29
Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Prioritarianism and Climate Change

Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop

June, 2015

Page 2: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Overview of Talk

• The social welfare function (SWF) framework• The prioritarian SWF (presented, and

contrasted with the utilitarian SWF)• Prioritarianism under risk: “Ex ante” versus “ex

post” prioritarianism • Possible implications for climate change:

research questions? • This talk based upon joint work with Nicolas Treich, Adler/Treich (2015),

although he should not be held responsible for everything I say here!

Page 3: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

The SWF Framework

• An interpersonally comparable well-being function w(.) and a rule E whereby outcomes are ranked:

outcome x is at least as good as y (x ≽E y)iff

(w1(x), w2(x), …, wN(x)) E (w1(y), w2(y), …, wN(y))• Actions (policy choices) are in turn ranked in light of the

outcome ranking.• SWFs originate in theoretical welfare economics; now used in

optimal tax theory, public finance, environmental economics (including climate change), etc.

• Adler, Well-Being and Fair Distribution (2012); Adler and Fleurbaey, Oxford Handbook of Well-Being and Public Policy (forthcoming), provide overviews

Page 4: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

The SWF as a tool for ethical decisionmaking

• I view the SWF as a tool for ethical (moral, “social”) decisionmaking. Specifying an SWF means making ethical choices. Descriptive facts don’t settle normative questions. (Hume et al: no “ought” from “is.”) Moreover, since individuals in any modern, pluralistic, society have diverse ethical views, it’s problematic (I think) to see society having a single SWF, or to try to “infer” what that SWF is. The electoral process determines whose ethical views get to influence policy (for now, until the next election).

• Bergson: “A notable feature in welfare economics is the attempt to formulate a criterion of social welfare without recourse to controversial ethical premises… [T]his goal for the criterion is an illusion.” Harsanyi: “This function Wi that individual i will use in evaluating social situations from a moral point of view will be called his social welfare function.”

• That said, ethical thinking is not wholly unstructured. The axiomatic method of welfare economics/social choice theory is hugely valuable in sorting through the “space” of SWFs and well-being measures; and contemporary moral philosophy, in bringing to light sophisticated arguments for different possible approaches.

Page 5: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Normative Choices in Elaborating the SWF Framework

• What is the well-being measure w(.)? Preferences, happiness, objective goods.

• What is the ethical rule E for ranking well-being vectors? Utilitarian, Prioritarian, other

• Application under risk (well-defined probabilities) Utilitarianism, ex ante prioritarianism, ex post prioritarianism, “transformed” versions

• Deep uncertainty• Variable populations E.g., Parfit’s “repugnant conclusion”

• Ethics versus self-interest. Sidgwick. To what extent is it reasonable for the current generation to give priority to its own interests, even though an ethical perspective requires impartiality vis a vis the future?

Page 6: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

The Well-Being Measure• Let c denote an individual’s consumption of marketed goods; a her non-market attributes

(e.g., health, environmental quality); and R her preferences over (c, a) bundles. • Different forms for w(.):

– Objective good/”capability”: w(c, a, R) = o(c, a)– Happiness: w(c, a, R) = h(c, a, R)– Preference-based

• Simple case: Individuals have the same preferences. Very often assumed by economists who use SWFs. w(c, a, R) = uR(c, a), with uR(.) a vNM utility function representing the common preferences R—or F(uR(c, a)), F(.) increasing, in more general formulation.

• Heterogeneous preferences. Harsanyi’s concept of “extended preferences”. w(c, a, R) = s(R)uR(c, a) + t(R), with s(.) and t(.) scaling factors for the various vNM functions—or F(s(R)uR(c, a) + t(R))

• Complex mixture of normative and descriptive. Although the choice between these views is normative, the application of specific views will in turn depend on empirical facts. On the preference view, well-being depends upon individuals’ preferences; and it’s in turn an empirical question what those preferences are.

