Legal Realism Green Wmlj

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    1/86

    * Associate Professor, George Mason University School of Law. Ph.D. (Philosophy), YaleUniversity, 1990; J.D., Yale Law School, 1996. I would like to thank Ken Himma, BrianLeiter, Richard Posner, and an audience at William and Mary School of Law for helpfulcomments on this Article. This Article was written with support from George MasonUniversity School of Law and its Center for Law and Economics.

    1915

    William and MaryLaw Review

    V OLUME 46 N O . 6, 2005

    LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW

    M ICHAEL STEVEN GREEN *

    T ABLE OF C ONTENTS

    . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .I NTRODUCTION 1917I. T HE R EALISTS T HEORIES OF L AW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1921

    A. What Are Legal Rules? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1921 B. What Is the Prediction Theory of Law? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1926C. Did the Realists Have a Novel Theory of Law at All? . . 1936

    II. H ART ON THE N ORMATIVITY OF L AW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1939 A. Harts Theory of Law . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1940

    B. Can Hart Explain the Laws Normativity? . . . . . . . . . . . 1945C. Shared Cooperative Activities? . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1947

    D. The Revenge of the Natural Law Theorist . . . . . . . . . . . 1950E. Non-Cognitivism and the Internal Point of View . . . . . . 1953

    III. T HE F IRST A RGUMENT A GAINST L EGAL R ULES . . . . . . . . . 1956 A. Legal Rules Are Causally Inert . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1958 B. The First Argument and the

    Rejection of Vested Rights . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1962C. The First Argument and the Decision Theory of Law . . 1966

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    2/86

    1916 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    IV . T HE S ECOND A RGUMENT A GAINST L EGAL R ULES . . . . . . . 1967 A. Legal Obligation and Moral Autonomy . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1969 B. The Second Argument and the Realists

    Theory of Adjudication . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1975C. The Second Argument and

    Mechanical Jurisprudence . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1982 V. E XPLAINING THE P REDICTION AND

    D ECISION T HEORIES OF L AW . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1985 A. The Decision Theory of Law Revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1986 B. Bishop Hoadly . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1988C. The Prediction Theory of Law Revisited . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1993

    D. The Scandinavian Realists . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 1998C ONCLUSION . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . 2000

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    3/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1917

    1. L AURA K ALMAN , L EGAL R EALISM AT Y ALE , 1927-1960, at 229 (1986).2 . Gregory S. Alexander, Comparing the Two Legal RealismsAmerican and

    Scandinavian , 50 A M . J. C OMP . L. 131, 131 (2002) (We are all Realists now, as the sayinggoes.); Brian Leiter, Rethinking Legal Realism: Toward a Na turalized Jurisprudence , 76 T EX .L. R EV . 267, 267-68 (1997 ) (beginning with the premise th at we are all legal realists now todiscuss the meaning of legal realism); Joseph William Singer, Legal Realism Now , 76 C AL .

    L. R EV . 465, 467 (1988) (All major current schools of thought are, in significant ways,products of legal realism. To some extent, we are all realists now.); see also B RIAN B IX ,J URISPRUDENCE : T HEORY AND C ONTEXT 165 (2d ed. 1999); W ILLIAM T WINING , K ARL L LEWELLYN

    AND THE R EALIST M OVEMENT 382 (1973); John Henry Schlegel, American Legal Realism andEmp irical Social Science: From the Yale Exp erience , 28 B UFF . L. R EV . 459, 460 (1979); LouiseWeinberg, Federal Common Law , 83 N W . U. L. R EV . 805, 834 (1989).

    3 . H .L .A . H ART , T HE C ONCEPT OF L AW 124-54 (2d ed. 1994); see also T HEODORE B ENDITT ,L AW AS R ULE AND P RINCIPLE 46-47 (1978); R ONALD D WORKIN , L AW S E MPIRE 36-37 (1986);D AVID L UBAN , L AWYERS AND J USTICE : A N E THICAL S TUDY 20-21 (1988); Andrew Altman, LegalRealism, Critical Legal Studies, and Dworkin , 15 P HIL . & P UB . A FF . 205, 206-07 (1986) (notingthat contemporary legal philosophers largely view Harts critique of realism as cogent);Michael C. Dorf, Prediction and the Rule of Law , 42 UCLA L. R EV . 651, 657-59 (1995)(outlining Harts critique of the realist prediction model); Leslie Green, The Concept of LawRevisited , 94 M ICH . L. R EV . 1687, 1694 (1996) (referring to Harts argument distinguish[ing]rules from other regularities of behavior as decisive against philosophical realism); Brian

    Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism Reconsidered , 111 E THICS 278, 278 (2001)[hereinafter Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism ] (noting the widespread view thatHart exposed realism as a jurisprudential joke); Leiter, supra note 2, at 270 (Hartsdevastating critique of the Realists in Chapter VII of The Concept of Law rendered Realisma philosophical joke in the English-speaking world.).

    4. H ART , supra note 3, at 136.

    I NTRODUCTION

    The legal realist movement flourished back in the 1920s and 30s,primarily at Yale and Colum bia law schools and at Johns H opkinssshort-lived Institute of Law. And yet it is often saidindee d so oftensaid that it has become a clich to call it a clich that we are all1

    realists now. The clich is wrong, however, for there is at least one2

    identifiable (if not sizable) group that rejects realism philosophe rsof law. To them, realism is dead, mercifully put to rest by H.L.A.Harts decisive critique of rule-skepticism in the seventh chapter

    of The Concept of Law .3

    Hart rejected two forms of rule-skepticism advocated by therealists. It was, on the one hand, a theory of law the view thattalk of rules is a myth, cloaking the truth that law consists simplyof the decisions of courts and the prediction of them .... Harts 4

    argument here was brief, for he thought that this form of rule-

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    4/86

    1918 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    5. Id . at 137.6. D WORKIN , supra note 3, at 37.

    7. J EFFRIE G. M URPHY & J ULES L. C OLEMAN , P HILOSOPHY OF L AW 34 (1990).8 . L ei te r, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 278.9. H ART , supra note 3, at 147.

    10 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3; Leiter, supra note 2.11 . See Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 290-93.12 . See infra Part I.C.

    skepticism was an obvious failure. Decisions cannot be all there is5

    to the law, for courts deciding cases are guided by the law by thelegal rules that can be found in constitutions, statutes, regulationsand past judicial opinions. The philosophical community agreed.The realists theory of law was, in the philosophers words, deeplyimplausible, open to easy refutation, and a jurisprudential6 7

    joke. 8

    Hart took rule-skepticism as a theory of adjudication a bit moreseriously. According to this theory, statutes and the like may be law,but they are too indeterminate to be significant influences on, orpredictors of, judges decisions. Because the law is indeterminate,

    judges actually decide cases on the basis of nonlegal conside rations.Hart did not argue that this theory was incoherent, but he did thinkit was a great exaggeration. The law is indeterminate at the9

    margins, he arguedit has what he called open texture but it isnot indeterminate in its core as the realists claimed.

    The seventh chapter of Th e Concept of Law has cast such a longshadow that only recently has the study of legal realism becomehalfway respectable in philosophical circles. A prominent exampleof the renewed interest in the realists is Brian Leiters defense of their theory of adjudication against Harts critique. But Leiter, like10

    the rest of the philosophers, has nothing good to say about theirtheory of law; indeed, part of his strategy for rehabilitating the

    realists is insisting that they did not mean to offer rule-skepticismas a theory of law in the first place. 11

    I will find little to criticize in Leiters defense of the realiststheory of adjudication. But Hart was clearly right about the realistsdesire to present rule-skepticism as a genuine theory of law. If the 12

    realists are to be rehabilitated, we m ust defend this theory. That isthe goal of this Article.

    I will defend the realists theory of law, howev er, only in the senseof showing that it is plausible , not that it is beyond criticism. A

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    5/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1919

    13 . See M ORTON J. H ORWITZ , T HE T RANSFORMATION OF A MERICAN L AW , 1870-1960, at 169(1992). My list of realists is taken from L eiter, supra note 2, at 269; and Leiter, Legal Realismand Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 280.

    14. Mart in P. Golding, Realism and Functionalism in the Legal Thought of Felix S. Cohen ,66 C ORNELL L. R EV . 1032, 1032-33 (1981). Cohen had a Ph.D. in philosophy from H arvard, inaddition to having a law degree from Columbia. Dalia Tsuk, The New Deal Origins of

    American Legal Pluralism , 29 F LA . S T . U. L. R EV . 189, 209 (2001).15 . See Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 290-93.

    16. H ART , supra note 3, at 136.17 . Id . Compare R ONALD D WORKIN , T AKING R IGHTS S ERIOUSLY 15 (1977):

    In [the realists] view the concepts of legal obligation and the law are myths,invented and sustained by lawyers for a dismal mix of conscious andsubconscious motives. The puzzles we find in these concepts are merelysymptoms that they are myths. They are unsolvable because unreal, and our

    number of weaknesses, inconsistencies, and oddities will remain.But the theory is not the absurdity that the philosophical commu-nity has made it out to be.

