SSRN-id2229053.pdf

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    1/21Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2229053

    DEPARTMENT OF

    ECONOMICS

    Public Finance without Taxation:Free-Riding as Institutional Artifact

    Richard E. Wagner

    George Mason UniversityDepartment of EconomicsWorking Paper No. 13-05

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    2/21Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2229053

    1

    Public Finance without Taxation:Free-Riding as Institutional Artifact:

    Richard E. Wagner

    Department of Economics, 3G4George Mason UniversityFairfax, VA 22030, USA

    Tel: ++1-703-993-1132Fax: +1-703-993-1133

    [email protected]

    http://mason.gmu.edu/~rwagner

    Abstract

    Expositions of the theory of public finance mostly wrongly assume thattaxation is necessary to finance public goods. Taxation isnt necessary to financepublic goods because free riding is an institutional artifact of the analyticaldichotomy between public and private goods, which prevents recognition ofsocial interaction through the institutions of civil society. Free riding is alsoabetted through the particular institutional presumption that public goods must beprovided by collective entities that operate without alienable ownership. Freeriding is a product of a particular institutional arrangement and is not a universalquality of societal living together. There is a deep similarity between cities andsuch entities as hotels and malls which supply public goods without taxation.Center stage in the theory of public finance can alternatively be occupied by thesocial organization of shared consumption, with taxation relegated to side showstatus.

    Keywords: free riding; forced carrying; preference revelation; collective propertyrights; institution-centered public finance; markets and public goods; civil society;political elites; ruling classes

    JEL Codes: D23, D71, H20, H41

    [Preliminary draft for presentation at Public Choice Society, New Orleans, March7-10, 2013]

    mailto:[email protected]:[email protected]://mason.gmu.edu/~rwagnerhttp://mason.gmu.edu/~rwagnerhttp://mason.gmu.edu/~rwagnermailto:[email protected]
  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    3/21Electronic copy available at: http://ssrn.com/abstract=2229053

    2

    Public Finance without Taxation:Free-Riding as Institutional Artifact:

    Taxation occupies center stage in the contemporary theory of public

    finance, as the numerous treatments of optimal and corrective taxation illustrate.

    This centrality of taxation is articulated cogently in

    1955) oft-cited papers that draw a stark contrast between public goods and

    private goods. That contrast creates a disjunction between two domains of

    economic activity. One is the domain of private goods where market pricing can

    operate as envisioned by the theory of free competition. The other is the domain

    of public goods that must be provided by taxation through some political process

    that is independent of the market process because free riding would prevent

    ordinary market processes from generating a supply of those goods. While this

    mode of thought has found nearly universal acceptance among fiscal scholars, it

    nonetheless universalizes what is really just a particular institutional arrangement

    when other arrangements have existed historically and can be understood

    theoretically. Indeed, it is acceptance of that particular institutional arrangement

    and not analytical necessity that sets taxation in the center of the analytical stage

    for the theory of public finance. By exploring how free riding is an artifact of a

    particular set of institutional presumptions, this paper explains why the social

    organization of shared consumption and not taxation should occupy the center of

    the analytical stage for a theory of public finance. In other words, this paper

    accepts the manifold existence of public goods and explains how their social

    provisioning can be accommodated within an institutional framework that is not

    centered on taxation.

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    4/21

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    5/21

    4

    arrangements and processes through which public goods can be and have been

    supplied through market-like processes, as illustrated by MacCallum (1970),

    Foldvary (1994), and the essays collected in (Beito, Gordon, and Tabarrok 2002).

    The common public-private dichotomy reduces reality to an institutional

    dichotomy when societies are more accurately characterized as trichotomies.

    The missing element in the common dichotomy is the congeries of organizations

    various voluntary organizations that undertake collective action. Public finance

    theorists have too readily accepted the Samuelsonian lens as the proper way for

    posing questions regarding the social organization of shared consumption,

    thereby short-circuiting the examination of different institutional arrangements.

    Behind this common dichotomy lies the presumption that markets and

    governments provide a useful way of thinking about the world we experience.

    Part of this mode of thought is driven by the equilibrium-centered reduction of

    complex networks of interaction to simple, representative instances of median-

    voter choice. While this reduction might seem to bring analytical tractability, it

    also distorts the resulting analysis by reducing social interaction to a single act of

    choice under two environments. Once, shared consumption is examined within

    the trichotomy of market, state, and civil society, taxation recedes in significance

    for a theory of public finance, as Wagner (2011, 2012b) sketches. Recognition of

    this trichotomy expands the scope for social collaboration in the supply of public

    goods. Taxation becomes but a side-show for a theory of public finance because

    center stage is occupied by a focus on how alternative institutional arrangements

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    6/21

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    7/21

    6

    European lands. For instance, in Saxony and Prussia, public enterprises

    generated nearly 60 percent of public revenue, and with agricultural production

    generating up to 20 percent.