Page 7: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

The Rule E These formulas assume fixed population: N(x) = N(y) = N for all outcomes

• Utilitarian: x at least as good as y iff ∑wi(x) ≥ ∑wi(y)

• Prioritarian: x at least as good as y iff ∑g(wi(x)) ≥ ∑g(wi(y)), with g(.) strictly increasing and concave.

• Prioritarians give greater weight to well-being changes affecting worse off individuals. Vibrant philosophical literature starting with Parfit (1991). Key axiomatic difference from utilitarianism is Pigou-Dalton principle. PD principle says that (1, 3, 8, 10) is ethically preferred to (1, 2, 9, 10).

• Atkinson SWF: (1-γ)-1∑wi1-γ, with γ an inequality aversion parameter >0

(becomes utilitarian at 0, and leximin at ∞)

Page 8: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

The Prioritarian SWF

Page 9: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Axioms for E

• Pareto superiority: (3, 4, 10, 13) (3, 4, 10, 12)≻• Anonymity/Impartiality: (7, 12, 4, 60) (12, 60, 4, 7)∼• Pigou-Dalton: (1, 3, 8, 10) (1, 2, 9, 10)≻• Separability:

(7, 100, 100, 7) (4, 100, 100, 12) iff ≽(7, 7, 7, 7) (4, 7, 7, 12)≽

• Continuity: If (1, 3, 50000, 50000) (1, 3, 6, 8), then (1, 3±≻ ε, 50000, 50000) (1, 3, 6, 8) for ≻ ε sufficiently small

• Ratio rescaling invariance: (10, 12, 17, 20) (10, 10, 20, 20) iff (50, 60, 85, 100) (50, ≽ ≽50, 100, 100)

Page 10: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015
Page 11: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Three Justificatory Schemes• Different ways to choose among SWFs, consistent with the

“separateness of persons”• The veil of ignorance. Harsanyi versus Rawls. The Harsanyi VOI (with a risk

neutrality assumption) yields utilitarianism. x ≽M y iff (1/N, (x 1); … ; 1/N, (x N)) at least as good as (1/N, (y 1); … ; 1//N, (y N)) iff 1/N w1(x) + …+ 1/N wN(x) ≥ 1/N w1(y) + …+ 1/N wN(y)

• Temkin’s complaints (“claims within outcomes”). In each outcome, worse-off individuals have complaints against better-off individuals (modulo resp.). The ranking of outcomes (in light of persons’ interests) balances complaint

minimization versus overall well-being. • Adler “claims across outcomes” (building on Nagel). As between two

outcomes, each individual has a claim in favor of the outcome in which she is better off. The ranking of outcomes (in light of persons’ interests) balances these claims.

Page 12: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Claims across Outcomes versus Complaints (claims within outcomes)

x y Amy 10 10

Betty 10 10

Mark Z 90 100

z w Amy 5 5

Betty 60 70

Mark Z

90 80

• Why believe that the balancing of overall well-being and complaint minimization necessarily yields the Pareto superior outcome? By contrast, the claim-across-outcome view directly justifies both the Pareto and Pigou-Dalton principles. Or, it helps us see the deep connection between these principles; or, why, a Paretian welfarist should also care about equity in the sense of Pigou-Dalton.

Page 13: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Equality and Priority• Do prioritarians care about equality? Extensionally, yes. A decomposition

theorem: Any SWF that respects Pareto, anonymity, Pigou-Dalton and continuity (with or without separability) can be represented as overall well-being discounted by the degree of inequality.

x ≽M y iff ∑g(wi(x)) ≥ ∑g(wi(y)) iff

[1-Ig(w1(x), …, wN(x))] ∑(wi(x)) ≥ [1-Ig(w1(y), …, wN(y))] ∑(wi(y))

• However, the justification offered here for the prioritarian SWF is based on individuals’ claims-across-outcomes, not a concern for comparative well-being within outcomes. (Contrast the case in which Temkin-style claims balanced against overall well-being somehow yield a Paretian, Pigou-Dalton, and separable SWF!).