    Admittedly, it is dangerous to speak of a theory held by therealists as a group, even when the group is limited to those mostcommonly agreed to be realistsKarl Llewellyn, Jerome Frank,Walter Wheeler Cook, Felix Cohen, Hessel Yntema, HermanOliphant, Max Radin, Leon Green, and Joseph Hutcheson. It is 13

    still more dangerous when the theory is in the philosophy of law,given that the realistsCohen excepted did not have significant14

    training in philosophy. Nevertheless, realism remains a subject of 15

    more than historical interest precisely because unifying them es canbe found in the realists writings. And some of the most importantthemes are philosophical. The fact that most of the realists lackedphilosophical training does not mean they lacked philosophicalopinions. All it means is that these opinions were expressedimperfectly in their works, making some philosophical reconstruc-tion necessary.

    As a part of this philosophical reconstruction, I will argue that therealists actually held a number of theories of law tha t differ in theirdegree of plau sibility. Both the realists and their critics tend to treatthese theories as if they were equivalent. Hart, for example,describes the realists theory of law as the view that talk of rules is

    a myth , cloaking the truth that law consists simply of the decisionsof courts and the prediction of them. But there are at least two16

    theories of law in this description. Th e first is the idea that talk of rules is a myth. Surprisingly, the realists rejection of legal rules17

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    6/86

    1920 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    concern with them is just one feature of our enslavement. We would do betterto flush away the puzzles and the concepts altogether, and pursue our importantsocial objectives without this excess baggage.

    18. Oliver Wendell Holmes, The Path of the Law , 10 H ARV . L. R EV . 457, 461 (1897).Holmess formulation was followed by many realists. See, e.g. , W ALTER W HEELER C OOK , T HEL OGICAL AND L EGAL B ASES OF THE C ONFLICT OF L AWS 8, 29-30 (1942) [hereinafter C OOK ,

    L OGICAL AND L EGAL B ASES ]; Felix S. Cohen, Transcendental Nonsense and the Functional Approach , 35 C OLUM . L. R EV . 809, 828-29 (1935); Walter Wheeler Cook, Substance andProcedure in the Conflict of Laws , 42 Y ALE L.J. 333, 347-48 (1933) [hereinafter Cook,Substance and Procedure ]; Max Radin, Permanent Problems of the Law , 15 C ORNELL L.Q.1, 3 (1929).

    19. H ART , supra note 3, at 136.

    is their most defensib le theory of law, and it will be the focus of this Article. Properly understood, howev er, it does not deny that statutesand the like can be law; nor does it deny that these laws can guidea judges decision making when the judges attitudes recommendconformity w ith the law. Instead, the theory rejects the ability of thelaw to provide reasons for conformity with what the law recom-men ds that exist indepen dently of the judges attitudes. The realistsrejection of legal rules was an attack on the idea of politicalobligation and the duty to obey the law. A statute can be the lawwithout being a lega l rule in the relevant sense, for its status as lawmay not provide a rebellious judge with any reason to adjudicate as

    the statute instructs.But the realists were also comm itted to a less plausible theory of

    lawthe famous prediction theory that they borrowed fromHolmes. This theory is captured by the second part of Harts18

    description, that law consists simply of the decisions of courts andthe prediction of them, and it does indeed cast doubt on the idea19

    that statutes and the like can be law. P roperly understood, however,even this theory (or rather theories, for the prediction theory tooktwo forms in the realists writings) was not quite as crazy as thephilosophers make it out to be. What is more important, eventhough the prediction theories ultimately fail, they are at leastunderstandable when seen in the light of the realists rejection of

    legal rules. The realists thoughtwrongly but reasonablythatthese theories followed from the laws inability to provide reasonsfor obedience.

    I will begin in Part I by clarifying the various theories of law thatI will attribute to the realists, in addition to criticizing Leitersargument that they did not mean to offer a novel theory of law at

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    7/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1921

    20. Scott Shapiro describes this guiding function as epistemic guidance. Scott J. Shapiro,Law, Morality, and the Guidance of Conduct , 6 L EGAL T HEORY 127, 146 (2000) (Central to

    all. In Part II, I will set the stage for m y defens e of the realists firsttheory of law their rejection of legal rulesb y briefly outlining theproblems that Hart and h is followers have encountered arguing forthe normativity of law. Hart and the realists began from a verysimilar premisethat the law is fundam entally a matter of social

    facts . But Hart believed that this does not preclude the lawscapacity to provide reasons for action. Harts position has beenpersuasively criticized, howeverm ost notably by Ron ald Dworkin.In Parts III and IV, I will describe the two arguments that led therealists to think that the law is non-norm ative, the second of whichhas strong similarities to Dworkins critique of Hart. I will end the

    Article, in Part V, with a discussion of wh y the realists were inclinedtoward prediction theories of law. Although I agree with thephilosophers that the theories should be rejected, when seen in thelight of the realists rejection of legal rules they are more plausiblethan has been assumed.

    I. T HE R EALISTS T HEORIES OF L AW

    What Are Legal Rules? A.

    It is important to identify the type of legal rules that the realistsrejected, for there are alternative conceptions of legal rules in w hich

    their existence could not seriously be denied. Assume that I issuethe following command: Every payday, cash your paycheck and givethe money to m e. My comm and undoubtedly is (or expresses) a rulein some sense. You can a ct or fail to act in accordance with w hat mycommand instructs you to do. If you want to obey me for example,because you love me, or fear the sanctions I might impose fordisobediencemy command will guide your behavior. It has thisguiding power by virtue of its propositional content, the meaningthe command expresses. Conversely, the command Every toves,cash your wabe and give the morogoves to m e is not a rule in thissense, because it lacks sufficient propositional content. Someonewho wants to abide by this command will have no idea how toregulate her behavior to do so. 20

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    8/86

    1922 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    epistemic guidance is the fact that the rule was the source of information regarding whatcounts as conformity, not necessarily the source of motivation for conformity.).

    21 . See H.L.A. H ART , E SSAYS ON B ENTHAM 243 (1982); Jules L. Coleman & Brian Leiter,Legal Positivism , in A C OMPANION TO P HILOSOPHY OF L AW AND L EGAL T HEORY 241, 241-42(Dennis Patterson ed., 1996).

    22. On the distinction between prima facie and overriding duties, see W.D. R OSS , T HER IGHT AND THE G OOD (1930) (discussing prima facie moral obligations); M.B.E. Smith, IsThere a Prima Facie Obligation to Obey the Law? , 82 Y ALE L.J. 950, 951-52 (1973).

    The realists did not reject legal rules in the propositional sense of the term. Though they thought substantial indeterminacy infectsthe law (and not merely at the margins as Hart claimed), theyadmitted that the law can meaningfully instruct people to act incertain ways rather than others to some extent , and for this reasoncan gu ide the behavior of those who seek to obey its commands. If I want to abide by a statute that says that the speed limit is 55m.p.h., I know what to do (nam ely, drive 55 m.p.h. or less). By thesame token, a judge wh o wants to adjudicate in accordance with thestatute knows what to do (namely, sanction only those who drivefaster than 55 m.p.h.).

    There is another sense of rule, however, in which the existenceof legal rules can be questioned. This is the idea of a rule assomething providing a reason for action . If one violates a rule in21

    this sense, one has done something wrong , something one ought nothave done. My command is not a rule in this sense, for there isnothing about the fact that I command you to do something thatgives you a reason to do w hat I saynothing that justifies or makesappropriate your compliance with my command. I will argue thatthe realists rejected legal rules in this reason-for-action sense.

    One important question, which I w ill leave largely unanswered,is whether the reasons for action that legal rules would provide if they existed must be overriding reasons (that is, reasons that trum p

    all other reasons for action, including all moral reasons) or whethe rthey may be prima facie reasons (that is, reasons that can beoverridden by sufficiently weighty countervailing reasons). An 22

    example of a prima facie reason for action is the moral reason thatI have to keep my prom ises. If I promise to loan you an axe, I havea prima facie moral reason to keep my promise in the sense that,absent any countervailing considerations, I ought to loan you myaxe. Assume, however, that you recently killed fourteen people w ithan axe. Yo u lost it soon after the murders, but you are sure to start

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    9/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1923

    23 . See, e.g. , H ART , supra note 21, at 253-56; J OSEPH R AZ , T HE A UTHORITY OF L AW : E SSAYSON L AW AND M ORALITY 29-31 (1979). For a nuan ced view, see K ENT G REENAWALT , C ONFLICTSOF L AW AND M ORALITY 6-24 (1989).

    24 . See R AZ , supra note 23, at 233-34; Smith, supra note 22, at 951.

    again once you get your hands on another one. The moral reasonI have to protect the lives of innocents is now a countervailingconsideration that trumps my reason to keep my promise. There-fore, my reason to keep m y promise is only p rima facie, not overrid-ing.

    That legal rules, if they existed, wou ld provide overriding reasonsfor action is suggested by the laws apparent claim to ultimacy inthe practical reasoning of its subjects. Indeed, the law, it seems,does not merely claim to trump other reasons for action, but to

    preclude the consideration of these other reasons, in the sense thatthey should be removed from the subjects deliberation. On the 23

    other hand, that legal rules provide only prima facie reasons foraction is suggested by the fact that all other reasonseven thestrongest of moral reasons, such as the moral reason not to killinnocentsare probably only prima facie. It is unlikely that thereasons for action provided by the law would be overriding wheneven the moral duty not to kill innocents can be trumped (forexample, when killing an innocent would prevent the deaths of millions of people).

