Metaphor and Space

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    1/24

    Metaphor and Space

    Franson ManjaliJawaharlal Nehru University,

    New Delhi

    1. Spatial models

    Along with the decline of the logicist paradigms, there has been

    increasing reference to spatial modeling and schemata in contemporary

    linguistics and semiotics. Perhaps, it is the need to rescue linguistic, and

    particularly, meaning analysis from the obscurely mentalist accounts, and

    to give it a physicalist or materialist orientation that has prompted such a

    shift towards spatiality. Parallelly, scholars have shied away from the

    definition of language as an abstract system consisting of arbitrary

    symbols and the rules of their computation. The semiotic field is no longer

    the container or the expresser of some otherwise indecipherable logical

    entities or processes, but it can henceforth be, so to say, stretched out on

    the ground in plain daylight. Language, which according to Saussures

    original idea, was analogically the substratum to which other cultural

    discourses could be compared and thus studied, now had to submit itself

    to an abstract or real space in order to render its structure clear. The

    guiding principle here is that by taking recourse to spatiality, the symbolic

    structure can be exteriorized. Consequently, The pre-symbolic base of the

    symbolic level is taken to be constituted of the spatial dimension.

    Further, in contrast to the mentalist approaches of the type followed byNoam Chomsky, which insisted on an uncompromising universalism, the

    spatial analyses were amenable to culturally specific accounts, while

    retaining for themselves the factum of the universality of space.

    What Hjelmslev called the localist hypothesis in grammatical theory,

    especially with reference to the debates within nineteenth century

    German scholarship (Hjelmslev, 1935; see Manjali, 1991 for a brief

    summary of the relevant sections of this work), seems to have returnedas the methodological principle of spatialization of form in the second

    1

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    2/24

    half of the twentieth century. Lucien Tesnire in his proposal for an

    actantial theory of syntactic structure, had suggested that the

    syntactico-semantic part of sentences could be viewed as a vitalistic little

    drama, characterised by a theatre-like, and hence, anthropomorphic

    performers or actants and context-defining circumstants. Edward Sapir

    had proposed a similar actantial and localistic model of sentence-

    structure.1 In the more recent American context, the spatialisation of

    form principle has been more seriously followed by Charles Fillmore,

    Ronald Langacker and Len Talmy.

    The localist-actantial theory has been submitted to rigorous

    mathematical-topological formalisation in the works of the French

    scientists Ren Thom and Jean Petitot. Proceeding from Thomscatastrophe-theoretical modelling, Petitot in his Morphognse du sens

    (1985)goes on to propose a Kantian-type of schematisation of linguistic

    and semiotic structures. In developing structur-alism as a cognitive theory

    of morphodynamics, Petitot has also reinforced Gilles Deleuzes idea

    that structures are essentially topological and relational, that is, even

    before they are filled with any specific content. What is assumed in this

    approach is an isomorphism between the dynamics of the rational

    interiority of the human mind and the physical dynamics of the externalworld.

    2. Iconicity and motivation

    In order to understand the fundaments of the spatialisation project it is

    perhaps useful to take recourse, via Roman Jakobson, to Charles Sanders

    Peirces Semiotic. The latter being a semiotics that subsists our logical

    understanding of the natural world, eschews Saussures imperative of alinguistic mediation between the nebulous thought and the equally

    chaotic reality of the world by the system of discrete signs. At the top

    of Peirces ternarian hierarchy, signs are divided into icons, indexes and

    symbols. These are characterised by relations of factual similarity,

    1 Discussed by Roman Jakobson in Quest for the Essence of Language, SelectedWritings Vol. II, p. 351. Such models, especially the actantial ones, have an historicalantecedent in the work of the 6th century Indian philosopher of language, Bhartrhari

    (see Manjali, 2000). According to Bhartrhari, sentence meaning is comprehended as aunified whole, like a picture.

    2

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    3/24

    factual, existential contiguity, and imputed and learned contiguity

    respectively between the signifier and the signified (or, representamen

    and object in Peirces terms). In the symbol, its two parts are connected

    by a conventional rule. Peirce avers that these are not names of pure

    sign-types, but are indications of certain predominant tendencies within

    each. These tendencies may and do exist as combinations in any given

    sign, including the linguistic sign. Jakobson notes in this context that

    according to Peirce the most perfect signs are those in which the iconic,

    the indexical and the symbolic characters are blended as equally as

    possible. (Jakobson, Quest, p. 349)

    Equally important for our discussion is Peirces further division of icons

    into images, diagrams and metaphors. As per his definitions, the imagesare icons which partake of simple qualities...; the diagrams are those

    which represent relations, mainly dyadic, or so regarded, of the parts of

    one thing by analogous relations in their parts; and the metaphors are

    those which represent the representative character of a representamen

    by representing a parallelism in something else. (see Hiraga, 1994, p. 6,

    fn.)

