21
On the relationship On the relationship between Keynes’s between Keynes’s conception of evidential conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg weight and the Ellsberg paradox paradox Alberto Feduzi Alberto Feduzi University of Cambridge and University of Rome III University of Cambridge and University of Rome III FUR XII 2006 FUR XII 2006

On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

  • Upload
    marsha

  • View
    22

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox. Alberto Feduzi University of Cambridge and University of Rome III FUR XII 2006. Facts. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

On the relationship On the relationship between Keynes’s between Keynes’s

conception of evidential conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg weight and the Ellsberg

paradoxparadox

Alberto FeduziAlberto FeduziUniversity of Cambridge and University of Rome III University of Cambridge and University of Rome III

FUR XII 2006FUR XII 2006

Page 2: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

FactsFacts Keynes’s contribution to the development of the theory of Keynes’s contribution to the development of the theory of

probability has been ‘seriously underestimated’ or even probability has been ‘seriously underestimated’ or even completely denied. completely denied.

Ellsberg’s seminal 1961QJE critique of the subjective expected Ellsberg’s seminal 1961QJE critique of the subjective expected utility model bears certain resemblances to ideas expressed in utility model bears certain resemblances to ideas expressed in J. M. Keynes’s 1921 A Treatise on Probability. J. M. Keynes’s 1921 A Treatise on Probability.

Ellsberg did not mention Keynes’s work in his article and Ellsberg did not mention Keynes’s work in his article and referred instead to F. Knight’s distinction between ‘risk’ and referred instead to F. Knight’s distinction between ‘risk’ and ‘uncertainty’, thus inspiring a literature on various aspects of ‘uncertainty’, thus inspiring a literature on various aspects of ‘Knightian uncertainty’. ‘Knightian uncertainty’.

The recent publication of Ellsberg’s PhD dissertation (2001), The recent publication of Ellsberg’s PhD dissertation (2001), submitted to the University of Harvard in 1962, reveals that submitted to the University of Harvard in 1962, reveals that Ellsberg was actually aware of Keynes’s work.Ellsberg was actually aware of Keynes’s work.

Page 3: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

AimAim

Reconsidering Keynes's contribution to Reconsidering Keynes's contribution to modern decision theory, by clarifying the modern decision theory, by clarifying the relationship between his work on probability relationship between his work on probability and Ellsberg's on ambiguity and Ellsberg's on ambiguity

Research QuestionsResearch Questions Why Ellsberg did not mention Keynes in his Why Ellsberg did not mention Keynes in his

QJE article and refer instead to Knight?QJE article and refer instead to Knight? Did Ellsberg recognize Keynes’s actual Did Ellsberg recognize Keynes’s actual

contribution?contribution? Has Keynes’s contribution to decision theory Has Keynes’s contribution to decision theory

been fully exploited?been fully exploited?

Page 4: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (1)Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (1) ProbabilityProbability

Probability is conceived as a logical relation between a Probability is conceived as a logical relation between a proposition stating some conclusion on the one hand, and a proposition stating some conclusion on the one hand, and a set of evidential propositions on the other. set of evidential propositions on the other.

If H is the conclusion of an argument and E is a set of If H is the conclusion of an argument and E is a set of premises, then p = H/E represents the degree of rational premises, then p = H/E represents the degree of rational belief that the probability relation between H and E belief that the probability relation between H and E justifies. justifies.

Numerical probabilitiesNumerical probabilities

Degrees of belief can be measured numerically only in Degrees of belief can be measured numerically only in two particular situationstwo particular situations:: when it is possible to apply the when it is possible to apply the ‘Principle of Indifference’ and when it is possible to ‘Principle of Indifference’ and when it is possible to estimate statistical frequencies.estimate statistical frequencies.

Page 5: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (2)Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (2)

ProbabilityProbability

Non-numerical probabilitiesNon-numerical probabilities

In many cases ‘no exercise of the practical judgement is In many cases ‘no exercise of the practical judgement is possible, by which a numerical value can actually be possible, by which a numerical value can actually be given to the probability…’ given to the probability…’ (CW VIII, p. 29).(CW VIII, p. 29).

Non-comparable probabilities Non-comparable probabilities

‘‘So far from our being able to measure them, it is not So far from our being able to measure them, it is not even clear that we are always able to place them in an even clear that we are always able to place them in an order of magnitude’ (CW VIII, p. 29). order of magnitude’ (CW VIII, p. 29).