Page 14: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Choosing a g(.) function

• The Atkinson family is attractive: g(w) = (1-γ)-1w1-γ • γ is an ethical parameter, capturing the “social planner’s” own

moral/ethical views. Problematic to try to estimate empirically. Not to be conflated with parameter λR of individual risk aversion w/r/t consumption for CRRA utility.

• Leaky bucket question. Poor is at utility level W, while Rich is at level KW. If we reduce Rich’s well-being by ∆w, and increase Poor’s by f∆w, 0<f<1, what is the smallest value of f such that this remains a moral improvement? For given γ, f = (1/K)γ

• Equalization question. Is it an improvement to move from (W, W*) to (W+, W+), where W + W* > 2W+?

1 1( ) (1 )RR Ru c c

Page 15: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

A contrast with climate change scholarship

• Assuming a preference-based well-being measure, and the Atkinson g(.), the prioritarian formula for ranking outcomes (modulo zeroing-out) is:

E(x) = (1-γ)-1 ∑i [s(Ri)uRi(ci(x), ai(x)) + t(Ri)]1-γ • By contrast, the utilitarian formula often used in climate change scholarship

ignores non-market attributes and preference heterogeneity, has a pure time preference (well-being discount factor), and no inequality-aversion prameter

E(x) = ∑i di u(ci), with di > dj if individual j exists later in time than i

• Even ignoring preference heterogeneity and non-market attributes, and with CRRA consumption utility, the two approaches are different:

E(x) = (1-γ)-1 ∑i [u(ci)]1-γ vs. E(x) = ∑i diu(ci), with u(ci) = (1-λ)-1ci1-λ

• Time preference: violates anonymity; an ad hoc way to handle extinction risk; and counterintuitive features of zero discounting can be mitigated, by prioritarians, by increasing the inequality-aversion parameter

Page 16: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Utilitarianism and Prioritarianism under Risk

• Utilitarianism E(a) = ∑x πa(x) (∑i wi(x)) = ∑i ∑xπa(x) wi(x)

• “Ex post” prior. E(a) = ∑xπa(x) (∑i g(wi(x))) = ∑i∑xπa(x) g(wi(x))

• “Ex ante” prior. E(a) = ∑i g(∑x πa(x) wi(x))

• Utilitarianism and ex post prioritarianism apply expected-utility theory at the level of ethical choice: maximizing expected ethical value (i.e., sum of utilities or transformed utilities). Ex ante prioritarianism does not.

• “Transformed” approaches: ∑x πa(x) H(∑i wi(x)) or ∑x πa(x) H(∑i g(wi(x))). Problematic w/r/t separability

Page 17: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Util. vs. EPP vs. EAP

Policy a Policy bx y Exp. wb z zz Exp. wb

Jim 70 30 50 50 60 55June 30 70 50 50 40 45

Note: The outcomes are equiprobable, i.e., πa(x) = πa(y) = 1/2, and πb(z) = πb(zz) = 1/2.

Utilitarianism is indifferent between the policies. Ex post prioritarianism prefers policy b. Ex ante prioritarianism prefers policy a.

Page 18: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Which is most attractive?

Stochastic Dominance

Sure Thing

Time Consistent

Pigou Dalton

Ex Ante Pareto

Util. Yes Yes Yes No Yes EPP Yes Yes Yes Yes No EAP No No No Yes Yes

For those who find axioms of stochastic dominance, sure thing, and time consistency to be normatively compelling—anyone attracted to expected utility theory! —EAP will seem highly problematic. The choice is, for them, between utilitarianism and EPP.