    Thus, the specific properties characterising the three types of icons arequalitative imitation, structural analogy and imputed parallelism

    respectively. The images and the diagrams will have some objective

    correspondence between the representamen / signifier and the object /

    signified, while in the case of the metaphor-icons, the correspondence

    may be perceptually or experientially constituted on the basis of a

    parallelism. Peircean units seem to form a continuum starting from those

    having a maximum of objective correspondence between the object and

    the spatial / temporal form of the representamen as in the case of theimage, and ending with the arbitrary or law-like symbol, where such a

    correspondence is almost absent. In this continuum, the metaphor

    occupies a somewhat middle position, the nature of the correspondence

    here being a parallelism that is subjectively felt. The iconicity of the

    metaphor is thus part-objective, part-subjective. I.e.,

    Obj. ICON (IMAGE, DIAGRAM, METAPHOR) INDEX SYMBOLSubj.

    pole pole

    3

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    4/24

    Peircean semiotics is thus directly amenable to a spatial perspective. The

    icon and the index with the similarity and contiguity principles that govern

    them, are clearly signs that subscribe to a spatial dimension. So are the

    two subtypes of icons, viz., images and diagrams. And when it comes to

    the metaphors as the third subtype of icon, Peirce refers us to a quasi-

    spatial notion of parallelism. Only the symbol, among the first five type

    of signs stands apart as primarily based on arbitrariness / convention

    (law). Even these are not exempt from being iconically or indexically

    conditioned.

    Saussure addresses the problem of the natural or conventional

    relationship between the signifier and signified, not by way of a typology

    of signs la Peirce, but in terms of two principles, motivation andarbitrariness, the latter being the dominant one. Since signs, individually

    or in combinations, are all arbitrary (except for odd instances of sound-

    symbolism and onomatopoeia), according to Saussure, they do not

    resemble anything outside of language.2 Now, Jakobson, in his Quest

    essay, makes it amply clear that iconicity or motivation can be attested

    not only at the level of unitary signs, but also at the level of syntax and

    morphology. Saussure himself was acutely aware of this issue,

    introducing it under the heading Absolute and Relative Arbitrariness inhis Cours de linguistique gnrale. Though he favours the fundamental

    principle of the arbitrariness of the sign, he insists on the limits of

    arbitrariness. As he outlines the problem:

    ...the whole system of language is based on the irrational principle

    of the arbitrariness of the sign, which would lead to the worst sort of

    complication if applied without restriction. But the mind contrives to

    introduce a principle oforder and regularityinto certain parts of themass of signs, and this is the role of relative motivation. (Course, p.

    133) (italics added)

    In any given language, though some signs (most of which appear to be

    individual ones) may be absolutely arbitrary, other signs (which may

    appear in sign-combinations) can be spoken of only in terms of degrees

    of arbitrariness. Signs can be radically or relatively arbitrary, and

    2

    Though Saussure does not admit any direct extra-systemic similarity between thesignifier and the signified, he accepts a principle of analogy working within thelanguage system. The latter renders possible paradigms of (similarly) significant forms.

    4

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    5/24

    individual languages may combine these two (sub-)principles in

    unpredictable ways:

    There is no language in which nothing is motivated, and our

    definition makes it impossible to conceive of a language in which

    everything is motivated. Between the two extremes a minimum of

    organization and a minimum of arbitrariness we find all possible

    varieties. Diverse languages always include elements of both

    portions that vary greatly... (ibid., p. 133)

    The weight of evidence in favour of the new principle of relative

    motivation is indeed strong. Providing us with useful lexical and syntactic

    examples, Saussure states that one can speak of relative motivationwhenever a sign can be syntagmatically analysed into parts, and any of

    the part/s thus obtained can be associatively compared with other signs

    (of the same system). His well-known example in this regard is the

    opposition between vingtand dix-neuf. The former is radically arbitrary

    and the latter, because of the associations its two components, dix and

    neuf have with other words in the system of the French language, e.g.,

    dix-huitand vingt-neuf,is relatively arbitrary / motivated.

    Let us follow Saussures argument more closely. Language is made up of

    discrete signs, which owing to fact that they emerge from collective

    behaviour or by convention, acquire the irrational principle of

    arbitrariness, according to which there cannot be any natural connection

    between the signifier and the signified. The limited or partial motivation

    that the system of language has is due to our minds contriving to

    introduce a principle oforder and regularity. And this is so because, the

    mechanism of language is but a partial correction of a system that is bynature chaotic. Saussure seems to be saying this: Because language

    arises due to convention, it possesses an irrational principle of

    arbitrariness, which makes it naturally chaotic. In other words, languages

    being conventional gives it a chaotic nature. Mind introduces an order on

    it by reducing its arbitrariness, and making it partially motivated. It is

    because of the minds action that there are natural connections between

    some signifiers and the corresponding signifieds. Mind organizes the vast

    5

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    6/24

    and chaotic array of arbitrary signs into a relatively well-ordered system

    of language by means of the classical (Aristotelian) principle of analogy.3

    Without paying much heed to Saussures explanation of relative

    motivation in morphology and syntax in terms of the syntagmatic and

    associative axes of language, a method presumably forced on him by the

    linear and systemic character of language, Jakobson adopts a Peircean

    approach to the problem. True to the Peircean categories, Jakobson

    renames the Saussurean problem of relative motivation as the problem

    of iconicity in language.4 More precisely, in terms of the diagram-icon.

    And, correspondingly, he restates the problem as a problem of parts and

    wholes within a syntagmatically analysable sign-unit:

    Not only the combination of words into syntactic groups but also the

    combination of morphemes into words exhibits a clear-cut

    diagrammatic character. Both in syntax and morphology any

    relation of parts and wholes agrees with Peirces definition of

    diagrams and their iconic nature. (Quest, p. 352)

    Following Peirce and Jakobson, but in contradistinction to Saussure,5

    contemporary Cognitive Linguistics tends to see iconicity in sentencestructures. Consequently, even a correspondence between the order of

    the elements in a sentence, and that of the things / events in the

    referential world can be taken as a case of (diagrammatic) iconicity.