    If it is true that legal reason s for action are prima facie, then legalrules in the relevant sense could exist even though a considerationof all available reasons for action would show civil disobedience tobe permissible, indeed mandatory. The fact that one ought to

    disobey the law would simply mean that the balance of reasons,including moral reasons, was in favor of disobedience, no t that thelaw did not provide reasons for action at all.

    A num ber of further clarifications are in order. First, the fact thatone has a reason to do w hat the law says is not enough to show thatlegal rules exist. Consider a statute prohibiting the killing of innocents. Altho ugh I have rea sons not to kill innocents, the statutemight not contribute to those reasons, for it may be that I wouldhave had exactly the same reasons (namely, moral reasons) had thestatute not been law. For legal rules to exist, it must be the case24

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    10/86

    1924 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    25 . See J OSEPH R AZ , T HE M ORALITY OF F REEDOM 35-37 (1986).26 . See William A. Edmundson, State of the Art: The Duty to Obey the Law , 10 L EGAL

    T HEORY 215, 215-16 (2004); Smith, supra note 22, at 951-52.

    that there are reasons to do what the law says because the law saysso. 25

    Second, and most important, the relevant reasons for actionmust be objective . One has a subjective reason to act if the action isrecommended by ones de facto attitudes. The simplest example of a subjective reason for action is the reason I have to do what I wantto do. I have a subjective reason to sing Le avin on a Jet Plane, forexample, if I want to sing Leavin on a Jet Plane. A slightly morecomplicated example of a subjective reason for action is the reasonI have to do som ething th at I do not directly want to do, but that Ibelieve is instrumental to something that I directly want. If I want

    to drive a screw into a piece of wood, and believe that using aPhillips-he ad screwdriver is the action that will lead this want to besatisfied, then I have a subjective reason to use a Phillips-headscrewdriver.

    But subjective reasons for action need not depend only upon brutedesires. More complex attitudesincluding moral attitudescangenerate such reasons as well. For exam ple, if I (wrongly) think thatletting children drown is morally important, I would have asubjective reason not to save a drowning child.

    To say that the reasons for action generated by legal rules areobjective is to say that they exist independently of the attitudes of the person to whom they apply. In being objective, legal reasons for

    action look very much like moral reasons for action. I have a moralreason to keep my promises even if keeping my prom ises is not thebest course of action in light of my attitudes. I do not escape themoral obligation to keep my promises simply because I really wantto break my promises or because I think (wrongly) that breakingpromises is morally important. Analogously, if legal reasons foraction exist, citizens are not released from them simply becausetheir attitudes recommend disobedience.

    Third, if legal rules exist, then everyone to whom a valid lawapplies has a reason for compliance with its demands. The second26

    and the third requirements are related because the objectivity of legal reasons for action appears to be the only explanation of why

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    11/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1925

    27 . See Coleman & Leiter, supra note 21, at 245.

    these reasons would exist for everyone to whom a valid law applies. Although there are subjective reasons for most people to obey manylaws, it is not likely that everyone has a subjective reason to obeyevery valid law.

    Conside r the fact that the law is often backed up by sa nctions. If,like most people, I do not want to lose my property or freedom, thenthese sanctions will give me a subjective reason to do what the lawsays. But sanctions cannot provide everyone with subjective reasonsto obey all valid laws, for it is easy to imagine a legal systemourown, for examplein which some v alid laws are not enforced. 27

    The occasional coordinating function of the law also provides

    subjective reasons for obedience. The fact that the law of Britainsays people should drive on the left gives me a powerful subjectivereason to drive on the left while in Britain, becau se, given that otherpeople are obeying the law, doing the same is the best way of satisfying my desire to avoid accidents. But legal systems can beimaginedonce again, our own system is an example in which notall law s bring with them the benefits of coordination. It is the lawthat one must pay to use the subway, but the fact that other peoplepay does not necessarily make it in ones interest to follow along.Indeed, as far as many peoples attitudes are concerned, the bestcourse of action may be to encourage others to pay and not to payoneself.

    Of course, one can come up with other explanations for whyobedience to law is recommended by the attitudes of those subjectto its comm ands. But it is not likely that these explanations couldexplain why all citizens, in every legal system, have a subjectivereason to obey all the valid laws of the system . It is alway s possibleto imagine people w hose attitudes do not recommen d conformity tovalid law. If there are such things a s legal reasons for action, theyare surely objectivereasons for conformity to law that bindwhatever ones attitudes.

    Therefore, to say that the realists denied the existence of legalrules is to attribute to them the following position: The fact thatsomething is valid law does not give those to whom the law appliesan objective reason for obedience. In this sense, the realists rule-skepticism is similar to philosophical anarchism . The philosophical

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    12/86

    1926 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    28 . See Edmundson, supra note 26, at 218-19; see also R AZ , supra note 23, at 233-34; A.J OHN S IMMONS , M ORAL P RINCIPLES AND P OLITICAL O BLIGATIONS (1979); A. J OHN S IMMONS , O NTHE E DGE OF A NARCHY : L OCKE , C ONSENT , AND THE L IMITS OF S OCIETY (1993); A. JohnSimmons, Philosophical Anarchism , in F OR AND A GAINST THE S TATE : N EW P HILOSOPHICALR EADINGS 19 (John T. Sanders & Jan Narveson eds., 1996) [hereinafter Simmons,

    Philosophical Anarchism ]; Smith, supra note 22. Some have argued, more strongly, that anobligation to obey the law is incompatible with autonom y. Because the law appears to displaceother reasons for action (even moral reasons) in deliberation, obedience to law seems torequire insensitivity to ones own moral views. See, e.g. , R OBERT P AUL W OLFF , I N D EFENSE OF

    A NARCHISM 14 (1970) ([The philosophical ana rchist] may do what [the law] tells him, but notbecause he has been told to do it.). There is, however, a long philosophical tradition of attempting to show how legitimate authority can be possible. R AZ , supra note 23, at 3-27;Heidi M. Hurd, Challenging Authority , 100 Y ALE L.J. 1611 (1991). Joseph Raz has argued forthe possibility that an agent may be more likely to act on the moral reasons tha t apply to himby following the authority than by trying to act on the balance of reasons him self. R AZ , supra

    note 25, at 53-57. But most who offer such justificationsincluding Razseek only to showth e possibility of legitimate authority. They do not argue that it exists with respect to everyvalid law in every legal system. Although Raz argues that the law always claims authority,R AZ , supra note 23, at 29-30, he does not argue that it always has it. R AZ , supra note 25, at80. He argues tha t there is no duty, even a prima facie duty, to obey the law . R AZ , supra note23, at 233-49.

    anarchist denies that valid law always gives those to whom itapplies a moral reason (even a prima facie moral reason) forcompliance. But legal realism goes beyond philosophical anarchism28

    as it is usually understood. The philosophical anarchist can acceptthat the law provide s objective reasons for action that are no t moral.He is concerned solely with rejecting the natural law position, inwhich legal obligation is a species of moral obligation. As we shallsee, although H.L.A. Hart rejected natural law theory, he appearsto have accepted that objective legal obligationsand so legalrulesexist. The realists, in contrast, rejected the idea of legalobligation entirely.

    B. What Is the Prediction Theory of Law?

    So far, I have only described w hat it mean s to reject legal rules inthe relevant sense. I will offer my evidence that the realists in factheld this position in Parts III and IV, where I discuss the realiststwo arguments that the social facts concerning official practices onthe basis of which something is law do not give citizensand inparticular judges adjudicating casesobjective reasons for obedi-ence.

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    13/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1927

    29. For an example of the criticism at the time the realists were writing, see JohnDickinson, Legal Rules: Their Function in the Process of Decision , 79 U. P A . L. R EV . 833, 844(1931) (The judge will find himself confronted with one or more legal rules applicable, orconceivably applicable, to the case before him. For him these rules cannot be conceived asmere rules of prediction. He is not interested in predicting what he himself is about to do.).

    Se e also M.H. Fisch, Justice Holmes, the Prediction Theory of Law, and Pragmatism , 39 J.P HIL . 85, 87 (1942); Hermann Kantorowicz, Some Rationalism About Realism , 43 Y ALE L.J.1240, 1250 (1934).

    30. Leiter may be wrong not merely in his reading of the prediction theory, but also in hisreading of Hart, for it is not clear that this criticism ca n be found in Harts discussion of therealists.

    In light of these arguments, the realists rejection of legal rulesemerges as a theory of law a generally applicable philosophicalaccount of the law. But it is not a comprehensive the ory, for asidefrom telling us that the law is non-normative, it does not give us anyidea which items should be identified as law. For example, it isentirely compatible with the realists rejection of legal rules thatstatutes are law, provided that their status as law does not give onean objective reason for compliance with their demands.

    The realists prediction theory of law, in contrast, is an account of the items that should be identified as law. As we shall see, however,the prediction theory (in both its forms) is inadequa tefor it, quite

    simply, identifies the wrong set of items as law. It often fails toidentify constitutions, statutes and the like as law, even thoughthese are clearly items that fall under our concept of law. As aconsequence, the prediction theory cannot make sense of some

    judicial errorsfor example, a decision by a court that is contraryto a valid statute.

