualactivity,includingthemostbasicinstancesofdiscursivethought, asrequiringwhathecallsthe“originalunityofapperception”(B132). Thisunity, asoriginal, isnotitselfbroughtaboutbysomementalactofcombiningrepresentations, butasKantsays, is“whatmakestheconceptofcombinationpossible”(B131), anditisitselfthegroundofthe“possibilityoftheunderstanding”(B131).

Second, theoriginalunityofapperceptionrequireswhateverformofself-consciousnesschar-acteristicallyrelatestothe“I think”. AsKantfamouslysays, “the I think mustbeabletoaccom-panyallmyrepresentations”(B131). Moreover, the“I think”essentiallyinvolvesactivityonthepartofthesubject–itisanexpressionofthesubject’sfreeactivityor“spontaneity”(B132). Thismeansthat, accordingtoKant, onlybeingscapableofspontaneousactivity–i.e. self-initiatedactivitythatisultimatelytracedtocausesoutsidethereachofnaturalcausallaws–aregoingtobecapableof thought inthesensewithwhichKantisconcerned.

Third, andrelatedtothepreviouspoint, Kantseemstodenythatasubjectcouldattainthekindofrepresentationalunitycharacteristicofthoughtifheronlyresourceswereaggregativemethods. Kantmakesthispointlaterinthe Critique whenhesays, “representationsthataredistributedamongdifferentbeings(forinstance, theindividualwordsofaverse)neverconstituteawholethought(averse)”(A 352). Inanoften-citedpassage, WilliamJamesprovidesavividarticulationoftheidea: “Takeasentenceofadozenwords, andtaketwelvemenandtelltoeachoneword. Thenstandthemeninaroworjamtheminabunch, andleteachthinkofhiswordasintentlyashewill; nowherewilltherebeaconsciousnessofthewholesentence”(James(1890), 160). Kantthusconstruesconsciousnessasthe“holding-together”ofthevariouscomponentsofathoughtinamannerthatseemsradicallyopposedtoanyconceptionofunitarythoughtwhichtriestoexplainitintermsofsometrainorsuccessionofitscomponents(Pr4:304;seeKitcher(2010); Engstrom(2013)forcontrastingtreatmentsofthisissue).

TheexactcontentofKant’sargumentfortheconnectionbetweensubjectandobjectintheTranscendentalDeductionishighlydisputed, anditislikelythatnosinglereconstructionoftheargumentcanitselfcaptureallofthepointsforwhichKantarguesintheDeduction. BelowI presentatleastonestrandofKant’sargumentasitappearsinthefirsthalfoftheDeduction.HereI focusonKant’sdenialthattheunityofthesubjectanditspowersofrepresentationalcombinationcouldbeaccountedforbyamerelyassociationist (i.e. Humean)conceptionofmentalcombination, sometimes termedhis “argument fromabove” (seeA119; Carl (1989);Pereboom(1995)). I takeKant’sargumenthereasfollows(seePereboom(2009)):

1. I amconsciousof the identityofmyselfas thesubjectofdifferentself-attributionsofmentalstates.

2. I amnotdirectlyconsciousoftheidentityofthissubjectofdifferentself-attributionsofmentalstates.

September16, 2015 14| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

3. If(1)and(2)aretrue, thenthisconsciousnessofidentityisaccountedforindirectlybymyconsciousnessofaparticularkindofunityofmymentalstates.

4. ∴ Thisconsciousnessof identity isaccountedfor indirectlybymyconsciousnessofaparticularkindofunityofmymentalstates. (1, 2, 3)

5. If(4)istrue, thenmymentalstatesindeedhavethisparticularkindofunity.6. Thisparticularkindofunityofmymentalstatescannotbeaccountedforbyassociation.

(5)7. If (6) is true, thenthisparticularkindofunityofmymentalstatesisaccountedforby

synthesisbyaprioriconcepts.8. ∴ Thisparticularkindofunityofmymentalstatesisaccountedforbysynthesisbyapriori

concepts. (6, 7)

Premise(1)saysthatI amawareofmyself(oratleastinapositiontobesoaware)asthesubjectofdifferentstates. Forexample, rightnowI mightbehungryaswellassleepy. PreviouslyI wassleepyandslightlybored. Premise(2)claimsthatI havenoimmediateordirectawarenessofthebeingwhichhasallofthesestates. InKant’sterms, I lackany intuition ofthesubjectofsuchself-ascribedstates, insteadhavingintuitiononlyofthestatesthemselves. Nevertheless,I amawareofallofthesestatesasrelatedtoasubject(itis I whoambored, hungry, sleepy),anditisinvirtueoftheseconnectionsthatI cancalloneandallofthesestates mine. Hence,aspremise(3)argues, theremustbesomeunity tomymentalstateswhichaccounts formy(indirect)awareness(ormybeinginapositiontobesoaware)oftheirunity. Myrepresentationsmusthavesomebasis forwhich theygo together, and it is thebasis for their“togetherness”thatexplainshowI canconsiderthem, oneandall, tobemine. Premises(4)and(5)unpackthispoint, andpremise(6)arguesthatassociationcouldnotaccountforsuchunity(thetheoryofassociationwasarticulatedinaparticularlyinfluentialformby DavidHume (1888, Hume(2007))andthereadershouldlooktothatentryforrelevantbackgrounddiscussion).

Kant’spoint, inpremise(6)oftheaboveargument, isthatforcesofassociationactingonmentalrepresentations(whetherimpressionsorideas)cannotaccountforeithertheexperienceofatrainofrepresentationsas mine, orforthe“togetherness”ofthoserepresentations, bothinasinglethoughtorinaseriesofinferences. Humearguesthatwehavenoimpression(andthusnoensuingidea)ofanempiricalself(Hume(1888), I.iv.6). Kantalsoacceptsthispointwhenhesaysthat“theempiricalconsciousnessthataccompaniesdifferentrepresentationsisbyitselfdispersedandwithoutrelationtotheidentityofthesubject”(B133). BythisKantmeansthatwhenweintrospectininnersense, allweevergetareparticularmentalstates(e.g. boredom,happiness, particularthoughts, etc.). Welackanyintuitionofasubjectofthosementalstates.Humeconcludesthattheideaofapersistingselfwhichgroundsallofthesementalstatesasitssubjectmustbeafiction. Kantdisagrees. Kant’scontrastingviewtakestheminenessandtogethernessofone’sintrospectiblementalstatesasadatumneedingexplanation, andsinceanassociativepsychologicaltheorylikethatofHume’scannotexplainthesefeaturesoffirst-personconsciousness(Humehimselfwasawareofthisproblem, seeHume(1888), III.Appendix), weneedtofindanothertheory–viz. Kant’stheoryofmentalsynthesis.

Recallthat, priortotheargumentoftheTranscendentalDeduction, Kantlinkstheoperationsofsynthesistopossessionofasetofaprioriconcepts(conceptswhosecontentisnotderivedfromexperience)–viz. thecategories. Hence, inarguingthatsynthesisisrequiredtoexplain

September16, 2015 15| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

theminenessandtogethernessofone’smentalstates, andbylinkingsynthesistotheapplica-tionofthecategories, Kantarguesthatwecouldnothavetheexperienceoftheminenessandtogethernessofourmentalstateswithoutapplyingthecategories.