Page 19: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Illustrating the axiomsPolicy a Policy bx y Exp. wb z zz Exp. wb

Jim 10 90 50 50-ε 50-ε 50-εJune 90 10 50 50-ε 50-ε 50-ε

Illustrates stochastic dominance and ex ante Pareto for three approaches

Policy a Policy bx y Exp. wb z y EU

Jim 80 50 65 90 50 70June 20 50 35 10 50 30

Policy a* Policy b*x y* Exp. wb z y* Exp. wb

Jim 80 10 45 90 10 50June 20 200 110 10 200 105

Ilustrates sure thing principle for three approaches

Page 20: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Time Inconsistency• A simple example. Assume 2 generations. The news about the effect of

climate change on the second generation can either be “good” or “bad.” At an initial point, the decisionmaker assigns each equal probability. She then learns and, if “bad” news, can mitigate the bad effects (at some cost to the current generation). If “good,” the well-being of the two generations is (200, 300). With “bad” and no mitigation it’s (200, 100); with “bad” and mitigation it’s (140, 140).

• Assume a prioritarian sufficiently inequality averse to prefer the outcome (140, 140) to (200, 100). At the initial point, the expected well-being of the generations, with a plan not to mitigate upon learning the news, is (200, 200); with a plan to mitigate, it’s (170, 220). Thus EAP initially plans not to mitigate – but then, if bad news is learned, prefers to mitigate.

• By contrast, Util consistently plans not to mitigate if bad news, and EPP consistently plan to mitigate if bad news.

Page 21: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

EPP vs. Utilitarianism: Climate Policy

• The extent to which EPP (ex post prioritarianism) and utilitarianism diverge substantially with respect to climate policy, given the empirics of our climate system, global economy and population, etc., is an open question, on which research is now needed. What follows are possible differences …

Page 22: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Climate Change: SCCU vs. SCCEPP

max

2

1 1

( )) ( )

( ( )) ( )

Tt

t t tt s

cN g u c u c

e

g u c u c

P

P PP

P

max

2

1

( )

( )

Tt

t tt s

cN u c

e

u c

P

PP

PSCCU

SCCEPP

c is per capita (normalized) consumption. Equality within each generation. P is an economic/climate path. es is emissions at time s. Current consumption c1 is numeraire.

Note that SCCEPP > < SCCU depending on the relative likelihood of paths where future generations are worse off vs. better off compared to the present

Page 23: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Optimal Abatement

• A toy model. 2 periods; resources in first period either consumed or invested at rate r; CRRA utility. With intragenerational equality, utilitarian optimum is c2 = c1(1+r)1/λ. Prioritarian optimum is c2 = c1(1+r)

1/[λ+γ(1-λ)]. Assuming λ < 1 (to avoid negative utilities), less is invested for future and less inequality between generations. As γ approaches infinity, the optimal allocation approaches equality between the 2 generations

• With π = fraction held by worse off in second generation and (to simplify) linear utility, the utilitarian invests everything. The prioritarian optimum is c2 = (c1/2)(1+r)1/γ[π1-y+(1-π)1-γ]1/γ. Subtle interactions between π and γ, i.e., between future inequality and inequality aversion. Ratio c2/c1 is increasing in π for γ < 1, independent for γ =1, and decreasing in π for γ > 1

Page 24: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Other Climate Change Implications

• “Catastrophe”: Let WL be a specified “low” level of well-being. A policy will reduce the risk of generations falling below WL, at some cost to above-WL generations. EPP is willing to incur greater such costs than Utilitarianism.

• Decreasing Risk: A policy reduces the downside risk for a given generation of being badly off, but also their upside prospects, so that expected well-being remains the same. EPP prefers the policy, while Utilitarianism is indifferent.

Page 25: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Deep Uncertainty

• How to model this is a burgeoning area of research in economics and decision theory (“ambiguity”). Many approaches now use a set of probabilities, e.g., Gilboa/Schmeidler maximin EU, or Klibanoff et al. second-order risk aversion. It would seem that such approaches are equally applicable to Util. and EPP, simply changing the social maximand.

( ) ( ) ( )Pa

P x

P H x E x

Klibanoff et al., with E(x) either sum of utilities for Util. or sum of transformed utilities for EPP.

Page 26: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Variable population• Average utilitarianism/prioritarianism: Non-separable, violates “negative

expansion” principle

• Total utilitarianism/prioritarianism: “Repugnant conclusion”

• Critical level utilitarianism/prioritarianism: With critical level above level of life just worth living/equally good as nonexistence, this approach is separable, satisfies “negative expansion” principle, and no repugnant conclusion.

