18
Lucretius First published Wed Aug 4, 2004; substantive revision Tue Aug 19, 2008 Titus Lucretius Carus (died c. 50 BCE) was an Epicurean poet writing in the middle years of the first century BCE. His six-book Latin hexameter poem De rerum natura (DRN for short), variously translated On the nature of things and On the nature of the universe, survives virtually intact, although it is disputed whether he lived to put the finishing touches to it. As well as being a pioneering figure in the history of philosophical poetry, Lucretius has come to be our primary source of information on Epicurean physics, the official topic of his poem. Among numerous other Epicurean doctrines, the atomic ‘swerve’ is known to us mainly from Lucretius' account of it. His defence of the Epicurean system is deftly and passionately argued, and is particularly admired for its eloquent critique of the fear of death in book 3. 1. Life 2. The poem's structure 3. Epicurean background 4. Physics 5. Ethics 6. Religion 7. Influence Bibliography o Editions o Translations o Commentaries Other Internet Resources Related Entries 1. Life We know virtually nothing, beyond what little can be inferred from the poem itself, of Lucretius' biography. There is just one contemporary reference to him (or near contemporary, depending on the date of his death): it is found in a letter of Cicero, written in 54 BCE, where he briefly agrees with his brother about the ‘flashes of genius’ and ‘craftsmanship’ that characterize Lucretius' poetry. What we can say for sure is that the poem is dedicated and addressed to a Roman aristocrat named Memmius, although it is not altogether certain which member of the Memmius family this was. Lucretius expresses a hope for Memmius'

Lucretius - Stanford

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Lucretius - Stanfordencyclopedia of philosophy

Citation preview

  • Lucretius

    First published Wed Aug 4, 2004; substantive revision Tue Aug 19, 2008

    Titus Lucretius Carus (died c. 50 BCE) was an Epicurean poet writing in the

    middle years of the first century BCE. His six-book Latin hexameter poem De

    rerum natura (DRN for short), variously translated On the nature of things and On

    the nature of the universe, survives virtually intact, although it is disputed whether

    he lived to put the finishing touches to it. As well as being a pioneering figure in

    the history of philosophical poetry, Lucretius has come to be our primary source of

    information on Epicurean physics, the official topic of his poem. Among numerous

    other Epicurean doctrines, the atomic swerve is known to us mainly from

    Lucretius' account of it. His defence of the Epicurean system is deftly and

    passionately argued, and is particularly admired for its eloquent critique of the fear

    of death in book 3.

    1. Life

    2. The poem's structure

    3. Epicurean background

    4. Physics

    5. Ethics

    6. Religion

    7. Influence

    Bibliography

    o Editions

    o Translations

    o Commentaries

    Other Internet Resources

    Related Entries

    1. Life

    We know virtually nothing, beyond what little can be inferred from the poem itself,

    of Lucretius' biography. There is just one contemporary reference to him (or near

    contemporary, depending on the date of his death): it is found in a letter of Cicero,

    written in 54 BCE, where he briefly agrees with his brother about the flashes of

    genius and craftsmanship that characterize Lucretius' poetry.

    What we can say for sure is that the poem is dedicated and addressed to a Roman

    aristocrat named Memmius, although it is not altogether certain which member of

    the Memmius family this was. Lucretius expresses a hope for Memmius'

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Lifhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#PoeStrhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#EpiBachttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Phyhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Ethhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Religionhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Infhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Bibhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Edihttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Trahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Comhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Othhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Rel

  • friendship, but that does not rule out the possibility of an asymmetric client-patron

    relation, as distinct from one of genuine social equality.

    The other bibliographical data are late and untrustworthy. They put his birth in 94

    BCE, his death in either 54 or 51. (A case has even been made, by Hutchinson

    2001, for dating his death later still, to the early 40s BCE). We can, at all events,

    say with some confidence that Lucretius wrote his poem in the mid first century

    BCE.

    Because early Christianity branded Lucretius an enemy of religion, his life and

    death had to be depicted as appropriately wretched. Thus, according to St Jerome,

    he was driven mad by a love philtre, wrote poetry in his lucid intervals, and died

    by his own hand, leaving his poem to be edited posthumously by Cicero. This

    apart from the last detail, which some have found credible is a palpable

    fabrication. Its portrayal of wretched insanity is implicitly contradicted by

    Lucretius' younger contemporary and admirer Virgil, who felt able to write of him

    in his Georgics, a didactic poem heavily in Lucretius' debt, the celebrated lines

    (2.490-2) Happy he who was able to know the causes of things (felix qui potuit

    rerum cognoscere causas), and who trampled beneath his feet all fears, inexorable

    fate, and the roar of devouring hell. With these admiring words, Virgil neatly

    encapsulates four dominant themes of the poem universal causal explanation,

    leading to elimination of the threats the world seems to pose, a vindication of free

    will, and disproof of the soul's survival after death. But he also, in advertising

    Lucretius' philosophical understanding as his enviable source of happiness, makes

    it implausible that the author of DRN had by this date acquired his later reputation

    as a suicidal psychotic.