WhilethisargumentisonlyhalfofKant’sargumentinthefirstpartoftheDeduction(theotherhalfconsistingofan“argument frombelow”, concerning theconditionsnecessary fortherepresentationofunitaryobjects, seePereboom(1995), (2009)), itshowshowtightlyKanttooktheconnectiontobebetweenthecapacitiesforspontaneity, synthesisandapperception,andthelegitimacyofthecategories. AccordingtoKant, theonlypossibleexplanationofone’sapperceptiveawarenessofone’spsychological statesasone’sownandasall related tooneanotheristhat, asthesubjectofsuchstates, onepossessesaspontaneouspowerforsynthesizingone’srepresentationsaccordingtogeneralprinciplesorrules, thecontentofwhichisgivenbypureaprioriconcepts–thecategories. Thefactthatthecategoriesplaysuchafundamentalrole in thegenerationof self-consciouspsychological states is thusapowerfulargument fordemonstrationoftheirlegitimacy.

Given thatKant leveragescertainaspectsofourcapacity for self-knowledge inhisargu-mentforthelegitimacyofthecategories, theextenttowhichhearguesforradicallimitsonourcapacityforself-knowledgemaysurpriseone. InthefinalsectionI discussKant’sargumentsconcerningourcapacityforaprioriknowledgeoftheselfanditsfundamentalfeatures. How-ever, inthenextsectionI lookatoneofthecentraldebatesinKantinterpretationconcerningtheroleofconceptsinperceptualexperience.

3. Concepts&Perception

DuringthediscussionofsynthesisaboveI characterizedconceptualismasclaimingthatthereisadependencerelationbetweenasubject’shavingconscioussensoryexperienceofanobjectiveworld, and the repertoireofconceptspossessedby thesubjectandexercised inactsbyherfacultyofunderstanding.

Asafirstpassatsharpeningthisformulation, wemayunderstandconceptualismasathe-sisconsistingoftwoclaims: (i)senseexperiencehascorrectnessconditionsdeterminedbythe“content”oftheexperience; (ii)thecontentofanexperienceisastructuredentitywhosecom-ponentsareconcepts. Let’staketheseinturn.

a. Content&Correctness

Animportantbackgroundassumptiongoverning theconceptualismdebateconstruesmentalstatesas related to theworldcognitively (asopposed tomerelycausally) ifandonly if theypossesscorrectnessconditions. Thatwhichdeterminesthecorrectnessconditionforastateisthatstate’s“content”(seeSiegel(2010), (2011); Schellenberg(2011)).

Suppose, forexample, thatanexperienceE hasthefollowingcontentC:

C:Thatcupiswhite.

ThiscontentdeterminesacorrectnessconditionV:

September16, 2015 16| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

V:S’sexperienceE iscorrectiffthecupvisuallypresentedtothesubjectasthecontentofthedemonstrativeiswhiteandthecontentC correspondstohowthingsseemtothesubjecttobevisuallypresented.

Herethecontentoftheexperientialstatefunctionsmuchlikethecontentofabeliefstatetodeterminewhethertheexperience, likethebelief, isorisnotcorrect.

A state’spossessionofcontentthusdeterminesacorrectnesscondition, invirtueofwhichwecanconstruethestateasmapping, mirroring, orotherwisetrackingaspectsofthesubject’senvironment.

Thereare reasons forquestioningwhetherKant endorses thecontent assumptionas I’vearticulateditabove(seeMcLear(2015a)). Kantseemstodenyseveralclaimswhichareintegraltoit. First, invariousplacesheexplicitlydeniesthatintuition, orthedeliverancesofthesensesmoregenerally, arethekindofthingwhichcouldbecorrectorincorrect(A293–4/B350; An§117:146; cf. LL 24:83ff, 103, 720ff, 825ff). Second, Kant’sconceptionofrepresentationalcontentrequiresanactofmentalunification(Pr4:304; cf. JL §179:101; LL 24:928), somethingwhichKantexplicitlydeniesispresentinanintuition(B129-30; cf. B176-7). ThisisnottodenythatKantusesanotionof“content”insomeothersense, butratheronlythathefailstouseinthesenserequiredbyinterpretationsendorsingthecontentassumption(seeTolley(2014), (2013)).Finally, Kant’s“modal”conditiononcognition, thatitprovideademonstrationofwhatisreallyactualratherthanmerelylogicallypossible, seemstoprecludeanendorsementofthecontentassumption(Bxxvii, note; cf. Chignell(2014)). However, forthepurposesofunderstandingtheconceptualismdebate, wewillassumethatKantdoesendorsethecontentassumption. Thequestionthenishowtounderstandthenatureofthecontentsounderstood.

b. ConceptualContent

Inadditiontothecontentassumption, I definedconceptualismascommittedtoaconceptionof thecontentof intuitionasbeingcompletelycomposedofconcepts. Against this, ClintonTolley(Tolley(2013), Tolley(2014))hasarguedthattheimmediacy/mediacydistinctionbetweenintuitionandconceptentailsadifferenceinthecontentofintuitionandconcept.

if we understand by “content”…a representation’s particular relation to an ob-ject…thenitisclearthatweshouldconcludethatKantacceptsnon-conceptualcontent. ThisisbecauseKantacceptsthatintuitionsputusinarepresentationalrelationtoobjectsthatisdistinctinkindfromtherelationthatpertainstoconcepts.I argued, furthermore, thatthisisthemeaningthatKanthimselfassignstotheterm“content”. (Tolley(2013), 128)

InsofarasKantoftenspeaksofthe“content”[Inhalt]ofarepresentationasconsistinginapartic-ularkindofrelationtoanobject(Tolley(2013), 112; cf. B83, B87)Tolley’sproposalthusgivesusgroundforasimpleandstraightforwardargumentforanon-conceptualistreadingofKant.HoweveritdoesnotnecessarilyprovethatthecontentofwhatKantcallsanintuitionisnotsomethingthat we wouldconstrueasconceptual, inawidersenseofthatterm. Forexample,bothpure(e.g. that, this)andcomplexdemonstrativeexpressions(e.g. thatcolor, thisperson)haveconceptualform, andhavebeenproposedasappropriateforcapturingthecontentofex-perience(e.g. McDowell(1996), ch. 3; fordiscussionseeHeck(2000)). Demonstrativesarenot,inKant’sterms, “conceptual”sincetheydonotexhibittherequisitegeneralitywhich, accordingtoKant, allconceptualrepresentationmust.

September16, 2015 17| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

c. Conceptualism&Synthesis

Ifitisn’ttextuallyplausibletounderstandthecontentofanintuitioninconceptualterms(atleastasKantunderstandsthenotionofaconcept)thenwhatwoulditmeantosaythatKantendorsesconceptualismwith regard toexperience? Themostplausible interpretation, endorsedbyawidevarietyofinterpreters, readsKantasarguingthatthegenerationofanintuition, whetherpureorsensory, dependsatleastinpartontheactivityoftheunderstanding. Onthiswayofcarvingthings, conceptualismdoes not consistinthenarrowclaimthatintuitionshaveconceptsascontentsorcomponents, butratherconsistsinthebroaderclaimthattheoccurrenceofanintuitiondependsatleastinpartonthediscursiveactivityoftheunderstanding. Thespecificactivityof theunderstanding is thatwhichKantcalls“synthesis”, the“running through, andgatheringtogether”ofrepresentations(A99).