    Jakobsons famous example in this regard are Julius Caesars words Veni,

    vidi, vici, which reflect the order of the emperors deeds. This

    3 What Saussure is saying amounts to this: Individual signs which arise from collective

    behaviuor and established by convention may be arbitrary in the sense of not havingany natural connection between the signifier and the signified. But as part of a systemof signs, the originally arbitrary signs have been subjected, at least partially, to somesort of analogical ordering by the action of mind. Here, as elsewhere in the Course, theeconomic metaphor might be at work: individual notes or coins may be arbitrary inrealtion to thier monetary value, but within a particular currency system, there is boundto be an analogical ordering based on the size of the notes, or the weight of the coins.Higher the denomination, greater the size of the notes, or the weight of the coins.4 In contemporary Cognitive Linguistics, the Jakobsonian term iconicity is widelyaccepted.

    5

    Saussure takes most sentences, except the formula ones, to be a unit ofspeech(parole), and not of the language system (langue).

    6

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    7/24

    correspondence in order between the signans and the signatum is

    regarded as a good enough principle of iconicity in Cognitive Linguistics.

    Now, we should note here that principle of analogy invoked by Saussure

    for accounting for the limitation of arbitrariness and the notion of

    diagrammatic iconicity suggested by Peirce and Jakboson are indeed

    parallel and conceptually proximate. Their difference is that whereas, the

    diagram, owing to its iconicity can function either within or without a

    system of signs, analogy lacks a direct and referential iconicity and

    suggests a parallelism that is merely system-internal. Thus the relative

    motivation in morphology or syntactic structure, is strictly speaking,

    analogical and not diagrammatic.

    This iconicity principle has been used extensively by George Lakoff and

    Mark Johnson in their accounts of what they call the conceptual

    metaphors. Lakoff and Johnson have argued that metaphors are not just

    linguistic entities or categories, but are in fact conceptual in nature. They

    claim that metaphors partially structure our everyday concepts and that

    this structure is reflected in our literal language (quoted in MacCormac,

    1985: 57). The preponderance of metaphors in language use dead,

    conventional, fresh, or poetic and the systematic and networkedrelations among them suggest that metaphors are not just a matter of

    linguistic play, but are indeed the manner in which human beings conduct

    their thought or conceptualize. Metaphor is thus a universally prevalent

    and pre-eminent cognitive process. These conceptual metaphors, they

    further claim, function on the basis of iconicity, that is, their creation and

    use involve bodily experienced or perceived similarity, between items or

    events in the world. Further, in the creation of metaphors, they assume a

    clearly discernible directionality: they proceed from domains that aremore concrete and more immediate to those that are less concrete or

    abstract. Thus, they also conclude that our body is the ultimate and the

    most primitive resource of our more abstract perceptual and conceptual

    constructions. They also emphasize the importance of schemas derived

    from the structure and the basic functions and activities of the human

    body. Experientially-constituted image-schemas based on the structure

    and basic actions of our body are at the root of our complex and abstract

    thought.

    7

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    8/24

    According to Johnson our very basic and very complex range of bodily

    experiences... occurring at [the] experiential and pre-linguistic level

    results in the embodiment of meaning, which provides a semantic basis

    for linguistic forms, meaning and the structure of speech acts. (Johnson,

    1992: 348) Lakoff and Johnsons basic argument runs as follows. Primitive

    bodily experience gives rise to the image-schemas with their iconic

    quality, play structuring role in our cognition and language. Thus, our

    cognition, language and other social practices bear definite traces of the

    bodily image-schemas. Even most of our new experiences and novel use

    of language are coloured by these traces. Owing to their iconic or image-

    schematic character of these traces, which in turn is a basic part of our

    cognitive processes, their linguistic manifestation at the syntactic,

    semantic or pragmatic levels of language should be thought aswidespread occurrence of conceptual metaphors. Thus, even the literal

    language is suffused with metaphors, which are not dead, but which come

    alive every time the latent conceptual metaphors are again put to work.

    Poetic metaphors are only further creative extensions of this inexorable

    (bodily and iconically rooted) metaphoricity in thought and language.

    3. The classical approach: imitation and metaphor

    Let us delve deeper into the problem. In Platos well-known dialogue,

    Cratylus, we find Socrates at first agreeing with Cratylus naturalist view

    on the origin and nature of language. Socrates argues that at the origin of

    language, a hypothetical name-giver must have employed some sort of

    sound-symbolism in order to arrive at the right names for things, just as

    the painter or the musician would employ the right forms and colours or

    the right sounds to undertake their respective artistic activities, with

    natural correctness. As Socrates puts it, the name-giver must have

    created:

    by letters and syllables a sign and a name for each and every thing,

    and from those names he compounds all the rest by imitation.

    The examples of such sound-symbolism that Socrates provides us with

    are indeed instructive. The consonantal sound r is (naturally) appropriate

    as an excellent instrument for the expression of motion (many Greekwords relating to motion containing this sound) because the tongue is

    8

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    9/24

    least agitated and least at rest in pronunciation of this letter. He gives

    similar natural reasons for the use of other consonants to express some

    primitive meaning essences: the sibilants and fricatives whose

    pronunciation is accompanied by a great expenditure of breath are used

    for imitating windiness involved in shivering, seething, shock, etc.; the

    closing and pressure of the tongue in the utterance of d and t is

    expressive of binding and rest in a place; liquid movement of l, in the

    pronunciation of which the tongue slip, and in this he found in this he

    found the expression of smoothness. And as for vowels, Socrates

    mentions o, which [is] the sign of roundness...