    2. The poem's structure

    Whether or not the poem is altogether in the finished state that Lucretius would

    have wanted, its six-book structure is itself clearly a carefully planned one. It falls

    into three matching pairs of books:

    1. The permanent constituents of the universe: atoms and void

    2. How atoms explain phenomena

    3. The nature and mortality of the soul

    4. Phenomena of the soul

    5. The cosmos and its mortality

    6. Cosmic phenomena

    The sequence is one of ascending scale: the first pair of books deals with the

    microscopic world of atoms, the second with human beings, the third with the

    cosmos as a whole. Within each pair of books, the first explains the basic nature of

  • the entity or entities in question, the second goes on to examine a range of

    individual phenomena associated with them. A further symmetry lies in the theme

    of mortality, treated by the odd-numbered books. Book I stresses from the outset

    the indestructibility of the basic elements, while books III and V in pointed

    contrast give matching prominence to the perishability and transience of,

    respectively, the soul and the cosmos.

    In addition to this division into three matching pairs of books, the poem can also be

    seen as constituted by two balanced halves, orchestrated by the themes of life and

    death. It opens with a hymn to Venus as the force inspiring birth and life. The first

    half closes, at the end of III, with Lucretius' long and eloquent denunciation of the

    fear of death. And the poem as a whole returns at its close to the theme of death,

    with the disquieting passage on the frightful Athenian plague during the

    Peloponnesian War: whether or not this, as we have it, is in its finished form, there

    can be little doubt that the placing of its theme itself somehow represents the

    author's own orchestration.

    There has been much dispute over this ending. Some judge it a poetically effective

    closure as it stands, others believe that Lucretius would, had he lived, at least have

    completed it with a suitable moral. The former party maintains that Lucretius by

    this point in the poem is liable to leave readers to work out the moral for

    themselves. On this, however, see further 5 below.

    3. Epicurean background

    Epicurus founded his system in the early decades of the 3rd century BCE, and it

    became one of the most influential of the Hellenistic age. Lucretius lived in Italy in

    a period when Epicureanism flourished there, especially in the area of the Bay of

    Naples, where a major Epicurean circle had formed around Philodemus.

    Philodemus' library was rediscovered during the 18th-century excavations of

    Herculaneum (recent claims to have found remains of a copy of Lucretius' poem

    among its badly damaged contents may be unduly optimistic). In addition, the

    main Epicurean school was still flourishing in Athens, despite the departure of

    most other schools from their metropolitan headquarters there, and it had other

    regional branches to which a Roman might equally well go for study. In any case,

    Epicureanism was by now one of the four leading philosophical systems

    thatany aspiring philosophy student was expected to master. Romans who, against

    this background, became Epicureans included Cicero's friend Atticus, and Cassius,

    later an assassin of Caesar. It therefore becomes both easy and attractive to think of

    Lucretius' turn to Epicureanism as part of a trend among the Roman intelligentsia.

    Curiously, however, his poem shows few if any signs of contemporary

    philosophical or scientific engagement. We know a good deal about recent trends

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Eth

  • in the Epicurean school for example, its sophisticated debates with the Stoics on

    scientific method and mathematics yet we find little or no evidence in Lucretius'

    poem that he is aware of, let alone engaged in, these developments. And although

    he includes a number of critiques of anonymous opponents, none of these

    opponents can plausibly be identified with anyone who lived in the two centuries

    separating Epicurus' own lifetime from Lucretius', including adherents of the era's

    most prestigious school, the Stoa. It may, then, be more accurate to think of

    Lucretius as philosophically isolated, drawing his inspiration from Epicurus' own

    treasured writings, and for that reason adopting Epicurus' polemical targets as his

    own.

    This alternative fits well with the apparent facts about Lucretius' use of sources. So

    far as one can tell, the material on physics that he started from and reworked was

    all taken from the first fifteen books of Epicurus' 37-book magnum opus, On

    nature. Thanks to the accidental survival in Lucretius' book 4 of two alternative

    programmatic passages for the book, we can work out that what we call book 4

    was initially planned to come directly after book 2, a sequence of topics which

    would have exactly reproduced Epicurus' own in On nature, and that it was only in

    a later phase that he reorganised his material so that our book 3 came to intervene.

    This gives good grounds for the guess that the relatively small number of other

    demonstrable departures from Epicurus' original sequence likewise represent the

    process by which, either while or after completing a first draft, Lucretius set about

    reorganising the poem's contents into the six-book structure we possess today. So

    far as one can tell, his rewriting of books 1-3 was complete, but that of books 4-6

    was still under way at the time of his death. (This is all argued at length in Sedley

    1998.) Among other signs of incompleteness, the latter three books are very long,

    and would probably have been cut down to something like the length of books 1-3

    in the final revision.

    Because of the way he worked, there are grounds for confidence that, by and large,

    the central philosophical content of Lucretius' poem closely mirrors what he found

    in Epicurus. His departures from Epicurus are more in the matter of sequence than

    of doctrine or argument. This adherence to Epicurus' own text is further confirmed

    by the reverent tones in which Lucretius speaks of his master's writings: I follow

    you, glory of the Greek race, as in your footprints I now plant my own, not so

    much out of any desire to compete with you as for love, for my wish is to imitate

    you You are our father, the discoverer of reality. You pass to us your paternal

    precepts, and from your scrolls, glorious one, just as bees sip all they can find in

    the flowery glades, we likewise feed upon all of your golden words golden, and

    ever deserving of perpetual life (3.3-13).

  • At 1.921-50 (lines which later recur in part as the proem to book 4) Lucretius' sets

    out his poetic manifesto, declaring the revolutionary novelty of his task. By this he

    means, no doubt, above all his task as the first poet of Epicureanism. Philosophical

    poetry had been pioneered by the early Greek writers Xenophanes, Parmenides and

    Empedocles, the last of whom Lucretius both reveres and imitates. But none before

    him had written poetry in defence of Epicureanism, or for that matter (and

    Lucretius may have this innovation in mind too) philosophical poetry in Latin.

