12
Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References Expressing May and Must Dynamic Semantics at Work William Starr Cornell University Sage School of Philosophy [email protected] http://williamstarr.net December 27, 2011 William Starr Expressing May and Must Dynamic Semantics Session ASL 2012 0/43 Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References Outline 1 Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics 2 Dynamic Preference Semantics William Starr Expressing May and Must Dynamic Semantics Session ASL 2012 0/43 Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References The Role of Information In Inquiry and Conversation Informational contents (propositions ) are sets of possible worlds These sets distinguish ways world might be (worlds in the set) from ways it isn’t (worlds excluded from set) One informational content is particularly useful for understanding how linguistic interactions unfold: Contextual Possibilities (c) As communication and inquiry unfold, a body of information accumulates. Think of this information as what the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying this information c, short for contextual possibilities. (Stalnaker 1978; Lewis 1979) William Starr Expressing May and Must Dynamic Semantics Session ASL 2012 1/43 Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References Gaining Information And Eliminating Possibilities Figure: Accepting the information that A Inquiry progresses by using information to eliminate uncertainty, i.e. the elimination of worlds. {w AB ,w Ab ,w aB ,w ab }⇒{w AB ,w Ab } William Starr Expressing May and Must Dynamic Semantics Session ASL 2012 2/43

Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

  • Upload
    others

  • View
    1

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Expressing May and MustDynamic Semantics at Work

William Starr

Cornell UniversitySage School of Philosophy

[email protected]://williamstarr.net

December 27, 2011

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 0/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Outline

1 Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics

2 Dynamic Preference Semantics

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 0/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Role of InformationIn Inquiry and Conversation

• Informational contents (propositions) are sets ofpossible worlds

• These sets distinguish ways world might be (worlds inthe set) from ways it isn’t (worlds excluded from set)

• One informational content is particularly useful forunderstanding how linguistic interactions unfold:

Contextual Possibilities (c)

As communication and inquiry unfold, a body ofinformation accumulates. Think of this information as whatthe agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. Icall the set of worlds embodying this information c, shortfor contextual possibilities. (Stalnaker 1978; Lewis 1979)

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 1/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Gaining InformationAnd Eliminating Possibilities

Figure: Accepting the information that A

• Inquiry progresses by using information to eliminateuncertainty, i.e. the elimination of worlds.

• {wAB,wAb,waB,wab}⇒ {wAB,wAb}

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 2/43

Page 2: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

QuestionHow are Semantics and Information Change Related?

Classical Picture

1 Semantics: pair sentences w/propositions

• JφK is a set of worlds

2 Pragmatics: rules for rational agents

• When presented with information, rational agents useit to eliminate possibilities (update using intersection)

The Point Semantics specifies informational content of asentence, but nothing in particular about howsentence changes contextual information (c)

• Instead, pragmatics says how thesentence’s content impacts c: c ∩ JφK

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 3/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Classical PictureIn More Detail

Classical Possible Worlds Semantics

1 JAK = {w ∣ w(A) = 1}

2 J¬φK =W − JφK3 Jφ ∧ ψK = JφK ∩ JψK4 Jφ ∨ ψK = JφK ∪ JψK5 J◇φK = {w ∣ ∃w′ ∶ w′ ∈ Acc(w) & w′ ∈ JφK}

• Acc(w) is the set of worlds accessible from w

Classical Truth and Consequence

Truth w ⊧ φ ⇐⇒ w ∈ JφKConsequence φ ⊧ ψ ⇐⇒ JφK ⊆ JψK

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 4/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Two Important ConsequencesOf the Classical Approach

Fact 1: ◇A ⊧◇A ∨◇B

• Consequence is content inclusion:

• J◇AK ⊆ J◇A ∨◇BK• Disjunction is union:

• J◇AK ⊆ J◇AK ∪ J◇BK

Fact 2: ◇A ∨◇B ⊭◇A

• This would require:

• J◇AK ∪ J◇BK ⊆ J◇AK• But this only holds when J◇BK = ∅

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 5/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The First Problem of Free ChoiceKamp (1973) and Ross (1941)

(1) Billy may go to the beach

• Best classical approximation of May : some species of ◇

• MayB?=◇B

Problem: MayB does not entail MayB ∨MayC

X: Billy may go to the beach

Y: Ah, so Billy may go to the beach, or Billy may go thecinema × ×

Why is this a problem?

