64
1 Positive political Theory: an introduction General information Credits: 6 (40 hours) for both EPS curricula (EPA&PPP); 3 (20 hours) for Ph.D Students in Political Studies (Political Science) Period: 22 th September - 1 st December (no classroom 24 th Sept) Instructor: Francesco Zucchini ( [email protected] ) Office hours: Tuesday 15.30-17.30, room 308, third floor, Dpt. Studi Sociali e Politici

Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Positive political Theory: an introduction General information. Credits: 6 (40 hours) for both EPS curricula (EPA&PPP); 3 (20 hours) for Ph.D Students in Political Studies (Political Science) ‏ Period: 22 th September - 1 st December (no classroom 24 th Sept) - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

1

Positive political Theory: an introductionGeneral information

Credits: 6 (40 hours) for both EPS curricula (EPA&PPP); 3 (20 hours) for Ph.D Students in Political Studies (Political Science)

Period: 22th September - 1st December (no classroom 24th Sept)

Instructor: Francesco Zucchini ([email protected] )

Office hours: Tuesday 15.30-17.30, room 308, third floor, Dpt. Studi Sociali e Politici

Page 2: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

2

Course: aims, structure, assessment The course is an introduction to the study of politics from a

rational choice perspective. Students are introduced both to the analytical tools of the

approach and to the results most relevant to the political science. We will focus on the institutional effects of decision-making processes and on the nature of political actors in the democracies.

All students are expected to do all the reading for each class session and may be called upon at any time to provide summary statements of it.

Evaluation of all students is based upon the regular participation in the classroom activities (30%) and a final written exam.

Evaluation of Ph.Students is also based upon individual presentations (30%).

Page 3: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Topics (in yellow also for Ph.D students)

Page 4: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

4

Positive political Theory: An introduction

Lecture 1: Epistemological foundation of the Rational Choice approachFrancesco Zucchini

Page 5: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

What the rational choice is not

Theories without actors:

•System analysis •Structuralism•Functionalism (Parsons)

Theories with non rational actors:

•Relative deprivation theory•Imitation instinct (Tarde)•False consciouness (Engels)•Inconscient pulsions (Freud)•Habitus (Bourdieu)

“NON RATIONAL CHOICE THEORIES

Page 6: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

What the rational choice is

Weak Requirements of Rationality:

1) Impossibility of contradictory beliefs or preferences

2) Impossibility of intransitive preferences

3) Conformity to the axioms of probability calculus

Page 7: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Weak requirements of Rationality

1) Impossibility of contradictory beliefs or preferences:

if an actor holds contradictory beliefs she cannot reason

if an actor hold contradictory preferences she can choose any option

Important: contradiction refers to beliefs or preferences at a given moment in time.

Page 8: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Weak requirements of Rationality

2) Impossibility of intransitive preferences:if an actor prefers alternative a over b and b over c ,

she must prefer a over c . One can create a “money pump” from a person with

intransitive preferences. Person Z has the following preference ordering: a>b>c>a ; she holds a. I can persuade her to

exchange a for c provided she pays 1$; then I can persuade her to exchange c for b for 1$ more; again I can persuade her to pay 1$ to exchange b for a. She holds a as at the beginning but she is $3 poorer

Page 9: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Weak requirements of Rationality

3) Conformity to the axioms of probability calculus

A1 No probability is less than zero. P(i)>=0

A2 Probability of a sure event is one

A3 If i and j are two mutually exclusive events, then P (i or j)= P(i )+P(j)

Page 10: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

10

A small quantity of formalization... A choice between different alternatives

S = (s1, s2, … si)

Each alternative can be put on a nominal, ordinal o cardinal scale

The choice produces a result R = (r1, r2, … ri)

An actor chooses as a function of a preference ordering relation among the results. Such ordering is complete transitive

Page 11: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

11

Utility

A ( mostly) continuous preference ordering assigns a position to each result

We can assign a number to such ordering called utility

A result r can be characterized by these features (x,y,z) to which an utility value u = f(x,y,z) corresponds

Rational action maximizes the utility function

Page 12: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

12

Single-peak utility functions

One dimension (the real line)Actor with ideal point A, outcome xLinear utility function:

U = - |x – A|

Quadratic utility function:U = - (x – A)2

U

A x

U

A x

+

+

-

-

Page 13: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

13

Expected utility

There could be unknown factors that could come in between a choice of action and a result

.. as a function of different states of the world M = (m1, m2, … mi)