    There has been much discussion regarding the supposed unorthodoxy of an

    Epicurean writing philosophical verse, but it has not been established that

    Lucretius was breaking any school edict. Epicurus' own hostility to poetry had, it

    seems, belonged in a tradition that went back at least to Plato, focusing on the

    morally harmful content of the poetry, by Homer and others, that played such a

    large part in the Greek educational curriculum. That versification as such was

    considered objectionable in the school's earlier tradition has not been shown.

    Lucretius' own explanation of his choice of a poetic medium is that philosophy is

    medicine for the soul, and that the charms of verse can function like the honey that

    doctors smear on the rim of a cup of bitter medicine, to persuade children to drink

    it for their own good. For, Lucretius loves to remind us, when it comes to fear of

    the unknown, we are all of us mere children, terrified of the dark.

    A feature germane to philosophical prose which Lucretius retains and even

    enhances in his verse is the carefully tabulated order of a series of arguments for

    each demonstrandum, even though additional, more rhetorical features of his

    argumentative techniques have been rightly noted by scholars (e.g., Asmis 1983).

    Another is the defence of a hypothesis by appeal to analogy with familiar empirical

    data. This latter procedure, integral to Epicurean methodology, presents Lucretius

    with frequent occasion to develop rich and complex poetic similes one of the

    most admired and appreciated aspects of his writing.

    4. Physics

    Book 1 sets out the fundamental principles of Epicurean atomism.

    1.149-482. First comes, in effect, Lucretius' ontology. Nothing comes into being

    out of nothing or perishes into nothing. The only two per se entities are body and

    void; all other existing things are inseparable or accidental properties of these

    (Lucretius' own terms for which are coniuncta and eventa respectively). Two

    further items that might be suspected of existing independently of any concurrently

    existing body or void, (1) time and (2) historical facts, are argued to be in fact

    existentially parasitic on the presently existing world, and thus not after all per

    se existents.

  • 1.483-634. Lucretius next turns to the basic truths of physics. Body comes in

    minute and physically indivisible portions, atoms although Lucretius does not

    use this Greek loan-word, and prefers a series of circumlocutions such as first

    beginnings of things (primordia rerum), seeds, and matter (materies, derived

    from mater, mother), which serve his poetic purposes by evoking the creative

    powers of these primary particles. It is by their combination into complex

    structures that all phenomenal beings are generated.

    Epicurus had attached enormous importance to the internal structure of atoms,

    which he held to consist of altogether partless magnitudes called minima.

    Lucretius condenses and largely edits out this doctrine. What little he does say in

    support of it is mixed in with his defence of atoms themselves (1.599-634), rather

    than exhibited as a separate part of the physical theory. Whether this policy reflects

    the theory's difficulty for himself or his readers, the economies entailed by keeping

    the overall subject matter within the chosen six-book structure, or a theoretical

    difference from early Epicureanism, is destined to be a matter for speculation only.

    1.635-920. Lucretius now turns polemical, attacking in sequence three Presocratic

    philosophers representing three rival physical systems as these had come to be

    classified in the Aristotelian tradition: monism, finite pluralism and infinite

    pluralism. Heraclitus, with his reduction of everything to fire, is the token monist;

    Empedocles, with his four elements, represents finite pluralism; and Anaxagoras,

    read through the lens of Aristotelian doxography as making all the

    homoeomerous or like-parted stuffs the elements, is treated as

    fundamentally sui generis. None of these thinkers had a significant, if indeed any,

    following in Lucretius' day (even if Heraclitus had been accorded an honourable

    place in the prehistory of Stoicism). His choice of them as targets probably reflects

    his readiness to take over from Epicurus (On nature books 14 and 15) the critiques

    which the school founder had felt it appropriate to launch in his own historical

    context.

    1.951-1117. The final part of book 1 is a leap from the invisibly small to the

    unimaginably large. The universe is infinite, he argues, consisting of infinitely

    extended space and an infinite number of atoms. Some philosophers, he adds,

    mistakenly picture our world as formed around a spherical earth, itself located at

    the universe's centre. Although Lucretius does not say so, the juxtaposition of these

    two themes was natural because the latter thesis a version of the Platonic one

    that privileged our own world as unique - was the main rival to that of the

    universe's infinity. Modern readers may therefore well sympathize with the

    motivation of Lucretius' critique of it, even if at the same time regretting his too

    ready dismissal of the ridiculous image of animals walking upside down in the

    antipodes, where it is day when it is night here (1.1058-67).

  • Book 2 explains the nature of atomic compounds.

    2.80-332. The opening exposition of book 2 descends into the details of atoms'

    behaviour and qualities. They are in perpetual motion at enormous speed, since in

    the void they get no resistance from the medium, and when they collide they can

    only be deflected, not halted. Their weight gives them an inherent tendency to

    move downwards, but collisions can divert those motions in other directions. The

    result is that, when in a cosmic arrangement, atoms build up complex and

    relatively stable patterns of motion, which at the macroscopic level appear to us as

    states of rest or relatively gentle motion. Lucretius compares a flock of sheep on a

    distant hillside, which appears as a stationary white patch, even though close up the

    constituent sheep prove to be in motion (2.317-22). The most celebrated part of

    this account, however, is at 2.216-93, where Lucretius maintains that not only to

    explain how atomic collisions can occur in the first place, but also to account for

    the evident fact of free will in the animal kingdom, it is necessary to postulate a