    But even if we must reject the prediction theory in the end, it isimportant to be fair to the realists when characterizing the itemsthat the theory identifies as law. It is comm onboth now and at thetime that the realists were active for critics to misread the29

    realists as arguing that the law for a judge deciding a case is aprediction of how that judge would decide. In order to decide in

    accordance with the law, a judge would have to try to abide bypredictions of her decision. Since this is bizarre, the critics concludethat the prediction theory is bizarre as well. Brian L eiter offers sucha criticism of the prediction theory, attributing it to H.L.A. Hart: 30

    [A]ccording to the [prediction theory], a judge who sets out todiscover the law on some issue upon which she must render a

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    14/86

    1928 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    31 . Le it er, supra note 2, at 270; see also R ICHARD P OSNER , T HE P ROBLEMS OFJ URISPRUDENCE 224 (1990) (stating that the argum ent that the prediction theory fails becausea judge cannot predict his own beh avior is formidable, but only with res pect to judges of the highest court of the jurisdiction); Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note3, at 290 (offering an example of the prediction theorys silly implications); David Luban,The Bad Man a nd the Good Lawyer: A Centennial Essay on Holmess The Path of the Law, 72N.Y.U. L. R EV . 1547, 1577-78 (1997) (If law is prophecies of what the courts will do, thencourt-made law cons ists of self-fulfilling prophecies.).

    32 . See R OBERT S AMUEL S UMMERS , I NSTRUMENTALISM AND A MERICAN L EGAL T HEORY 12 2(1982).

    33. J EROME F RANK , L AW AND THE M ODERN M IND 128 (1930).34. K ARL N. L LEWELLYN , T HE B RAMBLE B USH 12 (1960). It should be kept in mind,

    however, that in the foreword to the second edition Llewellyn refers to this passage asunhappy words and plainly at best a very partial statement of the whole truth. Id . at 9.

    35. F RANK , supra note 33, at 125.3 6. R ad in , supra note 18, at 10.

    decision is really just trying to discover what she will do, sincethe law is equivalent to a prediction of what she w ill do! These,and other m anifestly silly implications of the [prediction theory],convinced mo st Anglo-American legal philosophers that Realismwas best forgotten. 31

    Leiters argument is mistaken, however, for the realists did notthink that the applicable law for a judge deciding a case is aprediction of how that judge will decide. The law , they argued, is the

    judges decision itself. 32

    The law con sists of decisions , not of rules. If so, then when-ever a judge decides a case he is making law . 33

    What officials do about disputes is, to my mind, the lawitself .34

    Law is mad e up not of rules for decision laid down by the courtsbut of the decisions themselves. 35

    [L]aw arises when som e one is asked to determine the lawful-nessthat is the rightnessof an event, necessarily a pastevent. 36

    Indeed, the realists position is better described as the decisiontheory of law. Predictions are relevant, not for judges, but forprivate citizensespecially litigants. Since the law is what a judge

    decides, we must predict how a judge will decide to determine w hatthe law is. Predictions are attemp ts to discover the law, they are notthemselves law:

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    15/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1929

    37. F RANK , supra note 33, at 46.3 8. C oh en , supra note 18, at 840.39. F ELIX S. C OHEN , E THICAL S YSTEMS AND L EGAL I DEALS 13 n.16 (1933).

    40 . See H ART , supra note 3, at 105; H.L.A. Hart, Scandinavian Realism , 1959 C AMBRIDGEL.J. 233, 237.

    41 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 290; see also B ENDITT ,supra note 3, at 86-88; D WORKIN , supra note 3, at 36-37 ([R]ealism remains deeplyimplausible as a semantic theory [of the meaning of the word law]. For it is hardlycontradictoryindeed it is commonfor lawyers to predict that judges will make a mistake

    For any particular lay person, the law, with respect to anyparticular set of facts, is a decision of a court with respect tothose facts so far as that decision affects that pa rticular person.Until a court has passed on those facts no law on that sub ject isyet in existence. Prior to such a decision, the only law availableis the opinion of lawyers as to the law relating to that personand to those facts. Such opinion is not actually law but only aguess as to what a court will decide. 37

    Because whatever she decides will be the law, a judge, unlike aprivate citizen, is unconcerned about predictions of her behavior.

    She is concerned solely with what the law should be. The mistakein Leiters argume nt is his assumption that it would be possible fora judge to discover the law at all if the decision theory were true.Since whatever a judge decides is law, there is simply no preexistinglaw to discover. This w as precisely the realists response to Leitersargument: When a judge puts this question [what is the law ?], inthe course of writing his opinion, he is not attempting to predict hisown behavior. He is in effect raising the question, in an obscureway, of whe ther or not liability should be attached to certain acts. 38

    Leiters argume nt, Cohen claimed, wrongly assume[s] that a judgesduty is to find the law rather than to mould it, an assumption whichno realist makes. 39

    But the realists defense of the decision theory is short-lived, foreven properly understood it is vulnerable to a withering objection,which also can b e found in Leiters discussion of the realists, as wellas Harts. Precisely because there is no law limiting a judges40

    decision, the theory does violence to the notion that courts decidecases in a way that is constrained by the law. As Leiter puts it, thetheory makes it impossible to articulate the simple idea that thelaw is one thing, and a particular courts decision another. Judges 41

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    16/86

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    17/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1931

    45. H ART , supra note 3, at 136; see also Kantorowicz, supra note 29, at 1246 (arguing thatcourts can be identified only through rules); Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supranote 3, at 289 n.40 (accepting Harts argument).

    rules at all. This is so because ... the existence of a court entailsthe existence of secondary rules conferring jurisdiction on achanging su ccession of individuals and so making their decisionsauthoritative.... There would be nothing to distinguish thedecision of a private person from that of a court. 45

    Without assuming that a non-decision like the United StatesConstitution is law, the realists would not b e able to tell that ninepeople at 1 F irst Street N.E. in Washington D.C., rather than ninepeople stuck on a freeway in Los Angeles, are Justices of theSupreme Court.

    Hart appears to think this argument undermines not only thedecision theory, but also the realists rejection of legal rules. Therealists reliance on the Constitution when identifying courts, hesuggests, commits them to the Constitutions status as a legal rulein the reason-for-action sense. But this is a mistake. Even if therealists must admit that the Constitution should be called law,they can still reject the idea that the Constitutions status as lawgives peopleincluding judgesobjective reasons for compliancewith its demands. To be sure, if a judge decides a case in a mannerthat is contrary to the Constitution she may hav e created a decisionthat is not law. But it does not follow that she has an objectivereason to adjudicate in accordance with the Constitution, for she

    may have no objective reason to prefer the creation of law over non-law. As an analogy, imagine some people are playing a game called

    torture-the-kitten. The participants in the game have agreed tofollow the rule (in the propositional sense) that a player musttorture a kitten when he ha s scored a point. This is as much a validrule in the game as the Constitution is a valid rule in our legalsystem. But the fact that it is a valid rule in the game does notmean that participants have objective reasons to torture kittensafter scoring a point. One is still free to argue that they have noobjective reasons, not even prima facie reason s, to do what that ruletells them to do. By the same token, even if the realist must accept

    that the Constitution is law, he can still maintain that its status

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    18/86

    1932 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    46 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 281; see also Brian Leiter, American Legal Realism , in T HE B LACKWELL G UIDE TO THE P HILOSOPHY OF L AW AND L EGALT HEORY 50, 52-53 (Martin P. Golding & William A. Edmundson eds., 2005) [hereinafterLeiter, American Legal Realism ].

    47 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 292.

    as law fails to give judges objective reasons for adjudicating inaccordance with its instructions.

    Leiter, like Hart, criticizes the decision theory on the groundsthat the realists were tacitly committed to non-decisions beinglaw. He argues that the realists would be unable to articulatetheir theory of adjudicationthat is, their view that judges reactprimarily to the underlying facts of the case, rather than toapplicable legal rules and reasons if the decision theory were46

    true:

    The class of legal reasons is the class of reasons that mayproperly justify a legal conclusion (and thus compel it insofaras legal actors are responsive to valid legal reasons). So, forexample, appeal to a statutory provision or valid precedent areparts of the class of legal reasons, wh ile appeal to the authorityof Platos Republic is not: a judge is not obliged to decide one wayrather than another because Plato says so. Any argument forindeterminacy, then, presupposes some view about the bound-aries of the class of legal reasons. When Oliphant argues, forexample, that the promise-not-to-compete cases are decided notby reference to law but by reference to uncodified normsprevalent in the commer cial culture in which the disputes arose,this only shows that the law is indeterm inate on the assumptionthat the normative reasons the courts are actually relying upon

    are not themselves legal reasons.47

    Leiter is undo ubtedly righ t that it is inconsistent for the realiststo say, on the one hand, that the law consists only of decisions and,on the other hand, that judges arriving at these decisions areinsensitive to law. To the extent that they thought that judgesdecisions are insensitive to law, they presupposed a stand ard theoryof law in which non-decisions (e.g. statutes) can be law. But Leiter,like Hart, suggests that the realists were committed not m erely tonon-decisions being law, but also to these non-decisions being legal

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    19/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1933

    48. At one point, Leiter appears to address this issue, albeit with respect to nonlegalreasons. He notes that the talk about reasons in his account of the realists theory of adjudication presupposes a residual norm ativity: [C]ausal explanation of decisions in termsof reasons (even nonlegal reasons) d oes require taking the normative force of the reasons quareasons seriously. Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 285. But hemakes it clear that this residual normativity is the idea of human beings as rationalagentsthat is, as acting on the basis of their subjective reasons for action. To give upnormativity in this sense would mean adopting a purely behavioristic approach. And, as Leiterrightly notes, the realistsUnderhill Moore exceptedwere not strict behaviorists.

