1
Sir — Your Opinion article (“Distasteful but necessary”, Nature 417, 673; 2002) does not explore in depth the morality of experimenting on non-human primates. You claim that the issue is “simple”, that “potential benefits must be weighed against the suffering caused”. But nobody would apply a cost-benefit test to experi- menting on people against their will. What is the difference? Your argument can only be that non-human primates are one sort of primate and we are another, so it is acceptable for us to cause them pain. That approach cannot withstand any intellectual scrutiny. Primates are just as capable of suffering as we are. Suffering, and its avoidance, lies at the heart of all moral philosophy. If it is wrong to cause suffering to people deliberately — whatever the benefits to others — it must also be wrong to do so to other primates. You also say that it is time to inform public opinion about primate research. I agree. But that has to mean full information, not simply such information as researchers find it convenient to disclose. It should not take undercover investigations, such as that recently carried out by the British Union for the Abolition of Vivisection (BUAV) into primate research at Cambridge University, to reveal the extent of suffering involved (caused both by the experiments and the housing conditions) and to raise serious questions about the usefulness of the research. BUAV is calling for an inquiry into primate research in the United Kingdom independent of the Home Office, which has once again shown, in the Cambridge case, that it is not up to its regulatory task. Will primate researchers support BUAV in this call? If not, it will only strengthen the growing perception that researchers and government alike would prefer to keep the public in the dark. Michelle Thew British Union for the Abolition of Vivisection, 16a Crane Grove, London N7 8NN, UK correspondence NATURE | VOL 418 | 18 JULY 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 273 Are results of primate research worth the suffering it causes? Researchers must be honest about methods and goals. Names: a historical or political perspective? Sir — I have two questions in response to Rognes’s Correspondence (Nature 417, 379; 2002). First, has most of his research work been done before or after June 1967? The “occupied territories” have been within Israel’s borders since that date. If the major piece of research was performed after 1967, surely the territories should be referred to by their current names? Would anyone in the scientific community nowadays call India a part of the ‘British Dominion’, or place Ukraine in the ‘USSR’? Would anyone use the name ‘Rhodesia’ when referring to Zimbabwe or ‘Ceylon’ instead of Sri Lanka? As with any scientific nomenclature, a scientist is required by a journal to use the current names of territories, regardless of his or her politics. It may be useful to add comments regarding historical names if they are relevant to the research described. Second is the issue of showing some respect to the publisher’s country. If you know that certain names are a sensitive issue in certain countries, and you do not wish to take sides in a political debate local to the area, why not use the terms that are used by the country concerned and by most of the world? I do not think Nature’s publishers in the United Kingdom would be happy to review manuscripts referring to the Falkland Islands as the ‘Malvinas’. Sharona Even-Ram National Institute of Dental and Craniofacial Research, National Institutes of Health, 30 Convent Drive, Bethesda, Maryland 20892, USA Nature allows contributors to use their own choice of name (if in standard use) for the region from which they are writing. This holds for the Falkland Islands/ Malvinas as for other regions of the world, such as Taiwan — Editor, Correspondence Only vital need justifies primate experiments Sir — In your recent Opinion article on when experiments with non-human primates can be justified (Nature 417, 684–687, 2002), a relevant perspective can be found in US constitutional law. A non-human primate can be regarded as belonging to the ‘quasi-person’ class originally used in 1865 to define African- Americans, who were not accorded full constitutional personhood in law, but were entitled to some natural rights under the US constitution, including that of self- interest (see R. M. Lebovitz, St Thomas Law Review, 14, 561–600; 2002). But does this mean that primates are entitled constitutionally to be free from the physical abuse produced by experimentation? No constitutional right is absolute, but there must be an important and persuasive reason for abrogating it. In the United States, a person’s so-called ‘liberty interest’ is a fundamental constitutional right, yet the government can infringe upon it when the circumstances are important enough. A famous example is an early twentieth century case in which an adult man refused to be vaccinated against smallpox, despite a Massachusetts state law requiring it. The case made its way to the US Supreme Court, where the justices wrote that constitutional rights are not unencumbered, but may be infringed when necessary for the good of the community, including for reasons of public safety to protect the population from a disease epidemic (Jacobson vs Massachusetts, 197 US 11; 1905). Using the same rationale, it can be argued that, although most animal experimentation is not significant enough to warrant violating a primate’s right of self-interest, some experimentation may meet this high standard. For instance, research on a particular vaccine may be important enough as a societal concern to excuse intrusion on the animal’s right of self-interest. We must carefully scrutinize the goals of experimentation to determine when it justifies extinguishing a US animal’s constitutional right of self-interest. Richard M. Lebovitz Interdisciplinary Bioscience PhD Program, George Mason University, 4400 University Drive, Fairfax, Virginia 22030-4444, USA Little funding to develop non-animal testing Sir — Your News Feature “The great primate debate” (Nature 417, 684–687; 2002) did not discuss the potential of in vitro and clinical studies to replace many primate experiments in drug development, neuroscience and AIDS research. Non- animal methods can — and should — be supported by all sides of the debate. While verbal support is often forthcoming, resources to develop such alternative methods are not. Despite its responsibility under European legislation, the British government’s budget for alternatives is sub-divided into different areas, with the intention that developing replacements for animal experiments should receive about £56,000 (US$85,500) a year — barely enough to fund one research project. Gill Langley Dr Hadwen Trust for Humane Research, 84a Tilehouse Street, Hitchin, Herts SG5 2DY, UK © 2002 Nature Publishing Group

Little funding to develop non-animal testing

  • Upload
    gill

  • View
    217

  • Download
    4

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Little funding to develop non-animal testing

Sir — Your Opinion article (“Distastefulbut necessary”, Nature 417, 673; 2002)does not explore in depth the morality ofexperimenting on non-human primates.You claim that the issue is “simple”, that“potential benefits must be weighedagainst the suffering caused”. But nobodywould apply a cost-benefit test to experi-menting on people against their will. Whatis the difference? Your argument can onlybe that non-human primates are one sortof primate and we are another, so it isacceptable for us to cause them pain.