    minimal indeterminacy in the motions of atoms, an unpredictable swerve

    (clinamen) at no fixed place or time. Otherwise we would all be automata, our

    motions determined by infinitely extended and unbreakable causal chains. A

    striking resemblance to the indeterminacy postulated by modern quantum physics

    which has also often been invoked in debates about determinism has helped

    make this passage the subject of particularly intense debate. Analogously to

    various modern philosophical attempts to exploit quantum indeterminacy as a basis

    for psychological indeterminism, interpreters of Lucretius have long debated what

    relation he postulates between the swerve and free will. Some have read him as

    positing at least one atomic swerve in the soul to coincide with (and probably help

    constitute) every new volition. Others have drawn attention to his remark that the

    swerve is needed so that cause should not follow cause from infinity (2.255) and

    argued that the theory aims merely to ensure that our present self is not the

    necessary product of our entire past atomic history.

    2.333-1022. After his account of atoms' motion, Lucretius turns to their properties,

    explaining how a vast but finite number of atomic shapes underlies and accounts

    for the vast but finite phenomenal variety that the world has to offer, without the

    atoms themselves possessing either sensible properties such as colours or mental

    powers.

    2.1023-1174. The final part of the book returns, symmetrically with the end of

    book 1, to the nature of the universe beyond the confines of our own world. This

    time Lucretius' theme is the existence of other worlds besides our own, it being

    inconceivable, he argues, that in an infinite universe it should be only here that a

    world has formed. Moreover, he adds, worlds come and go, our own included.

    Both themes the numberless plurality of worlds and their transience

  • Lucretius regards as helpfully damaging to the religious view of our world as a

    product of divine creation.

    Book 3 turns to the soul and its mortality.

    3.94-416. the soul's constitution. The soul consists of two parts. The spirit

    (anima) is spread throughout the body, while the mind (animus) is the command

    centre, located in the chest. The soul in both aspects can be shown to be corporeal,

    Lucretius argues. Its characteristic sensitivity and mobility are explicable by the

    special combination of atoms that constitute it: it is a blend of the types of atoms

    constitutive of air, wind and fire, along with a fourth, ultra-fine type unique to soul.

    Although modern readers will find the details of this physiology hopelessly

    outdated, they can usefully replace Lucretian mind and spirit with, respectively,

    the brain and nervous system, in order to appreciate the enduring relevance of what

    follows, Lucretius' argument that our conscious selves cannot survive death.

    3.417-829. Given that it is atomically constituted, the soul must like every atomic

    compound be destined for eventual dissolution. Once the body dies, there is

    nothing to hold the soul together, and its atoms will disperse as Lucretius argues

    with a massive battery of proofs (around thirty, the exact number depending on

    alternative ways of dividing up the text). For example, he argues, our mental

    development tracks that of the body through infancy, maturity and senility alike, so

    it is only to be expected that the body's final disintegration should be accompanied

    by that of our mental faculties. There is therefore, contrary to the prevailing

    religious tradition, no survival after death, no reincarnation, and no punishment in

    Hades. For the consequent lesson that death is not to be feared, see 5 below.

    Book 4 moves the focus to the soul's powers.

    4.26-215. Lucretius starts by setting out the theory of simulacra atom-thin and

    lightning-fast images that stream from the surfaces of solid objects (or sometimes

    form spontaneously in mid air) and enter the eyes or mind to cause vision and

    visualization.

    4.216-1059. The basic theory is then applied to sense-perception, and above all to

    vision and imagination, including dreams. (The non-visual senses are addressed

    too, even though, technically speaking, they rely not on simulacra but on other

    kinds of effluence.) Lucretius devotes a substantial section to describing optical

    illusions, which his atomic theory claims to be able to account for without

    sacrificing its fundamental position that it is never the senses that lie, only our

    interpretations of their data. Indeed, he defends this latter Epicurean paradox by

    deploying a classic self-refutation argument against the sceptical alternative: to

    deny that we have access to knowledge through the senses (its only possible entry

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Eth

  • route) is a philosophical stance that disqualifies its own adherents by depriving

    them of any possible grounds for its assertion (4.469-521).

    Although cognitive mechanisms provide the main focus, a variety of other animal

    functions, including nutrition and locomotion, are covered by this part of the book.

    Among the gems is a digression attacking the teleologists' mode of physiological

    explanation (4.823-57). To explain bodily limbs and organs on the model of

    artefacts, as divinely created for the sake of their use, is a misapplication of the

    craft-nature analogy. Artefacts were invented for the better fulfilment of functions

    that alreadyexisted in nature cups to facilitate drinking, beds to improve sleep,

    weapons for more effective fighting. No analogous story can be told about e.g., the

    eye being created for seeing, because before there were eyes there was no such

    function as seeing.

    Books 5 and 6 set out to explain the cosmos as a whole and its phenomenal

    contents.

    5.91-415 expands the earlier argument that our world is no more than a transient

    amalgam of atoms. This finding is taken by Lucretius to be damning to

    creationism, for a benevolent creator would surely (as Plato had maintained) have

    ensured that his product would be everlasting. Besides, he argues, the world is an

    environment too hostile to human beings to lend any credence to the creationist

    thesis that it was made for them. While other creatures seem to have it easy, we

    struggle all our lives to eke out a living. When the new-born human baby takes its

    first look at the world and bursts into tears, one can admire its prescience,

    considering all the troubles that lie ahead for it.