Choice under uncertainty is based associating subjective probabilities to each state of the world, choosing a lottery of results L = (r1,p1;r2,p2; … ri,pi)

We have then an expected utility function EU = u(r1)p1+u(r2)p2+ … u(ri)pi

Page 14: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Strong Requirements of Rationality

1) Conformity to the prescriptions of game theory

2) Probabilities approximate objective frequencies in equilibrium

3) Beliefs approximate reality in equilibrium

Page 15: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

15

Strong Requirements of Rationality1) Conformity to the prescriptions of game

theory: digression..Uncertainty between choices and outcomes

could also result from the (unknown) decisions taken by other rational actors

Game theory studies the strategic interdependence between actors, how one actor’s utility is also function of other actors’ decisions, how actors choose best strategies, and the resulting equilibrium outcomes

Page 16: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

16

Principles of game theory

Players have preferences and utility functions Game is represented by a sequence of moves

(actors’ – or Nature – choices) How information is distributed is key Strategy is a complete action plan, based on the

anticipation of other actors’ decisions A combination of strategies determines an outcome This outcome determines a payoff to each player,

and a level of utility (the payoff is an argument of the player’s utility function)

Page 17: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

17

Principles of game theory (2)

Games in the extensive form are represented by a decision tree

which illustrates the possible conditional strategic options

The distribution of information: complete/incomplete (game structure), perfect/imperfect (actors’ types), common knowledge

Page 18: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

18

Principles of game theory (3)

Solutions is by backward induction, by identifying the subgame perfect equilibria

Nash equilibrium: the profile of the best responses, conditional on the anticipation of other actors’ best responses

A Nash equilibrium is stable: no-one unilaterally changes strategy

Page 19: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Strong Requirements of Rationality

2) Subjective probabilities approximate objective frequencies in equilibrium.Every “player” makes the best use of his previous probability assessments and the new information that he gets from the environment.Beliefs are updated according to Bayes’s rule.

Page 20: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

• P(A) is the prior probability or marginal probability of A. It is "prior" in the sense that it doesnot take into account any information about B.

• P(A|B) is the conditional probability of A, given B. It is also called the posterior probabilitybecause it is derived from or depends upon the specified value of B.

• P(B|A) is the conditional probability of B given A. • P(B) is the prior or marginal probability of B

Bayesian updating of beliefs

Strong Requirements of Rationality

Page 21: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Strong Requirements of Rationality

3) Beliefs should approximate reality

Beliefs and behavior not only have to be consistent but also have to correspond with the real world at equilibrium

Page 22: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Rational Choice: only a normative theory ?

Usual criticism to the Rational Choice theory:

In the real world people are incapable of making all the required calculations and computations. Rational choice is not “realistic”

Usual answer (M.Friedman): people behave as if they were rational:

“In so far as a theory can be said to have “assumptions” at all, and in so far as their “realism” can be judged independently of the validity of predictions, the relation between the significance of a theory and the “realism” of its “assumptions” is almost the opposite of that suggested by the view under criticism. Truly important and significant hypotheses will be found to have “assumptions” that are wildly inaccurate descriptive representations of reality, and, in general, the more significant the theory, the more unrealistic the assumptions (in this sense). The reason is simple. A hypothesis is important if it “explains” much by little, that is, if it abstracts the common and crucial elements from the mass of complex and detailed circumstances surrounding the phenomena to be explained and permits valid predictions on the basis of them alone. To be important, therefore, a hypothesis must be descriptively false in its assumptions; it takes account of, and accounts for, none of the many other attendant circumstances, since its very success shows them to be irrelevant for the phenomena to be explained.

As if argument claims that the rationality assumption, regardless of its accuracy, is a way to model human behaviour Rationality as model argument (look at Fiorina article)

Page 23: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Rational Choice: only a normative theory ?

Tsebelis counter argument to “rationality as model argument” :

1)“the assumptions of a theory are, in a trivial sense, also conclusions of the theory . A scientist who is willing to make the “wildly inaccurate” assumptions Friedman wants him to make admits that “wildly inaccurate” behaviour can be generated as a conclusion of his theory”.

2) Rationality refers to a subset of human behavior. Rational choice cannot explain every phenomenon. Rational choice is a better approach to situations in which the actors’ identity and goals are established and the rules of interaction are precise and known to the interacting agents.

Political games structure the situation as well ; the study of political actors under the assumption of rationality is a legitimate approximation of realistic situations, motives, calculations and behavior.