• Fact 1: ◇B ⊧◇B ∨◇C

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 6/43

Page 3: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Second Problem of Free ChoiceKamp (1973)

(2) Billy may go to the beach or he may go to the cinema

Problem: MayB ∨MayC does entail MayB

X: Billy may go to the beach or he may go to the cinema

Y: Ah, so Billy may go to the beach ✓

• Indeed: MayB ∨MayC entails MayB ∧MayC

Why is this a problem?

• Fact 2: ◇A ∨◇B ⊭◇A

• So there are at least two problems for classicalapproach to may

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 7/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Tentative DiagnosisThe Performative Function of May

• A pragmatic approach...

• Competence with a word is involved, so a semanticapproach is preferable

• Also, classical pragmatics assumes (declarative)sentences denote propositions

• Proposition gets intersected with c

• MayA shouldn’t change c, but rather Acc• This operation can’t be intersection (sphere ofaccessibility should grow w/permission)

• This would also require MayA to denote anaccessibility relation

• So many problems w/this

• Alternative: approach to semantics that can directlyencode (features of) communicative function of a word

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 8/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

QuestionHow are Semantics and Information Change Related?

Classical Picture

1 Semantics: pair sentences w/propositions

• JφK is a set of worlds

2 Pragmatics: rules for rational agents

• When presented with information, rational agents useit to eliminate possibilities (update using intersection)

Dynamic Picture (Veltman, Heim)

1 Semantics: pair sentences with ways of changingcontexts

• φ eliminates worlds from c

2 Pragmatics: mechanisms for additional changes

• General rationality, theory of mind, etc.

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 9/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Dynamic PictureIn More Detail

The Basic Idea

Assign each φ a function [φ] encoding how it changes c:c[φ] = c′ (Better notation: [φ](c) = c′)

Dynamic Informational Semantics

1 c[A] = {w ∈ c ∣ w(A) = 1}

2 c[¬φ] = c − c[φ]

3 c[φ ∧ ψ] = (c[φ])[ψ]

4 c[φ ∨ ψ] = c[φ] ∪ c[ψ]

5 c[◇φ] = {w ∣ ∃w′ ∶ w′ ∈ Acc(w) & w′ ∈ c[φ]}

• Veltman (1996): for epistemic might, Acc(w) is c

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 10/43

Page 4: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Dynamic Informational SemanticsSemantic Concepts and a New Perspective on Classical Ones

Support, Consequence (Veltman)

• c⊫ φ ⇐⇒ c[φ] = c

• φ1, . . . , φn ⊫ ψ ⇐⇒ ∀c ∶ c[φ1]⋯[φn]⊫ ψ

Truth, Propositions (Starr)

w ⊧ φ ⇐⇒ {w}[φ] = {w} JφK = {w ∣ w ⊧ φ}

Classical Consequence (Starr)

φ1, . . . , φn ⊧ ψ ⇐⇒ ∀w ∶ {w}[φ1]⋯[φn]⊫ ψ

• Classical logic is the logic of perfect information

• Equivalent to standard ⊧ for modal free fragment

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 11/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Dynamic Informational SemanticsUnderstanding Classical vs. Dynamic Semantics

Corollary (Boolean Equivalence)

1 JAK = {w ∣ w(A) = 1}

2 J¬φK =W − JφK3 Jφ ∧ ψK = JφK ∩ JψK4 Jφ ∨ ψK = JφK ∪ JψK

• Booleans behave classically

• Boolean fragment: ⊧ and ⊫ are identical

• It’s only with modals that ⊧ and ⊫ come apart

• Surprise: w ∉ J◇φK unless Acc(w) = {w} and w ∈ JφK• Then J◇φK ⊆ JφK and so ◇φ ⊧ φ

• Yet ◇φ⊯ φ

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 12/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Illustrating Our Surprise◇A is false unless A is true and Acc(w) = {w}