    5.416-770. Following up on this theme, Lucretius now reconstructs the blind

    process of atomic conglomeration that gave rise to our world. He then continues

    with a matchingly non-theistic series of explanations of individual celestial

    phenomena. In true Epicurean spirit (here and in book 6 too; see especially 6.703-

    11), his favoured policy is to list a plurality of explanations of one and the same

    phenomenon without selecting one as correct. What matters is that, however many

    such explanations we acknowledge, they should be exclusively material

    explanations sufficient to render unnecessary the postulation of divine intervention.

    Being intrinsically possible, they must also be true, if not in our world, then at any

    rate somewhere, for in an infinite universe no possibility can remain unactualized

    (an application of the Principle of Plenitude). Lucretius is here relying on an

    Epicurean modal theory based on actual not just possible worlds, whereby

    possible is equated with true in one or more (actual) worlds, necessary with

    true in all (actual) worlds.

  • 5.771-1427. Continuing the early history of our world, Lucretius envisages how

    life first emerged from the earth, and (an especially admired and influential

    reconstruction) how humans developed from nomadic hunters to city-dwellers with

    language, law and the arts. In this prehistory the exclusion of divine intervention,

    while rarely foregrounded, is plainly the underlying motivation. The fertile young

    earth naturally sprouted with life forms, and the organisms thus generated were

    innumerable random formations. Of these, most perished, but a minority proved

    capable of surviving thanks to strength, cunning, or utility to man and of

    reproducing their kind. This account, which has won admiration for its partial

    anticipation of Darwin's principle of the survival of the fittest, is plainly using a

    kind of natural selection to account non-teleologically for the apparent presence of

    design in the animal kingdom.

    Much the same anti-teleological program underlies the ensuing prehistory of

    civilization (5.925-1457). Each cultural advance was prompted by nature, and only

    subsequently taken up and developed by human beings. Hence, it is implied, no

    divine intervention need be postulated as an explanatory tool. No Prometheus was

    needed to introduce fire, which rather was first brought to human attention by

    naturally kindled forest fires (5.1091-1101). Language emerged (5.1028-90)

    because people started to notice how their instinctive vocal responses to things,

    comparable to animal noises, could be put at the service of their intuitive desire to

    communicate (for which infants' pre-linguistic pointing is cited as evidence). The

    same part of book 5 is rich in other cultural reconstructions, including the origin of

    friendship and justice in a primitive social contract (5.1011-27), and of

    conventional religion in early mankind's misguided tendency to link visions of the

    gods, above all in dreams, to their desire to explain cosmic phenomena (5.1161-

    1240).

    6.96-1286. To conclude his poem, Lucretius works through a range of the

    phenomena that physical theorists were standardly called upon to account for:

    storms, waterspouts, earthquakes, plagues and the like. Once more the exclusion of

    divine causation undoubtedly motivates the account, the phenomena in question

    being nearly all ones popularly regarded as manifestations of divine intervention.

    Lucretius not only explains them naturalistically, but is ready to mock the rival,

    theological explanations: for example, if thunderbolts are weapons hurled by Zeus

    at human miscreants, why does he waste so much of his ammunition on

    uninhabited regions, or, when he does score a hit, sometimes strike his own temple

    (6.387-422)?

    5. Ethics

  • The De rerum natura is, as its title confirms, a work of physics, written in the

    venerable tradition of Greek treatises On nature. Nevertheless, Lucretius writes as

    a complete Epicurean, offering his reader not just cosmological understanding but

    the full recipe for happiness. Certainly to eliminate fear of the divine through

    physical understanding is one component of this task, but not the only one.

    According to the Epicurean canon, the fear of death must also be countered, and

    the rational management of pleasures and pains learnt.

    Such an agenda manifests itself at various strategically significant points of the

    poem, in the form of Lucretius' uplifting pleas for Epicurean values. The

    magnificent finale of book 3 (830-1094) is a diatribe against the fear of death,

    taking as its starting point the preceding demonstration that death is simply

    annihilation. To fear a future state of death, Lucretius argues, is to make the

    conceptual blunder of supposing yourself present to regret and bewail your own

    non-existence. The reality is that being dead will be no worse (just as it will be no

    better) than it was, long ago, not yet to have been born. This Lucretian symmetry

    argument (see Warren 2004; also Death 2.3), which has enjoyed widespread

    discussion in the recent philosophical literature on death, is found in company with

    a whole battery of further arguments for acquiescing in the prospect of one's own

    dissolution. Book 4's treatment of sex (1037-1287) includes a matching diatribe,

    denouncing and deriding the folly of enslavement to sexual passion (1121-1191).

    The proem to book 2 extols the Epicurean life of detached tranquillity, portrayed as

    maintaining modest and easily satisfied appetites while shunning lofty ambitions

    and the disquiet these inevitably bring in their wake. And the proem to book 6, in

    praising the city of Athens for the gifts of civilisation, adds that these are,

    nevertheless, dwarfed by that city's greatest gift to mankind, Epicurus and his

    philosophy. For it is Epicurus alone who has made life genuinely worth living, not

    only by releasing us from the torment of fear but also by teaching us how to

    moderate our desires to the point where we can enjoy their genuine and lasting

    satisfaction. Lucretius' entire history of civilisation in book 5 (1011-1457) can be

    read as strengthening this same motif (cf. Furley 1978): civilization has advanced

    because of man's desire to better his lot, but to no avail, because every advance

    eliminates one source of grief only to replace it with another. The root cause of our

    troubles lies elsewhere, Lucretius is implying, and, even after civilization had

    reached its peak, it remained for Epicurus to bring that cause to light.