    Now, what is remarkable in these Socratic assertions, is not just the fact

    of imitation by sound, but indeed it is the specific character of theimitation. r imitates motion because of the agitation of the tongue, and its

    lack of rest. The windiness of the sibilants and the fricatives imitates

    the rapid expiration involved in emotions like shock, anger, etc. These

    imitations involve certain rhythmic or steady movement of the tongue in

    time, and are therefore appropriate for imitating events or actions that

    have a sudden temporal / dynamic character. As a converse ofr, closing

    and pressure of the tongue in d and t, imitates rest in a place. Here a

    certain steady spatial posture of the tongue imitates a state of rest. Andsimilarly, and perhaps more apparently, the rounded shape of the mouth

    while pronouncing o, which is also imitated in the shape of the Greek

    letter o,is naturally appropriate for imitating the corresponding sound o!

    It is really not just a case of a sound that imitates the meaning, but rather

    it is the shape of the mouth-orifice while producing a particular sound that

    mimics the meaning. A particular sound has acquired a corresponding

    symbolic meaning, because there is a mimetic relationship between the

    spatial (and temporal) mode of articulating the sound and a certain(spatial and temporal) essence of the thing referred to. The iconicity

    here is indeed that of the bodily, i.e., the oral, gesture. One may add here

    that the view pertaining to oral iconicity put forward by Socrates in quasi-

    defence of Cratylus naturalism, if stretched to its impossible logical

    conclusion, would indeed seem to threaten the much avowed structuralist

    principle of double articulation. But this does not happen because any

    natural connection that may exist between a sound and its manner of

    articulation on the one hand and the corresponding meaning on the other,

    9

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    10/24

    is progressively attenuated by means of analogy, metaphorization and

    compounding in the larger discursive process.

    (The same phenomenon of bodily mimesis can be attested elsewhere too.

    For example, it has been noted by the present author that the syllable

    mu which involves, in its articulation, a protrusion and near-closure of

    the lips is present word-initially in the Malayalam language in a number

    words that contain the signification of pointed or sharp angularity, e.g. the

    point of a knife, thorn, breast, corner, etc. Here again, it is the shape of

    the mouth and by extension the corresponding sound that imitates the

    shape an essence of the thing denoted.)

    If Socrates intuition in this respect is correct, then unlike in painting ormusic, immediate and intimate resources of the body are employed in

    linguistic imitation. Language, or naming involves, according to Socrates,

    a natural kind of action for imitating the essences of things. This

    imitation, he thinks, is different from the imitation in music and painting,

    which have to imitate only the sounds (in the former) and the form and

    the colours (in the latter) pertaining to events or objects in the world.

    Here, we notice that even when Socrates perceives a difference between

    the artistic imitation in such arts as music and painting, which is a kind ofform-to-form imitation (where both the forms can be located in the

    spatial or temporal dimension) and the (art of ) linguistic imitation which

    involves an imitation of the essences of things by sounds, while speaking

    of the latter, he actually reduces these so-called essences to their spatial

    or temporal forms, which are in turn imitated by the manner of

    articulation of the speech sounds. These essences need not be a priori,

    but are constituted in our encounter with the objects and events, and the

    role of language is only to copy them with the given resources of ourbody. As per this account, at the very basic level linguistic articulation

    begins with mimesis, and language is essentially mimicry.

    (Strictly speaking, we notice that Socrates is concerned with two kinds of

    imitation in language, which correspond to the generic distinction

    between music and painting. For instance, when the sound r imitates

    motion, the type of imitation may be referred to as that involving a

    certain temporal-rhythmicity, because it is the rhythmic movement

    occurring in time that is imitated by the articulation of the sound r.

    10

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    11/24

    Whereas, when the sound o imitates roundness, the imitation may be

    that of a spatial-figurative kind.)

    What is significant about this account of mimicry at the origin of language

    is that it is not forced on him by the nature of things. Things do not cause

    imitation. The latter results from the correct matching of a property

    extracted from (the nature of) things and a sound unit extracted from the

    phonetic stream. As such, the initial imitation is neither caused or

    motivated, nor is it random or arbitrary. It is a creative action that man

    performs according to his sense of the fitness of things. The fundamental

    sound symbolism and mimicry is not just a process oriented to an

    objective truth, but rather a proto-sthetic or phonsthetic activity.

    The preceding discussion highlights only Socrates arguments in favour of

    naturalism. Later in the dialogue, he counterposes the thesis for an all-out

    naturalism with the anti-thesis of a strong conventionalism. He argues

    that the conception of natural correctness assumed by the hypothetical

    name-giver, could very well be wrong. And if that is the case, we who

    are his followers and have inherited his conception would also be wrong.

    It is at this point that Socrates distances from a position of strong

    naturalism:

    everyone should expend his chief thought and attention on the

    consideration of first principles:- are they or are they not rightly laid

    down? and when he has duly sifted them, all the rest will follow.

    Thus we see, at the base of language Socrates is arguing for a principle of

    natural correctness rooted in bodily mimicry, oral gesture. But, one may

    discover this principle to be wrongly founded. The historically laterfollowers of the hypothetical name-giver may progressively correct this

    founding principle, or they may introduce more appropriate principles.