Page 6: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (3)Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (3) Keynes’s Theory of ProbabilityKeynes’s Theory of Probability

““O represents impossibility, I certainty, and A a numerically measurable probability O represents impossibility, I certainty, and A a numerically measurable probability intermediate between O and I; U, V, W, X, Y, Z are non-numerical probabilities, of intermediate between O and I; U, V, W, X, Y, Z are non-numerical probabilities, of which, however, V is less than the numerical probability A, and is also less than W, which, however, V is less than the numerical probability A, and is also less than W, X and Y. X and Y are both greater than W, and greater than V, but are not X and Y. X and Y are both greater than W, and greater than V, but are not comparable with one another, or with A. V and Z are both less than W, X, and Y, but comparable with one another, or with A. V and Z are both less than W, X, and Y, but are not comparable with one another, U is not quantitatively comparable with any are not comparable with one another, U is not quantitatively comparable with any of the probabilities V, W, X, Y, Z” (CW VIII, p. 42). of the probabilities V, W, X, Y, Z” (CW VIII, p. 42).

Page 7: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (4)Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (4)

Weight of ArgumentWeight of Argument

[…] as the relevant evidence at our disposal increases, the magnitude of as the relevant evidence at our disposal increases, the magnitude of the probability of the argument may either decrease or increase, the probability of the argument may either decrease or increase, according as the new knowledge strengthens the unfavourable or the according as the new knowledge strengthens the unfavourable or the favourable evidence; but something seems to have increased in either favourable evidence; but something seems to have increased in either case, - we have a more substantial basis upon which to rest our case, - we have a more substantial basis upon which to rest our conclusion. I express this by saying that conclusion. I express this by saying that an accession of new evidence an accession of new evidence increases the weight of an argumentincreases the weight of an argument. New evidence will sometimes . New evidence will sometimes decrease the probability of an argument, but it will always increase its decrease the probability of an argument, but it will always increase its “weight”’ (CW VIII, p. 77).“weight”’ (CW VIII, p. 77).

TThe weight of arguments is a measure of the absolute amount of relevant he weight of arguments is a measure of the absolute amount of relevant knowledge expressed in the evidential premises of a probability relation.knowledge expressed in the evidential premises of a probability relation.

‘‘One argument has more weight than another if it is based on a greater One argument has more weight than another if it is based on a greater amount of relevant evidence…’ (CW VIII, p. 84). amount of relevant evidence…’ (CW VIII, p. 84).

Page 8: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability Keynes’s A Treatise on Probability (5)(5)

Weight of ArgumentWeight of Argument

Keynes’s ‘two-colour’ urn example: Keynes’s ‘two-colour’ urn example:

[…] in the first case we know that the urn contains […] in the first case we know that the urn contains black and white in equal proportions; in the second black and white in equal proportions; in the second case the proportion of each colour is unknown, and case the proportion of each colour is unknown, and each ball is as likely to be black as white. It is each ball is as likely to be black as white. It is evident that in either case the probability of evident that in either case the probability of drawing a white ball is 1/2, but that the drawing a white ball is 1/2, but that the weight of weight of the argumentthe argument in favour of this conclusion is in favour of this conclusion is greater in the first case (CW VIII, p. 82). greater in the first case (CW VIII, p. 82).

Page 9: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Ellsberg’s ‘Risk, Ambiguity, and the Ellsberg’s ‘Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms’ (1) Savage Axioms’ (1)

The main purpose of Ellsberg’s article was to point out that there are some ‘uncertainties’ that are not ‘risks’ and to revive Knight’s distinction between ‘risk’ and ‘uncertainty’. .

There is a class of choice-situations characterised by the necessity to consider the ambiguity of information, being ‘a quality depending on the amount, type, reliability and unanimity of information, and giving rise to one’s degree of “confidence” in an estimate of relative likelihoods’ (Ellsberg, 1961, p. 657).

Page 10: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Ellsberg’s ‘Risk, Ambiguity, and the Ellsberg’s ‘Risk, Ambiguity, and the Savage Axioms’ (2) Savage Axioms’ (2)

Ellsberg’s ‘two-colours’ urn example: Ellsberg’s ‘two-colours’ urn example:

Suppose that there are two urns, each one containing Suppose that there are two urns, each one containing 100 balls. The first urn is known to contain 50 red and 100 balls. The first urn is known to contain 50 red and 50 black balls, whereas the second urn is know to 50 black balls, whereas the second urn is know to contain 100 balls, each of which may be either red or contain 100 balls, each of which may be either red or black (i.e. the proportion of red/black balls is black (i.e. the proportion of red/black balls is unknown). The subject is asked to choose an urn and unknown). The subject is asked to choose an urn and a colour, and to draw a ball from the urn you named. a colour, and to draw a ball from the urn you named. He or she will win $100 if the ball drawn has the He or she will win $100 if the ball drawn has the colour chosen, and nothing otherwise. colour chosen, and nothing otherwise.

Page 11: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Traces of Keynes (1)Traces of Keynes (1)

Ellsberg did not refer to Keynes in his QJE article. Ellsberg did not refer to Keynes in his QJE article. Yet the remarkable similarities between some of the Yet the remarkable similarities between some of the ideas advanced by the two authors are readily ideas advanced by the two authors are readily apparent.apparent.