    The Epicurean fourfold cure (tetrapharmakos) read: God holds no fears, death no

    worries. Good is easily attainable, evil easily endurable. The first three of these

    maxims are fully represented by the poem's moral commentary, but the fourth is

    curiously absent. How was evil to be endured? Epicurus' recipe for accepting pain

    with equanimity lay in such strategies as concentrating the mind on past pleasures,

  • and, where the pain was terminally severe, on its imminent eclipse by the painless

    state of death. Although this recipe has not always impressed Epicurus' modern

    interpreters, it was widely and admiringly quoted by his ancient followers and

    sympathizers. It is hard to believe that Lucretius, with his deep understanding of

    Epicurean ethics, did not plan to rectify its glaring omission from his poem. If he

    did so plan, the obvious place to incorporate the final maxim of the canon would

    have been in connection with the frightful sufferings in the great Athenian plague,

    horrifyingly described in the poem's closing verses. Those who believe that the

    poem is unfinished, and that Lucretius had he lived would have developed or

    restructured its final part, may justifiably suspect that the possibility of good cheer

    and optimism in the face of pain was the motif that he was saving for that role,

    wherever and however he might eventually have chosen to work it in.

    6. Religion

    Lucretius presents Epicurus' chief achievement as the defeat of religio. Although

    this Latin word is correctly translated into English as religion, its literal meaning

    is binding down, and it therefore serves Lucretius as a term, not for all attitudes

    of reverence towards the divine, but for those which cow people's spirits, rather

    than, as he thinks such attitudes should, elevate them to a joyful state of

    tranquillity.

    Epicurus had insisted on the existence of the gods, but the mode of existence he

    attributed to them has become a matter of controversy. They have only quasi-

    bodies, for example, and are constituted by nothing more than the wafer-thin and

    lightning-fast images (Latin simulacra, see above 4) which according to

    Epicurus enter our eyes and minds to become the stuff of vision, imagination and

    dreams. Some scholars take this constitution out of simulacra to describe a highly

    attenuated mode of biological being which somehow makes the immortal gods an

    exception to the rule that compounds must eventually disintegrate, so that they are

    able to live on forever, not in any world like ours (since all worlds must themselves

    eventually perish) but in the much safer regions between worlds. Others, who

    doubt such a realist interpretation, take the reduction of gods to simulacra to be

    Epicurus' way of saying that these immortal beings are our own intuitive thought-

    constructs, our personal idealizations of the ideally tranquil life to which we

    naturally aspire, and that he is not committed to the further view that such beings

    must actually exist as living organisms somewhere in the universe. Epicurus'

    recorded instruction to think of god as a blessed and immortal being does not help

    us choose between the two readings. It would probably be a mistake to assume that

    any text or texts of Epicurus were available to resolve the ambiguity definitively,

    similar ambiguities being an endemic characteristic of much religious discourse

    (the most famous case in antiquity was Plato's account of the creation in

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/lucretius/#Phy

  • his Timaeus, on whose interpretation his followers never agreed despite possessing

    his entire works). Lucretius shows signs of assuming the realist view of the gods

    (2.153-4, 6.76-7), yet his account of the origin of religion (5.1169-82) leans more

    towards the idealist reading. Disappointingly, the actual exposition of the gods'

    nature that he promises us (5.155) never materializes. One may wonder whether he

    ever located in his massive Epicurean source the explicit account of the gods' mode

    of being that he was expecting to find there.

    Either way, what is not in doubt is that the gods' role as moral ideals is paramount

    in the Epicurean system. And this is the function Lucretius too gives them,

    especially in the proems to books 1, 3, 5 and 6. The gods live a supremely tranquil

    life, never disquieted by either favour or anger towards us. By contemplating them

    as they truly are we can aspire to achieve that same blissful state within the

    confines of a human lifespan. But Lucretius adds another dimension to this

    theology: for as the poem progresses Epicurus himself is increasingly presented as

    a god. In itself this apotheosis is probably consistent with Epicurean theology:

    Epicurus did after all attain the same morally paradigmatic status which

    characterizes the gods. But in the proem to book 5 Epicurus is permitted to go

    beyond this paradigmatic role, and to become a heroic benefactor of mankind.

    Here Lucretius follows a trend which had gathered pace after Epicurus' own day,

    the rationalistic practice associated with the name of Euhemerus of

    explaining the gods as pioneering human benefactors whose service had been

    institutionally acknowledged by formal divinization. What Lucretius effectively

    asserts is that, on a Euhemeristic ranking, Epicurus is a far greater god than Ceres

    or Bacchus, held to have originally been the institutors of, respectively, agriculture

    and wine, and also a far greater god than the divinized Hercules. For Hercules rid

    the world merely of literal monsters like the Hydra, but it's not as if there aren't

    plenty of wild beasts left in the world to terrorize us today. Epicurus on the other

    hand has offered us real and permanent salvation from monsters, namely those

    truly frightful monsters that haunt our souls, such as insatiable desires, fears, and

    arrogance.

    Another possibly Euhemerizing tendency, one that is an unsurprising feature of

    Latin poetry and, if only for that reason, to be found in the pages of Lucretius, is

    the use of gods' names to designate items of special significance for human life,

    such as Venus for love or sex, and Bacchus for wine. At 2.598-660 Lucretius

    discusses the religious portrayal of Earth as divine mother, and concludes

    that if one is going to call sea Neptune, corn Ceres, wine Bacchus, etc. as

    he himself indeed often enough does one might reasonably also personify the

    earth as their mother, hence as mother of the gods. But, he adds in an important

    codicil, this usage is permissible only if one avoids the pernicious religious beliefs

    that such locutions imply.