    Thus, there would be increasing movement (at least from a historical

    point of view) from nature to convention; from mere natural correctness

    to conventionally constituted truth without relinquishing the materiality

    and corporeality upon which imitation and similarity are predicated.

    The scenario Socrates presents us with is the following. The name-giver

    imitates the specific / assumed essences of things with his bodily / oral

    11

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    12/24

    resources. The recognition of the semantically-appropriate sounds is

    preceded by an analysis of the process of articulation. Articulation of

    sounds is appropriate for the expression of particular essences of things.

    There is a matching between the formal essences of things and the

    sounds at one level, and between the substantive form of the things and

    the manner of articulation at another level. Using Hjelmslevian terms, we

    can say that the first level involves an equivalence between the form of

    content and the form of expression, and the second level involves an

    equivalence between the substance of content and the substance of

    expression. The first results in sound symbolism, and the second in

    mimicry:

    Essence of thing : Imitating sound

    (Sound symbolism)

    (Form of Content) : (Form of expression)

    Thing : Imitative action (Mimicry)

    (Substance of Content) : (Substance of Expression)

    But, such equivalencies may neither be adequate to begin with, nor would

    they hold for everyone and for all eternity. The correctness of the bodily

    and spatially articulated names are unstable. The names may not be

    equivalent to the things. The equivalence may be wrongly conceived by

    the name-giver. The names being given according to the conception of

    the name-giver may be more or less than appropriate to the things. The

    imitation may be more or less adequate. (This is not unlike metaphors,

    which are also signifiers that suggest an exaggeration or a diminution of

    the thing referred to.) In oral imitation or mimicry, the names are already

    distanced from and re-configured in relation to things. They are already

    deviant, tropes. Though there can be more and more of names, more or

    less deviant, Socrates warns us that [h]e who follows names in the

    search of things, and analyses their meaning, is in great danger of being

    deceived. Names can never be entirely true to things.

    Besides, since the first imitation is not a plastic imitation, it is transmitted

    socially from the name-giver to other possible users of language. And

    because naming is imitative action displayed for the benefit of the others,there is a going-beyond of the name from the self to the others. Socrates:

    12

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    13/24

    And if [the name-givers] conception was erroneous, and he gave names

    according to his conception, in what position shall we who are his

    followers find ourselves? Shall we not be deceived by him. But since we

    also have just the same bodily and spatial resources and capacities for

    imitatively creating names, names which are ever-deviant, that is

    metaphors, these names constantly go beyond the things and our own

    selves, in a lateral process that can go on infinitely.

    Perhaps now we are in a position to better appreciate Aristotles

    discussion on imitation and metaphor in Poetics. According to Aristotle,

    imitation and metaphor are two special qualities that man is endowed

    with, and they are described as one of the two causes for the origin of

    poetry (the other is harmony and rhythm), and as the mark of poeticexcellence, respectively.

    Poetry has sprung from two causes, each of them lying deep in our

    nature. First, the instinct of imitation is implanted in man from

    childhood, one difference between him and other animals being that

    he is the most imitative of living creatures, and through imitation he

    learns his earliest lessons; and no less universal is the pleasure felt

    in things imitated. We have evidence for this... Objects which inthemselves we view with pain, we delight when reproduced with

    minute fidelity: such as the forms of the most ignoble animals and

    of dead bodies.

    Thus, in the Aristotelian syllogism implicitly at work here, the instinct of

    imitation is linked with learning. And learning gives man the liveliest

    pleasure. Therefore, Aristotle is able to conclude that men enjoy seeing

    a likeness...

    This likeness returns later when Aristotle discusses metaphor as one of

    the modes of linguistic expression. Metaphor is defined as the application

    of an alien name by transference. Though, poetic excellence generally

    involves observation of propriety in the use of the modes of expression,

    metaphor has a very special status. Here propriety is not the matter of a

    pre-given or natural correctness in the relationship between the signifier

    and the signified. It is that of an aptitude for noting likenesses on the

    13

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    14/24

    basis of which a name originally used for one signified can be transferred

    to another. Of all the poetic qualities, Aristotle notes,

    ...the greatest thing is to have a command of metaphor. This alone

    cannot be imparted by another, it is the mark of genius, for to make

    good metaphor implies an eye for resemblances.

    Thus imitation, which is a natural human instinct, is also an ideal tool for

    learning, and it therefore gives pleasure to all men equally. Whereas the

    poetic metaphor, though it too involves an eye for resemblances, is

    something special, perhaps restricted to those with strong artistic

    sensibility. It is a mark of genius and cannot be learnt by way of

    instruction.6

    4. Embodiment of speech and culture

    Unlike Socrates, for whom iconicity is a matter of spatial or temporal

    form which is imitated by the spatial resources of the body, Maurice

    Merleau-Ponty, a phenomenologist of our own times, views the perceptual

    process as a result of the interaction between a persons body and the

    spatial dimension into which she is thrown from her birth. Merleau-Pontys

    theory of cognition, itself based in the primacy of perception, is informed

    by his principal notions of embodiment, enaction and embeddedness.7 A

    person uses her body as the central point of orientation while perceiving

    and conceptually describing both the space that surrounds her as well as

    the objects that appear in space. There is a continuous going back-and-

    forth between the space outside and the figure-space of the human body,

    which involves a projection of the body of the subject into the world, and

    a corresponding introjection of the world on the subject. The relation

    between body and space, is not to be seen as the relation of interiority

    between an physically-existing body and an objective space in which the

    former is located. Beneath the objective space, there is a spatiality

    which merges with the bodys very being. To be a body, is to be tied to a

    6 In his long and engaging discussion of the role of metaphor in philosophy, Derridaoverlooks the fact that for Aristotle metaphor has simultaneously an aesthetic and an

    aletheic status. See Derrida, J., 1982, pp. 230-45.7 See Varela, F. (1991) for a useful discussion of the relevant issues.