The conceptualist further argues that taking intuitions as generated via acts of synthesis,whicharedirectedbyorotherwisedependentuponconceptualcapacities, providessomebasisfortheclaimthatwhatevercorrectnessconditionsmightbehadbyintuitionmustbeinaccordwiththeconceptualsynthesiswhichgeneratedthem. ThisarguablyfitswellwithKant’smuchquotedclaim,

Thesamefunctionthatgivesunitytothedifferentrepresentationsin ajudgmentalso gives unity to the mere synthesis of different representations in an intu-ition, which, expressed generally, is called the pure concept of understanding.(A79/B104-5)

Thelinkbetweenintuition, synthesisinaccordancewithconcepts, andrelationtoanobjectismadeevenclearerbyKant’sclaimin§17oftheB-editionTranscendentalDeductionthat,

Understanding is, generallyspeaking, thefacultyof cognitions. Theseconsistinthedeterminaterelationofgivenrepresentationstoanobject. An object, however,isthatintheconceptofwhichthemanifoldofagivenintuitionis united. (B137;emphasisintheoriginal)

Howeverelsewearetounderstandthispassage, Kanthereindicatesthattheunityofanintuitionnecessaryforittostandasacognitionofanobjectrequiresasynthesisbytheconcept<object>.Inotherwords, cognitionofanobjectrequiresthatintuitionbeunifiedbyanactoractsoftheunderstanding.

Accordingtotheconceptualistinterpretationwemustunderstandthenotionofarepresen-tation’scontentasa relation toanobject, which in turndependsonaconceptuallyguidedsynthesis. Sowecanreviseourinitialdefinitionofconceptualismtoreaditasclaimingthat(i)thecontentof anintuitionisakindofrelationtoanobject; (ii)therelationtoanobjectdependsonasynthesisdirectedinaccordancewithconcepts; (iii)synthesisinaccordancewithconceptssetscorrectnessconditionsfortheintuition’srepresentationofamind-independentobject.

September16, 2015 18| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

d. ObjectionstoConceptualism

Attheheartofnon-conceptualistreadingsofKantstandsthedenialthatmentalactsofsynthesiscarriedoutbytheunderstandingarenecessaryfortheoccurrenceofcognitivementalstatesofthetypewhichKantdesignatesbytheterm“intuition”[Anschauung]. Thoughitiscontroversialastowhatmightbeconsideredthe“natural”or“default”readingofKant’smaturecriticalphi-losophy, thereareatleastfourconsiderationswhichlendstrongsupporttoanon-conceptualistinterpretationofKant’smaturework.

First, Kantrepeatedlyandforcefullystatesthatinourcognitionthereisastrictdivisionofcognitivelabor—objectsaregivenbysensibilityandthoughtviatheunderstanding.

Objectsaregiventousbymeansofsensibility, anditaloneyieldsusintuitions; theyarethoughtthroughtheunderstanding, andfromtheunderstandingariseconcepts(A19/B33; cf. A50/B74, A51/B75–6, A271/B327).

AsRobertHannahasargued, whenKantdiscussesthedependenceofintuitiononconceptualjudgmentintheAnalyticofConcepts, heisspecificallytalkingabout cognition ratherthanwhatwewouldconsidertobeperceptualexperience(Hanna(2005), 265-7).

Second, Kant characterizes the representational capacities characteristic of sensibility asmoreprimitivethanthosecharacteristicoftheunderstanding(orreason), andasplausiblypartofwhathumanssharewiththerestoftheanimalkingdom(Kantconnectsthepossessionofafacultyofsensibilitytoanimalnatureinvariousplaces, e.g. A546/B574, A802/B830; An7:196.)Forexample, Kant’sdistinctionbetweenthefacultiesofsensibilityandunderstandingasseemsintendedtocapturethedifferencebetweenthe“sub-rational”powersofthemindthatwesharewithnon-humananimals, andthe“rationalorhigher-levelcognitivepowers”thatarespecialtohumanbeings. (Hanna(2005), 249; cf. Allais(2009); McLear(2011))

Ifoneweretodenythat, accordingtoKant, sensibilityaloneiscapableofproducingmentalstatesthatwerecognitiveincharacterthen, aswaspointedoutinthesectiononconsciousness,itwouldseemthatanyanimalwhichlacksafacultyofunderstanding, andthusthecapacityforconceptualsynthesis, wouldtherebylackanycapacityforgenuinely perceptual experience.Thementallivesofnon-rationalanimalswouldthus, atbest, consistofnon-cognitivesensorystateswhichcausallycorrelatewithchangesintheanimal’senvironment. Asidefromanun-appealingandimplausiblecharacterizationofthecognitivecapacitiesofanimals(forrelevantdiscussionofsomeoftheissuesincontemporarycognitiveethologyseeBermúdez(2003); Lurz(2009); Andrews(2014), aswellasthepapersinLurz(2011)), thisreadingalsofacestextualhur-dles. Kantisonrecordinvariousplacesassayingthatanimalshavesensoryrepresentationsoftheirenvironment(CPJ 5:464; LM 28:449; cf. An7:212), thattheyhaveintuitions(LL 24:702),andthattheyareacquaintedwithobjectsthoughtheydonotcognizethem(JL 9:64–5)(seeNaragon(1990); Allais(2009); McLear(2011)).

Hence, ifKant’spositionisthatsyntheticactscarriedoutbytheunderstandingarenecessaryforthecognitivestandingofamentalstate, thenKantiscontradictingfundamentalelementsofhisownpositionincreditingintuitions(ortheirpossibility)tonon-rationalanimals.

Third, anypositionwhichregardsperceptualexperienceasdependentuponactsofsynthesiscarriedoutbytheunderstandingwouldpresumablyalsoconstruethe“pure”intuitionsofspaceandtimeasdependentuponactsofsynthesis(seeLonguenesse(1998), ch. 9; Griffith(2012)).

September16, 2015 19| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

However, Kant’sdiscussionofspace(andanalogously, time)inthethirdandfourtharguments(fourthandfifthinthecaseoftime)oftheMetaphysicalExpositionofSpaceintheTranscendentalAestheticseemsincompatiblewithsuchaproposedrelationofdependence.

Kant’spointinthethirdandfourthargumentsoftheMetaphysicalExpositionofspace(andsimilarlyoftime)isthatnofiniteintellectcouldgrasptheextentandnatureofspaceasaninfinitewholeviaasyntheticprocessinvolvingmovementfromrepresentationofaparttorepresenta-tionofthewhole. Iftheunityoftheformsofintuitionwereitselfsomethingdependentuponintellectualactivity, thenthisunitywouldnecessarilyinvolvethediscursive(thoughnotneces-sarilyconceptual)runningthroughandgatheringtogetherofagivenmultiplicity(presumablyofdifferentlocationsormoments)intoacombinedwhole, whichKantbelievesischaracteristicofsynthesisgenerally(A99).

ButKant’sarguments in theMetaphysicalExpositionsof spaceand time require that thefundamentalbasisofourrepresentationofspaceandtimedoesnotproceedfromagraspofthemultiplicityoffeaturesofanintuitedparticulartothewholethathasthosefeatures. Insteadtheformofpureintuitionconstitutesarepresentationalwholethatis prior tothatofitscomponentparts(cf. CJ 5:407-8, 409).

Hence, Kant’spositionisthatthepureintuitionsofspaceandtimepossessaunitywhollydifferentfromthatgivenbythediscursiveunityoftheunderstanding(whetheritbeinconcep-tualjudgmentortheintellectual cum imaginativesynthesisofintuitedobjectsmoregenerally).Theunityofaesthetic representation—characterizedby the formsof spaceand time—hasastructure inwhich the representationalpartsdependon thewhole. Theunityofdiscursiverepresentation—representationwheretheactivityoftheunderstandingisinvolved—hasastruc-tureinwhichtherepresentationalwholedependsonitsparts(seeMcLear(2015b)).