    Accepting this residual normativity is compatible with rejecting the more robustnormativity provided by objective reasons for action. The econom ist, for example, is committedto residual normativity insofar as he explains human action as a product of ends-meansreasoning. But he is not thereby committed to the more robust normativity of objectivereasons for action. He draws no normative distinction between som eone who saves a drowning

    child and someone who tortures kittens, provided that each acts in a manner calculated tosatisfy his weighted preferences. Se e , e.g. , R ICHARD A. P OSNER , E CONOMIC A NALYSIS OF L AW3 (3d ed. 1986); Herbert Hovenkam p, Rationality in Law & Economics , 60 G EO . W ASH . L. R EV .293, 293 (1992); Richard A. Posner, Rational Choice, Behavioral Economics, and the Law , 5 0S TAN . L. R EV . 1551, 1551 (1998). From the more robust norma tive perspective, in contrast, thefirst acts in a way that is sensitive to objective reasons for a ction, while the latter does not.

    rules , in the sense that they give judges objective reasons toadjudicate in accordance with them. T his does not follow.

    I say that Leiter suggests that the realists were committed tolegal rules in the reason-for-action sense, because he might under-stand statutes and the like to be legal rules and reasons only inthe sense that they provide subjective reasons for decisions. A statute penalizing driving in excess of 55 m.p.h. would be a legalrule or reason only in the sense that it was a reason to penalizedriving in excess of 55 m.p.h. for those judges with attitudesrecommending adjudication in conformity with the law. 48

    If Leiter does understand legal rules objectively, however, his

    argument fails. The realists theory of adjudication gives us noreason to think they believed in such legal rules. Although itcommitted them to a standard theory of law under which statutesand the like are law, they could still maintain that the fact that astatute is valid law does not give judges an objective reason toadjudicate as the statute instructs.

    Although the decision theory of law is prevalent in the realistswritings, one can also find a prediction theory of sorts. But this isnot the view that the law for a judge deciding a case is a predictionof how that judge would decide. It is instead the view that the lawis a prediction of how judges and other officials in a jurisdiction

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    20/86

    1934 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    49. Walter Wheeler Cook, The Logical and Legal Bases of the Conflict of Laws , 33 Y ALEL.J. 457, 476 (1924) [hereinafter Cook, Conflict of Laws ]. Although Cook objected to beinglableled a realist, Walter Wheeler Cook, An Unpublished Chapter of the Logical and Legal

    Bases of the Conflict of Laws , 37 I LL . L. R EV . 418, 423 (1943), the non-normative approach to

    the law that he employed is a cornerstone of realist jurisprudence. Se e K ALMAN , supra note1, at 3-44. Cook has been included among the legal realists for just this reason. See, e.g. , id .at 7.

    50. C OOK , L OGICAL AND L EGAL B ASES , supra note 18, at 33.51 . Id . at 29.52 . Id . at 31 n.57.

    would generally decide. According to Walter Wheeler Cook, forexample, a statement that a certain rule of law is the law of England is m erely a more or less convenient shorthand way of saying that, on the basis of certain observations of past phenomena,we predict certain future behavior of the appropriate Englishofficials. Assertions that legal rights exist are nothing more than49

    a conventiona l way of describing past and predicting future behaviorof human beingsjudges and other officials. Such statements are50

    true if they accurately ... describe the past behavior and predict thefuture behavior of societal agents. 51

    According to this prediction theory, a judges decision would no t

    be law simply because it was made, nor would it be law by virtue of its conformity with predictions of how that particular judge w oulddecide the case. It would be law only if it was in conformity withpredictions of how judges would generally decide cases in that

    jurisdiction. An unpreced ented decision could be law, therefore, onlyif its issuance led us to believe that other judges in the jurisdictionwould decide similarly in the future. As Cook put it, a decisionmakes law only if it has given us new data upon the basis of whichwe believ e that we are able to predict action in another case like thecase just decided. Accordingly, if a renegade judge decided a case52

    in accordance with Platos Republic , her decision would not be thelaw, because the Republic would still not be usefu l for predicting the

    future decisions of officials in the jurisdiction.Not only are some decisions not law under this form of the

    prediction theory, some non-decisions (e.g. the Constitution) arelaw. A judge deciding a case w ould be ab le to call the Constitutionlaw in the sense that she could predict that most judges wouldenforce it. Nevertheless, it is unlikely that the prediction theorywould identify exactly the same items as law as a standard theory

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    21/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1935

    53 . See infra note 202.54. H ART , supra note 3, at 137-38.

    of law. After all, if the realists theory of adjudication is correct,much that we would normally call law is useless in predicting

    judicial behavior. According to the prediction theory, therefore, itwould not be law. By the sam e token, some items that we would notnormally call law could be useful for predicting judicial behaviorand so would be law under the prediction theory. If, as KarlLlewellyn argued, judicial belief in an implicit obligation of goodfaith in contractual dealing drove contract decisions in a predictablefashion even before this obligation was included within Article 2 of the UCC, the obligation of good faith was the law according to theprediction theory even before it was so included. 53

    The truth is, however, that Harts primary criticism of theprediction theory is not that it picks out the wrong items as law.Even if the prediction theory identified precisely the same itemsthat would be identified in a standard theory, the prediction theorywould fail because it would be unable to explain the laws capacityto give reasons for action:

    [I]t cannot be doubted that at any rate in relation to somespheres of conduct in a m odern state individuals do exhibit thewhole range of conduct and attitudes which we hav e called theinternal point of view. Laws function in their lives not merely ashabits or the basis for predicting the decisions of courts or theactions of other officials, but as accepted legal standards of behaviour. That is, they not only do with tolerable regularitywhat the law requires of them, but they look upon it as a legalstandard of conduct, refer to it in criticizing others, or in

    justifying demands, and in admitting criticism and demandsmade by others. 54

    If all it meant to say that the Con stitution is law were that judgesin a jurisdiction predictably decide in accordance with the Constitu-tion, a judge who recognized that the Constitution was law w ouldhave no reason to decide in accordance with the Constitutionherself.

    The fundam ental problem with the prediction theory, accordingto Hart, is that it forces us to reject legal rules in the reason-for-

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    22/86

    1936 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    55 . See Brian Leiter, Legal Realism , in A C OMPANION TO P HILOSOPHY OF L AW AND L EGALT HEORY 261, 263 (Dennis Patterson ed., 1996); Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism ,supra note 3, at 291-92.

    56 . Le it er, supra note 55, at 263.

    action sense. It treats a statement about the law as a statementabout a non -normativ e factthat a certain decision will, in fact, bearrived atnot the type of normative fact that could justify or givea reason for a citizens or judges conformity to law.

    C. Did the Realists Have a Novel Theory of Law at All?

    I have so far described three theories of law advocated by therealists. The first, and most plausible, is their rejection of legalrules that is, their argument that the law fails to provide objectivereasons for compliance with its demands. The second, and least

    plausible, is the decision theory of law , according to which only theconcrete decisions of courts are law. The third is the predictiontheory of law , in which statements about the law are equivalent topredictions of the decisions of courts within a jurisdiction.

    As we have seen, both Hart and Leiter argue that the realistsimplicitly accepted a standard theory of law (in which statutes, forexam ple, can be law) that is at odds with the decision and pred ictiontheories. Although Hart uses this inconsistency to prove that thetheories are incoherent, Leiter uses it to question whether therealists offered these theoriesor indeed any novel theory of lawat all. The realists spoke of the law in terms of concretedecisions and predictions of decisions, Leiter argues, only because

    they were concerned with the practical meaning of the law tolawyers, whose job it is to protect their clients from adverse

    judgments. They were not aiming for a generally applicable55

    analysis of the concept of law. 56

    But the evidence Leiter offers for his reading is weak . First of all,he concentrates on only two figuresJustice Holmes, w ho predatedthe legal realist movement, and Jerome Frank without addressingthe many expressions of novel theories of law, quoted earlier, fromrealists such as C ohen and Cook. Furthermore, it is only throughselective quotation that Leiter is able to generate evidence con-cerning Holmes and Frank. Leiter argues, for example, that theprediction theory of law that Holmes offers in the The Path of the

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    23/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1937

    57. I t appears that in the The Path of the Law , Holmes, like Cook, offers the predictiontheory of law, not the decision theory. For example, Holmes does not deny that statutes arelawbut he understands them as law only insofar as they allow us to predict how judges ina jurisdiction in general decide cases. Se e Holmes, supra note 18, at 457 (stating that statutes

    are scattered prophecies of the past up on the cases in which the axe will fall).58 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 291 (quoting Holmes,

    supra note 18, at 457).5 9. H ol m es , supra note 18, at 457.60 . Id . at 459-61; see also William Twining, Other Peoples Power: The Bad Man and

    English Positivism, 1897-1997 , 63 B ROOK . L. R EV . 189, 204-06 (1997) (noting bad man

    La w should not be taken as generally applicable, because Holmes57

    begins the essay by emphasizing that he is talking about themeaning of law to lawyers who will appear before judges, or ...advise people in such a way as to keep them out of court. But the 58

    following is what Holmes actually says in the beginning of thatessay: When we study law we are not studying a m ystery but a wellknown profession. We are studying what we shall want in order toappear before judges, or to advise peop le in such a w ay as to keepthem out of court. 59

    Holmes does not suggest that he is setting aside a generalconception of law in favor of the more narrow perspective of a

    lawyer advising h is client. He talks about the lawyers perspectivebecause he believ es it is relevant to the law in general the materialstudied by his audience.

