29
See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/321255666 Karl Marx and the Marxist School Working Paper · November 2017 DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.27320.03847 CITATIONS 0 READS 15,446 1 author: Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects: From Pool of Profits to Surplus and Deficit Industries View project Scott Carter University of Tulsa 19 PUBLICATIONS 59 CITATIONS SEE PROFILE All content following this page was uploaded by Scott Carter on 23 November 2017. The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.

Karl Marx and the Marxist School

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    3

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

See discussions, stats, and author profiles for this publication at: https://www.researchgate.net/publication/321255666

Karl Marx and the Marxist School

Working Paper · November 2017

DOI: 10.13140/RG.2.2.27320.03847

CITATIONS

0READS

15,446

1 author:

Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:

From Pool of Profits to Surplus and Deficit Industries View project

Scott Carter

University of Tulsa

19 PUBLICATIONS   59 CITATIONS   

SEE PROFILE

All content following this page was uploaded by Scott Carter on 23 November 2017.

The user has requested enhancement of the downloaded file.

Page 2: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

1

Karl Marx and the Marxist School Scott Carter, The University of Tulsa ([email protected])1

• Marx was a working class revolutionary thinker whose economic theories were designed for a mass working class audience

• Marx’s economic thought developed as a sustained critique of Classical Political Economy and addressed many of the short-comings in the labor theory of value of that approach

• Marx’s method of historical materialism considers social formations as evolving and developing from earlier forms often through revolutionary struggle

• Marx’s contribution to the Classical labor theory of value includes the notion of the value of labor power and theory of surplus-value defined as the exploitation of the unpaid labor of workers

• Marx’s theory of surplus value expresses itself in an understanding of the division of the working-day into necessary and surplus labor time which serves as the foundation upon which his economic theories are built

• Marx’s economic theories are rich and includes among other things theories of accumulation, circuits of revenue and capital, schemes of social reproduction, crisis theory and the falling rate of profit, the reserve army of labor, and the transformation of values into prices of production

0. Introductory Few figures in the history of economic thought have been the source of more controversy, ranging from complete scorn and vilification to sanctification and adulation, than Karl Heinrich Marx (1818-1883). Marx was a philosopher, profoundly deep social thinker, political economist, and working-class intellectual and revolutionary. Marx was a mighty thinker with a very fertile mind of immense prowess and intellectual stature upon whose work the Marxist School is founded. But Marx’s impact is not limited to the School that bears his name, as many Schools of thought - friend and foe alike - owe a tremendous debt of gratitude to the Old Moor, as Marx was affectionately called by his friends, ostensibly due to his dark complexion and coarse hair. Marx’s economic theory as devised by the Master himself was intended to be revolutionary and written from the historical perspective of a class-conscious revolutionary proletariat and working-class. Whether or not this necessarily matters in terms of the analytics of Marx’s economic theory strictly-speaking is a subject of some debate, as there are certain authors that argue the “partisan political revolutionary” elements need to be separated from the “objective economic” in appraisals of Marx’s overall merit in terms of an economic theoretician (see for example Morishima 1973, pp.4-5). But for Marx the theory was explicitly developed through active struggle as a working-class

1 Associate Professor, Department of Economics, The University of Tulsa, Oklahoma, USA. Chapter to appear in Hassan Bougrine and Louis-Philippe Rochon A Short History Of Economic Thought: Major Contributions since Adam Smith, (forthcoming Edward Elgar).

Page 3: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

2

perspective on, and understanding of, the capitalist mode of production. One commentator writes that:

“Marx wrote his political economy for what he hoped would be a mass working-class audience; whatever its actual reception, it was intended as a weapon in the class struggle” (King 1980, p. 370).

Marx considered his approach advancing the mantle of political economy as a science beyond what, in the Afterward to the Second German Edition of Das Kapital, he called the “bourgeois horizon” that had confounded the Classical Political Economy of his predecessors, namely Adam Smith (1723-90), David Ricardo (1772-1823), Thomas Robert Malthus (1766-1834), and John Stuart Mill (1806-73) to name some of the most important figures in that approach (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 14; Fowkes. p. 96). 2 It is important also to understand that although Marx is most associated with theories of socialism and communism, in fact the overwhelming majority of his inquiries concerned only capitalism. Marx and the school of thought he inspired approaches the study of capitalism through the lens of historic-specificity, by which is meant that capitalism as a mode of production has a lifespan of its own: it was born at a specific historical juncture, has matured since that time in ways that have often been remarkably transformative, and eventually it will die and give way to post-capitalist socio-economic formations. This is a unique feature of the Marxist School that as discussed below relies heavily on the Marxian method of historical materialism. 1. Marx in the history of economic thought The history of economic thought is unlike the history of most other sciences in that the development of ideas does not proceed in a linear fashion where early notions once shown to be “wrong” are jettisoned in favor of newer ones that are shown to be “right”. Economic thought instead proceeds zig-zag like, with starts and stops such that many years later (sometimes decades and/or centuries), ideas thought to be long dead are revived and given modern polish and relevance. This attribute arises because some of the most fundamental foundational building blocks of economic science still to this day remain unresolved. Nowhere is this more obvious than the theory of value and price, and it is from that perch the present study of Marx and the Marxist school begins. By theory of value we mean the theory or explanation that underlies the exchange relation observed in social formations governed by the market mechanism, where goods and services are produced for

2 To facilitate study of the original material which readers are strongly encouraged to do, quotes by Marx from Capital Volume I are cited from two alternative sources: (i) Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Vol. 35 where Volume I falls; and (ii) citation from the Ben Fowkes translation originally published in 1976 by Vintage Press and later picked up by Penguin Classics. The Fowkes translation is the edition studied by the present writer in graduate school, etc., although the trend lately is to cite from the Collected Works so as to facilitate study across the corpus the writings of Marx and Engels. All citations in the present essay are from MECW. The Marx-Engels Collected Works (complied between 1975 and 2005) is a 50-volume set of the works of Marx and Engels translated from original German Marx-Engels-Gesamtausgabe (MEGA) into English originally arranged by the Institute of Marxism-Leninism in Moscow and published by Lawrence & Wishart in the UK in collaboration with International Publishers in the USA under the auspice of an international commission of scholars from the then-USSR and later Russian Republic, USA, and UK. Interested readers can find freely available online versions and transcriptions of the entire MECW as well as a plethora of other resources at the Marxist Internet Archive (https://www.marxists.org/).

Page 4: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

3

exchange thereby fetching a unit-price, and whose allocation is garnered through exchange of commodities for money (“buying”) and money for commodities (“selling”). It is important to emphasize that the exchange relation is an objective condition faced in market societies, and the role of economic science is (or at least should be) to provide cogent, logically-consistent, and robust explanations for this objective fact. To illustrate consider the following heuristic example. Let there be two different goods, A and B. Suppose that in the market it is observed that 2 units of A (2A) costs the same as 1 unit of B (1B), and that for simplicity that cost is $1. This says that for one dollar buyers can purchase 2 units of A and for the same dollar they can alternatively purchase 1 unit of B. The question any theory of value must try to answer is, why? What is it about 2A that makes it equal in value to 1B, such that for the same $1 buyers can purchase these very different quantities of these very different things? To this question economic thought has forwarded broadly speaking at least two different underlying mechanisms. For the earlier Classical Political Economy approach beginning around the 1700s until 1870, it was posited that 2A = 1B due to equal expenditure in production for the different quantities of the different goods, with that cost being reduced to labor-time objectively expended or bestowed in production according to the socially average level of technology of the day. For the later approach of Neoclassical Economics beginning in 1870 until the present, the selfsame exchange relation is explained as a function of the equal amounts of utility or satisfaction the subjective individual receives when consuming 2A as he/she does when consuming 1B, with the further caveat that this occurs at the margin of constrained choice. Both theories contain a similar methodological character in that sought for in explaining the exchange between any two objects for sale is a “common third” (Kurz 2013, p. 46). In the early labor theory of value (LTV) this “common third” is commensurable quantities of socially-necessary labor time in production, and in the later marginal utility theory of value (MUTV) the “common third” is commensurable quantities of utility at the margin of constrained choice. To illustrate this, a brief account of the history of thought is shown in Figure 1 below. This (woefully incomplete) timeline is only a thumbnail sketch intended to give an overall flavor of the non-linear character of the theory of value and price.

Page 5: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

4

Figure 1: A non-linear sketch of the History of Economic Thought

In Fig. 1 the theory of value has been divided into two camps:

A. Classical Political Economy (c. 1700s - 1870) – Theory of value based on commensurate expenditure in production B. Neoclassical Economics (1870 - present) – Theory of value based on commensurate utility in consumption

Note that the heterodox approaches are seen to emanate both from the earlier CPE approach as well as the groundbreaking work of John Maynard Keynes. Modern Austrian Approaches are also considered by some to be heterodox although certainly their origins are traced to the work of Carl Menger and in that capacity are a break from earlier Classical doctrines.