Finally, therehasbeenextensivediscussionofthenon-conceptualityofintuitioninthesec-ondary literatureonKant’sphilosophyofmathematics. Forexample, MichaelFriedmanhasarguedthattheexpressivelimitationsoftheprevailinglogicinKant’stimerequiredthepostula-tionofintuitionasaformofsingular, non-conceptualrepresentation(Friedman(1992), ch. 2;Anderson(2005); Sutherland(2008)). IncontrasttoFriedman’sview, CharlesParsonsandEmilyCarsonhavearguedthattheimmediacyofintuition, bothpureandempirical, shouldbecon-struedina“phenomenological”manner. Spaceinparticularisunderstoodontheirinterpre-tationasanoriginal, non-conceptualrepresentation, whichKanttakestobenecessaryforthedemonstrationoftherealpossibilityofconstructedmathematicalobjectsasrequiredforgeo-metricknowledge(Parsons(1964); Parsons(1992); Carson(1997); Carson(1999); cf. Hanna(2002). ForageneraloverviewofrelatedissuesinKant’sphilosophyofmathematicsseeShabel(2006)andtheworkscitedthereinatp. 107, note29.)

Ultimately, however, therearedifficultiesinassessingwhetherKant’sphilosophyofmath-ematicscanhaverelevancefortheconceptualismdebate, sincethesenseinwhichintuitionmustbenon-conceptualinaccountingformathematicalknowledgeisnotobviouslyincompat-iblewithclaimingthatintuitionsthemselves(includingpureintuition)aredependentuponaconceptually-guidedsynthesis.

Thenon-conceptualistreadingisthusclearlycommittedtoallowingthatsensibilityaloneprovides, inaperhapsveryprimitivemanner, objectiverepresentationoftheempiricalworld.Sensibility isconstruedasanindependentcognitivefaculty, whichhumanssharewithothernon-rationalanimals, andwhich is the jumping-offpoint formore sophisticatedconceptualrepresentationofempiricalreality.

September16, 2015 20| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

Inthenextandfinalsection, I lookatKant’sviewsregardingthenatureandlimitsofself-knowledgeandtheramificationsofthisfortraditionalrationalistviewsoftheself.

4. RationalPsychology&Self-Knowledge

Kantdiscussesthenatureandlimitsofourself-knowledgemostextensivelyinthefirst Critique,inasectionofthe TranscendentalDialectic calledthe“ParalogismsofPureReason”. HereKantisconcernedtocriticizetheclaimsofwhathecalls“rationalpsychology”, andspecifically, theclaimthatwecanhavesubstantivemetaphysicalknowledgeofthenatureofthesubject, basedpurelyonananalysisof theconceptof thethinkingself, orasKant typicallyputs it, the <Ithink>.

I think isthusthesoletextofrationalpsychology, fromwhichitistodevelopitsentirewisdom…becausetheleastempiricalpredicatewouldcorrupttherationalpurityandindependenceofthesciencefromallexperience. (A343/B401)

Therearefour“Paralogisms”. Eachargumentispresentedasa syllogism, whichconsistsoftwopremisesandaconclusion. AccordingtoKant, eachargumentisguiltyofanequivocationonatermcommontothepremises, suchthattheargumentisinvalid. Kant’saim, inhisdiscussionofeachParalogism, istodiagnosetheequivocation, andexplainwhytherationalpsychologist’sargumentultimatelyfails. InsodoingKantprovidesagreatdealofinformationabouthisownviewsconcerningthemind(SeeAmeriks(2000)forextensivediscussion). TheargumentofthefirstParalogismconcernsourknowledgeoftheselfassubstance; thesecond, thesimplicityoftheself; thethird, thenumericalidentityoftheself; thefourth, knowledgeoftheselfversusknowledgeofthingsinspace. We’lltaketheseargumentsinturn.

a. Substantiality(A348-51/B410-11)

Kantpresentstherationalist’sargumentintheFirstParalogismasfollows:

1. Whatcannotbethoughtotherwisethanassubjectdoesnotexistotherwisethanassubject,andisthereforesubstance.

2. Nowathinkingbeing, consideredmerelyassuch, cannotbethoughtotherwisethanassubject.

3. ∴ A thinkingbeingalsoexistsonlyassuchathing, i.e., assubstance.

Kant’spresentationoftheargumentisrathercompressed. Inmoreexplicitformwecanputitasfollows(seeProops(2010)):

1. Allentitiesthatcannotbethoughtotherwisethanassubjectsareentitiesthatcannotexistotherwisethanassubjects, andtherefore(bydefinition)aresubstances. (AllM areP)

2. Allentitiesthatarethinkingbeings(consideredmerelyassuch)areentitiesthatcannotbethoughtotherwisethanassubjects. (AllS areM)

3. ∴ Allentitiesthatarethinkingbeings(consideredmerelyassuch)areentitiesthatcannotexistotherwisethanassubjects, andthereforearesubstances(AllS areP)

September16, 2015 21| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

Therelevantequivocationisinthetermthatoccupiesthe“M” placeintheargument–viz. “en-titiesthatcannotbethoughtotherwisethanassubjects”. Kantspecificallylocatestheambiguityintheuseoftheterm“thought”[DasDenken], whichheclaimsistakeninthefirstpremisetoconcernanobjectingeneral, andthussomethingthatcouldbegiveninapossibleintuition. Inthesecondpremisetheuseof“thought”issupposedtoapplyonlytoafeatureofthoughtand,thus, nottoanobjectofapossibleintuition(B411-12).

Whileitisn’tobviouswhatKantmeansbythisclaim, somethinglikethefollowingseemsapt. Kanttakesthefirstpremisetobemakingaclaimabouttheobjectsofthought–viz. thatanobjectwhichexistsasanindependentsubjectorbearerofpropertiescannotbeconceivedofasanythingelse(e.g. itselfbeapropertyofafurthersubject). Thisisthusametaphysicalclaimaboutwhatkindsofobjectscouldreallyexist, whichexplainsKant’sreferencetoan“objectingeneral”thatcouldbegiveninintuition.

Incontrast, premise(2)makesamerely logical claimconcerningtheroleoftherepresenta-tion <I> inapossiblejudgment. Kant’spointhereisthatwecannotusetherepresentation <I>inanyplaceotherthanthesubjectplaceofajudgment. Forexample, whileI canmaketheclaim“I amtall”, I cannotmaketheclaim(itwouldmakenosense)“thetallisI”.

Againsttherationalpsychologist, Kantarguesthatwecannotmakeanylegitimateinferencefromtheconditionsunderwhich the representation <I> maybe thought, oremployed inajudgment, tothestatusofthe“I” asametaphysicalsubjectofproperties. Kantmakesthispointexplicitwhenhesays,

thefirstsyllogismoftranscendentalpsychologyimposesonusanonlyallegedlynewinsightwhenitpassesofftheconstantlogicalsubjectofthinkingasthecogni-tionofarealsubjectofinherence, withwhichwedonotandcannothavetheleastacquaintance, becauseconsciousnessistheonesinglethingthatmakesallrepre-sentationsintothoughts, andinwhich, therefore, asinthetranscendentalsubject,ourperceptionsmustbeencountered; andapartfromthislogicalsignificanceoftheI,wehavenoacquaintancewiththesubjectinitselfthatgroundsthisI asasubstratum, justasitgroundsallthoughts. (A350)

Kantthusarguesthatweshoulddifferentiatebetweendifferentconceptionsof“substance”andtheroletheyplayinourthoughtconcerningtheworld.