• Recall w ∈ J◇AK ⇐⇒ {w}[◇A] = {w}

• Consider whether wA ∈ J◇AK:

{wA}[◇A] = {w ∣ ∃w′ ∶ w′ ∈ Acc(w) & w′ ∈ {wA}[A]}

= {w ∣ wA ∈ Acc(w)}

• Unless Acc(wA) = {wA}, {wA}[◇A] ≠ {wA}

• Consider whether wa ∈ J◇AK

{wa}[◇A] = {w ∣ ∃w′ ∶ w′ ∈ Acc(w) & w′ ∈ {wa}[A]}

= {w ∣ ∃w′ ∶ w′ ∈ Acc(w) & w′ ∈ ∅}

= ∅

• Nope! So J◇AK ⊆ JAK

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 13/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Classical Logic as Logic of OmniscienceA Logic of Omniscience is Not Suited for Modality

d’Alembert (1751) on Truth

“The universe... would only be one fact and one great truthfor whoever knew how to embrace it from a single point ofview.” (d’Alembert 1995: 29)

• A sentence is true iff it corresponds w/‘the great truth’

• Correspond: cohere w/the great truth, {w}[φ] = {w}

• But modal sentences are indexical to uncertainty orutilities of agent(s) evaluating them

• Whether they cohere with the great truth is irrelevant

• We want an evaluative concept that targets how theycohere with partial information: c[φ] = c (support)

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 14/43

Page 5: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Dynamic Informational SemanticsBack to Free Choice

• This system is quite useful for epistemic modals• A ∧◇¬A is inconsistent (cf. Veltman and Yalcin)• ◇φ can add possibilities to c

• Not possible to get with c ∩ J◇φK• But it does not solve the problem of free choice:

• ◇φ⊫◇φ ∨◇ψ• ◇φ ∨◇ψ ⊯◇φ

• However, it is the backbone of a system that does:• may ’s meaning resides in how it changes context• Use of ⊫ rather than ⊧

Basic Idea

Capture the non-informational impact of may bysophisticating the contexts sentences operate on

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 15/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextInformation and the Process of Inquiry

Figure: Accepting the information that A

• Inquiry progresses by gaining information, i.e. theelimination of worlds.

• {wAB,wAb,waB,wab}⇒ {wAB,wAb}

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 16/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextIssues

• It’s not just information that accumulates incommunication and inquiry (Bromberger 1966)

• There are issues (e.g. Hamblin 1958; Roberts 1996).

• They can be thought of as ways of grouping worlds inc into competing alternative propositions.

Alternatives (C) (e.g. Groenendijk 1999)

Alternatives represent open, competing propositions theagents are concerned with deciding between; their issues.Formally, this grouping of c may be identified with a set ofsets of worlds; call it C. There is no need to also keep trackof c: it is just the union of all the alternatives in C.

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 17/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextIssues and Inquiry

Figure: Recognizing the issue whether A

• Inquiry also progresses by recognizing issues, i.e.introducing alternatives

• {{wAB,wAb,waB,wab}}⇒ {{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}}

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 18/43

Page 6: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextPreferences

• Agents not only gather information and identifycompeting alternatives, they form preferencesregarding those alternatives

• Central to decision theoretic approaches to rationalchoice, as applied in philosophy, AI and economics(e.g. Ramsey 1931; Newell 1992)

• Of relevance here: the preferences being mutuallytaken for granted for the purposes of an interaction

• Parallel to Stalnaker’s common ground

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 19/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextPreferences

• A body of preferences can be represented as a binarypreference relation on the alternatives

• I.e. a set of pairs of propositions constructed from c

Preference State (R)

• R: binary relation on alternatives (open propositions)

• R(a, a′): a is preferred to a′

• Each pair in R is called a preference

• Set of (non-empty) alternatives over which R isdefined: issues at stake in R, CR

• Set of worlds among those alternatives: the contextualpossibilities written cR

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 20/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextInformation in a Preference State

Figure: Accepting the information that A

• {wAB,wAb,waB,wb}⇒ {wAB,wAb}

• { ⟨{wAB,wAb,waB,wb},∅⟩ }⇒ { ⟨{wAB,wAb},∅⟩ }

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 21/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextIssues in a Preference State