The recent (2001) publication of Ellsberg’s PhD The recent (2001) publication of Ellsberg’s PhD dissertation, ‘dissertation, ‘Risk, Ambiguity and Decision’Risk, Ambiguity and Decision’, , submitted to the University of Harvard in 1962, submitted to the University of Harvard in 1962, reveals that Ellsberg was actually aware of Keynes’s reveals that Ellsberg was actually aware of Keynes’s work. work.

In the second section of his dissertation, entitled In the second section of his dissertation, entitled ‘Vagueness, Confidence and The Weight of ‘Vagueness, Confidence and The Weight of Arguments’Arguments’, Ellsberg discusses Keynes’s , Ellsberg discusses Keynes’s fundamental ideas on probability and their fundamental ideas on probability and their relationships with his notion of ambiguity. relationships with his notion of ambiguity.

Page 12: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Traces of Keynes (2)Traces of Keynes (2)

Ellsberg recognises the link between his Ellsberg recognises the link between his notion of ambiguity and Keynes’s conception notion of ambiguity and Keynes’s conception of weightof weight

Keynes ‘introduced formally the notion of non-comparability Keynes ‘introduced formally the notion of non-comparability of beliefs’ (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 9). of beliefs’ (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 9).

   ‘‘Keynes, in particular, introduces a notion of “the weight of Keynes, in particular, introduces a notion of “the weight of

arguments” (as opposed to their relative probability) which arguments” (as opposed to their relative probability) which seems closely related to our notion of “ambiguity”’ (Ellsberg seems closely related to our notion of “ambiguity”’ (Ellsberg 2001, p. 11). 2001, p. 11).

‘‘differences in relative weight seems related to differences in differences in relative weight seems related to differences in the ‘confidence’ with which we hold different opinions…’ the ‘confidence’ with which we hold different opinions…’ (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 12). (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 12).

Page 13: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Traces of Keynes (3)Traces of Keynes (3)

Ellsberg criticizes the constructive part Ellsberg criticizes the constructive part of Keynes’s analysisof Keynes’s analysis

‘how may the web of action systematically reflect the varying degrees of “vagueness”, of “ambiguity/weight”, of ‘confidence’ in our judgment?’. On this question Knight, Savage and Keynes are ‘virtually’ silent’ (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 13).

[…] Keynes, like Knight, emphasizes that these matters do seem relevant to decision-making, though admitting frankly his own vagueness and lack of confidence on this particular question (Ellsberg, 2001, p. 13).

Page 14: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between Ellsberg and Keynesbetween Ellsberg and Keynes (1) (1)

1.1. The The ‘mystery’‘mystery’ of why Ellsberg did not mention of why Ellsberg did not mention Keynes in his QJE article has a simple solution: Keynes in his QJE article has a simple solution: his dissertation was only completed after he had his dissertation was only completed after he had written the QJE article and he had only come written the QJE article and he had only come across Keynes after writing the QJE article across Keynes after writing the QJE article (Ellsberg, personal communication, 2005).(Ellsberg, personal communication, 2005).

Ellsberg was not influenced by Keynes when Ellsberg was not influenced by Keynes when writing the QJE article and arrived at the ideas writing the QJE article and arrived at the ideas expressed therein independently.expressed therein independently.

Page 15: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between Ellsberg and Keynes (2)between Ellsberg and Keynes (2)

Contrary to what Ellsberg thought:

(A) Keynes’s hesitancy about the relevance of the concept of evidential weight was not directed at the urn-type decision situations that were the subject of Ellsberg’s study;

(B) Keynes actually did develop decision-criteria that can be applied to choice situations of this kind.

Page 16: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between Ellsberg and Keynes (3)between Ellsberg and Keynes (3)

A) Keynes’s HesitancyA) Keynes’s Hesitancy

Keynes regards the absence of a rational principle that Keynes regards the absence of a rational principle that determines when to stop the process of acquiring information as determines when to stop the process of acquiring information as a possible objection against the use of the weight of argument. a possible objection against the use of the weight of argument.

This problem, which is the source of Keynes’s perplexities and This problem, which is the source of Keynes’s perplexities and which we could term which we could term ‘the stopping problem’‘the stopping problem’, does however , does however not apply to the urn-type decision situations analysed by not apply to the urn-type decision situations analysed by Ellsberg.Ellsberg.

In urn-type choice-situations, the weight of argument can be In urn-type choice-situations, the weight of argument can be identified as a measure of the sample size and it is possible to identified as a measure of the sample size and it is possible to apply standard statistical criteria to solve the “stopping apply standard statistical criteria to solve the “stopping problem”.problem”.