    Holmes looks at the law from the perspective of the lawyeradvising his client for the same reason he looks at it from theperspective of the bad m an. Freed of any feelings of obligation tothe law, these people see the law for what it really is:

    If you want to know the law an d nothing else, you must look atit as a bad man, who cares only for the material consequenceswhich such know ledge enables him to predict, not as a good one,who finds his reasons for conduct, whether inside the law oroutside of it, in the vaguer sanctions of conscience.... Take thefundam ental question, What constitutes the law? ... [I]f we takethe view of our friend the b ad man w e shall find that he does notcare two straws for the axioms or deductions, but that he doeswant to know what the Massachusetts or English courts arelikely to do in fact. I am much of his mind. The prophecies of what the courts will do in fact, and nothing more pretentious,are what I mean by the law. 60

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    24/86

    1938 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    emphasizes the separability thesis); William Twining, The Bad Man Revisited , 58 C ORNELLL. R EV . 275, 282 (1973).

    6 1. H ol m es , supra note 18, at 458.62 . Le it er, Legal Realism and Legal Positivism , supra note 3, at 291 (quoting F RANK ,

    supra note 33, at 47 n.*).63. F RANK , supra note 33, at 47 n.*.

    For Holmes, as for the realists, the prediction theory of law wasgenerally applicable. And, like the realists, Holmes was inclinedtoward this theory because he thought it followed once one lookedat the law non -normativelythat is, once one rejected the idea of legal obligation.

    Holmes presents the prediction theory as a general theory of lawelsewhere in the essay as well, arguing, for example, that [t]heprimary rights and duties with which jurisprudence busies itself again are nothing but prophecies. Jurisprudence busies itself with61

    the law in general, not merely the lawyers perspective on the law.Leiter pursues the same strategy with respect to Frank, arguing

    that the decision theory presented in Law and the Modern Mind isnot generally applicable, because Frank cautions the reader earlyon that he is primarily concerned with law as it affects the workof the practicing lawyer and the needs of the clients who retainhim. Had Frank not concentrated on this perspective, Leiter62

    sugges ts, he would have accepted that statutes and the like are law.Let us set aside the fact that this cautionary language is in a

    footnote almost fifty pages into the book. Only by ignoring the restof the footnote can Leiter m ake it appear as if Frank is not offeringa generally applicable theory of law. To be sure, Frank says thatreducing the law to the decisions of courts is admittedly artificialand that this artificiality has to do with his emphasis on the

    perspective of a lawyer. But the problem is not that his approachfails to treat statutes as law, but that empha sizing judicial behav iorignores the ways of a ll governmental officials and the reactionsof non-official persons to the ways of judges and other officials. A 63

    less distorting a pproach would not speak of statutes as the law, itwould speak of the law as reducible to the decisions of judicial andnon-judicial officials (and the reactions of private citizens to thosedecisions). Frank defends his focus on adjudication as excusable,

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    25/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1939

    64 . Id . For a similar criticism of Leiters reading of the realists, see M ICHAEL M OORE ,E DUCATING O NESELF IN P UBLIC 36-37 (2000).

    65. F RANK , supra note 33, at 127.66 . Id . at 128.

    however, because it roughly corresponds to the notion of thecontemporary layman when consulting his lawyer. 64

    Indeed, Frank makes it clear that the decision theory appliesbeyon d a lawyers perspective, for he describes it as appropriate for

    judges deciding cases as well:

    The business of the judges is to decide par ticular cases. They, orsome third person viewing their handiwork, may choose togeneralize from these decisions and describe the commonelements as rules. But those descriptions of alleged commonelements are, at best, some aid to lawyers in guessing orbringing about future jud icial conduct or some help to judges insettling other disputes. The rules will not directly decide anyother cases in any given way, nor authoritatively compel the

    judges to decide those other cases in any given way . Rules,whether stated by judges or others, whether in statutes,opinions or text-books by learned authors, are not the Law .... 65

    And so Frank con cludes, [t]he law, therefore, consists of decisions ,not of rules. If so, then when ever a judge decides a case he is mak ing law .66

    We must accept, even if Leiter cannot, that the realists meantwhat they repeatedly and un ambiguously said. If the realists are tobe defended, we must make sense of why they were inclined to the

    prediction and decision theories. A primary reason, I will argue, isthat they wrongly thought that these theories followed fromanother, far more defensib le positiontheir rejection of legal rules.

    II. H ART ON THE N ORMATIVITY OF L AW

    Before addressing the realists arguments a gainst legal rules, itis useful to look at how H.L.A. Hart dealt with the sam e problem.This is not merely because Harts arguments in favor of legalobligation ran into difficulties that put the realists non-normativeapproach in a sympathetic light. It is also because, aside from their

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    26/86

    1940 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    67 . See Kenneth Einar Himma, Substance and Method in Conceptual Jurisprudence andLegal Theory , 88 V A . L. R EV . 1119, 1152 (2002) (reviewing J ULES L. C OLEMAN , T HE P RACTICEOF P RINCIPLE : I N D EFENCE OF A P RAGMATIST A PPROACH TO L EGAL T HEORY 75-77 (2001)).

    68 . See H ART , supra note 3, at 110, 292-93; Jeffrey D. Goldsworthy, The Self-Destructionof Legal Positivism , 10 O XFORD J. L EGAL S TUD . 449, 452 (1990); Philip Soper, Legal Theory

    and the Obligation of a Judge: The Hart/Dworkin D ispute , 75 M ICH . L. R EV . 473, 512 (1977).69 . See Coleman & Leiter, supra note 21, at 241-42; Leiter, Legal Realism and Legal

    Positivism , supra note 3, at 286.70. J OHN A USTIN , T HE P ROVINCE OF J URISPRUDENCE D ETERMINED 193-94 (Dartmouth

    Publg 1998) (1832).71 . Id . at 13-14.

    differing views about the laws normativity, the realists theory of law was remarkably similar to Harts.

    A.H arts Theory of Law

    Hart, like most legal positivists, believed that the foundation for67

    a legal systemthe ultimate explanation of why something is avalid lawwas a set of social facts , in particular, the beliefs,attitudes and behavior of a population. This is an attractive notion,68

    not the least because revolutions, in which legal systems change ,consist of transformations in social facts of this sort. The British

    legal system was replaced by the American legal system in lateeighteenth century English-speaking North America, because of changes in the beliefs, attitudes and behavior of these English-speaking North Americans.

    Hart argued, however, that an adequate explanation of a legalsystem in terms of social facts must also explain the normativity of lawthat is, why it provides reasons for action. The failure to69

    explain the laws normativity is one of the primary reasons Hartrejected John Austins philosophy of law, despite the fact that

    Austin, like H art, explained the existence of a legal system in termsof social facts.

    According to Austin, a legal system exists whenever there is a

    sovereign , understood as a person (or group of people) whosecommands are habitually obeyed by the bulk of the population andwho habitually obeys no one else. All valid laws can ultimately be70

    traced back to the sovereigns command that is, an expression bythe sovereign of his desire that someone act or refrain from acting,combined with the threat of sanctions for noncompliance. 71

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    27/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1941

    72. H ART , supra note 3, at 58-60.

    73 . Id . at 82.74 . Id . at 55.75 . See Benjamin C. Zipursky, The Model of Social Facts , in H ART S P OSTSCRIPT 219, 227-

    28 (Jules Coleman ed., 2001). Although this content might be expressed linguistically (as isthe case in the Code of Hammurabi), Hart notes that this is, in fact, rare. H ART , supra note3, at 101.

    One reason Hart criticized Austins account has nothing to dowith the laws normativity. Hart argued that Austin was u nable toexplain the possibility that everyone in a legal system was legallyconstrained. How can there be laws governing the succession of sovereigns within a legal system, Hart asked, if all laws emanatefrom a sovereign? The very idea of legal succession of sovereignty72

    assumes that each sovereign is subject to an authorizing law h e didnot command.