5 arguments

Page 24: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Five arguments in defense of the Rational Choice Approach (Tsebelis)

1) Salience of issues and information

2) Learning

3) Heterogeneity of individuals

4) Natural Selection

5) Statistics

Page 25: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Five arguments in defense of the Rational Choice Approach (Tsebelis)

3) Heterogeneity of individuals: equilibria with some sophisticated agents (read fully rational) will tend toward equilibria where all agents are sophisticated in the cases of “congestion effects” , that is where each agent is worse off the higher the number of other agents who make the same choice as he. An equilibrium with a small number of sophisticated agents is practically indistinguishable from an equilibrium where all agents are sophisticated

Page 26: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Five arguments in defense of the Rational Choice Approach (Tsebelis)

3) Statistics: rationality is a small but systematic component of any individual , and all other influences are distributed at random. The systematic component has a magnitude x and the random element is normally distributed with variance s. Each individual of population will execute a decision in the interval [x-(2s), x+(2s)] 95 percent of the time. However in a sample of a million individuals the average individual will make a decision in the interval [x-(2s/1000), x+(2s/1000)] 95 percent of the time

Page 27: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Rational choice: a theory for the institutionsIn the rational choice approach individual action is assumed to be an optimal adaptation to an institutional environment, and the interaction among individuals is assumed to be an optimal response to each other. The prevailing institutions (the rules of the game) determine the behavior of the actors, which in turn produces political or social outcomes.

Rational choice is unconcerned with individuals or actors per se and focuses its attention on political and social institutions

Page 28: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Advantages of the Rational choice Approach

• Theoretical clarity and parsimony Ad hoc explanations are eliminated• Equilibrium analysisOptimal behavior is discovered, it is easy to formulate

hypothesis and to eliminate alternative explanations. • Deductive reasoning In RC we deal with tautology. If a model does not work , as

the model is still correct, you have to change the assumption (usually the structure of the game..).Therefore also the “wrong” models are useful for the cumulation of the knowledge.

• Interchangeability of individuals

Page 29: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

29

Positive political Theory: An introduction

Lecture 2: Basic tools of analytical politics

Francesco Zucchini

Page 30: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

30

Spatial representation

In case of more than one dimension, we have iso-utility curves (indifference curves)

Utility diminishes as we move away from the ideal point

The shape of the iso-utility curve varies as a function of the salience of the dimensions

Page 31: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Continuous utility functions in 1 dimensionUtility

Dimension xxi

Spatial representation

Page 32: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

..and in 2 Dimensions

Iso-utility curves or indifference curves

Page 33: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

33

Spatial representation

In case of more than one dimension, we have iso-utility curves (indifference curves)

Utility diminishes as we move away from the ideal point

The shape of the iso-utility curve varies as a function of the salience of the dimensions

Page 34: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

34

Indifference curve

I

X

YP

Z

Player I prefers a point which is inside the indifference curve (such as P) to one outside (such as Z), and is indifferent between two points on the same curve (like X and Y)

Page 35: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

35

A basic equation in positive political theoryPreferences x Institutions = Outcomes

Comparative statics (i.e. propositions) that form the basis to testable hypotheses can be derived as follows:

As preferences change, outcomes changeAs institutions change, outcomes change

Page 36: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

36

A typical institution: a voting rule Committee/assembly of N members K = p N minimum number of members to approve a committee’s

decision

In Simple Majority Rule (SMR) K > (1/2)N

Of course, there are several exceptions to SMR Filibuster in the U.S. Senate: debate must end with a motion of

cloture approved by 3/5 (60 over 100) of senators UE Council of Ministers: qualified majority (255 votes out of 345,

73.9 %) Bicameralism

Page 37: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

37

A proposition: the voting paradox If a majority prefers some alternatives to x, these set

of alternatives is called winset of x, W(x); if an alternative x has an empty winset , W(x)=Ø, then x is an equilibrium, namely is a majority position that cannot be defeated.

If no alternative has an empty winset then we have cycling majorities

SMR cannot guarantee a majority position – a Condorcet winner which can beat any other alternative in pairwise comparisons. In other terms SMR cannot guarantee that there is an alternative x whose W(x)=Ø

Page 38: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Condorcet Paradox

Imagine 3 legislators with the following preference’s orders

Alternatives can be chosen by majority rule

Whoever control the agenda can completely control the outcome

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

Page 39: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

1,2 choose z against x but..

Page 40: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

2,3 choose y against z but again..

Page 41: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

1,3 choose x against y..

z defeats x that defeats y that defeats z.