Figure: Recognizing the issue whether A

• {{wAB,wAb,waB,wab}}⇒ {{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}}

• { ⟨{wAB,wAb,waB,wab},∅⟩ }

⇒ { ⟨{wAB,wAb},∅⟩, ⟨{waB,wab},∅⟩ }

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 22/43

Page 7: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextPreference and Inquiry

Figure: Coming to prefer A (to ¬A)

• { ⟨{wAB,wAb,waB,wab},∅⟩ }

⇒ { ⟨{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}⟩ }

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 23/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextPreference and Inquiry

Figure: A more complex preference involving A and B

{ ⟨{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}⟩, ⟨{wAB,waB},{wAb,wab}⟩ }

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 24/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextUsing Preference to Make Rational Choices

• Given preference relation, which alternatives are best?

• How do you use preferences to decide what to do?

• In decision theory, this takes the form of defining achoice function (Hansson & Grune-Yanoff 2009)

• A choice function Ch maps a preference state R to theset of best alternatives according to R

Proposal: Choice, Permission, Requirement

1 Ch(R) are the alternatives permissible according to R

2 Required by R: unique alternative permitted by R

• Not always the case!

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 25/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextThe Choice Function: Logical Weak Dominance

Which Alternatives are Best?

1 Competition between preferred alternatives P (R)

• Left member in some pair

2 If preferred alternative a is entailed another preferredone, then a is out

3 If a entails a dispreferred alternative, a is out

Choice: Formally

Ch(R) = {a ∈ P (R) ∣ ∄a′ ∈ P (R) ∶ a′ ⊂ a

& ∄a′ ∈D(R) ∶ a ⊆ a′}

[D(R): dispreferred alternatives]

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 26/43

Page 8: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextHow Choice Works: An Example

Figure: Preference for A with (separate) preference for B

• { ⟨{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}⟩, ⟨{wAB,waB},{wAb,wab}⟩ }• Two preferred (warm) alternatives, orange and yellow• Neither entails the other nor dispreferred (cold) alt.• So Ch(R) = {{wAB,wAb},{wAB,waB}}

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 27/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Preference, Rationality & ContextHow Choice Works: A More Complex Example

Figure: Pref A and B

• 4 pref. alt’s: yellow, orange, reds

• Yellow is out: reds entail it

• Orange is out: top red entails it

• Bottom red is out: it entails blue,which is a dispreferred alt

• Unique best alternative: top red

• A ∧B is required

{ ⟨{wAB,wAb,waB,wab},∅⟩, ⟨{wAB,wAb},{waB,wab}⟩,

⟨{wAB},{wAb}⟩, ⟨{waB},{wab}⟩,

⟨{wAB,waB},{wAb,wab}⟩ }

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 28/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Semantics: in briefThe New Approach

• Dynamic Meaning: function from contents to contents

• Now contents are preference states

• R[φ] = R′: R′ is the result of applying φ to R

The Basics

1 Mayφ tests that φ is consistent w/some a ∈ Ch(R)• If so, a preference for φ is added to R

• This doesn’t guarantee that φ will become Ch(R)

• Otherwise: fail, i.e. return {⟨∅,∅⟩}

2 Disjunction unions separate updates

3 Conjunction sequences updates

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 29/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Semantics AppliedHow May Works: An Example

[MayB]Ð→

Figure: R0 to R0[MayB]

• The best alternative (orange) is consistent w/B

• A preference and permission for B are introduced

• But a requirement for B is not

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 30/43

Page 9: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Semantics AppliedHow May Works: With Disjunction

[MayB]Ð→

Figure: R0 to R0[MayB]

• R0 would be the result of R0[MayA]• R0[MayA ∨MayB] = R0[MayA] ∪R0[MayB]

= R0[MayB]

• MayA⊯MayA ∨MayB? MayA ∨MayB⊫MayA?