Page 17: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between Ellsberg and Keynes (4)between Ellsberg and Keynes (4)

A) Keynes’s HesitancyA) Keynes’s Hesitancy

The perplexities that Keynes expresses thus simply do The perplexities that Keynes expresses thus simply do not apply to ‘not apply to ‘conventionalised choice situationsconventionalised choice situations’ ’ involving random drawing from urns.involving random drawing from urns.

Keynes was primarily interested in proving the Keynes was primarily interested in proving the effectiveness of the theory of evidential weight outside effectiveness of the theory of evidential weight outside conventionalised choice situations. We might refer to conventionalised choice situations. We might refer to decision situations of this kind as decision situations of this kind as ‘practical choice ‘practical choice situations’.situations’.

Page 18: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between between

Ellsberg and Keynes (5)Ellsberg and Keynes (5)

B) Keynes’s Decision Criterion B) Keynes’s Decision Criterion

Keynes hints at a possible rule to systematically Keynes hints at a possible rule to systematically discriminate between the two urns: “…if two discriminate between the two urns: “…if two probabilities are equal in degree, ought we, in probabilities are equal in degree, ought we, in choosing our course of action, to prefer that one choosing our course of action, to prefer that one which is based on a greater body of knowledge?” which is based on a greater body of knowledge?” (CW VIII, p. 345).(CW VIII, p. 345).

Keynes proposes the following conventional Keynes proposes the following conventional coefficient c of weight and risk, that is, a general coefficient c of weight and risk, that is, a general rule to combine both coefficient of risk and rule to combine both coefficient of risk and weight, and the probability:weight, and the probability:

)1)(1(

2

wq

pwc

Page 19: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Shedding light on the relationship Shedding light on the relationship between between

Ellsberg and Keynes (6)Ellsberg and Keynes (6)

The constructive part of Keynes’s analysis cannot be put The constructive part of Keynes’s analysis cannot be put on the same plane as that of Knight:on the same plane as that of Knight:

a) Knight’s ‘two-colours’ urn example needs to be further developed a) Knight’s ‘two-colours’ urn example needs to be further developed to criticize the standard theory of probability; to criticize the standard theory of probability;

b) his conclusions do not move in the direction of further criticisms;b) his conclusions do not move in the direction of further criticisms;

c) As pointed out by Ellsberg, his c) As pointed out by Ellsberg, his results ‘results ‘directly contradictdirectly contradict Knight’s own intuition about the situation’ (Ellsberg, 1961, p. 653).Knight’s own intuition about the situation’ (Ellsberg, 1961, p. 653).

It is paradoxical that some of the literature inspired by It is paradoxical that some of the literature inspired by Ellsberg’s paper is usually labelled ‘Knightian uncertainty’. Ellsberg’s paper is usually labelled ‘Knightian uncertainty’.

Page 20: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

The practical relevance of the The practical relevance of the concept of evidential weight in concept of evidential weight in

Keynes’s economic writingsKeynes’s economic writings    In his later economic writings, Keynes found space to In his later economic writings, Keynes found space to

provide a role to the concept of the weight of argument, provide a role to the concept of the weight of argument, by analyzing:by analyzing:

A) The ‘State of Long-Term Expectation’;A) The ‘State of Long-Term Expectation’;

B) The liquidity-premium. B) The liquidity-premium.

He never again referred to the problem of finding a He never again referred to the problem of finding a rational principle to decide where to stop the process of rational principle to decide where to stop the process of acquiring information, that is acquiring information, that is how muchhow much should the should the weight of an argument be strengthened before making weight of an argument be strengthened before making a decision.a decision.

Page 21: On the relationship between Keynes’s conception of evidential weight and the Ellsberg paradox

Conclusion Conclusion

The ‘mystery’ of why Ellsberg did not mention Keynes in The ‘mystery’ of why Ellsberg did not mention Keynes in his QJE article has a simple solution, namely that his his QJE article has a simple solution, namely that his dissertation was only completed after he had written the dissertation was only completed after he had written the QJE article and that he had only come across Keynes after QJE article and that he had only come across Keynes after writing the QJE article. writing the QJE article.

Ellsberg recognised the link between his notion of Ellsberg recognised the link between his notion of ambiguity and Keynes’s conception of the weight of ambiguity and Keynes’s conception of the weight of argument in his PhD dissertation, but he did not fully argument in his PhD dissertation, but he did not fully appreciate the fact that Keynes was more concerned with appreciate the fact that Keynes was more concerned with ‘practical’ rather than ‘conventionalised’ choice situations. ‘practical’ rather than ‘conventionalised’ choice situations.

It is fair to say that ‘Knightian uncertainty’ is in many It is fair to say that ‘Knightian uncertainty’ is in many ways closer to the ideas expressed by Keynes than by ways closer to the ideas expressed by Keynes than by Knight, and Keynes’s actual contribution to modern Knight, and Keynes’s actual contribution to modern decision theory has been underestimated.decision theory has been underestimated.