The economics of Karl Marx and the Marxist School comes at the end of the Classical tradition of the LTV. It is no accident that the marginal utility approach began to become accepted in 1870, only three years after Marx published the first volume of his opus Das Kapital in 1867. This is important because the principle of marginal utility that became the foundation of the theory of value after 1870 was not, as legend would have it, “discovered” independently in 1870 by the three independent marginal revolutionists William Stanley Jevons (1852-82), Marie-Esprit-Léon Walras (1834-1910), and Carl Menger (1840-1921). Rather the principle of marginal utility was pronounced as early as 1838 by Antoine Augustin Cournot (1801-77), in 1844 by Arsène Jules Émile Juvénal Dupuit (1804-66), and in 1854 by Hermann Heinrich Gossen (1810-58).3 The question then becomes, what was it about the year 1870 that brought to the foreground what was heretofore an approach to value that no serious political economist would have given a second thought towards? The Italian economist Piero Sraffa in notes from his Lectures on the Advanced Theory of Value given at University of Cambridge from 1928-31 put the matter this way:

3 The English translations are Cournot (1897 [1838]), Dupuit (1952 [1844]), and Gossen (1983 [1854]).

Modern Austrian Approaches Eugene Böhm-Bawerk

Knut Wicksell Friedrich von Weiser Friedrich von Hayek

B. Neoclassical Economics: Subjective marginal utility theory of value: Value based in utility maximization at the margin of constrained

choice

A. Classical Political Economy: Labor theory of Value (production based theory of value): Value based in integrated production ‘costs’

Page 6: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

5

“(Cournot, Dupuit, and Gossen)…were either cranks or amateur economists and therefore had no accounts to settle with the considerable body of knowledge that had been built up during a century…[E]ven more remarkable, was the contrast between the complete failure met by earlier theorists of marginal utility and the ready and widespread acceptance found by that very theory in the [1870s]… Of course, this change cannot be explained by the stupidity of the people in 1850, when they rejected the theory advanced by Gossen, and their intelligence in 1870 when they accepted the same theory as stated by Jevons…I rather prefer to accept [the] view, that there is a close relation between the appearance emerging of Marxism and the extraordinarily ready acceptance which the theory of marginal utility [gained] amongst orthodox economists. And that conservative minded people were only too glad to seize an opportunity of getting rid of the labour theory of value, notwithstanding the enormous authority it derived from the tradition of the classical economists” (Sraffa 1928-31, p. 16-7; online resource at https://drive.google.com/open?id=1srPZVD39ZD9SFMmXTrwqYyQJFIVDNoVZNtogQFcVI8w).

4 Here the revolutionary impact of Marx on economic science emerges, where he accepted the basic tenets of labor theory of value propagated by Smith, Ricardo, Malthus, and the Classical School and took it further into the revolutionary direction forged by Ricardian socialist school5 that had begun to arise after Ricardo’s death in 1823. The Classical school was correct, argued the Ricardian Socialists and later Marx, that value comes from the labor time necessary to produce a commodity. Where it failed was in the explanation of the source of profit. The quagmire became this: if the law of value holds that the prices of commodities comport to the bestowed labor time necessary to produce commodities, how is it when considered as “capital” a quantity of value fetches or commands a price that includes an over-plus of profit greater than the initial bestowed cost? Where did this “extra” come from? Although critics of Ricardo (both conservative and Socialist) acknowledged that as far back as Adam Smith (Wealth of Nations, Book I, Chapter VI “Of the component parts of the prices of commodities”) it was known labor bestowed no longer equals labor commanded in capitalistic commodity production, all failed to provide an adequate solution to the problem. For their part, conservative-minded economists - certainly this is the case with Nassau Senior (1790-1864), but also includes those proclaiming to be disciples of Ricardo like John Ramsay McCulloch (1789-1864) and self-styled progressives like John Stuart Mill (1806-73) - began to increasingly move away from the tenets of the LTV. Instead they began to focus more and more on the demand and supply approach that would eventually give way to the marginal utility theory of value as the heretofore rejected theories of the “cranks” Cournot, Dupuit, and Gossen became accepted by the science. For their

4 This view of the role of Marx in the ushering in of the marginalist revolution is also expressed in Dobb (1973) and Screpanti & Zamagni (2005), among many other places. For a different view in line with a more linear history readers can begin by consulting any of the works by Mark Blaug and also those by Samuel Hollander; particularly useful and erudite is Blaug (1997). 5 The Ricardian Socialists are primarily associated with the British writers William Thompson (1824), Thomas Hodgskin (1825, 1827), John Francis Bray (1839), the pseudonym Piercy Ravenstone (1821, 1824), and Thomas Rowe Edmonds (1833); see King (1980) for a thorough account of the contributions of these writers on the development on Marx’s thinking. Sraffa (1974) in his Index to the Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo (Volume XI) identifies Ravenstone as Richard Puller, otherwise a relatively unassuming character of whom “little else is known” (Sraffa 1974, p. xxviii). In Marx’s Economic Manuscripts from 1861-3, commonly referred to as Theories of Surplus Value (TSV), Marx devotes many pages to the works of Thompson, Hodgskin, and Ravenstone (see MECW Vol 33; TSV, Part III); and in notes written in 1845 entitled “Wages” Marx discusses the work of Bray (MECW Vol. 6). King (1980, p. 352) reports no evidence exists that Marx knew of Edmonds even though the theory of surplus-value in the latter’s work is very close to that developed by Marx.

Page 7: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

6

part, the Ricardian Socialists remained on the whole critical of capitalism based on moral and ethical arguments against the unequal exchange of the laborers being swindled out the products they produce; such arguments Marx’s longtime friend, collaborator, and sometimes benefactor Friedrich Engels would derisively call Utopian. The solution to all this would fall to Marx’s theory of surplus value. Marx agreed with the Classical School that the substance of value was labor time in production; he took it further by arguing that the substance of profit is in the unpaid labor time expended in the production process by workers who are paid less than their productivity. Here emerges the theory of extraction of unpaid labor that is the cornerstone of Marx’s exploitation theory of profits and indeed his entire theoretical framework. 2. Marx’s method of historical materialism Before delving into the details of Marx’s economic theory, it is instructive to consider the overall methodology he and Engels developed which informed and guided their thought; that method is called historical materialism. According to the appraisal by Engels after Marx’s death, historical materialism together with the theory of surplus value constitute the two most important theoretical discoveries and original contributions Marx made (MECW, Vol. 24, pp. 467-8).6 Historical materialism conceives of systems of human socio-economic reproduction using two analytical criteria: the forces of production and the relations of production, the combination of which comprises the concept of the mode of production. Forces of production consist of the material production processes and include among other things the state of the art and scope of technology, and the level of knowledge of the society. Forces of production, representing the material technical conditions of production, correspond to the relations of production which fundamentally relate to the social form of the labor process, the social relations among people, and the social relation between people and things. Relations of production fundamentally concern conditions of property ownership in society. Combining the two yields Marx’s concept of the mode of production which is the (dialectical and hence conflictual)7 unity of a society’s forces and relations of production that forms the economic base of society.

6 In his article “Karl Marx’s Funeral” written the day after Marx’s burial on March 17, 1883 and published just a few days later on the 22nd in the newspaper of the Socialist Workers’ Party of Germany, Der Sozialdemokrat, Engels writes:

“Just as Darwin discovered the law of development or organic nature, so Marx discovered the law of development of human history: the simple fact [that] the degree of economic development [is] attained by a given people or during a given epoch, [and] form[s] the foundation upon which the state institutions, the legal conceptions, art, and even the ideas on religion, of the people concerned have been evolved ….But that is not all. Marx also discovered the special law of motion governing the present-day capitalist mode of production, and the bourgeois society that this mode of production has created. The discovery of surplus value suddenly threw light on the problem, in trying to solve which all previous investigations, of both bourgeois economists and socialist critics, had been groping in the dark.” (MECW, Vol. 24, pp. 467-8).

