25
American Academy of Religion Structuralism, Hermeneutics, and Contextual Meaning Author(s): Elizabeth Struthers Malbon Reviewed work(s): Source: Journal of the American Academy of Religion, Vol. 51, No. 2 (Jun., 1983), pp. 207-230 Published by: Oxford University Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1463635 . Accessed: 27/04/2012 07:04 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. Oxford University Press and American Academy of Religion are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Journal of the American Academy of Religion. http://www.jstor.org

Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

American Academy of Religion

Structuralism, Hermeneutics, and Contextual MeaningAuthor(s): Elizabeth Struthers MalbonReviewed work(s):Source: Journal of the American Academy of Religion, Vol. 51, No. 2 (Jun., 1983), pp. 207-230Published by: Oxford University PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/1463635 .Accessed: 27/04/2012 07:04

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

Oxford University Press and American Academy of Religion are collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserveand extend access to Journal of the American Academy of Religion.

http://www.jstor.org

Page 2: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Journal of the American Academy of Religion, LI/2

Structuralism, Hermeneutics, and Contextual Meaning

Elizabeth Struthers Malbon

erhaps one should begin by defining one's terms. But, were I to attempt to define "structuralism" and "hermeneutics" carefully, completely, and in a way that would satisfy all-or even most-

structuralists or hermeneuticists, I fear I would never move beyond this

beginning. Thus, although I shall not begin entirely in mediis rebus, I must assume some experience of the workings of structuralism and of hermeneutics. I regard structuralism and hermeneutics as approaches to meaning, as ways of investigating the significance of "things"-from individual texts to whole cultures-and the significance of significance. My present task is to compare and contrast these two approaches to meaning-structuralism and hermeneutics-by considering especially their goals, or end points, and their presuppositions, or beginning points. Although my references will be chiefly to approaches to meaning in biblical studies, I wish to understand in a more general way the contexts in which structuralism and hermeneutics seek meaning and seek to make meaning.

Relations between structuralism and hermeneutics are often implied in the characterization of either structuralism or hermeneutics. For example, Robert Culley, in characterizing structuralism, presents a model of the three focal points of scholarly approaches to biblical texts: author, text, reader./1/ According to this model, the author is the shared focal point of source criticism; the text is the focus of rhetorical criticism and structural analysis; the reader is the focus of biblical hermeneutics (167-69). Thus Culley's model indicates a fundamental difference between structuralism and hermeneutics. A model presented by Robert Polzin, on the other hand, suggests a fundamental similarity between structuralism and hermeneutics: self-conscious awareness of the role of

Elizabeth Struthers Malbon (Ph.D., Florida State University) is Assistant Profes- sor of Religion at Virginia Polytechnic Institute and State University. She is the author of articles in Semeia, Catholic Biblical Quarterly, and New Testament Studies. This paper was first presented to the American Academy of Religion at its annual meeting in 1981.

Page 3: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

208 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

the subject, the analyst, in the analysis./2/ Since Polzin's "subject" is related to Culley's "reader," Polzin's stress on this aspect of structuralism that is shared with hermeneutics undercuts Culley's suggestion that structuralism is distinguished by its focus on the text from hermeneutics with its focus on the reader. Perhaps Culley's model overemphasizes the distinction between structuralism and hermeneutics, whereas Polzin's argument overemphasizes their commonality.

What is needed is a way both to compare and to contrast structural- ism and hermeneutics as approaches to meaning. Toward that end, the first step of my investigation involves an examination and classification of the respective-and various-goals of structuralists and of hermeneu- ticists. Goals are the projected end points of investigators, the "why" of investigations. Thus, a comparison of structuralist and hermeneutical goals should help us establish the scope of each of these two approaches to meaning. After a brief look at the basis of structuralism, we will turn to a systematization of several important goals of structuralists. Then we will repeat this procedure with regard to hermeneutics and the goals of hermeneuticists.