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 31/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

ConsequenceThe Old and the New

Support, Consequence (Veltman)

• c⊫ φ ⇐⇒ c[φ] = c

• φ1, . . . , φn ⊫ ψ ⇐⇒ ∀c ∶ c[φ1]⋯[φn]⊫ ψ

Preferential Support, Consequence (Starr)

• R ⊫ φ ⇐⇒ Ch(R) = Ch(R[φ])

• φ1, . . . , φn ⊫ ψ ⇐⇒ ∀R ∶ R[φ1]⋯[φn]⊫ ψ

• Both kinds of consequence and support are useful

• The first when tracking information

• The second when tracking the best alternatives

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 32/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The First Problem of Free ChoiceModal Disjunction Intro is Invalid!

[MayB]Ð→

Figure: R0 to R0[MayB] = R0[MayA ∨MayB]• MayA⊫MayA ∨MayB means:

Ch(R0[MayA]) = Ch(R0[MayA][MayA ∨MayB])

Ch(R0) = Ch(R0[MayB])

• But yellow is in Ch(R0[MayB]), and not Ch(R0)

• So MayA⊯MayA ∨MayB!

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 33/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Second Problem of Free ChoiceFrom Disjunction to Conjunction

• Disjunctions are felicitous only when each disjunctcompatible w/context (Stalnaker 1975: §III)

• If φ ∨ ψ is appropriate: R[φ] ≠ {⟨∅,∅⟩} ≠ R[ψ]

• What happens when φ is MayA?

• If MayA is compatible w/context then context passesits test and may adds preference for A

• So R[MayA] will be R plus a preference for A

• Same holds if ψ is MayB

• Since R[MayA ∨MayB] = R[MayA] ∪R[MayB]:• Resulting state will have pref for A and for B andboth will be consistent with best alternatives

• So after updating with MayA ∨MayB, MayA will notchange the best alternatives

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 34/43

Page 10: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The Second Problem of Free ChoiceFrom Disjunction to Conjunction

Important Observation

After updating with MayA ∨MayB, MayA will not changethe best alternatives

• The same holds for MayB

• But that is just to say:

• MayA ∨MayB⊫MayA• MayA ∨MayB⊫MayB• MayA ∨MayB⊫MayA ∧MayB

• Yet in the modal free fragment, ∨ and ∧ behaveexactly as the Boolean operators of classical semantics!

• Proviso: Stalnaker’s observation treated aspresupposition of ∨ and ⊫ is Strawsonian

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 35/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The SemanticsIn Full Detail

Atomic Semantics

• Where R = {⟨a0, a1⟩, . . . , ⟨an, an+1⟩}:

R[A] = {⟨a0[A], a1[A]⟩, . . . , ⟨an[A], an+1[A]⟩}

Connective Semantics

• R[φ ∧ ψ] = (R[φ])[ψ]

• R[φ ∨ ψ] =

⎧⎪⎪⎨⎪⎪⎩

R[φ] ∪R[ψ] if R[φ] ≠ {⟨∅,∅⟩} ≠ R[ψ]

Undefined otherwise

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 36/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

The SemanticsAnd Strawsonian Consequence

Modal Semantics

R[Mayφ] =

⎧⎪⎪⎨⎪⎪⎩

R ∪ {⟨cR[φ], cR − cR[φ]⟩} if ∃a ∈ Ch(R) ∶ a[φ] ≠ ∅

{⟨∅,∅⟩} otherwise

R[Mustφ] =

⎧⎪⎪⎨⎪⎪⎩

R ∪ {⟨cR[φ], cR − cR[φ]⟩} if ∀a ∈ Ch(R) ∶ a[φ] = a

{⟨∅,∅⟩} otherwise

Strawsonian Preferential Support, Consequence

• R ⊫ φ ⇐⇒ R[φ] is defined & Ch(R) = Ch(R[φ])

• φ1, . . . , φn ⊫ ψ ⇐⇒ ∀R ∶ R[φ1]⋯[φn]⊫ ψ ifR[φ1]⋯[φn][ψ] is defined

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 37/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

In Related WorkImperatives

• Free choice behavior of might?

• Veltman’s semantics + this implementation ofStalnaker’s observation

• Why not just use Veltman’s semantics for may?