7 The dialectic as a notion can be thought simply as a unity of opposites, referred to as the thesis and antithesis, which eventually gives rise (sometimes after sustained struggle and violence) to their resolution which forms the synthesis. This synthesis eventually becomes the new thesis, to which springs its eventual antithesis, and the dialectic struggle towards a new synthesis continues. Marx appropriated the dialectic from the German Philosopher Georg Hegel (1770-1831), although as Marx notes he turned Hegel on his head, by which Marx means that Hegel reified metaphysical relations whereas as he (Marx) remained grounded in the material conditions of life. On the importance of material conditions of life over reified abstract notions, Marx credits another German philosopher Ludwig Feuerbach (1804-72); although for Marx revolutionary action was necessary to affect the material conditions rather than simply philosophizing about them. This Marx makes clear in a series of Theses on Feuerbach he wrote in April of 1845 as he was on the cusp of what would be sustained class struggle for the next four years until being forced into exile to London in 1849; in the eleventh and final

Page 8: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

7

The economic base of a social formations is only one element of Marx’s theory. A society’s economic base is closely related to the ideological superstructure. The ideological superstructure comprises the legal, social, political, and other societal morays and relations that emanate from the economic base. The ideological superstructure continually interacts with and reflects upon the economic base causing tension, antagonisms, and eventually social revolutions; Marx refers to this as “fetters” or obstacles articulated by the relations of production onto the forces (see Larrain 1983). It is in the Preface to Marx’s 1859 A Contribution to a Critique of Political Economy that Marx states with clarity the principles of historical materialism developed in the decade of the 1840’s as he and his comrades were steeped in class struggle; although the quote is long, here the materialist conception of history is succinctly stated quite clearly by Marx himself:

“The general conclusion at which I arrived and which, once reached, became the guiding principle of my studies can be summarized as follows. In the social production of their existence, men {sic}8 inevitably enter into definite relations, which are independent of their will, namely relations of production appropriate to a given stage in the development of their material forces of production. The totality of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society, the real foundation, on which arises a legal and political superstructure and to which correspond definite forms of social consciousness. The mode of production of material life conditions the general process of social, political and intellectual life. It is not the consciousness of men that determines their existence, but their social existence that determines their consciousness. At a certain stage of development, the material productive forces of society come into conflict with the existing relations of production or – this merely expresses the same thing in legal terms – with the property relations within the framework of which they have operated hitherto. From form of development of the productive forces these relations turn into fetters. Then begin an era of social revolution. The changes in the economic foundation lead sooner or later to the transformation of the whole immense superstructure…No social formation is ever destroyed before all the productive forces to which it is sufficient have been developed, and new superior relations of production never replace older ones before the material conditions for their existence have matured within the framework of the old society….In broad outline, the Asiatic, ancient {e.g. slave}, feudal, and modern bourgeois (e.g. capitalist}9 modes of production may be designated as epochs marking progress in the economic development of society. The bourgeois relations of production are the last antagonistic form of the social process of production – antagonistic not in the sense of individual antagonism but of an antagonism that emanates from the individuals’ social conditions of existence – but the productive forces developing within bourgeois society create also the material conditions for a solution of this antagonism” (MECW, Vol. 29, pp. 264-6; italicized emphasis added).

Notice the italicized emphasis in the opening sentence of the passage and how Marx, through deep intellectual contemplation in conjunction with active and sustained class struggle, arrived at the

Thesis Marx writes: “The philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point is to change it” (MECW, Vol. 5, p. 5; emphasis in-text). 8 Curly brackets {} indicate insertions by the present writer, and the term “sic” is the Latin adverb “thus” which is used to indicate an error or some type of amendment in quoted passages, etc. In the present context, it is used to identify the sexist term “men” used by Marx, when the referent is of course expansive and inclusive in connotation to all humanity: men, women, transgender, etc. 9 Marx uses the term “bourgeois” (sometimes rather derisively) to refer to all things capitalist.

Page 9: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

8

materialist conception of history. This constitutes the revolutionary praxis, or unity between theory and action, endemic in Marx’s approach. The diagram below illustrates these complex relations. Depicted are the broad stages or modes of production of human society that Marx and Engels outlined in the Communist Manifest of 184810: primitive society and the hunting and gathering mode, the slave mode, the feudal mode, the capitalist mode, and post-capitalist classless society:

Figure 2: Marx’s Materialist Conception of Human Social History

(Diagram adapted from P. Kunzmann, F.-P. Burkard & F. Wiedmann (2011) dtv-Atlas Philosophie; translation from German by S. Bohnen, http://e-ducation.datapeak.net/marx.htm)

The diagram shows the forward progression of the forces of production as the single-arrowed line on the upward trajectory (the “hypotenuse” of the triangles). The forces correspond with the relations of production, depicted as the double-lined-arrow of the bases of the various smaller triangles representing the different modes of production. At the inception of the productive mode the forces and relations meet at the origin of the angle, and as time wears on they increasingly deviate causing social revolutions represented by the height of the triangles where, via social antagonism, successive modes eventually transform into higher stages of human social development. The diagram also shows (i) the class character of the intermittent modes: slavery has slave and master; feudalism has serf and lord, and capitalism has worker and capitalist; and (ii) the classless character of both the earliest primitive mode as well as the post-capitalist mode of socialism leading to communism, where the latter is characterized by Marx in Critique of the Gotha Program of 1875 as a society where “only then can the narrow horizon of bourgeois right be crossed in its entirety and

10 The years from 1843 through 1849 saw both Marx and Engels engaged in active and sustained class struggle on the European Continent, specifically in the cities of Cologne, Paris, and Brussels. Marx shuffled between these cities to avoid persecution and prosecution by the various authorities who by 1849 had all had enough thus forcing Marx to emigrate to London where he remained in exile until his death in 1883. As part of this sustained struggle Marx and Engels drafted the Manifesto for the Communist Party in 1848 while organizing in Brussels. For an interesting intellectual history of Marx including his revolutionary activity see Oakley (1983).

Page 10: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

9

society inscribe on its banners: From each according to his abilities, to each according to his needs!” (MECW, Vol. 24, p. 87). 3. Marx’s theory of value Marx considered his work as uncovering the key to the unresolved contradictions in the Classical tradition of the LTV. This is evident in the subtitle he gave in the first of three volumes of Das Kapital (1867), which is translated into English as Capital: A Critique of Political Economy.11 The key for Marx was the theory of surplus value, the latter concept defined as the unpaid labor-time performed by workers in the normal course of the capitalist production process. The term “normal course” reflects the fact that the source of profit is not arbitrary or capricious nor from swindle; that in fact the capitalist production process quite naturally produces profit by virtue of the inner-workings of the capitalist mode of production.12 This put Marx in a category apart from the Ricardian Socialists, the latter of whom on the whole remained convinced that the evils of capitalism were aberrations of an otherwise fair system of commerce and trade were the law of value to be honored. Not so with Marx, who saw the emergence of profit resultant from the normal course of developed capitalistic relations, and exploitation of workers as occurring without swindle when the law of value is honored and all commodities exchange at their value. It is on this score that Marx moved beyond the Ricardian Socialists from the British Isles as well the Socialist school on the Continent, all of whom Engels (1892; MECW Vol. 24) would label as Utopian in their socialism, as opposed to the developments by Marx and Engels which were deemed Scientific. The key to the distinction between Utopian and Scientific Socialism had to do with the manner in which the free laborer or wage-worker is rendered a commodity. It was Marx who first developed the notion that the labor performed by workers is not that which is in fact bought and sold; rather it is the capacity to labor, which he termed labor-power, that appears as the commodity on the labor market. The difference between labor and labor-power was for Marx huge and, as previously indicated with reference to Engels, together with the method of historical materialism counts among the most important discoveries and contributions Marx considered he made to economic science. To see this Marx’s theory of value must first be developed; only then does his theory of surplus value become cogent.

11 The intellectual history of the development of Marx’s writing from a bibliographic perspective is given in Oakley (1983) for all of Marx’s intellectual project and in Rosdolsky (1977) for specifically the relation between Marx’s notes from 1857-8 known as the Grundrisse (German for “foundations”) as they relate to the three volumes of Capital. Volumes II and III of Capital were, respectively, published posthumously by Engels in 1884 and 1894. Volume II was the more developed as Marx had spent time on that after Volume I was published in 1867. Volume III is the least developed and is taken mostly from notes that Marx wrote before around 1865 leading up to 1867. In terms of Marx’s economic writings, Grundrisse appears in MECW Vols. 28 and 29, Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy of 1859 in MECW Vols. 29 and 30, Marx’s Economic Manuscripts of 1861-3 including all three parts of Theories of Surplus Value in MECW Vols. 30-34, and Capital Volumes I, II, and III in, respectively, MECW Vols. 35, 36, and 37. 12 In fact, Marx does identify historically-early forms of profit as mostly of the capricious type of buying cheap and selling dear and terms this profit upon alienation. In the opening pages of Theories of Surplus Value Part I, Marx expounds on this form of profit in the discussion of the early Scottish thinker Sir James Steuart; “Steuart limits all profit of the individual capitalist to…profit upon alienation…always derived from the excess of price of the commodity over its real value” (MECW, Vol. 30, p. 351). Stueart in 1767 published An Inquiry into the Principles of Political Economy: Being an Essay on the Science of Domestic Policy of Free Nations, almost a decade before fellow Scot Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations appeared in 1776. Of Stueart’s work, Smith’s memorialist Dugald Stewart writes in 1794 that “It was indeed the only systematical work on the subject that had appeared in our language, previous to Mr. Smith’s Inquiry” (Ross 1982, p. 348; note).