    Starting late in the 19thcentury, such Italian economists as Antonio De Viti

    de Marco and Maffeo Pantaleoni sought to incorporate governmental activity

    within the general framework of economic analysis. The animating vision behind

    their efforts was a desire to incorporate collective activity within the framework of

    the theory of economic equilibrium that was then experiencing substantial

    refinement. These scholars sought to incorporate such economic principles as

    utility, cost, demand, production, and pricing into a general theory of economic

    equilibrium, where politically organized activity was an integral and intelligible

    part of the whole story. Indeed, Buchanan (1968), with its title The Demand and

    Supply of Public Goods, was an effort to carry forward this Italianate orientation

    as an alternative to the Samuelsonian-Musgravian formulation.

    De Viti (1888) was an initial formulation in this respect, which he extended

    and amplified throughout his career, which included long service as a member of

    Parliament, and which culminated in an English translation of his final formulation

    a form of pricing that was but one side of the transaction through which collective

    all income created a non-discriminatory system of taxation along the lines later

    elaborated by Buchanan and Congleton (1998). To be sure, different tax systems

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    8/21

    7

    could generate different patterns of public output by changing the amounts that

    different persons would demand, depending on how those differing demands

    interacted within a prevailing set of political and fiscal institutions. In this way, De

    Viti set forth an initial framework within which public and private activity could be

    brought within the same analytical framework, in sharp contrast to the

    Samuelsonian formulation.

    In referring to taxes as a form of public pricing, this reference is typically

    treated more as a metaphorical image than a facet of reality. The benefit principle

    of public finance has often been described as a theoretical curiosity whose

    applicability is limited to such cases as a city utility company charging residents

    for replacing their septic systems with a sewer connection. This description is

    misguided because it fails to consider the institutional framework that governs

    economic interaction and how this framework influences collective action. De

    metaphor but as a theoretical abstraction of actual practice. De Viti was, after all,

    for many years a member of the Italian Parliament, and he revised and expanded

    his original book twice while continuing to serve in Parliament. It is clear that De

    Viti thought that collective outcomes were influenced by the system through

    which collective activities were financed, though the relationship between prices

    and outcomes were more complex than they were for market outcomes.

    With respect to treating tax prices not as mere metaphor but as a

    abstraction that was useful in understanding political practice, Maffeo Pantaleoni

    (1911) conceptualized society as operating through two pricing systems, a

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    9/21

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    10/21

    9

    There is a striking similarity in form between cities and hotels even if it

    seems strange to think in this manner. Hotels operate subways that run vertically,

    and which are made available without direct charge. They provide parks of

    various types, some with artificial lakes, some with botanical gardens, and others

    with yet different types of amenities. The same point can be made about malls,

    for malls too provide both individual places of business and amenities that are

    made available to the entire public that frequents the mall. A mall is more than

    the set of individual shops that it contains, for the mall also provides common

    services and amenities that attract customers and increase the value of the

    individual shops. In this recognition lies an important lesson for public finance.

    Hotels and malls must attract business in an environment of open

    competition. To do this they must offer good value in exchange for the payments

    they require, and to do so in an environment where they must attract business in

    the presence of open competition. This is the central principle of good

    commercial conduct. Hotels and malls involve governmental activity of the same

    type that is present in the governance of cities. Among other things, they must

    make decisions about the type and quality of amenities to provide. Higher quality

    might bring more business but it will also be more costly to supply. An ordinary

    commercial calculus of cost-and-gain can be brought to bear on the operation of

    hotels and malls. Hotels and malls contain governments that provide public

    services just as surely as do cities and imperial powers.

    The main difference between cities and hotels resides in their capital

    accounts. A hotel might be owned by a single person or by many people

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    11/21

    10

    organized into a corporation. Whatever the particular form of ownership, the hotel

    faces the problem of having to attract investors and customers in an environment

    where those customers and investors have options. In contrast, cities are

    organized as cooperatives without alienable ownership. In a democratically

    organized city, someone acquires an ownership interest by virtue of residency

    and loses that ownership through leaving the city.