E(x) =∑i=1 to N(x) (wi(x) – w*) or E(x) = ∑i=1 to N(x) (g(wi(x)) – g(w*))with w* the critical level of well-being (above a life just worth living)

• Generalizes straightforwardly using EPP or utilitarian formula to choice under risk

E(a) =∑xπa(x) (∑I to N(x) wi(x) – w*) or E(a)=∑xπa(x) (∑I to N(x) g(wi(x)) – g(w*))

Page 27: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Scaling the Well-Being Function• While a well-being function w(c, a, R) unique up to a positive affine

transformation—which provides intra- and interpersonal comparisons of levels and differences—is sufficient for utilitarianism, this is not true for prioritarianism. In particular, the Atkinson SWF requires a w(.) unique up to a ratio transformation.

Original Renumbering 1 Renumbering 2 Renumbering 3x y Diff. x y Diff. x y Diff. x y Diff.

Jim 10 11 1 200 220 20 2 12 10 30 33 3Sue 30 25 −5 60 50 −10 202 152 −50 90 75 −15

Sum 40 36 260 270 204 164 120 108

• Renumbering 1 is individual-specific ratio transformation (preserves only intrapersonal info). Renumbering 2 is common affine transformation (preserves intra- and interpersonal levels and differences). Renumbering 3 is common ratio transform. Utilitarian SWF invariant to Renumberings 2 and 3, Atkinson only to 3.

Page 28: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Scaling the Well-Being Function• We construct w(.) by identifying a “zero” history (czero, azero, Rzero)• w(c, a, R) = [s(R)uR(c, a) + t(R)] − [s(Rzero) uR-zero(czero,azero) + t(Rzero)]• By construction, w(czero, azero, Rzero) = 0. • With the Atkinson SWF, the zero history (czero, azero, Rzero) is both

the “horizon of ethical assessment” and the point of absolute ethical priority. The Atkinson SWF is “badly behaved” if anyone has a negative w value in any outcome. Moreover, for any “positive” history such that w(c, a, R) > 0, the ratio between the ethical impact of adding an increment of well-being ∆w to the zero history, and the ethical impact of adding ∆w to the positive history, becomes infinite.

• (czero, azero, Rzero) should not be conflated with the level of a life worth living (cworth, aworth, Rworth) nor with the critical level history (ccrit, acrit, Rcrit).

• Relation to Weitzman’s “dismal theorem”

Page 29: Prioritarianism and Climate Change Matthew Adler, Duke University LSE, MSU Workshop June, 2015

Significance of choice of zero history Zero bundle at (csub, hdeath): w(c,h) =

log(c)m(h) – log(csub)m(hdeath). Zero bundle at (csub, hworst): w(c,h) = log(c)m(h) – log(csub)m(hworst)

Marginal moral impact of $1 for person with $100,000 and health h

w(100,000, h)-γ m(h)(1/100,000) = (11.51m(h) –log(csub)m(hdeath))-γ xm(h)(1/100,000)

w(100,000, h)-γ m(h)(1/100,000) = (11.51m(h) –log(csub)m(hworst))-γ xm(h)(1/100,000)

Marginal moral impact of $1 for person with $20,000 and health h

w(20,000, h)-γ m(h)(1/100,000) = (4.30m(h) –log(csub)m(hdeath))-γ xm(h)(1/20,000)

w(20,000, h)-γ m(h)(1/100,000) = (4.30m(h) –log(csub)m(hworst))-γ xm(h)(1/20,000)

Comparative marginal moral impact of $1

1 4.30 ( ) log( ) ( )5 11.51 ( ) log( ) ( )

sub death

sub death

m h c m hm h c m h

1 4.30 ( ) log( ) ( )5 11.51 ( ) log( ) ( )

sub worst

sub worst

m h c m hm h c m h