Page 11: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

10

Marx begins his theory of value with the commodity, defined as an article or good produced for sale. Here two different aspects emerge. The one aspect is the useful character of the article, what Marx calls the use-value of the commodity. Here the usefulness of the products of labor is paramount: e.g. pencils are used to write with, paper is used to write on, etc. The use-value character of the commodity is vital, as articles that have no use are ostensibly worthless and have no value in exchange. The other aspect of commodities is their value, defined as the socially-necessary labor time for their production. In commodity-producing societies generally, the value of produced goods emerges as the aforementioned “common third” and therefore the basis from which the relation of exchange manifests. Marx is clear to indicate that the labor time represents the socially-necessary labor time in the production of a commodity given the state of the art and level of technology in society:

“The labour-time socially necessary is that required to produce an article under normal conditions of production, and with the average degree of skill and intensity prevalent at the time” (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 49; Fowkes. p. 129)

Inasmuch as the value-creating substance is human labor, Marx reduces the concrete laboring activities of different tasks in the labor process to its essential quality, that being the expenditure of human social laboring capacity generally. Marx refers to this value-creating capacity as labor in the abstract, or abstract labor, which stands juxtaposed to concrete labor referring to the actual laboring activities performed:

“[W]e put out of sight both the useful character of the various kinds of labour embodied in them, and the concrete forms of that labour; there is nothing left but what is common to them all; all are reduced to one and the same sort of labour, human labour in the abstract” (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 48; Fowkes. p. 128).

Marx meticulously develops the exchange relation between different produced commodities in terms of exchange-value, which he sees as the unity of a commodity’s use-value and its value. He develops the argument sequentially in terms of the forms of value which works from the elementary form of biangular 2 x 2 trade, then to the multi-angular expanded form, then the general form, all the way up to the universal money form of value, the latter of which for Marx was commodity-money expressed in ounces of “gold”. The table below shows the different forms of value Marx lays out in Section 3 of the opening chapter of Capital, Volume I:

Page 12: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

11

Table 1: Forms of Value or Exchange Value

Marx assumes a common third of socially necessary abstract labor in developing the quantitative relations in the exchange between commodities. He spends a lot of time developing the biangular trade elementary form, and specifically distinguishes the role of the commodities on opposite sides of the equals sign. Consider Marx’s elementary form in row 1 of the table above. On the left-hand side (LHS) we have x units of good A and on the right-hand side (RHS) we have y units of goods B. Marx adopts the convention that the LHS represents the commodity whose value is to be measured and the RHS represents the commodity in whose units the measure of value is taken or expressed. Marx calls the former the relative form of value and the latter the equivalent form of value. The price in this example is read as “the value of x-units of commodity A is equal to y-units of commodity B”, and here we may think of this as expressing the “B-price of good A”. Understanding the difference in the relative form and equivalent form of value is key to understanding the forms of value discussion and indeed Marx’s entire theory of value, money, capital, and surplus value as the endeavor gets increasingly more complex analytically. This is seen when considering the gold-as-money price form in row 4 of the above table. Since x-units of A and y-units of B exchange for one ounce of gold, this means that each unit of A exchanges for 1/x units of gold and each unit of B exchanges for 1/y units of gold. Here gold serves as the universal equivalent or money-form of value, with the first being the gold-price of good A and the second the gold price of good B. Marx develops a commodity-money theory by setting the production of gold as the measure of value under the assumption that this measure is invariable, meaning that changes in prices will be the result from changes in conditions of production for the commodity whose value is being measured and not that of the (gold) measuring standard.

Currency notes (denoted “$”) are introduced into Marx’s framework with the assumption of the invariable value of money which we can express in terms of the mint price of gold, the latter defined as the exchange ratio between currency notes and ounces of gold. With this convention, the physical quantity of gold produced under the assumption of invariable conditions in the gold-mines can be

Forms of Value Exchange ratio 1. Elementary or accidental form

𝑥 commodity A = 𝑦 commodity B

2. Total or expanded form

𝑥 commodity A =

𝑦 commodity B …… 𝑧 commodity C …… 1 𝑜𝑧. 𝑜𝑓 𝑔𝑜𝑙𝑑 …

3. General form

𝑦 commodity B …

… 𝑧 commodity C …… 1 𝑜𝑧. 𝑜𝑓 𝑔𝑜𝑙𝑑 …

] = 𝑥 commodity A

4. Commodity-money form

𝑥 commodity A …

… 𝑦 commodity B …

… 𝑧 commodity C …] = 1 𝑜𝑧. 𝑜𝑓 𝑔𝑜𝑙𝑑

Page 13: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

12

expressed in terms of currency units, and through conversion of ounces into these notes prices are now expressed in currency units, and we have money prices. Marx assumes this relation holds for all commodities. 13 4. Marx’s Theory of Surplus Value Marx initially develops the LTV in terms of simple commodity production where equivalents exchange and the circuit of revenue is assumed to be the rule. The circuit of revenue expresses a quantity of value represented by the socially-necessary labor-time for production in its commodity form (C), which is exchanged for its money form (M) of equal value, and is again exchanged for another commodity of also of equal value thereby ending the circuit:

Circuit of Revenue: C – M – C

In the circuit of revenue, equal values are exchanged in the form of commodities put on the market (C) which are then sold for a quantity of money (M) which is then used to purchase another set of commodities of equal value (C). Changes in the logic and character of the theory of value spring forth once Marx introduces the capitalist mode of production, and here the Marx’s positive economic-theoretic contributions begin to truly take shape. In the first instance, the circuit of revenue is no longer center stage in the exchange relation, giving way instead to the circuit of money-capital. Here the purpose of exchange is not to secure equivalent values of different commodities, but rather to secure more money-value at the end of the circuit than initially advanced:

Circuit of Money Capital:

M – C – M’ ; where M < M’ and M = M’ - M Whereas in the circuit of revenue money mediates an exchange of equivalent commodity-values, in the circuit of money-capital commodities mediate the exchange between quantities of unequal money-value, with the amount of money-as-capital invested at the beginning being of a magnitude

less than the money-drawn-out at the end. The value form of this “extra” money (M) is referred to by Marx as surplus value:

“More money is withdrawn from circulation at the finish than was thrown into it at the

start…The exact form of this process is therefore M – C – M‘, where M’ = M + M = the original sum advanced, plus an increment. This increment or excess over the original value I call ‘surplus value’” (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 161; Fowkes, p. 251).

13 Of course, the theory of money has developed tremendously since the time Marx wrote his tome, and the question of the role of commodity money in the analysis is the subject of long and very interesting debate. But as our interest is to develop Marx’s own approach we shall continue with the commodity-money assumption. On modern notions of money within the context of Marx’s theory see among other works those of de Brunhoff (1976), Bellofiore (1989; 2004; 2005), other entries in the edited work by Moseley (2005), Foley (1983a, 1986) and Shaikh (2016) Chapters 5 and 15.

Page 14: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

13

Marx next turns to explain where this extra comes from, since the law of value previously defined as the exchange of equivalents is seemingly violated. And here Marx discovers what he calls the “secret of profit making”. The key to this is contained in the commodity elements C and C’ in the circuit of money-capital14 as mediated via the production process:

Circuit of Money-Capital (expanded):

Labor-power

M – C …P…C’ – M’ Means of Production

In the expanded circuit of money-capital, the primal role of the production process becomes evident. The initial money advanced (M) purchases on the market two different commodity inputs, means of production and labor-power. These inputs are combined in the production process (P) which results in the new commodity output C’ of greater value which is sold on the market for M’. The surplus value come from the fact that the commodity output is of a value greater than the inputs: C < C’. Marx argues that it is within the process of production that value “self-expands”. Capital is thus defined as a magnitude of self-expanding value; here capital emerges not as a ‘thing’ but rather as a social relation specific to the capitalist mode of production and capitalistic relations of private property (Shaikh 1987a). Given that the process of production results in the creation of more value than that which entered as inputs, Marx concludes that there must therefore be a commodity-input that adds more value to the production process than its cost. That input is labor-power where the purchase-price of labor, or wage-rate, is of a magnitude less than the value of the productive consumption15 of that labor:

“In order to be able to extract value from the consumption of a commodity, {the capitalist} must be so lucky as to find, within the sphere of circulation, in the market, a commodity, whose use-value possesses the peculiar property of being a source of value, whose actual consumption, therefore, is itself an embodiment of labour, and, consequently, a creation of

14 Marx devotes the first two-thirds of Volume II of Capital to the different circuits of capital (circuits of money-capital, commodity-capital, and productive-capital), as well as with the relationship between the circuits of capital and that of revenue; the latter third of Volume II concerns the process of social reproduction Marx discerned from the analysis of Francois Quesnay and the Physiocratic school referred to as the schemes of reproduction. Marx shows that the circuit of revenue does not “go away” once the circuit of capital enters as center-stage. Indeed, the wage-worker remains strictly within the confines of the circuit of revenue because the money wage s/he receives is exchanged for a wage-bundle of equal value; there is no over-plus from the perspective of the worker in the wage relation. For a succinct exposition of the circuits of capital and revenue and they role they play in the social reproduction process see Chapters V and VI of Desai (1979). Unfortunately, space prevents the proper development of circuits of capital and the reproduction schemes in this chapter. In addition to the Desai reference readers can also consult Kozo Uno’s (1977) masterful treatise on Marx’s economic theory for a thorough exposition of the main tenets of Marx’s entire approach; contained in Part II Chapters 2 and 3 are especially lucid expositions of the circuits of capital and the reproduction schemes, respectively. 15 Productive consumption is defined as the process whereby inputs are utilized in the process of production. The Classical tradition conceives of both means of production and living labor as productively consumed when production is commenced. So-ingrained is this notion for the Classical paradigm that Sraffa (parenthetically in the opening section) informs readers that productive consumption of inputs is implied in the very definition of what constitutes the methods of production:

“(We shall call these relations ‘the methods of production and productive consumption’, or, for short, the methods of production.)” (Sraffa 1960, p. 3; emphasis in-text).