  • The proems are the most original poetic compositions in the DRN, and one may

    suspect that the book 5 proem's brand of Euhemerizing theology goes beyond

    traditional Epicureanism. The same suspicion recurs with even greater force when

    we focus on the proem to book 1. In it Lucretius prays to Venus, not only as the

    universal life force but also as ancestress of the Romans, begging her to intervene

    with her lover Mars and save the troubled Roman republic from civil strife.

    Although this choice of motif may owe much to Lucretius' forerunner and model

    Empedocles, for whom Love or Aphrodite is the great creative force in the cosmos,

    it borders perilously on a betrayal of the poem's central motif, that we should not

    fear the gods because they do not, and never would, intervene in our world.

    Readers, as they progress further into the poem, are no doubt expected to

    accumulate the appropriate materials for understanding the proem as in tune with

    the true Epicurean message, but there is little agreement as to how this is meant to

    be achieved. One possibility is as follows. The warlike Mars is not, as such, a true

    Epicurean god, but a popular perversion of the true divine nature, resulting from

    people's projection of their own angry and competitive temperament onto this ideal

    being. If so, the prayer for Venus to pacify Mars is no more than the expressed

    hope that Romans will return to appreciating the true peaceful nature of divinity,

    which for an Epicurean like Lucretius is nothing different from their themselves

    striving to emulate this paradigm of peacefulness. The poem's lesson will itself, if

    successfully taught to its Roman audience, be enough to answer its author's

    opening prayer.

    7. Influence

    Lucretius was both admired and imitated by writers of the early Roman empire,

    and in the eyes of Roman patristic thinkers like Lactantius he came to be the

    leading spokesman of the godless Epicurean philosophy. His poem subsequently

    survived in two 9th-century manucripts (known as O and Q), which upon their

    rediscovery by Poggio Bracciolini in 1417 became the basis of the Renaissance

    editions. It was through Lucretius, along with the Latin translation of Diogenes

    Laertius' Life of Epicurus, that Epicurean ideas entered the main philosophical

    (especially ethical) debates of the age. However, despite his extensive impact in

    literary and philosophical circles he is, for example, among the writers most

    assiduously cited by Montaigne Lucretius struggled for two centuries to shake

    off the pejorative label of atheist. He became a key influence on the emergence of

    early modern atomism in the 17th century a development above all due to Pierre

    Gassendi's construction of an atomistic system which, while founded on Epicurus

    and Lucretius, had been so modified as to be acceptable to Christian ideology.

    Bibliography

  • Editions

    Bailey, C., 1947, Titi Lucreti Cari De Rerum Natura Libri Sex, 3 vols.,

    Oxford: Oxford University Press. (Monumental edition, with translation and

    commentary).

    Brown, P.M., 1984, Lucretius: De Rerum Natura I, Bristol: Bristol Classical

    Press.

    Brown, R.D., 1987, Lucretius on Love and Sex. A Commentary on De

    Rerum Natura IV, 1030-1287, with Prolegomena, Text and Translation,

    Leiden: Brill.

    Campbell, G., 2003, Lucretius on Creation and Evolution. A Commentary

    on De Rerum Natura Book Five Lines 772-1104, Oxford: Oxford University

    Press.

    Costa, C.D.N., 19984, Lucretius De Rerum Natura V, Oxford: Clarendon

    Press.

    Ernout, A., Robin, L., 1962, Lucrce, De rerum natura, commentaire

    exgtique et critique, 2nd edn., Paris.

    Fowler, D., 2002. Lucretius on Atomic Motion. A Commentary on De Rerum

    Natura 2.1-332, Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Godwin, J., 1986. Lucretius: De Rerum Natura IV. Warminster: Aris and

    Phillips.

    , 1991. Lucretius: De Rerum Natura VI. Warminster: Aris and Phillips.

    Kenney, E.J., 1981, Lucretius: De Rerum Natura Book III, Cambridge:

    Cambridge University Press.

    Smith, M.F. 1975, Lucretius, De Rerum Natura, with an English

    translation by W.H.D. Rouse, revised with new text, introduction, notes and

    index (Loeb Classical Library), London and Cambridge, Mass.

    Translations

    See Bailey and Smith, above. Also:

    Englert, W., 2003, Lucretius, On the Nature of Things. Newburyport, Mass.:

    Focus.

    Latham, R.E. and Godwin, J., 1994, Lucretius, On the Nature of the

    Universe, Harmondsworth: Penguin.

    Melville, Sir Ronald, 1997, Lucretius, On the Nature of the Universe, with

    introduction and notes by D. and P. Fowler, Oxford: Clarendon Press.

    Smith, M.F., 2001, Lucretius, On the Nature of Things. Indianapolis and

    Cambridge, Hackett.

    Commentaries

  • Algra, K.A., Koenen, M.H., Schrijvers, P.H. (eds.), 1997, Lucretius and his

    Intellectual Background, Amsterdam: Royal Netherlands Academy of Arts

    and Sciences.

    Asmis, E., 1983, Rhetoric and Reason in Lucretius, American Journal of

    Philology 104: 36-66.

    Bright, D.F., 1971, The plague and the structure of the De rerum

    natura, Latomus 30: 607-32.

    Classen, C.J. (ed.), 1986, Probleme der Lukrezforschung, Hildesheim:

    Olms.

    Clay, D., 1983, Lucretius and Epicurus. Ithaca, Cornell University Press.