    A hotel has a market value; a city does not. This difference, however, has

    nothing to do with the distinction between private and public goods. The

    difference is a product of the institutional framework governing the capital

    accounts of hotels and cities (Wagner 2011). For hotels, the capital account is

    established through willing participation by investors. Those investors, moreover,

    can sell their ownership in one way or another. The most direct and common

    form is through the sale of ownership shares on the open market if the hotel were

    a publicly held corporation. The hotel could, however, be a partnership or a

    closely held corporation. In this case there would be no active market in

    ownership, so no explicit market value would exist at any particular moment. Yet

    an implicit market value would exist all the same because someone could always

    offer to buy the corporation or a part of it, in which case valuation would be

    ascertained through the transaction.

    By contrast, there is no market value for cities due to the inalienable

    character of ownership. All cities have capital accounts, necessarily so, but the

    character of those accounts is a product of various institutional features. There

    are institutional arrangements that are similar to those that govern hotels. A city

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    12/21

    11

    entails a tied ownership of real estate and city assets. Someone who buys

    property in a city is also buying into the ownership of city assets. Since there is

    no direct ownership of city assets, the value of those assets is reflected in the

    value of real estate. Actions that increase the value of city assets are thus

    reflected not in an increase in the market value of the city but in an increase in

    the value of real estate in the city. One limiting institutional arrangement is where

    owners of real estate have votes weighted in proportion to their property values

    and where city activities are financed by a flat tax on property value. This

    institutional arrangement would approach that of the hotel, but would still fall

    short because people could not specialize in owning cities or owning real estate

    inside a city. Other institutional arrangements would widen the gap between

    cities and hotels. In any case, free riding does not accompany the provision of

    public goods; rather it accompanies the inalienability of ownership in conjunction

    with the ability of associated organizations to impose taxes on activities that take

    place within their precincts.

    3. Mind, Society, and the Entrepreneurial Negation of Free-Riding

    While free riding is an institutional artifact and not an inherent quality in the

    presence of public goods, that artifactual quality is surely hidden by the standard

    dichotomy between public and private goods. That dichotomy envisions the

    economic organization of society as occurring through two processes. One

    process is the market process where consumption occurs only in consequence of

    the exchange of money for service. In this setting preferences are revealed

    directly through market prices. In contrast, the public process is envisioned as

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    13/21

    12

    subject to non-exclusion at its core. A supplier provides a service and awaits

    payment even though the service can be consumed without payment.

    In this presumed setting, free riding is pretty much unavoidable. But it is a

    strange setting, though the strangeness of this setting is perhaps obscured by

    the blinders created by the standard market setting. For many purposes,

    economic analysis can be reduced to a set of choices made by solipsistic

    individuals. What we conventionally denote as the market is a form of commons

    in which people participate in two roles. In one role they participate in stocking

    the commons through providing factors of production. In the other role they

    remove items from the commons through their choices about consumption. The

    matching of what is produced for the societal commons and what is taken from

    the commons is addressed by the theory of economic equilibrium. Given that

    matching, the theory allows reduction of society to a set of producer and

    consumer choices that are rendered consistent by budget constraints and the

    payment of prices.

    While the theory of competitive equilibrium allows reduction of society to

    the choices of a solipsistic individual, societies are really arenas of interaction

    among individuals who are far from solipsistic. When society is treated as a unit

    of analysis, matters concerning interaction among persons come into the

    analytical foreground, which, among other things, diminishes the significance of

    free riding (Wagner 2007). In related fashion, it is notable that in experimental

    studies of free riding less free riding is observed when people in the experiment

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    14/21

    13

    interact with one another than when they choose anonymously (McCaleb and

    Wagner 1985).

    Suppose, for instance, that a mayor forms the idea of hosting an open-air

    music and arts festival under the presumption that residents of the city would

    value that festival sufficiently highly to make the event worthwhile. Institutionally,

    how might the mayor go about doing this? Within the spirit of anonymity and free

    riding, the mayor might install collection boxes in private places and ask

    residents to make donations. How much or how little a person donates would be

    known only to that person. In the experimental literature, some donations are

    made even under such circumstances, though they sum to less than what is

    Yet no sensible mayor would operate in such a fashion. The mayor would

    enlist allies who were of a similar mind about the festival, and these people would

    in turn establish an architectural pattern of participation that would be far

    removed from anonymity. That architecture could entail cellular patterns of

    discussion and contribution where friends ask friends for contributions. It could

    also entail publicity regarding the identity of contributors, perhaps even ranking

    them by contribution. In these and numerous other possible ways free riding

    would be obviated. In any event, an entrepreneurial mayor would never elicit

    anonymous donations. Instead, sponsors might be solicited, with those sponsors

    given various forms of publicity. While the festival might be open to all, there

    could also be places where seating was reserved for patrons who made

    significant contributions to support the festival. We would also expect to find that