Page 15: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

14

value. The possessor of money does find on the market such a special commodity in capacity for labour or labour-power” (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 177; Fowkes, p. 270).

We now arrive at the one of the most important developments of Marx’s critique of Classical political economy, namely that in the capitalist production process the quantity of value-added by wage-labor in terms of its productivity is of a greater magnitude than the quantity of value remunerated via the wage-form. This is the foundation for the exploitation theory of profits where the source of surplus value emerges as the unpaid labor time conceived as the difference between the value added by labor and the value at which this labor is paid. And here is one of Marx’s major contributions and advances to Classical doctrines, namely the distinction between labor and labor-power. The Classical economists, argued Marx, confused the productive capacity of living labor with the value of labor itself. But for Marx there was a fundamental distinction between the purchase of labor-power on the market by the capitalists and the use of this labor-power in the production process; in Marxian value language, this distinction is between (i) the value of labor-power (VLP) representing the value of the means of subsistence and consumption wage-goods socially necessary for the reproduction of the working class, the money form of which is expressed in the wage, and (ii) the value-added by the productive consumption of this labor-power in the course of the normal capitalist production process. The former is the exchange-value of labor and the latter its use-value.16 Marx makes the strong assumption that the capitalist purchases labor power on the market at its value. This is a marked break with the Ricardian Socialists in that there is no “swindle” involved. For Marx, surplus value is defined as the unpaid labor time performed by the worker in the course of the normal capitalist production process. The use-value expression of this is the surplus product which serves the material foundation from which capitalist consumption and investment expenditures emanate. Formally speaking, surplus value is equal to the value-added by living labor minus the value of labor power, which can be alternatively expressed as the value of the net product minus the value of the consumption bundle of workers. Here we arrive at the basic analytical framework of Marx’s theory of value in capitalist commodity production. The value of an individual commodity (C) is equal to the value of the means of production which went to produce it (c), plus the value of labor power (v), plus the surplus value (s):

C = c + v + s (1) This three-part breakdown of the value of an individual commodity is the hallmark of Marx’s approach to which he invented his own nomenclature. He called c constant capital in that the value of the means of production is wholly replaced in the value of the gross product; no new value results from the productive consumption of means of production as the value contributed to the gross product involves the wholesale transfer of a constant value. Marx called v variable capital in that productive consumption of the commodity labor-power results in a greater value-added than the VLP which the capitalist is assumed to have paid. And s is called surplus value which is the value created gratis in the normal course of the production process that does not have an equivalent cost.

16 Roman Rosdolsy (1977) has a fascinating discussion in Chapter 3 of that work on the economic importance of use-value, and there gives a lucid exposition of the use-value character of labor-power being able to produce more value than that at which is paid; on this see also Foley (1983b).

Page 16: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

15

By virtue of the property relations in the capitalist production process, the owner of the produced commodity is the capitalist who advanced the capital and therefore gets the profit; accordingly, surplus value serves as the material and value basis for the profit relation, the latter of course being the lifeblood and heartbeat of the capitalist mode of production. 5. Some of Marx’s other economic categories The breakdown of the value of an individual commodity given in Equation (1) serves as the basic fundamental building block of a tremendous and rich architecture that is Marxian economic theory. The inclusion from the outset of surplus value (s) in the most basic understanding of the value relation adds clarity to the notion of capital Marx defined and advanced. As discussed above, for Marx capital was a social relation such that a certain magnitude of value was able to draw out of the market a quantity of value greater than itself; Marx is quite clear about this in Capital, Volume I:

“Capital, therefore, is not only, as Adam Smith says,the command over labour. It is essentially the command over unpaid labour. All surplus value, whatever particular form (profit, interest, or rent), it may subsequently crystallise into, is in substance the materialisation of unpaid labour. The secret of the self-expansion of capital resolves itself into having the disposal of a definite quantity of other people's unpaid labour” (MECW, Vol. 35, p. 534; Fowkes, p. 672).

This relation of capital as the command of unpaid labor is depicted in the circuit of money-capital where initial money advanced (M) at the one pole leads to a greater quantity of money (M’) at the other. This is quite distinct from expenditure in general depicted by the circuit of revenue, where different commodities of equal value are mediated in the exchange relation by a quantity of money also of the same value. The transformation of money into capital involves the capitalistically-organized labor process. Here the direct producers, defined as the people who actually perform the labor of society, are transformed into wage-laborers, now called workers.17 Capitalist commodity production also involves the tandem process whereby money-owners accrue all of the social wealth and transform themselves into capitalists. Analytically-speaking, wage-workers represent the owners of labor-power, which is the only property in their possession, who sell it to the capitalist on a daily basis for a “fair” wage equal to the VLP. Capitalists represent the owners of the means of production and money-capital necessary to advance production. And as innocuous as this may sound, historically-speaking the actual processes whereby direct producers were transformed into wage-laborers and money-owners into capitalists was often coercive and violent, and the processes whereby this came about in England are described in detail by Marx in the chapters that appear in seventh and final Part of Capital, Volume I, dubbed “So-Called Primitive Accumulation”. Once the capitalist mode of production gets hold of the labor process the modus operandi of the endeavor changes. No longer is the matter concerned primarily with the production of use-values but rather with the production of profit, mediated through the production of use-values. Here the labor process is transformed into what Marx calls the valorization process and capital as self-expanding

17 The term direct producer is the general expression for those who engage in the laboring activities of society. In the slave mode of production, the direct producers are called slaves, in feudalism they are called serfs, and in capitalism wage laborers or workers.

Page 17: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

16

value begins to take shape. Marx meticulously analyzes the capitalist working-day, where the total value-added by living labor (l ) is considered on a per-day basis. By definition the VLP is defined as the labor-value of the “fair” wage-bundle, and under capitalistic relations this value is less than that added by the worker in the course of the working-day. This means that over the course of the working day, the worker will perform in a fraction of the day the labor necessary to replace the VLP. Marx calls this the necessary labor-time (NLT) as it represents the portion of the working day that is spent reproducing the value of what workers are being paid, i.e. paid labor. The remainder of the working day, that over and above the VLP, Marx calls the surplus labor-time (SLT) as it represents the portion of the working-day that is unremunerated and hence not paid, i.e. unpaid labor.

Figure 3: Breakdown of Working Day

Here Marx is able to clearly identify perhaps the important contributions of the analysis presented in Capital, Volume I, namely the ratio of unpaid to paid labor, which he calls the rate of surplus-value or rate of exploitation (e), defined as the ratio between the SLT and NLT portions of the working day

(e =𝑆𝐿𝑇

𝑁𝐿𝑇=

𝑢𝑛𝑝𝑎𝑖𝑑 𝑙𝑎𝑏𝑜𝑟

𝑝𝑎𝑖𝑑 𝑙𝑎𝑏𝑜𝑟=

𝑠

𝑣). Indeed, all of this first Volume can be characterized as an effort to

explicate and expound on the form exploitation assumes in capitalistically-organized social formations. Marx proceeds by describing the (logico-historical) process whereby the society’s production becomes increasingly subsumed under the law of capital as self-expanding value. Emerging capitalistic social relations of production first confront the technical forces of production (or level of technology) already in existence. Marx refers to this as the formal subsumption of labor to capital where relatively crude production techniques already in existence are given capitalistic social expression as direct producers become wage-workers and money-owners become capitalists. Since self-expansion is the prime motive of capital, the way in which surplus-value is expanded given the relatively unsophisticated older production techniques involves the lengthening of the working day, what Marx calls the creation of absolute surplus value (ASV).