Structuralism, Structuralists, and Goals

Historically, structuralism, particularly literary structuralism, is rooted in Saussurean linguistics. Conceptually, structuralism is centered in concern for relations, or networks of relations, rather than isolated elements. Ferdinand de Saussure, Swiss linguist of the late nineteenth and early twentieth century, is acclaimed the "grandfather" of structur- alism (Bovon:8), its "founding father" (Lane:27); and Saussure's Course in General Linguistics, first published in 1915 on the basis of the lecture notes of his students, is proclaimed "the magna carta of modern struc- tural linguistics" (Polzin:17). The "crux of de Saussure's theory ... is the role of relations in a system . . ."; for signs, as for phonemes, "to be is to be related" (Wells:97). A linguistic sign itself is a relation-between a signifier, or "sound-image," and a signified, or "concept." Language is a system of signs. Before Saussure, traditional linguistics focused on dia- chronic analysis, the study of changes in language over time. Saussure's insistence on the priority of synchronic analysis, the investigation of the structure of language, revolutionized linguistics.

Also seminal for the history and the concepts of structuralism was Vladimir Propp, Russian folklorist, whose Morphology of the Folktale has quite rightly been termed "the exemplar par excellence" of syntag- matic structural exegesis (Dundes:xi). In his study of Russian fairy tales, Propp isolated thirty-one "functions" (or types of actions) and seven "spheres of action" (or character types) that remain constant amid the varying details of the stories. Although Propp did not discover every

Page 4: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 209

function manifest in every tale, he did find the order (syntagm) of the functions in the narratives to be invariable. Propp's "important contribu- tion" was, in the words of Susan Wittig, "his typically Formalist proposal that the description of a tale's invariant structural features is a more appropriate mode of analysis than the description of the variable content which manifests the structure" (152).

Whereas Propp serves as a representative of syntagmatic structural

analysis, the "champion of paradigmatic structural analysis is Claude Levi-Strauss" (Dundes:xii). It is the contemporary French cultural

anthropologist Claude Levi-Strauss who is generally regarded as the "father" of structuralism (Bovon:8; Pettit:68), "the archetypal high priest of structuralism" (Polzin:41). To Levi-Strauss goes as well the dubious honor of being "perhaps the best-known and least understood structural- ist" (Polzin:17). His work is heralded as "the most extended and system- atic application of structuralist methods and the structuralist vision to human phenomena" (Lane:12). Levi-Strauss's work may be interpreted as both an extension of Saussure and a "correction" of Propp. Following Saussure, Levi-Strauss insists upon "the primacy of relations between terms" (Culler:23). These relations are underlying or implicit relations through which things can function as signs or as language and which the structuralist aims to make explicit (Culler:25). Yet the "language" to which Levi-Strauss applies this central concept is not natural language (the linguistic phenomenon of langue) but the "language" of kinship (Le"vi-Strauss, 1969) or the "language" of myth (1969-81). These cultural languages, like langue itself, have two dimensions: the syntagmatic and the paradigmatic. Against Propp, Levi-Strauss argues for (1) the greater significance of the paradigmatic dimension of narratives (tales, myths) over their syntagmatic dimension and (2) the importance of the ethno- graphic context of narratives to their overall significance and clarity (see Wittig:153-58).

We turn now from this briefest of looks at structuralism's foundation on the concern for relations, or networks of relations, to a systematization of several important goals of structuralism's "adherents" or "practition- ers."/3/ I employ the two terms "adherents" and "practitioners" advisedly, for structuralism in its broadest sense may aim toward either ideology or methodology. These two basic directions are not unique to structuralism, but common to intellectual movements generally; they represent what Michael Lane (13) refers to, although with somewhat different labels, as the two categories of "the means that men employ to order their universe."/4/ By ideology-or philosophy if its connotations are less abrasive/5/-is meant "any more or less consistent system of beliefs and values which describes and accounts for the relations of men to one another, and to the material, and not infrequently the immaterial, uni- verse" (13)./6/ Structuralism as an ideology or philosophy is, in the words