    14

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    15/24

    certain world, our body is not primarily in space: it is of it. (Merleau-

    Ponty, M., Phenomenology of Perception, p. 148)

    Merleau-Ponty insists that this primitive body-image plays a key role in

    our apprehensions of objects in space. Body-image is a way of stating

    that my body is in-the-world. (ibid., p. 101) The presence of body-image

    in this manner is evident in our use of spatial prepositions: When I say

    that the object is onthe table, I always mentally put myself either in the

    table or in the object, and apply to them a category which theoretically

    fits the relationship of my body to eternal objects. Stripped of this

    anthropological association, the word on is indistinguishable from the

    word underor the word beside.(ibid., p. 101)

    According to Merleau-Ponty, body and space are interrelated in two

    important ways. Firstly, a person recognises the spatial unity of her body

    enactively through perception and bodily movement in space. Secondly, a

    persons body for her is not like any other object in the world. It is instead,

    the centre of the world. Space is like an extension or an organic envelope

    of the body which in turn sustains the unity of the body-space system,

    just as the heart sustains (and is sustained by) the body:

    Our own body is in the world as the heart is in the organism: it

    keeps the visible spectacle constantly alive, it breathes life into it

    and sustains it inwardly, and with it forms a system. (p. 203)

    That is why we also understand the spatiality of objects in terms of the

    bodys spatiality. For example, we understand a cube not in terms of its

    purely objective properties arrayed in a disconnected manner, but as a

    fragment of space enclosed between its six equal faces, just as we canexperience ourselves as enclosed between the four walls of a room. (ibid.,

    p. 204)

    The whole philosophy of Merleau-Ponty is characterised by a corporeal

    and perceptual materialism. The experience of body-in-space and the

    inter-relationship between body and its ambient space is the most

    fundamental experience for an individual. A subject experiences the world

    through her body and perception. Further, the body is the affirmation of

    ones existence in the world. This affirmation is expressive in a certain

    15

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    16/24

    field of action formed by the external space and a persons body. (ibid.,

    p. 180) Merleau-Ponty would say, the body expresses existence at every

    moment, just as a word expresses thought, or a poem expresses its

    meaning. It is this capacity of body to be displayed in space, that makes it

    comparable to a work of art, just as in a picture or a piece of the idea is

    incommunicable by means other than the display of colours and sounds.

    (ibid., p. 150)

    Language, according to Merleau-Ponty begins with the bodys (existential)

    expressivity, and in the perception of this expressivity in others.

    Therefore the source of speech is in bodily gesture. The oral organs which

    have other biological functions, are specialised in man for linguistic

    expressivity, giving rise to a more specific oral gesticulation or a kind ofgestural onomatopoeia.8 Thus, in spoken language:

    ... a contraction of the throat, a sibilant emission of air between the

    tongue and teeth, a certain way of bringing the body into play

    suddenly allows itself to be invested with a figurative significance

    which is conveyed outside us. ... For the miracle to come about,

    phonetic gesticulation must use an alphabet of already acquired

    meanings, the word-gesture must be performed in a certain settingcommon to the speakers, just as the comprehension of other

    gestures presupposes a perceived world common to all, in which

    each one develops and spreads out meaning.

    The spoken expression, thus, is not something that can be computed from

    its parts. It stands as a whole, as a relief against the background of the

    speakers body and the surrounding space. It is a gesture in the

    figurative (iconic) as well as the deictic (indexical) sense of the term.

    The spoken word is a genuine gesture, and it contains its meaning

    in the same way as the gesture contains its. (ibid., 183)

    And,

    The spoken word is a gesture, and its meaning, a world. (ibid., p.

    184)

    8 Gill, J.H., 1991: 95.

    16

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    17/24

    Similarly, we understand the speech of others too as gestures, gestures

    again directed to specific tasks in the world. These gestures, Merleau-

    Ponty says, stand on their own, and cannot be reduced to some shared

    and pre-existing intellectual meanings. They too are understood as

    bodys intentionally-oriented responses to tasks in the world. What takes

    place in a verbal gesture is a body-to-body communication in a specific

    spatio-temporal world. The meaning of a gesture thus understood is not

    behind it, it is intermingled with the structure of the world outlined by the

    gesture, and which I take up on my own account. (ibid., p. 186.)

    History of the verbal gestures between individuals, and by extension

    between communities, sets up progressively a common world, and anynovel gesticulations refer to this fund of previous gestures, which function

    like a common spatial world within which every gesture is understood.