    But Hart also objected to Austins view that the norm ativity of lawthat is, its binding or obligatory charactercould be explainedby sanctions for noncompliance. Simple obedience out of prudence,

    as is the case when someone gives over his m oney to the person whothreatens him with a gun, cannot explain the reasons for action thatthe law provides: [W]e would say that [this person], if he obeyed,was obliged to hand over his money. It is, however, equally certainthat we should misdescribe the situation if we said, on these facts,that [the person] had an obligation or a duty to hand over themoney. 73

    Likewise the Austinian conception of a habit of obedience cannotexplain legal obligation. A habit, or mere convergence of behavior,is not enough to constitute the existence of a rule requiring thatbehaviour .... For a rule to exist, there must be reasons for74

    compliance, and Austinian habits cannot explain why these reasons

    exist.Harts alternative foundation for a legal system is a rule of

    recognition that is, a secondary rule (or rule about rules) identify-ing valid laws within the system. As we have seen, however, theterm rule is ambiguous. Sometimes Hart speaks of the rule of recognition as a proposition specifying the criteria of legal validitywithin the legal system. Harts approach is doomed, however, if the75

    foundation of a legal system were a rule of recognition in thepropositional sense, for an infinite number of these rulesand so an

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    28/86

    1942 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    76. The existence of a rule of recognition in a legal system also requires that the primaryrules that are valid according to the rule of recognition are generallyalthough notnecessarily always obeyed by the population. H ART , supra note 3, at 116-17.

    77. One should not conclude from the fact that officials generate the practice thatestablishes the legal system that officials are sovereign within that system . For a discussionof this confusion, see Michael Steven Green, Legal Revolutions: Six Mistakes About

    Discontinuity in the Legal Order , 83 N.C. L. R EV . 331, 352-74 (2005).78. H ART , supra note 3, at 55.79 . Id .

    infinite number of legal systemsexist. Consider the followingsentence: Michael Greens word is law. This expresses thepropositional rule of recognition that all valid laws must be tracedback to my command. If the foundation of legal systems is proposi-tions, a legal system in which I am an absolute sovereign mustexist.

    The solution to this problem is that Hartadding a thirdmeaning to the word rule (beyond the propositional and thereason-for-action senses)also uses the term rule of recognitionto refer to the social fact that a certain rule of recognition (in thepropositional sense) is practiced by officials. The proposition is

    practiced in the sense that officials agree to enforce only whateversatisfies the criteria in the proposition. For example, the British76

    rule of recognition (in the social facts sense) is the p ractice of Britishofficials enforcing only whatever satisfies the criteria in the rule of recognition (in the propositional sense) that is expressed by thefollowing sentence: What the Q ueen-in-Parliament en acts is law.

    Rules of recognition explain why sovereignty can be limitedlegally. If officials identify as law a principle governing the succes-sion of sovereigns, then it is law, even though it is not itself thecommand of any sovereign. More important for our purposes, Hart77

    believed that the set of social facts that constitute a rule of recogni-tion, unlike those social facts to which Austin appea led, can explain

    the normativity of lawthat is, why the law consists of rules in thereason-for-action sense. The foundation of Harts argument is thata rule of recognition is a social rule. A social rule exists when, in78

    addition to convergence of behavior, deviations are generallyregarded as lapses or faults open to criticism, and threateneddeviations meet with pressure for conformity .... Not only is79

    deviation from a standard criticized, but the criticism is regarded aslegitimate, not m erely by those criticizing, but also by most of those

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    29/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1943

    80 . Id . at 56.81 . Id . at 57.82 . Id .83 . See Coleman & Leiter, supra note 21, at 247. To be sure, Hart insists that a legal

    system exists only when citizens in general abide by the norms that the rule of recognitionidentifies as law. Se e H ART , supra note 3, at 201. He admits that citizens, however, unlike

    officials, can lack the tendency to criticize one another for nonconform ity with the law. See id.at 201-03. The majority of citizens in a legal system might have only the fear of naked forceas their reason for compliance. See id. at 201; see also Goldsworthy, supra note 68, at 457-58;Himma, supra note 67, at 1167-69. Himma calls this the Payne Problem. Id . at 1167 n.127;see also Michael Payne, Harts Concept of a Legal System , 18 W M . & M ARY L. R EV . 287 (1976).

    84. H ART , supra note 3, at 114-15; see also Coleman & Leiter, supra note 21, at 247.

    criticized: [E]xcept by a minority of hardened offenders, suchcriticism and demands are generally regarded as legitimate, ormade w ith good reason, both by those who make them and those towhom they are made. 80

    An example of a social rule is a gam e of chess. The participantsin this game do not merely find that their behavior converges, theyhave a reflective critical attitude to this pattern of behaviour:[T]hey regard it as a standard for all who play the game. Someone 81

    who m oves the Queen like a Knight will be criticized, and probablywill criticize herself, in normative terms: I (You) ought not to havemoved the Queen like that, I (You) must do that, That is right,

    That is wrong. Because the rule of recognition is a social82

    ruleand so has the pressure for conformity and the criticallyreflective attitudes characteristic of all social rulesHart believedthat it could explain why the law provides reasons for compliance.

    Hart rather quickly scales back his explanation of legal obliga-tion, however. Even if the rule of recognition has to be a social rule,the law s identified by the rule of recognition do not. Citizens neednot have a critically reflective attitude toward dev iation from everylaw in their legal system . They m ay obey out of sheer terror. Thismeans that H art cannot use the idea of a social rule to explain whycitizens (and perhaps eve n officials) have an obligation to obey theselaws. The most Hart can do is explain the obligations that officials83

    have by virtue of their participation in the rule of recognitionforexam ple, their obligation to enforce the laws identified by the rule. 84

    But even if one sets aside this substantial gap in Harts theory,the question still remains how rules of recognition generate theselimited obligations on officials. We know tha t the obligations cannotbe explained by the fact that officials are compelled by formal or

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    30/86

    1944 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    85. H ART , supra note 3, at 57.

    86 . See id. at 202-03.87 . Id . at 185-86. The distinction between legal and moral obligation that Hart draws is

    essential to his positivism, for a distinguishing feature of positivism is the separabilitythesis. Se e C OLEMAN , supra note 67, at 152.

    88. H ART , supra note 3, at 210 (arguing that the certification of som ething as legally validis not conclusive of the question of obedience).

    informal sanctions for disobedience. Otherwise Hart, like Au stin,would be explaining only why the officials are obliged to conformto the rule of recognition, not why they h ave an obligation to do so.

    Indeed, it seems that the officials reasons for conformity m ust beindepen dent not merely of their desire to avoid sanctions, but of alltheir attitudes. Although a rule of recognition exists only wh en mostofficials have a ttitudes recommending conformity w ith the rule, theobligations created by the rule bind everyone, including those Hartcalls the minority of hardened offendersthat is, those whoseattitudes fail to give them subjective reasons for conformity. Thereasons for conformity must, it seems, be objective.

    Consider, for example, Harts emphasis on the normativeterminology of ought, must, and should used by participants in85

    social rules. This terminology expresses the views of the partici-pants that there are reasons for conformity. But the terminology isused to apply to all those who deviate, including hardened offenders.If the normative terminology referred only to subjective reasons forconformity, the hardened offenders would be excused from anyobligations.

    Although the reasons for action provided by the rule of recogni-tion look objective, Hart makes it clear that they are not moral .86

    Legality does not necessarily depend on moral merit: [I]t is in nosense a necessary truth that laws reproduce or satisfy certain

    demands of m orality, though in fact they have often done so. 87Unfortunately, Hart has little to say about how legal and moral

    reasons for action figure together in determining what officials, onthe balance of reasons, ought to do. H e does suggest, however, thatlegal reasons are not overriding. The laws demands must bebalanced against moral concerns. But the fact remains that insofar88

    as he is committed to the existence of legal obligation, he appearscomm itted to legal reasons for action as factors in determining whatofficials ought to do.

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    31/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1945

    89. For a similar argument to the following, see Zipursky, supra note 75, at 237-47.

    Can H art Explain the Laws Normativity? B.

    Can H arts idea of a social rule explain these nonm oral objectivereasons for official conformity to the rule of recognition? Consider89

    a social rule according to which men rem ove their hats when theyenter a church. Such a practice would not exist, of course, unlessmost participants had subjective reasons to conform. But whatabout the hardened offenders, who lack subjective reasons? Whatobjective reasons do they have?

    Hart suggests that objective reasons for action exist because,without them, social rules cannot be distinguished from habits. Let

    us assume, how ever, that when people enter a church, 96.7% of themen wearing hats remove them. Assume further that the partici-pants have no objective reason s for conformity. Are we now at a lossto distinguish what goes on in church from mere regularity of behavior? Must we treat the removal of hats the same way w e wouldtreat peoples tendency to blink more when the wind picks upasa simple habit? Are we unable to account for the fact that peopletend to criticize those who fail to remove their hats?

    Of course not. We can understand those who remove their hats asmotivated by certain attitudes in a way that those who blink in thewind are notattitudes that incline them to criticize hardenedoffenders and to think that they have go od reasons for criticism. The

    conformists act as they do, n ot because of blind habit, but becausethey have subjective reasons to conform. But, by the same token, thehardened offenders act as they do because they have subjectivereasons to resist conformity. Since the attitudes that give theparticipants their divergent subjective reasons are matters of psychological and social fact, an explanation in terms of theseattitudes is available to people describing the practice withoutcommitting them to the view that the practice provides its partici-pants with objective reasons for conformity.

    A more promising a pproach is to argue that, by failing to removetheir hats, the hardened offenders will upset the settled expecta-tions or sensibilities of the other churchgoers or that, by enteringthe church, they implicitly promised to conform to accepted practice.These are reasons for conformity that would exist no matter what

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    32/86

    1946 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    90. D WORKIN , supra note 17, at 51; see also Andrei Marmor, Legal Conventionalism , 4L EGAL T HEORY 509, 530 (1998) (W hether judges, or anyone else, should or should not respectthe rules of recognition of a legal system is a purely moral issue tha t can only be resolved bymoral arguments.); Gerald J. Postema, Jurisprudence as Practical Philosophy , 4 L EGALT HEORY 329, 337 (1998).