Page 5: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

210 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

of Robert Scholes, "a way of looking for reality not in individual things but in relationships among them" (4). By way of an example, Levi- Strauss's desire to understand the structure of the human mind from an examination of its cultural products, his discovery of "vast homologies" (Bovon:11), represents an ideological (or philosophical) goal of structuralism. By methodology is meant "any set of rules or regulations which describes and prescribes the operations to be performed upon any matter . . . with the purpose of ordering it and understanding its working" (Lane:13). Most structuralists view structuralism as a methodol- ogy, although they may recognize that its basic presuppositions are philosophical (Lane:13,17; Patte, 1976:14,19; Bovon:6-7; Ehrmann:ix; Via:1; Gardner:10). I offer this distinction between ideology and method- ology as a descriptive one,/7/ not as an evaluative one, although "ideol- ogy," or its equivalent, generally serves as the negatively valued pole among commentators on structuralism./8/ In fact, neither ideology nor methodology is manifest concretely in total isolation-in structuralism or in any intellectual movement (Lane:13).

But, speaking abstractly, structuralism as a methodology may be said to focus upon either theory or analysis./9/ Structuralism as theory may be directed to various issues: a theory of Russian fairy tales (Propp), a theory of kinship or of myth (Levi-Strauss), a theory of narrativity (Grei- mas). In the field of literature, theoretical structuralism approaches not so much the meaning of individual works of literature as the meaning of meaning, that is, the presuppositions that enable literature to be written and to be read; theoretical structuralism seeks not so much to tell the meaning as to recreate the process of meaning (cf. Spivey:185; Culler:

30-85). From this description, the reverberations between theory and ideology should be loud and clear; in somewhat simplistic terms, ideol- ogy may be understood as theory (or theories) further abstracted and further generalized.

In the other direction, theory is resonant with analysis, for analysis is applied theory. In the field of literature, structuralism as analysis focuses upon the meaning of individual works, although this meaning must be con- sidered (theoretically) as a subset of the meaning of meaning. Structural- ism as analysis is concerned not just with the what of individual meaning, but with the how of individual meaning. Observers have noted that struc- turalism as theory appears dominant over structuralism as analysis (e.g., Lane:38; Culler:34; Jacobson:157; Detweiler:118); some commentators have even identified structuralism as theory with structuralism per se./10/ Since theoretical hypotheses offer starting points for analysis, theoretical

dcminance may be a mark of structuralism's youth; if so, signs of matura- tion (or aging, depending upon the point of view) may be discerned in an increasing number of analytical studies. However, theory and analysis, like ideology and methodology, are separable only in the abstract./11/

Page 6: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 211

Just as structuralism as methodology bifurcates into theory and anal-

ysis, so structuralism as analysis subdivides into structural exegesis and narrative hermeneutics. In relation to philosophy (or ideology), both

theory and analysis are forms of methodology./12/ In relation to theory, both structural exegesis and narrative hermeneutics are forms of analysis. As theory is, in a sense, applied philosophy, so structural exegesis is the-

ory applied to an "object" (a text) and narrative hermeneutics is struc- tural exegesis applied to a "subject" (a reader). /13/ Edgar McKnight's book on the interrelationships of hermeneutics and structuralism, from which I have borrowed the term "narrative hermeneutics," well repre- sents this goal of structuralism. Structural exegesis as a goal of structural- ism has been the aim of much of my research (Malbon, 1979; 1980; 1982; 198?).

structuralist goals

philosophy methodology (or ideology)

theory analysis

structural narrative exegesis hermeneutics

These four-philosophy (or ideology), theory, structural exegesis, narrative hermeneutics-may be considered terminal goals of structural- ism;/14/ a structuralist may choose any one of them as her or his ulti- mate goal, though she or he may reach it via another goal (or goals) as penultimate./15/ Thus, in the Mythologiques (1969-81), Levi-Strauss moves from an analysis of individual myths (structural exegesis) to a theory of myth to an ideological (or philosophical) understanding of what makes humanity human. In Structural Exegesis: From Theory to Practice, Daniel Patte and Aline Patte move from a semiotic theory to a structural exegesis of Mark 15 and 16 toward a narrative hermeneutic.