That approach cannot withstand anyintellectual scrutiny. Primates are just ascapable of suffering as we are. Suffering,and its avoidance, lies at the heart of allmoral philosophy. If it is wrong to causesuffering to people deliberately —whatever the benefits to others — it mustalso be wrong to do so to other primates.

You also say that it is time to informpublic opinion about primate research. I agree. But that has to mean full

information, not simply such informationas researchers find it convenient todisclose. It should not take undercoverinvestigations, such as that recently carriedout by the British Union for the Abolitionof Vivisection (BUAV) into primateresearch at Cambridge University, to revealthe extent of suffering involved (causedboth by the experiments and the housingconditions) and to raise serious questionsabout the usefulness of the research.

BUAV is calling for an inquiry intoprimate research in the United Kingdomindependent of the Home Office, whichhas once again shown, in the Cambridgecase, that it is not up to its regulatory task.Will primate researchers support BUAV inthis call? If not, it will only strengthen thegrowing perception that researchers andgovernment alike would prefer to keep the public in the dark.Michelle ThewBritish Union for the Abolition of Vivisection, 16a Crane Grove, London N7 8NN, UK

correspondence

NATURE | VOL 418 | 18 JULY 2002 | www.nature.com/nature 273

Are results of primate researchworth the suffering it causes? Researchers must be honest about methods and goals.

Names: a historical orpolitical perspective?Sir — I have two questions in response toRognes’s Correspondence (Nature 417, 379;2002). First, has most of his research workbeen done before or after June 1967? The“occupied territories” have been withinIsrael’s borders since that date. If the majorpiece of research was performed after 1967,surely the territories should be referred toby their current names? Would anyone inthe scientific community nowadays callIndia a part of the ‘British Dominion’, orplace Ukraine in the ‘USSR’? Would anyoneuse the name ‘Rhodesia’ when referring toZimbabwe or ‘Ceylon’ instead of Sri Lanka?

As with any scientific nomenclature, ascientist is required by a journal to use thecurrent names of territories, regardless ofhis or her politics. It may be useful to addcomments regarding historical names ifthey are relevant to the research described.

Second is the issue of showing somerespect to the publisher’s country. If youknow that certain names are a sensitiveissue in certain countries, and you do notwish to take sides in a political debate localto the area, why not use the terms that areused by the country concerned and bymost of the world? I do not think Nature’spublishers in the United Kingdom wouldbe happy to review manuscripts referringto the Falkland Islands as the ‘Malvinas’.Sharona Even-RamNational Institute of Dental and CraniofacialResearch, National Institutes of Health, 30 ConventDrive, Bethesda, Maryland 20892, USA

Nature allows contributors to use theirown choice of name (if in standard use)for the region from which they are writing.This holds for the Falkland Islands/Malvinas as for other regions of the world,such as Taiwan — Editor, Correspondence

Only vital need justifiesprimate experiments Sir — In your recent Opinion article onwhen experiments with non-humanprimates can be justified (Nature 417,684–687, 2002), a relevant perspective can be found in US constitutional law. Anon-human primate can be regarded asbelonging to the ‘quasi-person’ classoriginally used in 1865 to define African-Americans, who were not accorded fullconstitutional personhood in law, but wereentitled to some natural rights under theUS constitution, including that of self-interest (see R. M. Lebovitz, St Thomas Law Review, 14, 561–600; 2002). But doesthis mean that primates are entitled

constitutionally to be free from the physicalabuse produced by experimentation?

No constitutional right is absolute, butthere must be an important and persuasivereason for abrogating it. In the UnitedStates, a person’s so-called ‘liberty interest’is a fundamental constitutional right, yetthe government can infringe upon it whenthe circumstances are important enough.A famous example is an early twentiethcentury case in which an adult manrefused to be vaccinated against smallpox,despite a Massachusetts state law requiringit. The case made its way to the USSupreme Court, where the justices wrotethat constitutional rights are notunencumbered, but may be infringedwhen necessary for the good of thecommunity, including for reasons ofpublic safety to protect the populationfrom a disease epidemic (Jacobson vsMassachusetts, 197 US 11; 1905).

Using the same rationale, it can beargued that, although most animal experimentation is not significant enoughto warrant violating a primate’s right of self-interest, some experimentation maymeet this high standard. For instance,research on a particular vaccine may beimportant enough as a societal concern toexcuse intrusion on the animal’s right ofself-interest. We must carefully scrutinizethe goals of experimentation to determine

when it justifies extinguishing a US animal’sconstitutional right of self-interest. Richard M. Lebovitz Interdisciplinary Bioscience PhD Program, George Mason University, 4400 University Drive,Fairfax, Virginia 22030-4444, USA

Little funding to developnon-animal testingSir — Your News Feature “The greatprimate debate” (Nature 417, 684–687;2002) did not discuss the potential of invitro and clinical studies to replace manyprimate experiments in drug development,neuroscience and AIDS research. Non-animal methods can — and should — besupported by all sides of the debate. Whileverbal support is often forthcoming,resources to develop such alternativemethods are not. Despite its responsibilityunder European legislation, the Britishgovernment’s budget for alternatives issub-divided into different areas, with theintention that developing replacements foranimal experiments should receive about£56,000 (US$85,500) a year — barelyenough to fund one research project. Gill Langley Dr Hadwen Trust for Humane Research, 84a Tilehouse Street, Hitchin, Herts SG5 2DY, UK

© 2002 Nature Publishing Group