    91 . See infra Part II.D.

    ones attitudes. I do not escape m y obligation to keep my promisessimply because I have subjective reasons to break themforexample, because I really want to break them or think (wrongly)that breaking promises is obligatory. But the problem with such anargument is that these reasons for conformity, although objective,look moral , and H art seeks to distinguish legal and moral obliga-tion.

    Because the only objective reasons for conformity to the rule of recognition that seem available are moral, Harts positivism isthreatened, for positivists insist upon the separation of legal andmoral obligation. Ronald D workin identified this problem early in

    his career and it stands at the center of his critique of Hart:

    We might say that the sociologists assertion of a social rule istrue (or warranted) if a certain factual state of affairs occurs,that is, if the comm unity behaves in the w ay Hart describes inhis example. But we should want to say that the church-goersassertion of a normative rule is true (or warranted) only if acertain normative state of affairs exists, that is, only if individu-als in fact do have the duty that they suppose they have inHarts example. 90

    As Dworkin makes clear, the normative state of affairs is the91

    moral obligation that all church-goers even the hardened offenders have to remove their hats given the social facts described.

    Of course, if the only objective reasons for conformity to a socialrule are moral, the normativity of games would have to be ex-plained in moral terms too. Consider the set of social facts thatconstitutes the practice of chess. The practice would n ot exist unlessparticipants attitudes largely recommended conformity. But someparticipants might have attitudes that recomm end n onconformity.They m ight consider it important to move the Qu een like a Knight.It seems that our only av enue for showing that they h ave objectivereasons to move the Queen as the others do would be moral (for

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    33/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1947

    92. C OLEMAN , supra note 67, at 98; see also id . at 95-100; Kenneth Einar Himma, InclusiveLegal Positivism , in T HE O XFORD H ANDBOOK OF J URISPRUDENCE AND P HILOSOPHY OF L AW

    (Jules Coleman & Scott Shapiro eds., 2002) (discussing Bratmans theory); Scott J. Shapiro ,Law, Plans, and Practical Reason , 8 L EGAL T HEORY 387, 417, 432 (2002) (same).

    93 . See M ICHAEL E. B RATMAN , F ACES OF I NTENTION : S ELECTED E SSAYS ON I NTENTION AND A GENCY (1999); Michael E. Bratman, Shared Cooperative Activity: Three Features , 101 P HIL .R EV . 327 (1992) [hereinafter Bratman, Shared Cooperative Activity ]; Michael E. Bratman,Shared Intention , 104 E THICS 97 (1993) [hereinafter Bratman, Shared Intention ].

    exam ple, because it is morally wrong to upset the settled expecta-tions of the participants or because, by sitting down to play a gameof chess, they promised to conform to the practice).

    Of course, we could explain the normativity of chess withoutrecourse to morality if we gav e up the idea that rules provide par-ticipants with objective reasons for conformity. They could beunderstood simply as a set of propositions that guide the actions of those whose attitudes recommend conformity. Consider a gam e of torture-the-kitten that is kept in play through threats by a sup erior.The rules of the game would exist, despite the absence of objectivereasons for conformity, as an identifiable set of propositions that

    guide the actions of the coerced participants. Although this understanding of rules may have a good deal of

    merit, it is not one that Hart can adopt, for the commands of an Austinian sovereign are rules in this attenuated sense. A state inwhich officials conform to a rule of recognition solely due to fear of reprisals from a tyrant would be rule-governed in the attenuatedsense, but Hart makes it clear that this would be a system in whichthe officials were only obliged, not obligated, to conform.

    C. Shared Cooperative Activities?

    Positivists following in Harts footsteps have run into many of

    the same difficulties explaining laws normativity. Consider theapproach du jour the notion that a shared cooperative activity isable to make[ ] intelligible the claim that the rule of recognitioncan be a duty-imposing rule. Shared cooperative activities were92

    introduced into the philosophical lexicon by the philosopher Micha elBratman. Those who intend to participate in such activities share93

    a comm itment to joint action and therefore have reasons to respondto one another, as well as to support one another in the roles they

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    34/86

    1948 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    9 4. B ra tm a n, Shared Cooperative Activity , supra note 93, at 328.95 . Id . at 331-33.96 . See id. at 328.97. C OLEMAN , supra note 67, at 98 (quoting Himma, supra note 92, at 134-35).98 . See Thomas Christiano & Stefan Sciaraffa , Legal Positivism and the Nature of Legal

    Obligation , 22 L AW & P HIL . 487, 489-90 (2003) (reviewing C OLEMAN , supra note 67, andclaiming that a sh ared cooperative activities approach to legal obligation is akin to a naturallaw approach); Stephen R. Perry, Method and Principle in Legal Theory , 111 Y ALE L.J. 1757,1783-86 (2002) (reviewing C OLEMAN , supra note 67, and noting the similarity betweenColemans notion that shared cooperative activities commit judges to the rule of recognitionto achieve a durable legal practice and D workins approach).

    Colemans argument is complicated by his insistence that an account of the normativityof law does not have to explain why there is legal obligation. Indeed, Coleman insists that

    legal rules that purport to impose duties may not in fact do so. Him ma, supra note 67, at1167 (quoting Jules Coleman, Conventionality and Normativity (manuscript)). An account of the laws normativity must only mak e intelligible laws claim to govern by imposing contentindependent duties. Id . It is the job of the political philosopher to answ er the question underwhat conditions is laws claim to so govern true. Id . Shared cooperative activities need onlymake the laws claim to impose obligations intelligible ; it apparently does not matter that they

    are playing. An example of a shared cooperative activity is94

    painting a house together. The intention to engage in such a95

    practice gives the participants reasons for action. For example, myintention to paint a house with you gives m e a reason to share mybrush if your brush gets dirty. 96

    Some hav e suggested that if the ru le of recognition is a sharedcooperative activity, it could generate obligations of conformity forofficials participating in the rule:

    The notion of [a shared cooperative activity] involves more than just a convergence of unilateral acceptances of the rule of recognition. It involves a joint commitment on the part of theparticipants to the activity governed by the rule of recognition. And there is no m ystery (at least not one that a legal theoristis obliged to solve) about how joint commitmen ts can give rise toobligations; insofar as such comm itments induce reliance and a

    justified set of expectations (w hether explicitly or not), they cangive rise to obligations. 97

    But Dw orkins critique applies to this explanation of legal obligationas well. If one uses justified expectations and reliance to explainwhy all officialseven the hardened offendersare obligated toconform to legal practices, it looks like legal obligation is a speciesof moral obligation. 98

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    35/86

    2005] LEGAL REALISM AS THEORY OF LAW 1949

    fail actually to generate obligations. But if what makes a claim to impose obligationsintelligible need not explain why there actually are obligations, why not simply appeal to thelawmakers chutzpahthe fact that he believes, however wrongly, that his commands are

    imposing obligations? Why doesnt that make his claims intelligible? At any rate, it is clearthat Colemans approach is not Harts because Hart thought he needed to explain why legalobligation actually exists. See id. at 1169.

    99. Michael E. Bratman, Shapiro on Legal Positivism a nd Jointly Intentional Activity , 8L EGAL T HEORY 511, 517 (2002) (footnotes omitted); see also B RATMAN , supra note 93, at 132-36; Bratman, Shared Intention , supra note 93, at 111-12.

    The on ly nonmoral reasons for conformity that shared cooperativeactivities provide are subjective in the sense that they are bindingonly given ones continued intention or commitment to participate.It is for just this reason that Bratman himself doubts that sharedcooperative activities can explain lega l obligation. A rule of recogni-tion could not give rise to obligations on unwilling judicial partici-pants without the introduction of moral concerns:

    [W]hat happens when the authority knows that a subject doesnot in fact have the relevant intention? Perhaps a higher-court

    judge knows that a particular lower-court judge does notactually intend that the higher-court judges orders be a reasonfor him. The present account gives us no basis for saying thatthe lower-court judge, by virtue of his role, nevertheless hasreason to conform to the rulings of the higher-court judg e. It isnatural here to say that the authoritys orders still providereasons for the subject because the subject has, by taking on therelevant role, assured the authority and others or (anyway)intentionally given them the reason able expectation that he (thesubject) would treat the orders in this way. The advantage of this story is that it does not depend upon the sub jects actuallyintending that the orders be reasons. A possible problem is thata defense of this story will, I suppose, appeal to moral principlesof assurance-based obligation. And that may b e a kind of appeal

    to morality that is in ten sion with the legal po sitivists project.99

    This problem is evident when we consider whether reasons forconformity that bind unwilling participants would exist for sharedcooperative activities that are immoral. Imagine that we havedecided to torture a kitten together, using instruments to beconstructed collaboratively. I am torturing the kitten with our mostrecently completed instrument, and you are busy constructing the

  • 8/8/2019 Legal Realism Green Wmlj

    36/86

    1950 WILLIAM AND MARY LAW REVIEW [Vol. 46:1915

    100. Himma, defending Colemans argument, recognizes that the obligations createdthrough shared cooperative acti