In actuality, both Levi-Strauss and Patte and Patte move back and forth between goals, or forms, of structuralism in the process of discovering meaning. However, their respective directions and ultimate goals are clear: Levi-Strauss moves toward ideology, Patte and Patte toward hermeneutics. Yet ideology and narrative hermeneutics are not as unrelated as they might appear from the diagram above. The desire to philosophize on the basis of

Page 7: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

212 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

ethnography is not unlike the desire to theologize on the basis of

narratology. Ideology, in its philosophical aspects, and narrative herme- neutics, in its theological aspects, share a concern for the breadth of humanity and the depth of human beings./16/ It is true that the contin- uum might be represented as a line, running from ideology to narrative hermeneutics. But it might better be represented as a circle, in which ideol- ogy and narrative hermeneutics would not be poles apart but only ninety degrees apart. Furthermore, such a circle might better depict the move- ment among goals that often characterizes interpreters.

Thus, my typology of structuralist goals is not meant to pigeonhole scholars or to portray as static the dynamism of scholarship, but to clar- ify the basic thrust of various approaches. We turn now from this consid- eration of structuralist goals to a parallel consideration of hermeneutical goals, in our attempt to interrelate these two fundamental approaches to meaning.

Hermeneutics, Hermeneuticists, and Goals

Richard Palmer, James Robinson, and others open their discussions of hermeneutics with considerations of the various meanings of the Greek verb hermeneuein and its noun form hermaneia (Palmer:12-32; Robin- son:1-7; Achtemeier:13-14). The words share a linguistic root with the name of the Greek god Hermes, the messenger of the gods and the inventor or discoverer of language and writing. The three basic meanings of hermp- neuein are: (1) to speak (or express or say), (2) to explain (or interpret or comment upon), (3) to translate. As Palmer notes, "all three meanings may be expressed by the English verb 'to interpret,' yet each constitutes an independent and significant meaning of interpretation" (13-14). Since the ancient Greeks, each of these three meanings has found its applications by various hermeneuticists. Hermeneutics as speaking has included not only the oral recitation of Homer's epics but also the proclamation demanded by the new hermeneutic. Hermeneutics as commentary has a long and varied history in biblical exegesis, from third-century Alexandrian allegor- ization to nineteenth-century historical-critical method. Hermeneutics as translation may be seen not only literally in traditional philology but also metaphorically in Bultmannian "demythologizing." Yet one may note, with Palmer, that in all three cases "the foundational 'Hermes process' is at work: in all three cases, something foreign, strange, separated in time, space, or experience is made familiar, present, comprehensible; something requiring representation, explanation, or translation is somehow 'brought to understanding'-is 'interpreted'" (14). It is the new hermeneutic, claims Robinson, that has regained and reexpressed the "profound implication that these three functions belong together as interrelated aspects of a single hermeneutic" (16).

Page 8: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 213

From these three definitions-and implications-of the ancient Greek hermaneuein, Palmer moves to six modern definitions of hermeneutics (33-45). "From the beginning," comments Palmer, "the word has denoted the science of interpretation, especially the principles of proper textual

exegesis, but," Palmer adds, "the field of hermeneutics has been inter-

preted (in roughly chronological order) as: (1) the theory of biblical exege- sis; (2) general philological methodology; (3) the science of all linguistic understanding [Schleiermacher]; (4) the methodological foundation of Geisteswissenschaften [or "human studies"; Dilthey]; (5) phenomenology of existence and of existential understanding [Heidegger and Gadamer]; and (6) the systems of interpretation, both recollective and iconoclastic, used by man to reach the meaning behind myths and symbols [Ricoeur]" (Palmer:33). Furthermore, Palmer draws the important conclusion that "each of these definitions is more than an historical stage; each points to an important 'moment' or approach to the problems of interpretation" (33).