    Thus Merleau-Ponty believes that behind the conventional language there

    exists a primary and more direct form of bodily signification, which is

    inter-subjectively recognised. This incarnate significance is the central

    phenomenon of which body and mind, sign and significance are abstract

    moments. (ibid., p. 166) Behind the conceptual and delimiting meaning

    of words, there exists an emotional content of the word, which [is] itsgestural sense, which is all-important in poetry, for example. If this is

    really the case, then words, vowels and phonemes are so may ways of

    singing the world...and their function is to represent things, not as the

    nave onomatopoeic theory would have it, by means of an objective

    resemblance, but because they extract and literally express, their

    emotional essence. (ibid., p. 187)

    Our gestures, including our oral / phonetic gestures have an unmediated,and indirect meaning in the world. It conveys the subjects position in the

    world of meanings, that constitute our mental or cultural life, which

    borrows its structure from the natural life (ibid., p. 193). Thinking

    subject has its basis in an incarnate subject. Further, since the human

    body and its motility in space is responsible for the subjects view of the

    world and for making this view come into existence, the body is also the

    condition of possibility ... of all expressive operations and all acquired

    views which constitute the cultural world. (ibid., p. 388) Now, since the

    expressive gestures take place in ever new spatial and cultural fields,

    17

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    18/24

    speech, especially authentic speech, puts up a new sense. Considering

    that even the acquired significances were once new, Merleau-Ponty claims

    that there is an ultimate fact of this open and indefinite power of giving

    significance that is both of apprehending and conveying a meaning by

    which man transcends towards a new form of behaviour, or towards other

    people, or towards his own thought, through his body and his speech.

    (ibid., p. 194) And this process can tend towards some sort of a cultural

    universal, which is no longer the overarching universal of a strictly

    objective method, but a sort oflateral universal which we acquire through

    ethnological experience and its incessant testing of the self through the

    other person and the other person through the self (Merleau-Ponty,

    Signes, p. 150; Signs p. 120: quoted in Gill, J.H., 1991: 47; emphasis, the

    present authors). Merleau-Pontys other name for this infinitely lateralprocess is dialogue:

    In the experience of dialogue, there is constituted between the

    other person and myself a common ground; my thought and his are

    interwoven into a single fabric (...). We have here a dual being,

    where the other is for me no longer a mere bit of behaviour in my

    transcendental field, nor I in his; we are collaborators for each other

    in consummate reciprocity Our perspectives merge into each other,and we coexist through a common world. In the present dialogue, I

    am freed from myself, for other persons thoughts are certainly

    his... (Phenomenology of Perception, p. 354)

    This dialogue begins early in life with the childs imitation of the (gestural)

    language of the adults in response to tasks for which common results are

    intended. In the process, a whole array of signs is acquired. Now, since

    communication is essentially inter-corporeal, the sedimented meanings ofeach of these signs are less relevant for individuals than the expressive

    effect that the signs can have over and above their permutations and

    combinations in actual speech. Here, what Merleau-Ponty calls the

    speaking speech (as opposed to the cognitively sedimented, spoken

    speech) becomes another layer of expressive gesture, which is like a

    personal or a specific cultural style. This style or perspective is what

    Merleau-Ponty in his unfinished last work, The Visible and the Invisible,

    views as the metaphoric mode. This second layer or reflective style is

    indicative of a certain slacken[ing of] the intentional threads that attach

    18

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    19/24

    us to the world... (ibid., p. xviii). In this slackening, what is otherwise

    opaque becomes visible, and what is visible, is so only through the

    transparency of the style. The first of these movements means that,

    Language can vary and amplify inter-corporeal communication as

    much as we wish: it has the same source and style as the latter.

    Here too, what was secret must become public and almost visible.

    In language, as in inter-corporeal communication, significations

    come through in whole packages, scarcely sustained by a few

    peremptory gestures. (Signes, p. 27)

    And owing to the style or the metaphoric mode, which is also the cultural

    process of slackening:

    The effective, present, ultimate and primary being, the thing in

    itself, are in principle apprehended in transparency through their

    perspectives, offer themselves therefore only to someone who

    wishes not to have them, nor to hold them as with forceps, or to

    immobilise them as under the lens of a microscope, but to let them

    be and to witness their continued being... (Merleau-Ponty, 1968:

    101)

    Thus for Merleau-Ponty, the metaphoric, being closely related to reflective

    mode of thought and to cultural mode of being, is a specifically human

    mode of language, situated mid-way between the entirely mystical and

    the too positive. It is a mode wherein one is able to transport oneself

    beyond the subjective and the objective, and by means of which one

    establishes infinite inter-subjective worlds.9

    5. The sense of metaphor

    In the preceding sections we mainly focused on the spatial, the corporeal

    and the iconic dimensions of the linguistic phenomenon of metaphor.

    Whatever be the psychological and ideal aspects that it may be said to

    possess, fundamentally human language is an activity proceeding from

    9

    This idea, based on the etymological sense of metaphor as transport has beeneminently developed by E. Levinas, in his essay, Meaning and Sense. See referencebelow.

    19

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    20/24

    the human body situated in an ambient space and time. Therefore,

    language is a sort of gesture occurring in space (and time). However, it is

    not a gesture involving the whole of human body, but is specialised in and

    limited to the oro-oto-laryngeal region of the body. In addition to this

    communicative specialisation which man shares with many other species

    of animals, he is endowed with the unique property of being able to oro-

    laryngeally produce an imitative fragment of certain essential properties

    of objects and events in the world around him. This imitation, as assumed

    by classical Greek thought, is not stimulus-bound, but is creative. Thus,

    the human vocal organs can produce non-instrumentally a copy of the

    forms and figures and in the world. Hence Socrates hypothesis about o

    replicating roundness, sibilants replicating windiness, and d and t

    replicating levelness, etc.