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    15/21

    14

    those who made larger contributions were those who valued the festival and the

    associated activities more highly. Under an entrepreneurial institutional

    arrangement, organization of the festival is possible according to the benefit

    principle, and the free-riding problem is avoided. Whether the resulting pattern

    would correspond to some presumptions of postulated equilibrium is impossible

    to determine because those postulated conditions are just theoretical

    constructions that do not have existence independently of the relevant process of

    social organization (Buchanan 1982).

    4. Power, Transaction Cost, and the Persistence of Taxation

    While taxation is not necessary for securing a supply of public goods, it

    certainly seems to have a robust presence in the financing of collective activities

    all the same. Suppose we compare two idealized fiscal regimes: tax finance and

    price finance. Taxation shows no signs of giving way to price finance, though Vito

    Tanzi (1911) argues that the century-long period of growing taxation has ended.

    We may reasonably doubt, however, that tax finance will give way to price

    finance even though price finance can be pursued without free riding. How might

    the persistence of taxation be explained? There is a clear sense in which that

    persistence can be plausibly attributed to its ability to finance collective activity at

    lower transaction cost than would be possible with price finance. Yet transaction

    cost does not have the same meaning across institutional regimes as it has

    inside a particular regime.

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    16/21

    15

    Within a regime based on private ordering, there is clear meaning to

    differences in transaction costs associated with different schemes for organizing

    transactions because all transactions are voluntary in any case. In the presence

    of private ordering (Streit 1992), it would, for instance, be reasonable to speak of

    the comparative cost of different arrangements for organizing health insurance

    and automobile insurance. If health insurance is organized mainly through

    networks of vendor-to-employer relationships while automobile insurance is

    organized mainly through vendor-to-customer relationships, it would be

    reasonable to ascribe the different relationships as reflecting the operation of

    transaction costs because consent among participants governs all transactions.

    While at first glance vendor-to-employer relationships might seem to by-pass

    consent from empl

    as distinct from being able to conscript them.

    The situation changes with public ordering because public ordering

    operates with an admixture of consent and force, in contrast to the universal

    operation of consent with private ordering. Tax finance requires only partial

    consent among some controlling subset of people within democratic regimes.

    With government involving Faustian bargains (Ostrom 1996), forced carrying

    comes into play which does not operate under price finance. With price finance,

    supporters of a measure have no option but to attract customers. With tax

    finance they can force people to support the measure. Understandably, it is less

    expensive to organize transactions through takings than through consent. But

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    17/21

    16

    this difference in expense does not provide reasonable justification for replacing

    consent with takings.

    Taxation has been a feature of rulership throughout history. It is a

    persistent feature of political organization. Following Ostrom (1996), it is

    reasonable to think that the terms of the Faustian bargain might vary according to

    the constitutive features of regimes. Regimes can plausibly differ in their mixes of

    forced carrying and free riding, but forced carrying nonetheless will be present

    always in the presence of taxation, save for the genuine unanimity form of the

    Wicksellian (1958) suggestion, as distinct from the approximate unanimity that he

    ended up advocating.

    Pareto (1935) explained that an effective political ideology will activate the

    non-logical sentiments of people, inducing them to accept measures they would

    have rejected had they thought about those measures, only there is no reason to

    think about them because people cannot act upon those thoughts in any case.

    Within this ruling class or elite framework, it is reasonable to treat the exercise of

    state power as at least semi-autonomous (de Jasay 1985). There may exist

    circulation among elites, but custody of state power gives advantage in the

    organization of elite-favored activities due to their ability to impose taxes in place

    of the need to attract customers. That the use of power is accompanied by

    ideological articulations that resonate with common sentiments and thereby

    clothes the use of power is easy to understand. What is perhaps not so clear is

    the apparent readiness of scholars of political economy is to accept those

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    18/21

    17

    articulations in contrast to piercing the ideological veils, as illustrated by Wagner

    and Yazigi (forthcoming).

    5. Conclusion

    The orthodox theory of public finance has overwhelmingly been

    formulated with an eye to mirroring the parasitical qualities of public finance in

    large-scale nation-states. While these formulations do have a counsel of realism

    on their side, I note only that taxation is imposed not because it is the only way

    that collectively useful activities can be financed. It is imposed because the

    power contained within modern states allows this method of public finance.