Substance0: x isa substance0 iff the representationofxcannotbeusedasapredicate inacategoricaljudgment

Substance1: xisasubstance1 iffitsexistenceissuchthatitcannever inhere inanythingelse(B288, 407)

Thefirstconceptionof substance ismerely logicalorgrammatical. The secondconceptionisexplicitlymetaphysical. Finally, thereisanevenmoremetaphysicallydemandingusageof“substance”thatKantemploys.

(Empirical)Substance2: x isa substance2 iff it isa substance1 thatpersistsateverymoment(A144/B183, A182)

September16, 2015 22| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

AccordingtoKant, therationalpsychologistattemptstomovefromclaimsaboutsubstance0tothemorerobustlymetaphysicalclaimscharacteristicofourconceptionanduseofsubstance1andsubstance2. However, withoutfurthersubstantiveassumptions, whichgobeyondanythinggiveninananalysisoftheconcept <I>, wecanmakenolegitimateinferencefromournotionofasubstance0 toeitheroftheotherconceptionsofsubstance.

Since, aswesawinthediscussionoftheunityofconsciousnessabove, Kantdeniesthatwehaveanyintuition, empiricalorotherwise, ofourselvesassubjects, wecannot, merelyinreflectionon theconditionsof thinkingofourselvesusing thefirst-personconcept, come tohaveanyknowledgeconcerningwhatweare(e.g. intermsofbeingseitherasubstance1 orasubstance2). Noamountofintrospectionorreflectiononthecontentofthefirst-personconcept<I> willyieldsuchknowledge.

b. Simplicity(A351-61/B407-8)

Kant’sdiscussionof theproposedmetaphysical simplicityof the subject largelydependsonpointshemadeinthepreviousParalogismconcerningitsproposedsubstantiality. KantarticulatetheSecondParalogismasfollows:

1. Thesubjectwhoseactioncanneverberegardedastheconcurrenceofmanyactingthings,issimple. (AllA isB)

2. Theselfissuchasubject. (C isA)3. ∴ Theselfissimple. (C isB)

Heretheequivocationconcernsthenotionofa“subject”. Kant’spoint, aswiththepreviousParalogism, isthat, fromthefactthatone’sfirst-personrepresentationoftheselfisalwaysagram-maticalorlogicalsubject, nothingfollowsconcerningthemetaphysicalstatusofthereferentofthatrepresentation.

OfperhapsgreaterinterestinthisdiscussionoftheParalogismofsimplicityisKant’sanalysisofwhathecallsthe“Achillesofalldialecticalinferences”(A351). AccordingtotheAchillesargument, the soulormind is know tobe a simpleunitary substancebecauseonly suchasubstancecouldthinkunitarythoughts. Callthisthe“unityclaim”(seeBrook(1997)):

(UC): ifamultiplicityofrepresentationsaretoformasinglerepresentation, theymustbecon-tainedintheabsoluteunityofthethinkingsubstance. (A352)

AgainstUC,Kantarguesthatwehavenoreasontothinkthatthestructureofathought, asacomplexofrepresentations, isn’tmirroredinthecomplexstructureofanentitywhichthinksthethought. UC isnotanalytic, whichistosaythatthereisnocontradictionentailedbyitsnegation. UC alsofailstobeasyntheticaprioriclaim, sinceitfollowsneitherfromthenatureoftheformsofintuition, norfromthecategories. HenceUC couldonlybeshowntobetrueempirically, andsincewedonothaveanyempiricalintuitionoftheself, wehavenobasisforthinkingthatUC mustbetrue(A353).

Kant heremakes apoint familiar fromcontemporary functionalist accounts of themind(seeMeerbote(1991); Brook(1997)). Ourmentalfunctions, includingtheunityofconsciousthought, areconsistentwithavarietyofdifferentpossiblemedia inwhich the functionsarerealized. Kant’spointisthatthereisnocontradictioninthinkingthatapluralityofsubstancesmightsucceedingeneratingasingleunifiedthought. Hencewecannotknowthatthemindissuchthatitmustbesimpleinnature.

September16, 2015 23| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

c. NumericalIdentity(A361-66/B408)

KantarticulatestheThirdParalogismasfollows:

1. WhatisconsciousofthenumericalidentityofitsSelfindifferenttimes, istothatextentaperson. (AllC isP)

2. NowthesoulisconsciousofthenumericalidentityofitsSelfindifferenttimes. (S isC)3. ∴ Thesoulisaperson. (S isP)

Theinteresttakeninestablishingthepersonalityofthesoulormindbytherationalpsychologists,stemsfromtheimportanceofprovingthatnotonlywouldthemindpersistafterthedestructionofitsbody, butalsothatthismindwouldbethesameperson, andnotjustsomesortofbareconsciousnessorworse(e.g. existingonlyasa“baremonad”).

Kantheremakestwomainpoints. First, therationalpsychologistcannotinferfromthesame-nessofthefirst-personrepresentation(the“I think”), acrossapplicationsofitinjudgment, toanyconclusionconcerningthesamenessof themetaphysicalsubjectreferredtobythatrep-resentation. Kantisthusonceagainmakingafunctionalistpointthatthemediuminwhichaseriesofrepresentationalstatesinheresmaychangeovertime, andthereisnocontradictioninconceivingofaseriesofrepresentationsasbeingtransferredfromonesubstancetoanother(A363-4, note).

Second, Kantarguesthatwecanbeconfidentofthesoul’spossessionof personality invirtueofthepersistenceofapperception. Therelevantnotionof“personality”hereisoneconcerningthecontrastbetweenarationalbeingandananimal. Whilethepersistenceofapperception(i.e. thepersistenceofthe“I think”asbeingabletoattachtoallofone’srepresentations)doesnotprovideanapperceivingsubjectwithanyinsightintothetruemetaphysical nature ofthemind,itdoesprovideevidenceofthesoul’spossessionofanunderstanding. Animals, bycontrast, donotpossessanunderstandingbut, atbest(accordingtoKant), onlyananaloguethereof. AsKantsaysinthe Anthropology,

ThatmancanhavetheI amonghisrepresentationselevateshiminfinitelyaboveallotherlivingbeingsonearth. Heistherebyaperson[…]thatis, byrankandworthacompletelydistinctbeingfromthingsthatarethesameasreason-lessanimalswithwhichonecandoasonepleases. (An7:127, §1)

Hence, solongasasoulpossessesthecapacityforapperception, itwillsignalthepossessionofanunderstanding, andthusservestodistinguishthehumansoulfromthatofananimal(seeDyck(2010), 120).

d. RelationtoObjectsinSpace(A366-80/B409)

Finally, theFourthParalogismconcernstherelationbetweenourawarenessofourownmindsandourawarenessofotherobjectsdistinctfromourselves, andthusaslocatedinspace. KantdescribestheFourthParalogismasfollows:

1. Whatcanbeonlycausallyinferredisnevercertain. (AllI isnotC)2. Theexistenceouterobjectscanonlybecausallyinferred, notimmediatelyperceivedby

us. (O isI)

September16, 2015 24| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

3. ∴Wecanneverbecertainoftheexistenceofouterobjects. (O isnotC)

Kant locates thedamagingambiguity in theconceptionof“outer”objects. This ispuzzlingsinceitdoesn’tplaytherelevantroleasmiddleterminthesyllogism. ButKantisquiteclearthatthisiswheretheambiguityliesanddistinguishesbetweentwodistinctsensesofthe“outer”or“external”:

TrancendentallyOuter/External: aseperateexistence, inandofitselfEmpiricallyOuter/External: anexistenceinspace

Kant’spointhereisthatallappearancesinspaceareempiricallyexternaltothesubjectwhoperceivesorthinksaboutthem, whileneverthelessbeingtranscendentallyinternal, inthatsuchspatialappearancesdonothaveanentirelyindependentmetaphysicalnature, sincetheirspatialfeaturesdependatleastinpartonourformsofintuition.