Thus the six modern definitions, in conjunction with the three ancient ones, seem to suggest various goals toward which particular hermeneuti- cists may aim. The basic shape of the typology of structuralist goals appears to serve also for outlining hermeneutical goals, thus facilitating our comparison of these two basic approaches to meaning. Hermeneutics as speaking (or proclamation) moves toward philosophy (or theology). Hermeneutics as commentary (or explanation) aims at methodology, either in a general sense as theory, or in a specific, analytical (applied) sense as biblical exegesis. Hermeneutics as translation-and this is particularly clear with the new hermeneutic-sets its sights on existential understanding.

hermeneutical goals

philosophy methodology (or theology)

theory analysis

biblical existential exegesis understanding

In relation to philosophy, both theory and analysis are forms of methodology. In relation to theory, both biblical exegesis and existential understanding are forms of analysis. As theory is, in a sense, applied

Page 9: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

214 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

philosophy, so biblical exegesis is theory applied to a so-called "object" (a text) and existential understanding is biblical exegesis applied to a so- called "subject" (a reader). These four-philosophy (or theology), theory, biblical exegesis, existential understanding-may be considered terminal

goals of hermeneutics; a hermeneuticist may choose any one of them as her or his ultimate goal, though she or he may reach it via another goal (or goals) as penultimate.

As a check on the valididty and usefulness of this typology, let us consider the place within it of several important hermeneuticists. It would seem that the contrast between the work of Heidegger and Gada- mer on the one hand and of Schleiermacher, Dilthey, and Betti on the other represents a contrast between philosophy and methodology as her- meneutical goals. Palmer notes a "clear polarization" in contemporary hermeneutical thinking: "There is the tradition of Schleiermacher and Dilthey, whose adherents look to hermeneutics as a general body of methodological principles which underlie interpretation. And there are the followers of Heidegger, who see hermeneutics as a philosophical exploration of the character and requisite conditions for all understand- ing" (46, my emphasis). As a comparison of the thought of Hans-Georg Gadamer and Emilio Betti makes plain, however, having or not having philosophy as a goal of hermeneutics does not deliver a hermeneuticist from philosophical presuppositions; the conflict of Betti's "realist" pre- suppositions and Gadamer's "phenomenological" ones is in addition to the contrast of their methodological or philosophical goals (see Palmer: 46-65)./17/

The hermeneutical goals of archetypical new hermeneuticists Ger- hard Ebeling and Ernst Fuchs might be expressed as either philosophy or theology. "The proponents of the new hermeneutic," as Achtemeier notes, "in some instances, are quite prepared to invade the precincts of philosophy, so broad is their understanding of the implications of their approach. The new hermeneutic is therefore not limited to exegesis; it is a way of doing theology, and it will be better understood if that is kept in mind" (86-87; cf. Robinson:6,63,67). "Both Ebeling and Fuchs," Palmer observes, "have made the word event the center of their theolog- ical thinking, which has been labeled 'word-event theology'" (53). "The effect of the word event emphasis in theology," Palmer continues, "is to bring philosophy of language to the very center of hermeneutics" (54).

Philosophy (or theology) and methodology comprise the first branches of the tree of hermeneutical goals; the second branches are theory and analysis as forms of methodology. The theory/analysis option of my typology of hermeneutical goals appears to parallel what Palmer terms "the double focus of hermeneutics." According to Palmer, the "historical development of hermeneutics as an independent field seems to hold within itself two separate foci: one on the theory of understanding in a general

Page 10: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 215

sense, and the other on what is involved in the exegesis of linguistic texts, the hermeneutical problem. These two foci need not be either self-

canceling or absolutely independent, yet they are best held in sufficient separateness for one to instruct the other" (67). By way of an example, we noted above that Schleiermacher and Dilthey are to be associated with the hermeneutical goal of methodology rather than philosophy; methodology, however, is not a terminal goal within the typology; and both Schleier- macher and Dilthey are to be associated with the theory option of

methodology rather than the analysis option. In Palmer's words, "herme- neutics is true to its great past in Schleiermacher and Dilthey when it takes its bearings from a general theory of linguistic understanding" (68, my emphasis). Theory, however, as a goal of hermeneutics, might be concentrated on a number of areas: a theory of language (Schleiermacher and Dilthey), a theory of approaches unique to the "human sciences" (Dilthey), a theory of literary interpretation (Palmer:220-53).