• might has no ‘deontic reading’• Preference semantics captures deontic reading of may• Epistemic reading of may?

• In other work I use dynamic preference semantics toanalyze imperatives

• Having an analysis of deontic modals allows me tochart their connections

• E.g. !A⊫MayA

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 38/43

Page 11: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

ConclusionsAbout Dynamic Semantics

Summary

1 Classical semantics is a fragment of dynamic semantics

2 But expanding into the resources afforded only bydynamic semantics is fruitful

• Here: free choice

3 These provide something like an expressivist semantics

• Truth is not the only useful evaluative concept• Consequence is not always about truth

4 But avoids typical pitfalls

• How do you blend the truth-conditional and thenon-truth-conditional? (Frege-Geach)

• DS: truth-conditional behavior emerges for limitedfragment from more basic semantic constraints

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 39/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

Thank you!

(Slides available at http://williamstarr.net/research)

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 40/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

References I

Bromberger, S (1966). ‘Questions.’ The Journal of Philosophy, 63(20):597–606. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/2024253.

d’Alembert, JLR (1995). Preliminary Discourse to the Encyclopedia of Diderot.Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Originally published in 1751.

Groenendijk, J (1999). ‘The Logic of Interrogation: Classical Version.’ InT Matthews & D Strolovitch (eds.), Proceedings from Semantics andLinguistic Theory IX, 109–126. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University.

Hamblin, CL (1958). ‘Questions.’ Australasian Journal of Philosophy, 36:159–168.

Hansson, SO & Grune-Yanoff, T (2009). ‘Preferences.’ In EN Zalta (ed.), TheStanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, spring 2009 edn. URLhttp://plato.stanford.edu/archives/spr2009/entries/preferences/.

Kamp, H (1973). ‘Free Choice Permission.’ Proceedings of the AristotelianSociety, 74: 57–74. URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/4544849.

Lewis, DK (1979). ‘Scorekeeping in a Language Game.’ Journal of PhilosophicalLogic, 8(3): 339–359.

Newell, A (1992). Unified Theories of Cognition. Cambridge, Massachusetts:Harvard University Press.

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 41/43

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

References II

Ramsey, FP (1931). ‘Truth and Probability.’ In R Braithwaite (ed.), TheFoundations of Mathematics: Collected Papers of Frank P. Ramsey, 156–198.London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.

Roberts, C (1996). ‘Information Structure in Discourse: Towards an IntegratedFormal Theory of Pragmatics.’ Tech. rep., Linguistics Department, The OhioState University, Columbus, Ohio. OSU Working Papers in Linguistics,volume 49, Jae-Hak Yoon and Andreas Kathol, editors., URLhttp://www.ling.ohio-state.edu/~croberts/infostr.pdf.

Ross, A (1941). ‘Imperatives and Logic.’ Theoria, 25(7): 53–71. Page referencesto reprint Ross (1944).

Ross, A (1944). ‘Imperatives and Logic.’ Philosophy of Science, 11(1): 30–46.URL http://www.jstor.org/stable/184888.

Stalnaker, RC (1975). ‘Indicative Conditionals.’ Philosophia, 5: 269–286. Pagereferences to reprint in Stalnaker (1999).

Stalnaker, RC (1978). ‘Assertion.’ In P Cole (ed.), Syntax and Semantics 9:Pragmatics, 315–332. New York: Academic Press. References to reprint inStalnaker (1999).

Stalnaker, RC (1999). Context and Content: Essays on Intentionality in Speechand Thought. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 42/43

Page 12: Outline Expressing May and Mustwilliamstarr.net/research/ASL-4up.pdf · 2011. 12. 28. · the agents are mutually taking for granted in some way. I call the set of worlds embodying

Free Choice and Two Views of Semantics Dynamic Preference Semantics References

References III

Veltman, F (1996). ‘Defaults in Update Semantics.’ Journal of PhilosophicalLogic, 25(3): 221–261. URLhttp://www.pgrim.org/philosophersannual/xix/velt/index.htm.

William Starr ∣ Expressing May and Must ∣ Dynamic Semantics Session ∣ ASL 2012 43/43