Figure 4: Absolute surplus value Before lengthening:

After lengthening:

NLT = paid labor SLT = unpaid labor

Length of the total working day

NLT = paid labor SLT = unpaid labor

NLT = paid labor SLT = unpaid labor ASV increases

Workday Lengthens

Page 18: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

17

Marx recognized that the capitalist mode of production in fact eventually transforms and revolutionizes the production techniques themselves resulting in a labor process of much greater efficiency. Marx calls this the real subsumption of labor to capital as greater efficiency in techniques of production result in the technical improvements in the production of all commodities included those that comprise the wage-bundle. Here the length of the working day remains constant, and relative surplus-value results from the cheapening of the wage bundle in the form of a reduction in the labor-time necessary to produce the wage-goods that comprise the VLP.

Figure 5: Relative surplus value Old technique:

New technique:

Relative surplus value creation begins to take hold once the technical conditions of the labor process are turned in the conduit from which capital self-expands and the valorization process begins in full-force. This for Marx becomes the fundamental driver of the phenomenal technical changes that are the hallmark of the capitalist mode of production. So important is this that all of Part 4 of Capital, Volume I is devoted to the creation of relative surplus value; it is here that some of Marx’s most riveting chapters are written exploring the history and development of the modern manufacturing system and the conditions underlying these processes. Key here is productivity of labor increasing at a pace never before seen in human history, coupled with the cheapening of commodities workers consume as part of their “fair wage” as expressed in the VLP. Once launched on a world scale, the real subsumption of labor to capital generates massive quantities of surplus-value which serves as the material foundation for the profit form to flourish, all the while the revolutionizing the production process and ushering in technical changes that have been groundbreaking in their depth and scope and ongoing in their breadth and intensity. It is here that the analysis of the accumulation of capital expressed in the growth of the capital stock begins to take root. This accumulation has effects both on the revolutionized techniques of production as well as on the labor force these new techniques employ. Regarding effects on production techniques, Marx develops the framework such that new methods of production involve heavy outlays of machinery and other forms of constant capital which causes a rise in the ratio of constant to variable capital which Marx calls the organic composition of capital (OCK), where

𝑂𝐶𝐾 =𝑐

𝑣 (Mohun 1983; Shaikh 1987b). This rising OCK aspect of capital accumulation has

ramifications for the rate of profit (r), the latter defined as the ratio of profit to capital advanced conceived as what Marx calls cost-price which is constant plus variable capital (c + v).18 Writing the

18 In Sraffa’s (1960) approach the profit rate is assessed on constant capital alone with variable capital not being

considered in the formula for r, i.e. 𝑟 =𝑠

𝑐. The reason for this has to do with the specification Sraffa makes for the wage

NLT = paid labor SLT = unpaid labor

NLT = paid labor SLT = unpaid labor RSV increases

Improved techniques of production of wage goods

Page 19: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

18

profit rate in this manner allows for it to be alternatively expressed as a direct function of the rate of exploitation (Morishima 1973, p. 53 calls this the fundamental Marxian theorem) and an inverse function of the organic composition of capital (this is accomplished once each of the elements in both the numerator and denominator of the ratio are divided by v):

𝑟 =𝑠

(𝑐+𝑣)→ 𝑟 =

𝑠

𝑣

(𝑐

𝑣+1)

(2)

Equation (2) illustrates the offsetting effects on the profit rate with capital accumulation. In the numerator is the rate of surplus value which has a positive or direct effect on the profit rate: with increased exploitation of labor there is room for the profit rate to rise. However in the denominator the accumulation of capital according to methods of relative surplus value causes the OCK to rise which produces a negative effect on profit causing the tendency for the entire rate to fall. And here we have Marx’s theory of the falling rate of profit (FROP) which he characterized as the overarching tendency of long-run capital accumulation (Shaikh 1983b, pp. 159-60).19 For Marx the tendency for FROP led him to the conclusion consistent with method of historical materialism that capitalism is historical in character and thereby transient, and that the conditions for its own demise lay within the very belly of that beast and embedded in its life-blood. Hence capital’s insatiable need for self-valorization inherent in the underlying processes of accumulation itself plants seeds of crises which become endogenous to the normal functioning of the capitalist system. Marx notes however that this is only a tendency, which means that there can and often are counter-veiling forces at work that stave-off the FROP, specifically those that raise the rate of exploitation in the numerator at a pace greater than the OCK in the denominator. This speaks to the rich debates within Marxian crisis theories over the possibility versus the necessity of crises related to the FROP (Shaikh 1977, 1983c). The effects of capital accumulation are also felt by the labor force. Here Marx introduces the tendency for the system to produce persistent and ever-growing redundant population of potential workers, what he calls the reserve army of labor (Shaikh 1983d, pp. 422-3). Indeed Marx was among the first theorists to posit the notion that unemployment and underemployment of labor was a normal part of the capital accumulation process, so much so that John Maynard Keynes, despite being rather allergic to Marx, actually mentions the Old Moor when developing his (Keynes’) theory of employment and effective demand in the General Theory.20 Marx’s theory of the accumulation of capital entails offsetting effects on the labor force: on the one hand capital accumulation requires more labor as the methods of production expand in scale, but at the same time the technology adopted is often labor-displacing which means that in terms of intensity, less labor is required to move more means of production. This results in a dynamic process of ebb and flow with the reserve army of labor serving as a buffer to the often crisis-prone process of capital accumulation.

where he chose the wage-share or proportionate wage paid out of productivity rather than the wage-bundle implied in the VLP concept as introduced above. 19 In fact the notion that the rate of profit falls as capitalist production develops is not a Marxian notion exclusively, as one can find, albeit for different reasons, a similar idea in the works of Adam Smith, David Ricard, John Stuart Mill, and even John Maynard Keynes (Eltis 1987, pp. 276-80). 20 “The great puzzle of effective demand…vanished from the economic literature…It could only live on furtively, below the surface, in the underworlds of {among others} Karl Marx…” (Keynes 1936, p. 32).

Page 20: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

19

Crisis theory serves as one of the major platters upon which Marxian economic inquiry is served. For Marx and the Marxist School, economic crises are not aberrations in the otherwise smooth functioning of the capitalist mode of production (Shaikh 2016, 1983b). Rather such crises are endemic to the anarchy of social production under the auspice of profit-maximization, private enterprise and capitalistic property relations. Introduced above is the framework for crises borne of capital accumulation where increasing mechanization leads to a tendential fall in the rate of profit and rise in displaced workers causing unemployment. This is related to another source of crises, namely the problem of insufficient realization or sale of the output produced, which in modern guise is often couched in terms of a lack of effective demand referred to as underconsumption, defined as a shortfall in the demand of consumption (as opposed to investment) goods (Desai 1987, 494-7; Bleaney 1976). Each of these types of crises are endemic to the capitalist mode of production and Marx and the Marxist School incorporate this their approach from the outset. The theory of accumulation in Marx also considers the concentration and centralization of firms and industries, and the role this plays in socio-economic life within capitalistic social formations. Concentration defines the scope and intensity of power capitalist firms have over wage-labor in the sense that the labor process becomes a “concentrated mass of means of production commanding an army of workers” (Shaikh 1983a, p. 68). Centralization reinforces the concentration of capital through the process of competition which underlies the establishment of mega-capitals such as multi-national global industries and corporations some of whom have more power than sovereign countries within which they often operate. It is significant that the theory of competition derived from Marx takes the opposite tact of so-called “modern” approaches to competition defined in terms of the number of firms, among other criteria. Marx’s theory by contrast recognizes that huge mega-capitals are not the result from the absence of competition but rather its manifestation (on different approaches to the theory of competition including recent developments in Marxian theory see the edited book by Moudud, Bina, & Mason, 2011). The role of competition in Marx’s price theory is usually expressed in terms of inter-industry competition and the formation of a uniform or general rate of profit on capital advanced, which in the context of many capitals competing with one another causes deviations with labor values.21 In the literature this price-value deviation is referred to as the transformation of labor values into prices of production and is often derided with the moniker of the transformation problem, although frankly there is no “problem” inasmuch as the deviations are not arbitrary or capricious and occur in an orderly and systematic fashion in accordance with the organic compositions of the various competing capitals.

21 Formation of the general rate of profit among industries is referred to as inter-industry competition or competition between industries, which is the methodological point of departure for the transformation problem. However, Marx’s theory of competition is very rich and robust and extends to include intra-competition of firms within an industry. Regarding value theory this strictly speaking comes from Marx’s theory of rent, in terms of absolute rent (which Ricardo eschewed but Smith did not) as well as differential rent (on which all agreed as relevant) conceived both at the margin of cultivation (so-called extensive rent, labelled differential rent I ) and also at the infra-margin of technical change (so-called intensive rent labelled differential rent II ). Marx tackles the question of rent mostly in Volume III of Capital and also in some passages in Theories of Surplus Value. Anwar Shaikh has since the late 1970s developed Marx’s theory of competition at both the inter- and intra-margin into what he terms the theory of regulating capital; interested readers can consult his most recent tome (Shaikh 2016 Part II) for the final iteration of what he has dubbed the theory of real competition, as well as extensive references to the previous literature. Howard Botwinick (1993) extends Shaikh’s regulating capital theory to tackle to quest ion of persistent wage differentials and Mason (1995) uses the framework to look at matters dealing with racial discrimination, etc.