Page 42: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Whoever control the agenda can completely control the outcome

Imagine a legislative voting in two steps. If Leg 1 is the agenda setter..

ranking Leg.1Leg.2Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

x y

x

z

z

Page 43: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Whoever control the agenda can completely control the outcome If Leg 2 is the agenda setter..

ranking Leg.1Leg.2Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

z x

z

y

y

Page 44: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Whoever control the agenda can completely control the outcome

If Leg 3 is the agenda setter.

ranking Leg.1Leg.2Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

z y

y

x

x

Page 45: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Probability of Cyclical Majority

Number of Voters (n)

N.Alternatives (m) 3 5 7 9 11 limit

3 0.056 0.069 0.075 0.078 0.080 0.088

4 0.111 0.139 0.150 0.156 0.160 0.176

5 0.160 0.200 0.215 0.251

6 0.202 0.315

Limit 1.000 1.000 1.000 1.000 1.000 1.000

Page 46: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

46

Median voter theorem

A committee chooses by SMR among alternatives

Single-peak Euclidean utility functions

Winset of x W(x): set of alternatives that beat x in a committee that decides by SMR

Median voter theorem (Black): If the member of a committee G have single-peaked utility functions on a single dimension, the winset of the ideal point of the median voter is empty. W(xmed)=Ø

Page 47: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

When the alternatives can be disposed on only one dimension namely when the utility curves of each member are single peaked then there is a Condorcet winner: the median voter

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z z x

2° x y z

3° y x y

y z x

Utility

Page 48: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

When the alternatives can be disposed on only one dimension namely when the utility curves of each member are single peaked then there is a Condorcet winner: the median voter

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3

1° x z y

2° y y z

3° z x x

x y z

Utility

Page 49: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

When there is a Condorcet paradox (no winner) then the alternatives cannot be disposed on only one dimension namely the utility curves of each member are not single peaked

x z

Utility

ranking Leg.1Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

y

2 peaks

Page 50: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

When there is a Condorcet paradox (no winner) then the alternatives cannot be disposed on only one dimension namely the utility curves of each “legislator” are not ever single peaked

y z

Utility

ranking Leg.1Leg.2 Leg.3

1° z y x

2° x z y

3° y x z

x

2 peaks

In 2 or more dimensions a unique equilibrium is not guaranteed

Page 51: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

51

Electoral competition and median voter theorem

Page 52: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

52

Theorems

Chaos Theorem (McKelvey): In a multi-dimensional space, there are no points with a empty winset or no Condocet winners, if we apply SMR (with one exception, see below). There will be chaos and the agenda setter (i.e. which controls the order of voting) can determine the final outcome

Plot Theorem: In a multi-dimensional space, if actors’ ideal points are distributed radially and symmetrically with respect to x*, then the winset of x* is empty

Change of rules, institutions (bicameralism, dimension-by-dimension voting) can produce a stable equilibrium

Page 53: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

53

Cycling majorities

Page 54: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Plott’s Theorem

Page 55: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Plott’s Theorem

Page 56: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

Instability, majority rule and multidimensional space

Page 57: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

How institutions can affect the stability (and the nature) of the decisions ? Example with bicameralism

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° x z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

Imagine 6 legislators in one chamber and the following profiles of preferences.

Page 58: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

2,3,5,6 prefer x to z but..

Page 59: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

1,4,5,6 prefer w to x, but..

Page 60: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

all prefer y to w, but..

Page 61: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

1,2,3,4 prefer z to y, ….CYCLE!

Page 62: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

Imagine that the same legislators are grouped in two chambers in the following way (red chamber 1,2,3 and blue chamber 4,5,6) and that the final alternative must win a majority in both chambers.

2, 3, and 5, 6 prefer x to z

Page 63: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

However now w cannot be preferred to x as in the Red Chamber only 1 prefers w to x. …once approved against z , x cannot be defeated any longer

What happen if we start the process with y ?All legislators prefer y to w..

Page 64: Positive political Theory: an introduction General information

ranking Leg.1 Leg.2 Leg.3 Leg.4 Leg.5 Leg.6

1° z x x z y y

2° y z z y w w

3° w y y w x x

4° x w w x z z

However now z cannot be chosen against y as in the Blue Chamber only 4 prefers z to y. …once approved against w , y cannot be defeated any longer.

We have two stable equilibria: x and y. The final outcome will depend on the initial status quo (SQ)

1) If x (y) is the SQ then the final outcome will be x (y)2) If z (w) is the SQ then the final outcome will be x (y)