Kantthenusesthisdistinctionnotonlytoargueagainsttheassumptionoftherationalpsy-chologistthatthemindisbetterknownthananyobjectinspace(thisaclaimfamouslyarguedbyDescartes), butalsoagainstthoseformsofexternalworldskepticismchampionedby Descartesand Berkeley. KantidentifiesBerkeleywithwhathecalls“dogmaticidealism”andDescarteswithwhathecalls“problematicidealism”(A377).

ProblematicIdealism: wecannotbecertainoftheexistenceofanymaterialbodyDogmaticIdealism: wecanbecertainthatnomaterialbodyexists–thenotionofabodyis

self-contradictory

Kantbringstwoargumentstobearagainsttherationalpsychologist’sassumptionabouttheim-mediacyofourself-knowledge, aswellasthesetwoformsofskepticism, withmixedresults.Thetwoargumentsare(whatI amcalling)theargumentsfrom“immediacy”and“imagination”.We’lltaketheseinturn.

i. TheImmediacyArgument

InanextendedpassageintheFourthParalogism(A370-1)Kantmakesthefollowingargument:

externalobjects(bodies)aremerelyappearances, hencealsonothingotherthanaspeciesofmyrepresentations, whoseobjectsaresomethingonlythroughtheserepresentations, but arenothing separated from them. Thusexternal thingsex-istaswellasmyself, andindeedbothexistontheimmediatetestimonyofmyself-consciousness, onlywiththisdifference: therepresentationofmySelf, asthethinkingsubject, isrelatedmerelytoinnersense, buttherepresentationsthatdes-ignateextendedbeingsarealsorelatedtooutersense. I amnomorenecessitatedtodrawinferencesinrespectoftherealityofexternalobjectsthanI aminregardtotherealityoftheobjectsofmyinnersense(mythoughts), forinbothcasestheyarenothingbutrepresentations, theimmediateperception(consciousness)ofwhichisatthesametimeasufficientproofoftheirreality. (A370-1)

I taketheargumentheretobeasfollows:

September16, 2015 25| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

1. RationalPsychology(RP) privilegesawarenessofthesubjectanditsstatesoverawarenessofnon-subjectivestates.

2. Buttranscendentalidealismentailsthatweareawareofbothsubjectiveandobjectivestates, astheyappear, inthesameway –viz. viaaformof intuition.

3. Soeitherbothkindsofawarenessareimmediateortheyarebothmediate.4. Sinceawarenessofsubjectivestatesisobviouslyimmediatethenawarenessofobjective

statesmustalsobeimmediate.5. ∴Weareimmediatelyawareofthestatesorpropertiesofphysicalobjects.

HereKantdisplayswhathe takes tobeanadvantageofhis Transcendental Idealism. Sincebothinnerandoutersensedependonintuition, thereisnothingspecialaboutinnerintuitionthatprivilegesitoverouterintuition. Bothare, asintuitions, immediatepresentationsofobjects(at leastastheyappear). Unfortunately, Kantnevermakesclearwhathemeansbytheterm“immediate”[unmittelbar]. Thisissueismuchcontested(seeSmit(2000)). Attheveryleast,hemeanstosignalthatourawarenessinintuitionisnotmediatedbyanyexplicitorconsciousinference, aswhenhesaysthatthetranscendentalidealist“grantstomatter, asappearance, arealitywhichneednotbeinferred, butisimmediatelyperceived”(A371).

Itisnotobviousthatanexternalworldskepticwouldfindthisargumentconvincing, sincepartofthegripofsuchskepticismonusreliesonthe(atleastinitially)convincingpointthatthingscould seem toonejustastheycurrentlyare, evenif therereallyisnoexternalworldcausingone’sexperiences. ThismayjustbegthequestionagainstKant(particularlypremise(2)oftheaboveargument). AndcertainlyKantseemstothinkthathisargumentsfortheexistenceofthepureintuitionsofspaceandtimeintheTranscendentalAestheticlendsomeweighttohispositionhere. ThusKantisnotsomucharguing for TranscendentalIdealismhereasexplain-ingsomeofthefurtherbenefitsthatcomewhenthepositionisadopted. Hedoes, however,presentatleastonefurtherargumentagainsttheskepticalobjectionarticulatedabove–viz. theargumentfromimagination, towhichwe’llnowturn.

ii. TheArgumentfromImagination

Kant’sattempttorespondtotheskepticalworrythatthingsmightappeartobeoutsideuswhilenotactually existing outsideusappealstotherolethatimaginationwouldhavetoplaytomakesuchapossibilityplausible(A373-4; cf. Anthropology, 7:167-8).

Thismaterialorrealentity, however, thisSomethingthatistobeintuitedinspace,necessarilypresupposesperception, anditcannotbeinventedbyanypowerofimaginationorproducedindependentlyofperception, whichindicatestherealityofsomethinginspace. Thussensationisthatwhichdesignatesarealityinspaceandtime, accordingtowhetheritisrelatedtotheoneortheothermodeofsensibleintuition.

Whatfollowsismyreconstructionofthisargument.

1. Ifproblematicidealismiscorrectthenitispossibleforonetohaveneverperceivedanyspatialobjectbutonlytohaveimagineddoingso.

2. Butimaginationcannotfabricate–itcanonly re-fabricate.

September16, 2015 26| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

3. So, ifonehassensoryexperienceofouterspatialobjects, thenonemusthavehadatleastonesuccessfulperceptionofanexternalspatialobject.

4. ∴ Itiscertainthatanextendedspatialworldexists.

Kant’sideahereisthattheimaginationistoolimitedtogeneratethevariousqualitiesthatweexperienceasinstantiatedinexternalphysicalobjects. Hence, itwouldnotbepossibletosimplyimagine an external physicalworldwithout havingbeenoriginally exposed to thequalitiesinstantiatedinthephysicalworld, ergo thephysicalworldmustexist. EvenDescartesseemstoagreewiththis, notingin MeditationI that“[certainsimplekindsofqualities]areasitweretherealcoloursfromwhichweformalltheimagesofthings, whethertrueorfalse, thatoccurinourthought”(Descartes(1984), 13-14). ThoughDescartesgoesontodoubtourcapacitytoknowevensuchbasicqualitiesgiventhepossibleexistenceofanevildeceiver, itisnotablethatthedeceivermustbesomethingotherthanourselves, inordertoaccountforalltherichnessandvarietyofwhatweexperience(however, see MeditationVI (Descartes(1984), 54), whereDescarteswonderswhethertherecouldbesomehiddenfacultyinourselvesproducingallofourideas).