    Sufficiently powerful agents can take from others what they want more cheaply

    than they can negotiate with them to secure their consent, and this is the

    economizing reality of tax finance. What the excursions into welfare principles

    and notions of optimal taxation do is provide ideological cover for the deployment

    of power that democratic ideology claims to have subdued. Yet people surely are

    seldom so innocently engaged as when they are engaging in commercial

    activities. It has long been recognized that markets can operate as civilizing

    instruments (Hirschman 1977), and the entrepreneurial vision of public finance

    would extend the reach of that civilizing process (Elias 2000 [orig. ed. 1936]).

    The persistence of tax finance along with its continued theoretical justification

    reminds us that the civilizing process has not yet run its course.

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    19/21

    18

    References

    Public Choice53: 3-20.

    Beito, D. T., P. Gordon, and A. Tabarrok, eds. 2002, The Voluntary City: Choice,Community, and Civil Society.Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press.

    Journal of Law and Economics21: 111-32.

    Boudreaux, D. J. and R. PublicFinance Quarterly17: 264-80.

    Journal of

    Law and Economics18: 147-61.

    Buchanan, J. M. 1968. The Demand and Supply of Public Goods. Chicago: RandMcNally.

    Liiterature of Liberty5: 5.

    Buchanan, J. M. and R. D. Congleton. 1998. Politics by Principle, not Interest:Toward Nondiscriminatory Democracy. Cambridge: Cambridge UniversityPress.

    Journal of Law andEconomics17: 357-76.

    De Jasay, A. 1985. The State. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

    Journal of Law andEconomics13: 293-306.

    De Viti de Marco, A. 1888. . Rome:Pasqualucci.

    De Viti de Marco, A. 1936. First Principles of Public Finance. London: JonathanCape.

    Elias, N. 2000 [1936]. The Civilizing Process. Oxford: Basil Blackwell.

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    20/21

    19

    Eusepi, G. and R. E. Wagner. 2013. Continuing Relevance of Antonio de Viti de Marco. History of PoliticalEconomy45 (Spring 2013): .

    Foldvary, F. 1994. Public Goods and Private Communities.Cheltenham, UK:

    Edward Elgar.

    Hirschman, A. 1977. The Passions and the Interests: Political Arguments forCapitalism before Its Triumph. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.

    Justi, J.H.G. von 1969 [1771]. Natur und Wesen der Staaten. Darmstadt: ScientiaVerlag Aalen.

    MacCallum, S. 1970. The Art of Community. Menlo Park, CA: Institute forHumane Studies.

    McCaleb, T. S. and R. E. Wagner. 1985. "The Experimental Search for FreeRiders: Some Reflections and Observations." Public Choice47: 479-90.

    Journal of Law and Economics7: 71-80.

    Musgrave, R. A. 1959. The Theory of Public Finance. New York: McGraw-Hill.

    Constitutional Political Economy7: 303- 08.

    Giornale degli Economisti42: 9-29, 114-33.

    Radula, R. Elinor Ostr European Journal of Law and Economics30: 201-21.

    Review ofEconomics and Statistics36: 387-89.

    Review of Economics and Statistics37: 350-56.

    Spruynt, H. 1994. The Sovereign State and Its Competitors. Princeton, NJ,Princeton University Press.

    Journal ofInstitutional and Theoretical Economics148: 675-704.

  • 8/11/2019 SSRN-id2229053.pdf

    21/21

    20

    Tanzi, V. 2011. Government versus Markets: The Changing Economic Role ofthe State.Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Wagner, R. E. 2007. Fiscal Sociology and the Theory of Public Finance.Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar.

    Public Choice149:151-65.

    Wagner, R. E. 2012a. es:Some Economics of Economic American Journal of Economicsand Sociology71: 1185-1204.

    Wagner, R. E. 2012b. Deemphasizing Public Finance

    and Management12: 5-20.

    Wagner, R. E. 2012c Public Finance. In Jrgen G. Backhaus, ed., Handbook for the History ofEconomic Thought(Dordrecht: Springer), pp. 123-35.

    Wagner, R. E. and D. Yazigi. Forthcoming. through Competition: Elections, Markets, and Political Economy. Choice DOI: 10.1007/s11127-013-0065-y

    and A. T. Peacock, eds. Classics in the Theory of Public Finance. London:Macmillan, pp. 72-118.