Page 21: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

20

An instructive way to conceive of the transformation is to differentiate extraction of surplus-value from its distribution: surplus value is extracted as unpaid labor from the worker and then distributed as profit to the capitalist. However, the process of distribution of the profit accords to different mechanisms than that of its extraction. Specifically distribution requires a uniform rate of profit (r*) explicit in the principle of inter-industrial competition between capitals. Such competition means that each dollar invested in any industry is thought to receive an equal and aliquot portion of the total surplus value produced according to the value of the capital advanced. In a letter to Engels from 30 April, 1868, Marx calls this “capitalistic communism”:

Then it turns out that, assuming the rate of surplus value, i.e. the exploitation of labour,

as equal, the production of value and therefore the production of surplus value and

therefore the rate of profit are different in different branches of production. But from

these varying rates of profit a mean or general rate of profit is formed by

competition. This rate of profit, expressed absolutely, can be nothing but the surplus

value produced (annually) by the capitalist class in relation to the total of social capital

advanced…What the competition among the various masses of capital— invested in

different spheres of production and differently composed—is striving for is capitalist

communism, namely that the mass of capital employed in each sphere of production should get a

fractional part of the total surplus value proportionate to the part of the total social

capital that it forms. (MECW, Vol. 43, p. 23; emphasis in text).

Here then Marx states the matter quite succinctly. The different compositions of capital across the various industries ensure that the money-expression of labor values, referred to as direct prices, no longer correspond to the competitive prices, referred to as prices of production, which underlies the actual market prices of commodities. At the immediate level this difference has to do with the quantum of a capital’s unpaid labor extracted versus the profits distributed. For industries that are relatively labor intensive the amount of unpaid labor extracted from its workers is greater than the profit distributed to its capitalists, and for industries that are relatively capital intensive the reverse happens and the unpaid labor extracted by its workers falls short of what is necessary to distribute to its capitalists. This process is visualized in Figure 6:

Figure 6: Transformation of direct prices into prices of production

Figure 6 reflects the matter as Marx characterized it in Volume III, namely under the assumption that the inputs remain of the same magnitude both before and after the transformation (Marx

Page 22: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

21

however conceives of the matter in his numeric example using 5 industries rather than 2). This leads to the error of not transforming the inputs, an oversight on the part of Marx that became the source of tremendous debate and confusion in the years after the publication of Volume III posthumously by Engels in 1894. However, as Shaikh (1978) has shown, Marx’s own incomplete procedure is only the first of several iterations the end result of which has all inputs transformed and Marx’s methodology vindicated. The literature on the transformation of direct prices to prices of production is enormous and the debates robust.22 The take-away usually comports with the preconceptions the various authors bring to the table in the first place. For those sympathetic to Marx and the Marxist School, the transformation is simply another step in the concretization of abstract categories of analysis in moving form value to prices. For those antagonistic, the transformation is evidence of a contradiction between the labor theory of value presented in Capital, Volume I and the theory of production prices in Capital, Volume III. Conclusion: On the future of Marxian economic theory It has been attempted in the pages above to provide readers with an overall account of the intellectual history and conceptual content of the most important features of Marxian economic inquiry. But readers should be warned that the jury is very much out regarding many of the most basic tenets of Marxian theory. For example, in recent years there has been an approach to the transformation that re-orients the question of having to move from value to price with regard to the value of labor power. This approach is referred to as the New Interpretation (also called the New Solution) and was articulated independently by Gerard Dumenil and Duncan Foley in the early 1980s (Dumenil 1982-3; Foley 1982; Foley 2000). In this approach, the issue of a ‘given wage bundle’ is questioned since the wage bargain is carried out in terms of money-wages which are used by workers to purchase the means of subsistence and consumption. Clearly here the relation moves from money-price to the value of labor-power. This begs the important question of the specification of the wage in Marxian theory, with two not-necessarily-incompatible approaches emerging: (i) the conventional notion of wages being regulated by the value of the commodity wage-bundle, and (ii) the wage-share, referred to by Marx as the relative wage, which conceives of wages as an aliquot portion of workers productivity (see Levrero 2013 for a recent account of this matter). It is important to note that Marx himself used both notions of the wage and readers can find the specification of the relative wage in Wage labour and Capital from 1849 and Wages, Price, and Profits from 1865 to contrast with the specification of the commodity wage bundle in Capital; like many of his other ideas, Marx’s theory of wages remains unfinished and undeveloped and pregnant with tremendous potential much of which remains untapped. We are also in the fortunate position to have available for the first time in the history of economic thought all of the unpublished archival notes of the Cambridge Italian economist Piero Sraffa available online at the Trinity College, Cambridge, Wren Library website (https://janus.lib.cam.ac.uk/db/node.xsp?id=EAD%2FGBR%2F0016%2FSRAFFA) . Sraffa has long been associated with an anti-Marxian critique of the LTV, but this was due mostly to the those who follow the interpretation of writers such as Steedman (1977) and others who used the fact that one can arrive at prices in the Sraffa system without resorting to labor values as “proof” that the LTV is

22 For a very useful introduction to the matter readers can consult Hunt & Glick (1987), and also the masterful two volume A History of Marxian Economic Theory by M.C. Howard & J.E. King (1989, 1992).

Page 23: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

22

at best redundant and at worst just plain wrong. But as recent research from the Sraffa Archive shows, Sraffa was far from dismissive of the LTV and in fact some evidence suggests that he was very keen to re-orient that theory in modern guise (see Bellofiore 2008, 2012, 2014; Preti 2014, and Carter 2011, 2013, 2014a,b). The relationship between Marx and Sraffa at deep theoretical levels is very much open for debate and development and generally speaking the matter is rife with tremendous potential. Marxian economic inquiry contains a rich and robust analytical framework developed over a literature vast in content and varied in interpretation from antagonists and sympathizers alike. Written over a period of 150 years in many languages and various local dialects, Marxian economic inquiry comprises oceans of ink penned on forests of paper. This of course means that no single chapter can give proper service to the voluminous material, multiplicity of concepts at varied levels of abstraction, and variety of approaches that characterize Marx and the Marxist School. Readers should view the pages above as written as an effort to arm them with a relatively cogent understanding of the most important foundational notions that comprise the positive content and basis of Marx’s theory. Indeed, the reason we study the history of economic thought is not to learn names and dates, etc., of old (mostly) men, but rather gain a keen grasp on the unresolved questions and issues that still plague economic science today. And if looked at with these fresh eyes, Marxian economic inquiry remains very much alive and Marx’s theoretical project continues to be robust and relevant for the development of economic science into the 21st century and beyond.

Page 24: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

23

References Bellofiore, R. (1989). “A monetary labor theory of value”, Review of Radical Political Economics, 21(1-2), 1-26. Bellofiore, R. (2004). ”Marx and the macro-foundation of microeconomics.” In Bellofiore, R. and Taylor, N. (eds.) The Constitution of Capital: Essays on Volume I of Marx’s Capital. Palgrave Macmillan: Basingstoke Bellofiore, R. (2005). “The monetary aspects of the capitalist process in the Marxian system: an investigation from the point of view of the theory of the monetary circuit.” In: Fred Moseley (ed): Marx’ Theory of Money. Modern Appraisals. Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan Bellofiore, R. (2008) Sraffa after Marx: An open issue. In G. Chiodi & L. Ditta (Eds), Sraffa or an Alternative Economics). Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 68-92.

Bellofiore, R. (2012) The “tiresome objector” and Old Moor: a renewal of the debate of Marx and Sraffa based on the unpublished material at the Wren Library. Cambridge Journal of Economics, 36, 1385–99.

Bellofiore, R. (2014). The Loneliness of the Long Distance Thinker: Sraffa, Marx, and the Critique of Economic Theory. In R. Bellofiore & S. Carter (Eds). Towards a New Understanding of Sraffa: Insights from Archival Research, Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 198-240.

Blaug, M. (1997). Economic Theory in Retrospect. 5th Edition. Cambridge U.K.: Cambridge University Press. Bleaney, M. (1976). Underconsumption Theories. New York: International Publishers. Botwinick, H. (1993). Persistent Inequalities: Wage Disparity under Capitalist Competition. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press. Bray, J. F. (1839) Labour’s wrongs and labour’s remedy; or, the age of might and the age of right. Reprinted (1931), London. Carter, S. (2011) A simple model of the surplus approach to value, distribution, and growth. American Journal of Economics and Sociology, 70, 29–58.

Carter, S. (2013) Sraffa and the “corrected” organic composition of capital. In S. Levero, A. Palumbo & A. Stirati (Eds) Sraffa and the Reconstruction ofEconomic Theory, Volume III. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, pp. 228-57.