Unfortunately, itisn’tclearthattheargumentfromimaginationgetsKantaconclusionofthedesiredstrength, forallthatitshows(ifitshowsanything)isthattherewas atonetime aphysicalworld, whichaffectedone’ssensesandprovidedthematerialforone’ssenseexperiences. Thismightbeenoughtoshowthatonehasnotalwaysbeenradicallydeceived, butitisnotenoughtoshowthatoneisnot currently beingradicallydeceived. Evenworse, itisn’tevenclearthatweneeda physical worldtogeneratetherequisitematerialfortheimagination. Perhapsallthatisneededis something distinctfromthesubject, whichiscapableofgeneratinginittherequisitesensoryexperiences, whetherornot theyareveridical. This conclusion is thus compatiblewith that“something”beingDescartes’sevildemon, or incontemporaryepistemology, withthesubject’sbeinga braininavat. Hence, itisnotobviousthatKant’sargumentsucceedsinrefutingtheskeptic, ortotheextentthatitdoes, thatitshowsthatweknowthereisa physicalworld, asopposedmerelytotheexistenceofsomethingdistinctfromthesubject.

e. LessonsoftheParalogisms

BeyondthespecificargumentsoftheParalogismsandtheirconclusions, theypresentuswithtwocentraltenetsofKant’sconceptionofthemind. First, thatwecannotmovefromclaimsconcerningthecharacterorroleofthefirst-personrepresentation <I> toclaimsconcerningthenatureofthereferentofthatrepresentation. Thisisakeypartofhiscriticismofrationalpsychol-ogy. Second, thatwedonothaveprivilegedaccesstoourselfascomparedwiththingsoutsideus. Boththeself(oritsstates)andexternalobjectsareonparwithrespecttointuition. Thisalsomeansthatweonlyhaveaccesstoourselvesaswe appear, andnotaswefundamentally,metaphysically, are (cf. B157). Hence, accordingtoKant, ourself-awareness, justasmuchasourawarenessofanythingdistinctfromourselves, isconditionedbyoursensibility. Ourintel-lectualaccesstoourselvesinapperception, Kantargues, doesnotrevealanythingaboutourmetaphysicalnature, inthesenseofthekindof thing thatmustexisttorealizethevariouscog-nitivepowersthatKantdescribesascharacteristicofabeingcapableofapperception(e.g. aspontaneousunderstandingorintellect).

September16, 2015 27| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

5. Summary

Kant’sconceptionofthemind, hisdistinctionbetweensensoryandintellectualfaculties, hisfunctionalism, hisconceptionofmentalcontent, andhisworkonthenatureofthesubject/objectdistinction, wereallhugelyinfluential. Hisworkwasimmediatelyinspirationaltothe GermanIdealist movementandalsobecamecentral toemerging ideasconcerning theepistemologyofscienceinthelatenineteenthandearlytwentiethcenturies, inwhatbecameknownasthe“Neo-Kantian”movement incentralandsouthernGermany. ThoughAnglophone interest inKantebbedsomewhatintheearlytwentiethcentury, hisconceptionofthemindandcriticismsofrationalistpsychologywereagaininfluentialmid-centuryviatheworkof“analytic”KantianssuchasP.F.Strawson, JonathanBennett, andWilfridSellars. Intheearlytwenty-firstcenturyKant’sworkonthemindremainsatouchstoneforphilosophicalinvestigation, especiallyintheworkofthoseinfluencedbyStrawsonorSellars, suchasQuassimCassam, JohnMcDowell, andChristopherPeacocke.

6. ReferencesandFurtherReading

a. Kant’sWorksinEnglish

QuotationsfromKant’sworkarefromtheGermaneditionofKant’sworks, the AkademieAus-gabe, withthefirst Critique citedbythestandardA/B editionpagination, andtheotherworksbyvolumeandpage. Englishtranslationsaremyown, thoughI haveregularlyconsulted, andinmostcasesclosely followed, translations from theCambridgeEditions. Specific textsareabbreviatedasfollows:

• An: AnthropologyfromaPragmaticPointofView• C: Correspondence• CPR: CritiqueofPureReason• CJ: CritiqueofJudgment• JL: JäscheLogic• LA: LecturesonAnthropology• LL: LectursonLogic• LM: LecturesonMetaphysics• Pr: ProlegomenatoanyFutureMetaphysics

Themostused scholarlyEnglish translationsofKant’sworkarepublishedbyCambridgeUniversityPressasthe CambridgeEditionsoftheWorksofImmanuelKant. ThefollowingarefromthatcollectionandcontainsomeofKant’smostimportantandinfluentialwritings.

• Correspondence, ed. ArnulfZweig. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress, 1999.• CritiqueofPureReason, trans. PaulGuyerandAllenWood. Cambridge: Cambridge

UniversityPress, 1998.• CritiqueofthePowerofJudgment, trans. PaulGuyerandEricMatthews. Cambridge:

CambridgeUniversityPress, 2000.• History, Anthropology, andEducation, eds. GünterZöllerandRobertLouden. Cam-

bridge: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2007.

September16, 2015 28| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

• LecturesonAnthropology, ed. andtrans. AllenW.WoodandRobertB.Louden. Cam-bridge: CambridgeUniversityPress, 2012.

• LecturesonLogic, trans. J.MichaelYoung. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress,1992.

• LecturesonMetaphysics, ed. andtrans. KarlAmeriksandSteveNaragon. Cambridge:CambridgeUniversityPress, 2001.

• PracticalPhilosophy, ed. MaryGregor. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress, 1996.• TheoreticalPhilosophy1755-1770, ed. DavidWalford. Cambridge: CambridgeUniver-

sityPress, 2002.• Theoretical Philosophyafter 1781, eds. HenryAllison andPeterHeath. Cambridge:

CambridgeUniversityPress, 2002

b. SecondarySources

Allais, Lucy. 2009. “Kant, Non-ConceptualContentandtheRepresentationofSpace.” JournaloftheHistoryofPhilosophy 47(3): 383–413.

Allison, HenryE.2004. Kant’sTranscendental Idealism: RevisedandEnlarged. NewHaven:YaleUniversityPress.

Ameriks, Karl. 2000. KantandtheFateofAutonomy: ProblemsintheAppropriationoftheCriticalPhilosophy. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Anderson, R Lanier. 2005. “Neo-Kantianism and theRoots ofAnti-Psychologism.” BritishJournalfortheHistoryofPhilosophy 13(2): 287–323.

Andrews, Kristin. 2014. TheAnimalMind: AnIntroductiontothePhilosophyofAnimalCog-nition. London: Routledge.

Bennett, Jonathan. 1966. Kant’sAnalytic. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

———. 1974. Kant’sDialectic. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Bermúdez, JoséLuis. 2003. “AscribingThoughtstoNon-LinguisticCreatures.” FactaPhilosoph-ica 5(2): 313–34.

Brook, Andrew. 1997. KantandtheMind. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Buroker, JillVance. 2006. Kant’s CritiqueofPureReason: AnIntroduction. Cambridge: Cam-bridgeUniversityPress.

Carl, Wolfgang. 1989. “Kant’sFirstDraftsoftheDeductionoftheCategories.” In Kant’sTran-scendentalDeductions, editedbyEckartFörster, 3–20. Stanford: StanfordUniversityPress.

Carson, Emily. 1997. “KantonIntuitionandGeometry.” CJPhil 27(4): 489–512.

———. 1999. “KantontheMethodofMathematics.” JournaloftheHistoryofPhilosophy 37(4): 629–52.

September16, 2015 29| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

Caygill, Howard. 1995. A KantDictionary. Vol. 121. London: Blackwell.