    However, the copies need not always be vocally iconic. Just as the

    iconically produced voice is already another substance standing for the

    thing / event in the world, other substances such as letters and pictures

    can copy the thing. Further, there need not be a relation of concrete

    iconicity between the thing and its copy, i.e., either of the image or of the

    diagrammatic kind, in the sense of Peirce. Thus, substances that are not

    directly meant for the representational purpose, but which resemble anoriginal thing or its assumed property, can stand for the latter. Such is the

    case, for example, with the emblematic signs. By extension, words and

    other representations of such substances can stand for the original thing.

    And so on and so forth.

    The imitation that inaugurates human language is not forced on man.

    Language is an quasi-artistic activity, and thus in part comparable with

    painting and music. Many thinkers agree that at the root of languagethere is iconicity, similarity and figurativity, proceeding from the most

    easily available natural objects, especially the human body: For Socrates,

    certain essences of things in nature can be iconically reproduced by oral

    gestures. In due course, these iconic forms are subjected to inter-

    subjective correction, and are conventionalised. For Merleau-Ponty, on the

    other hand, the verbal gesticulation is decidedly a type of bodily display

    of existential / subjective responses in the situated space. Use of

    conventional signs, he argues, is a late form of relationship between

    20

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    21/24

    people, they presuppose an earlier means of communication.10 Jean-

    Jacques Rousseau similarly believes that it is not physical needs like

    hunger and thirst, but moral needs and passions such as love, hatred,

    pity, anger, etc., that first resulted in language, and figurative language

    was the first to be born. Mans first words were singable and passionate

    before they became simple and methodical.11

    There is implicit agreement among these philosophers that the source of

    language, one way or another, is physis, i.e., the body in and of nature.

    At the source, the truth of the linguistic signs is figurative. The figurative

    truth at first represented in iconic or indexical signs (in the Peircean sense

    of these terms) undergoes corrosion and dilution through repeated use of

    these signs whose values are relatively fixed by way of tacit convention.The task of philosophy in its classical sense is to discover truth with

    regard to and in language as a system of arbitrary signs. It is an

    excavation of the system of language. However, truth of the physis

    (nature / body) already figures in language.12 In Deleuzian terms, the

    series of the natural / figurative forms runs parallel to the series of the

    conventional / symbolic / arbitrary signs.13

    Thus, the figurative is neither before nor after the arbitrary signs. But it issomething other than the conventional. This is why Aristotle is full of

    praise for the use of metaphor. An eye for resemblance involves an

    abandonment of the conventionality and the arbitrariness of the given

    linguistic signs, and establishes new and previously unnoticed

    relationships of similarity between two objects or two words.14 Since

    10 Merleau-Ponty, Phenomenology of Perception, p. 187.

    11 Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, Essay of the Origin of Language, 1966 edn, p. 12.

    12For a discussion of some of these issues, see Nancy, 2000.

    13

    This point, of course, is of great relevance for a theory of narrative as well as in psycho-analysis. Speaking of metaphor and metonymy in the context of structuralism, Deleuzesays: Ce dplacement relative des deux sries nest pas du tout secondaire; il ne vientpas affecter un terme, du dehors et secondairement, comme pour lui donner undguisement imaginaire des tres et objets qui viennent secondairement occuper cesplaces. Cest porquoi le structuralisme porte tant dattention la mtaphore et lamtonymie. Celles-ci ne sont nullement des figures de limagination, mais dabord desfacteurs structuraux. (Deleuze, G., 1973: 321)

    14

    This rather positive cognitivist account of metaphors, though not without pitfalls, isassumed by many. Earl MacCormac (1985), for instance, notes that internally,metaphors operate as cognitive processes that produce new insights and new

    21

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    22/24

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    23/24

    Levinas, Emmanuel, 1987. Meaning and Sense, in A. Lingis (tr.) Levinas Collected Philosophical Papers. Dordrecht: Martinus Nijhoff.

    MacCormac, Earl, R., 1985. A Cognitive Theory of Metaphor. Cambridge(Mass.): MIT Press.

    Manjali, Franson, 1991. Nuclear Semantics Towards a Theory ofRelational Meaning. New Delhi: Bahri.

    Manjali, Franson, 2000. Body, Space and Metphorical-Cultural Worlds, inMeaning, Culture and Cognition. New Delhi: Bahri.

    Merleau-Ponty, Maurice, 1962 edn. Phenomenology of Perception. (tr.)

    Colin Smith. New Jersey: The Humanities Press.

    Merleau-Ponty, M., 1960. Signes. Paris: Gallimard.

    Merleau-Ponty, M., 1968 edn. The Visible and the Invisible. (ed.) ClaudeLefort; (tr.) A. Lingis. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

    Nancy, Jean-Luc, 2000. Entre deux, Magazine Littraire 392: 54-57.Paris.

    Petitot, Jean, 1985. Morphognse du sens. Paris: Presses Universitairesde France.

    Plato, Cratylus. in, Hayden, D.E. and E.P. Alworth (eds.) Classics inSemantics. London: Vision Books. (1965)

    Radwanska-Williams, Joanna, 1994. The problem of iconicity, inPragmatics 22: 23-36.

    Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 1966 edn. Essay on the Origin of Language. (tr.)J.H. Morgan and A. Gode. New York: F. Ungar.

    Saussure, F. de, 1974 edn. Course in General Linguistics. (tr.) WadeBaskin. Glasgow: Fontana.

    Varela, Francesco, Eleanor Rosch and Evan Thompson, 1991. TheEmbodied Mind. Cognitive Science and Human Experience. Cambridge(Mass.): MIT Press.

    *****

    23

  • 8/3/2019 Metaphor and Space

    24/24