Carter, S. (2014a). Sraffa and the Standard Commodity, in R. Bellofiore & S. Carter (Eds). Towards a New Understanding of Sraffa: Insights from Archival Research. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 47-68.

Carter, S. (2014b) From ‘pool of profits’ to surplus and deficit industries: Archival evidence on the

Page 25: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

24

evolution of Piero Sraffa’s thought’. Research in Political Economy, 29, 3-61.

Carter, S. (2018). ‘Heterodox theories of distribution’. In T. Jo, L. Chester, & C. D’Ippoliti (Eds). The Routledge Handbook ofHeterodox Economics: Theorizing, Analyzing, and Transforming Capitalism (pp. 127-144). New York: Routledge.

Cournort, A.A. (1897 [1838]). Mémoire sur les applications du calcul des chances à la statistique judiciaire", 1838, Journal des mathématiques pures et appliquées, 12. T. 3. p.257-334; English translation by N.T. Bacon as Researches into the Mathematical Principles of the Theory of Wealth, New York: Macmillan & Co. de Brunhoff, S. (1976). Marx on Money. New York: Urizen. Desai, M. (1979). Marxian Economics. Totowa, New Jersey: Littlefield, Adams & Co. Dobb, M. (1973). Theories of Value and Distribution since Adam Smith. Cambridge, U.: Cambridge University Press. Duménil, G. (1983). Beyond the Transformation Riddle: A Labour Theory of Value. Science and Society, 67(4), 427-450

Dupuit, J. (1952 [1844]).“De la mesure de l’utilité des travaux publics”, Annales des ponts et chaussées, v.8 (2), p.332-75 [English trans. "On the Measurement of the Utility of Public Works", (trans., 1952, International Economic Papers). Edmonds, T. R. (1833). Practical moral and political economy (1833). Reprinted (1969), New York: Augustus Kelley. Eltis, W. (1987). “Falling rate of profit,” in J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, and P. Newman (eds.). New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. London: Macmillan Press, 276-80. Foley, D. . (1986). Understanding Capital: Marx’s Economic Theory. Cambridge, U..: Harvard University Press.

Foley, D. (1982). The Value of Money, the Value of Labour Power, and the Marxian Transformation Problem, Review of Radical Political Economics, 14(2), 37-47.

Foley, D.K. (1983a). “Money”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 337-40. Foley, D.K. (1983b). “Use-value”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 504. Foley, Duncan. (2000). Recent Developments in the Labour Theory of Value. Review of Radical Political Economics, 32(1), 1-39.

Gossen, H.H (1983 [1854]). Entwickelung der Gesetze des menschlichen Verkehrs, und der daraus fliessenden Regeln für menschliche Handeln, transalated as "The Development of the Laws of Exchange among

Page 26: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

25

Men and of the Consequent Rules of Human Action", but first English 1983 translation by R.C. Blitz uses title Laws of Laws of Human Relations and the Rules of Human Action Derived Therefrom. Hodgskin, T. (1825). Labour defended against the claims of capital. Reprinted (1969), New York: Augustus Kelley.

Hodgskin, T. (1827). Popular political economy. Reprinted (1966), New York. Augustus Kelley Howard, M.C. & King, J.E. (1989). A History of Marxian Economics, Volume I. Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press. Howard, M.C. & King, J.E. (1992). A History of Marxian Economics, Volume II. Princeton N.J.: Princeton University Press. Hunt, E.. & Glick, M (1987). “Transformation problem”, in J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, and P. Newman (eds.). New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. London: Macmillan Press, 688-90. Keynes, J. M. (1936). The General Theory of Employment, Interest, and Money. New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich. King, J.E. (1980). ‘Utopian or scientific? A reconsideration of the Ricardian Socialists’, History of Political Economy, 15(3), 345-373. Kunzmann, P., F.-P. Burkard & F. Wiedmann (2011) dtv-Atlas Philosophie. München: Deutscher Taschenbuch Verlag GmbH & Co. KG. Kurz, H.D. (2013). Economics Thought: A Brief History. New York: Columbia University Press. Larrain, J. (1983). “Base and superstructure”, in in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 42-5.

Levrero, E. S. (2013). ‘Marx on absolute and relative wages and the modern theory of distribution.’ Review of Political Economy 1, 91-116. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1975). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 5. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1976). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 6. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1986). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 28. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1987). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 29. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1988a). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 30. London: Lawrence & Wishart.

Page 27: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

26

Marx, K & Engels, F. (1988b). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 43. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1989a). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 24. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1989b). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 31. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1989c). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 32. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1991). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 33. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1994). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 34. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1996). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 35: Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume I. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1997). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 36: Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume II. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K & Engels, F. (1998). Marx-Engels Collected Works (MECW) Volume 37: Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume III. London: Lawrence & Wishart. Marx, K. (1976 [1867]). Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Volume I. Translated by Ben Fowkes. London: Penguin Classics. Mason, P. (1995). “Race, competition, and differential wages.” Cambridge Journal of Economics, 19 (4), 545-67. Mohun, S. (1983). “Organic composition of capital”, in in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 356-8. Morishima, M. (1973). Marx’s Economics: A Dual Theory of Value and Growth, Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press.

Moseley, F. (ed). (2005): Marx’ Theory of Money. Modern Appraisals. Houndsmills: Palgrave Macmillan. Moudud, J., Bina, C., and Mason, P. (2011). Alternative Theories of Competition: Challenges to the Orthodoxy, New York: Routledge.

Page 28: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

27

Oakely, A. (1983). The Making of Marx’s Critical Theory: A Bibliographic Analysis. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul. Preti, D. (2014).” On the Neoricardian criticism of irrelevance, in R. Bellofiore & S. Carter (Eds). Towards a New Understanding of Sraffa: Insights from Archival Research. Basingstoke and New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 25-46. Ravenstone, P. (1821). A few doubts as to the correctness of some opinions generally entertained on the subjects of population and political economy. Reprinted (1966), New York: Augustus Kelley. Ravenstone, P. (1824). Thoughts on the funding system and its effects (1824). Reprinted (1966), New York: Augustus Kelley. Rosdolsky, R. (1977). The Making of Mar’s Capital. London: Pluto Press. Ross, I. S. (Ed.). (1982). ‘Dugald Stewart’s Account of Adam Smith’, in Wightman, W.P.D & Bryce, J.C. (Eds.) Essay on Philosophical Subjects, Volume III of The Works and Correspondence of Adam Smith, Raphael, D.D. & Skinner, A.S. General Editors. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Screpanti, E. & Zamagni, S. (2005). Outlines of a History of Economic Thought. London: Oxford University Press. Shaikh, A. (1978). “Marx’s theory pf val;ure and the ‘transformation problem;, in J. Schwartz (ed). The Subtle Anatomy of Capitalism. Santa Monica: Goodyear, 108-39. Shaikh, A. (1983a). “ Centralization and concentration of capital”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 68-9. Shaikh, A. (1983b). “Economic crises”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 138-143. Shaikh, A. (1983c). “Falling rate of profit”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 159-61. Shaikh, A. (1983d). “Reserve army of labour”, in T. Bottomore, L. Harris, V.G. Kiernan, & R. Miliband (eds). A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, 422-3. Shaikh, A. (1987a). “Capital as a Social Relation”, in J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, and P. Newman (eds.). New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. London: Macmillan Press, 333-6. Shaikh, A. (1987b). “Organic composition of capital”, in J. Eatwell, M. Milgate, and P. Newman (eds.). New Palgrave Dictionary of Economics. London: Macmillan Press, 755-7. Shaikh, A. (2016). Capitalism: Competition, Conflict, Crises. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Smith, A. (1776). An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Reprinted (1976) Glasgow Edition, R.H. Campbell & A.S. Skinner (eds). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

Page 29: Karl Marx and the Marxist School

28

Sraffa, P. (1928-31). Lecture Notes on the Advanced Theory of Value, 1928-31. Wren Library online resource at https://janus.lib.cam.ac.uk/db/node.xsp?id=EAD%2FGBR%2F0016%2FSRAFFA%2FD2%2F4 and images with transcriptions at https://drive.google.com/open?id=1srPZVD39ZD9SFMmXTrwqYyQJFIVDNoVZNtogQFcVI8w. Sraffa, P. (1960). Prodcution of Commodities by Means of Commodities. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. Sraffa, P. (1974). The Works and Correspondence of David Ricardo, Volume XI: General Index. Cambridge, U.K.: Cambridge University Press. Steedman, I. (1977). Marx After Sraffa. London: New Left Books. Thompson, W. (1824). An Inquiry into the Principle of the Distribution of Wealth, applied to the newly proposed system of voluntary equality of wealth. Reprinted (1963). New York: Augustus Kelley.

Uno, K. (1977). Principles of Political Economy: Theory of a Purely Capitalist Society. New Jersey: Humanities Press.

View publication statsView publication stats