Chignell, Andrew. 2014. “ModalMotivationsforNoumenalIgnorance: Knowledge, Cognition,andCoherence.” Kant-Studien 105(4): 573–97.

Descartes, Rene. 1984. ThePhilosophicalWritingsofDescartes. EditedbyJohnCottingham,RobertStoothoff, andDugaldMurdoch. Vol. 2. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Dicker, Georges. 2004. Kant’sTheoryofKnowledge : AnAnalytical Introduction. Oxford:OxfordUniversityPress.

Dyck, CoreyW.2010. “TheAeneasArgument: Personality and Immortality inKant’sThirdParalogism.” In KantYearbook, editedbyDietmarHeidemann, 95–122.

Engstrom, Stephen. 2013. “UnityofApperception.” StudiKantiani 26: 37–54.

Friedman, Michael. 1992. KantandtheExactSciences. Cambridge, MA:HarvardUniversityPress.

Gardner, Sebastian. 1999. KantandtheCritiqueofPureReason. London: Routledge.

Ginsborg, Hannah. 2006. “Kantand theProblemofExperience.” PhilosophicalTopics 34(1&amp;2): 59–106.

Griffith, AaronM.2012. “PerceptionandtheCategories: A ConceptualistReadingofKant’sCritiqueofPureReason.” EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 20(2): 193–222.

Grüne, Stefanie. 2009. BlindeAnschauung. VittorioKlostermann.

Guyer, Paul. 1987. KantandtheClaimsofKnowledge. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

———. 2014. Kant. London: Routledge.

Hanna, Robert. 2002. “MathematicsforHumans: Kant’sPhilosophyofArithmeticRevisited.”EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 10(3): 328–52.

———. 2005. “KantandNonconceptualContent.” EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 13(2):247–90.

Heck, RichardG.2000. “NonconceptualContentandthe‘SpaceofReasons’.” ThePhilosoph-icalReview 109(4): 483–523.

Hume, David. 1888. A TreatiseofHumanNature. EditedbyL A Selby-Bigge. Oxford: Claren-donPress.

———. 2007. AnEnquiryConcerningHumanUnderstanding. EditedbyPeterMillican. Ox-ford: OxfordUniversityPress.

James, William. 1890. ThePrinciplesofPsychology. NewYork: Holt.

September16, 2015 30| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

Keller, Pierre. 1998. KantandtheDemandsofSelf-Consciousness. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Kitcher, Patricia. 1993. Kant’sTranscendentalPsychology. NewYork: OxfordUniversityPress.

———. 2010. Kant’sThinker. NewYork: OxfordUniversityPress.

Leibniz, GottfriedWilhelmFreiherr. 1996. NewEssaysonHumanUnderstanding. EditedbyJonathanBennettandPeterRemnant. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Longuenesse, Béatrice. 1998. KantandtheCapacitytoJudge. Princeton: PrincetonUniversityPress.

Lurz, RobertW.2011. MindreadingAnimals: TheDebateoverWhatAnimalsKnowAboutOtherMinds. Cambridge, MA:MIT Press.

———, ed. 2009. ThePhilosophyofAnimalMinds. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Matherne, Samantha. “Kant’sTheoryofImagination.” In RoutledgeHandbookofthePhiloso-phyofImagination, editedbyAmyKind. NewYork: Routledge.

McDowell, John. 1996. MindandWorld: WithaNewIntroduction. Cambridge, MA:HarvardUniversityPress.

McLear, Colin. 2011. “KantonAnimalConsciousness.” Philosophers’Imprint 11(15): 1–16.

———. 2015a. “KantonPerceptualContent.” Mind.

———. 2015b. “TwoKindsofUnityinthe CritiqueofPureReason.” JournaloftheHistoryofPhilosophy 53(1): 79–110.

Meerbote, Ralf. 1991. “Kant’sFunctionalism.” In HistoricalFoundationsofCognitiveScience,editedbyJ-C Smith, 161–87. Dordrecht: KluwerAcademicPublishers.

Naragon, Steve. 1990. “KantonDescartesandtheBrutes.” Kant-Studien 81(1): 1–23.

Parsons, Charles. 1964. “InfinityandKant’sConceptionofthe‘PossibilityofExperience’.” ThePhilosophicalReview 73(2): 182–97.

———. 1992. “TheTranscendentalAesthetic.” In TheCambridgeCompaniontoKant, editedbyPaulGuyer, 62–100. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Paton, H J.1936. Kant’sMetaphysicofExperience. Vol. 1&2. London: G.Allen&amp;Unwin, Ltd.

Pendlebury, Michael. 1995. “MakingSenseofKant’sSchematism.” PPR 55(4): 777–97.

Pereboom, Derk. 1995. “DeterminismAlDente.” Noûs 29: 21–45.

———. 2006. “Kant’sMetaphysicalandTranscendentalDeductions.” In A CompaniontoKant,editedbyGrahamBird, 154–68. BlackwellPublishing.

September16, 2015 31| 32

Kant’sPhilosophyofMind ColinMcLear

———. 2009. “Kant’sTranscendentalArguments.” StanfordEncyclopediaofPhilosophy.

Proops, Ian. 2010. “Kant’sFirstParalogism.” ThePhilosophicalReview 119(4): 449.

Schellenberg, S.2011. “PerceptualContentDefended.” Noûs 45(4): 714–50.

Sellars, Wilfrid. 1956. “EmpiricismandthePhilosophyofMind.” MinnesotaStudies inthePhilosophyofScience 1: 253–329.

———. 1968. ScienceandMetaphysics: VariationsonKantianThemes. London: Routledge&amp; KeeganPaul.

———. 1978. “BerkeleyandDescartes: ReflectionsontheTheoryofIdeas.” In StudiesinPer-ception, editedbyP K MachamerandR G Turnbull, 259–311. Columbus: OhioUniversityPress.

Shabel, Lisa. 2006. “Kant’sPhilosophyofMathematics.” In TheCambridgeCompaniontoKantandthe CritiqueofPureReason, editedbyPaulGuyer, 94–128.

Siegel, Susanna. 2010. “TheContentsofPerception.” In TheStanfordEncyclopediaofPhiloso-phy, editedbyEdwardN Zalta.

———. 2011. TheContentsofVisualExperience. Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress.

Smit, Houston. 2000. “KantonMarksand the Immediacyof Intuition.” ThePhilosophicalReview 109(2): 235–66.

Strawson, PeterFrederick. 1966. TheBoundsofSense. London: Routledge.

———. 1970. “ImaginationandPerception.” In ExperienceandTheory, editedbyLawrenceFosterandJoeWilliamSwanson. Amherst: UniversityofMassachusetsPress.

Sutherland, Daniel. 2008. “ArithmeticfromKanttoFrege: Numbers, PureUnits, andtheLimitsofConceptualRepresentation.” In Kant andPhilosophyof ScienceToday(1), editedbyMichelaMassimi, 135–64. Cambridge: CambridgeUniversityPress.

Tolley, Clinton. 2013. “TheNon-ConceptualityoftheContentofIntuitions: A NewApproach.”KantianReview 18(01): 107–36.

———. 2014. “KantontheContentofCognition.” EuropeanJournalofPhilosophy 22(2):200–228.

VanCleve, James. 1999. ProblemsfromKant. Oxford: OxfordUniversityPress.

Wood, AllenW.2005. Kant. Oxford: BlackwellPublishing.

September16, 2015 32| 32