    Commager, H.S. Jr., 1957, Lucretius interpretation of the

    plague, Harvard Studies in Classical Philology 62: 105-21.

    Dalzell, A., 1972-3, 1973-4, A Bibliography of Work on Lucretius,1945-

    1972, Classical World 66: 389-427; 67: 65-112.

    De Lacy, P., 1948, Lucretius and the history of

    Epicureanism, Transactions of the Americal Philological Association 79:

    12-35.

    Edwards, M.J., 1989, Lucretius, Empedocles and Epicurean

    polemic, Antike und Abendland 35: 104-15.

    Fowler, D. 1989, Lucretius and politics, in M. Griffin, J. Barnes,

    (eds.), Philosophia Togata, Oxford, Oxford University Press: 120-50.

    Furley, D.J. 1966, Lucretius and the Stoics, Bulletin of the Institute of

    Classical Studies 13: 13-33; reprinted in Furley Cosmic

    Problems, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press, 1989:183-205.

    , 1978, Lucretius the Epicurean: on the history of man, Entretiens

    Hardt 24: 1-37; reprinted in Furley Cosmic Problems, Cambridge,

    Cambridge University Press, 1989: 206-22.

    Gale, M. 1994, Myth and Poetry in Lucretius, Cambridge, Cambridge

    University Press.

    , 2001, Lucretius and the Didactic Epic, London: Bristol Classical Press.

    , (ed.) 2007, Oxford Readings in Classical Studies: Lucretius, Oxford,

    Oxford University Press.

    Gillespie, S. and Hardie, P. (eds.) 2007, The Cambridge Companion to

    Lucretius, Cambridge, Cambridge University Press.

    Godwin, J., 2004, Lucretius, London: Bristol Classical Press.

    Gordon, C., 1962, A Bibliography of Lucretius, London: Hart-Davis.

    Hadzits, G.D., 1935, Lucretius and his Influence, London: Longman.

    Holmes, B., 2005, Daedala lingua: crafted speech in De rerum

    natura, American Journal of Philology 126: 527-85.

    Hutchinson, G., The date of De rerum natura, Classical Quarterly 51

    (2001): 150-62.

  • Johnson, W. R., 2000, Lucretius and the Modern World. London:

    Duckworth.

    Jones, H., 1989, The Epicurean Tradition. London and New York:

    Routledge.

    Kennedy, D., 2002, Rethinking Reality. Lucretius and the Textualization of

    Nature, Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Kleve, K., 1978, The philosophical polemics in Lucretius, Entretiens

    Hardt 24: 39-71.

    Kollman, E.D., 1971, Lucretius criticism of the early Greek

    philosophers, Studi Classici 13: 79-93.

    Konstan, D., 1973, Some Aspects of Epicurean Psychology. Leiden: Brill.

    Miller, J. and Inwood, B. (eds.), 2003. Hellenistic and Early Modern

    Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Nussbaum, M.C., 1994. The Therapy of Desire: Theory and Practice in

    Hellenistic Ethics. Princeton: Princeton University Press.

    Reinhardt, T., 2002, The speech of nature in Lucretius De Rerum

    Natura 3.931-71, Classical Quarterly 52: 291-304 .

    Rsler, W., 1973, Lukrez und die Vorsokratiker: doxographische Probleme

    im 1. Buch von De rerum natura,Hermes 101: 48-64.

    Schiesaro, A., 1990, Simulacrum et Imago: Gli argomenti analogici nel De

    rerum natura, Pisa: Giardini.

    Schrijvers, P.H., 1999, Lucrce et les sciences de la vie. (Mnemosyne

    supplementum) Leiden: Brill.

    Sedley, D., 1998, Lucretius and the Transformation of Greek Wisdom,

    Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Segal, C., 1990, Lucretius on Death and Anxiety, Princeton: Princeton

    University Press.

    Serres, M., 2000, The Birth of Physics (originally La Naissance de la

    physique dans le texte de Lucrce, 1977), Manchester: Clinamen Press.

    Tatum, W.J., 1984, The Presocratics in book one of Lucretius De rerum

    natura, Transactions of the American Philological Association 114: 177-

    89.

    Wardy, R., 1988, Lucretius on what atoms are not, Classical Philology 83:

    112-28.

    Warren, J., 2001, Lucretian palingenesis recycled, Classical Quarterly 51:

    499-508.

    , 2004, Facing Death: Epicurus and his Critics, Oxford: Oxford

    University Press.

    West, D., 1969, The Imagery and Poetry of Lucretius, Edinburgh:

    Edinburgh Press.

    , 1975, Lucretius methods of argument (3. 417-614), Classical

    Quarterly 25: 94-116.

  • Wiseman, T.P.,1974, The Two Worlds of Titus Lucretius Carus, in Cinna

    the Poet and Other Roman Essays, Leicester, Leicester University Press: 11-

    43.

    Other Internet Resources

    On the Nature of Things, A complete translation of Lucretius' poem, by

    W.E. Leonard, MIT.

    Leeds International Classical Studies, refereed articles on Lucretius.

    Related Entries

    Empedocles | Epicurus | Gassendi, Pierre | Montaigne, Michel de

    Copyright 2008 by

    David Sedley

    http://classics.mit.edu/Carus/nature_things.1.i.htmlhttp://www.leeds.ac.uk/classics/lics/themes.html#Lucretiushttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/empedocles/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epicurus/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/gassendi/http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/montaigne/http://plato.stanford.edu/info.html#cmailto:dns1%40cam.ac.uk