The direct alternative to theory as a hermeneutical goal is analysis. Analysis, however, does not represent a terminal goal in my typology of hermeneutical goals but suggests in turn the final option of biblical exe- gesis or existential understanding. Again my distinction is paralleled-in overall significance if not in specific terminology-by a distinction pointed out by Palmer. The distinction I see between biblical exegesis and existential understanding is comparable to the distinction Palmer observes "between the moment of understanding an object in terms of itself and the moment of seeing the existential meaning of the object for one's own life and future" (56). While the most traditional definition of hermeneutics is probably "the theory of interpretation," the most tradi- tional goal of hermeneuticists in the field of religion throughout the long history of hermeneutics is probably biblical exegesis. By the opening of the nineteenth century, as Achtemeier notes, the terms "hermeneutics" and "exegesis" were often used interchangeably (Achtemeier:14). How- ever, in the twentieth century-to a certain extent with Bultmann and more fully with the new hermeneutic-the goal of biblical exegesis has been overwhelmed by the insistent emphasis on existential understand- ing, on biblical exegesis pro nobis, pro me. As John Cobb notes: "In the new hermeneutic what is interpreted is ultimately and decisively the existence of the hearer of the proclamation. The text, rather than being the object of interpretation, as with Bultmann, becomes an aid in the interpretation of present existence" (Cobb:229-80; cf. Robinson:52 and McKnight:77-78).

Bultmann serves as a good reminder, however, that the typology of hermeneutical goals is not to be viewed as static. Certainly Bultmann shares much with the philosophical hermeneutics of Heidegger (see Palmer:48-52; Achtemeier:53-70; Thiselton: especially 227-84; McKnight: 65-71) and with the methodological or theoretical hermeneutics of Dilthey

Page 11: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

216 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

(see Thiselton:234-40; McKnight:65-71). Clearly, Bultmann the preacher and New Testament scholar is concerned with biblical exegesis (see Palmer:50), but, equally clearly, Bultmann the "demythologizer" and New Testament theologian aims at existential understanding of the biblical text (see Palmer:56). Thus, while theology (or philosophy), theory, and biblical

exegesis are for Bultmann penultimate goals of hermeneutics, the ultimate

goal is existential understanding./18/ Yet, as we observed analogously of the typology of structuralist goals, the continuum from theology (or philosophy) to theory to biblical exegesis to existential understanding might well be represented as a circle, with existential understanding moving toward theology. Certainly this movement is descriptive of Bultmann's exegesis of Paul and John for twentieth-century persons as part of a comprehensive theology.

The sketching out of parallel typologies of structuralist and hermeneu- tical goals suggests that, in terms of their end points, certain structuralists may have more in common with certain hermeneuticists than with other structuralists, and vice versa. For example, those structuralists most interested in narrative hermeneutics and those hermeneuticists most con- cerned with existential understanding might view each other as colleagues in a common endeavor as against their more "theoretical" associates on either side. Those very associates, however, whether structuralist or hermeneutical theorists, may welcome closer association as they aim at theoretical clarification rather than "simply" applied analysis. To remind us of what structural theorists have in common with structural exegetes, and hermeneuticists of one emphasis with those of another, we turn from a consideration of end points, or goals, to a brief consideration of beginning points, or presuppositions. We will concentrate on structuralist and hermeneutical presuppositions in two key areas: history and language.

The Historical, the Historic, and Historicity

Norman Perrin, in an aside to his discussion of the New Testament as myth and history, suggests three centers of meaning of the term "his- tory" (27-29): (1) history as the historical, or "factual history" of the type "that would satisfy a court of law"; (2) history as the historic, or the sig- nificance of factual history "in the broader context of the totality of human experience"; and (3) history as the historicity of human existence in the world, or all those things, from historical circumstances and events to ideas and interpretations, that can change one's life. To borrow, and extend, Perrin's example: all the authentic speeches of all the U.S. presi- dents are historical; Lincoln's "Gettysburg Address" is historic; and the "Gettysburg Address" has had an impact on the historicity of all Ameri- cans, changing the lives of both northerners and southerners, both whites and blacks.

Page 12: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 217

The distinctions among the historical, the historic, and historicity may, I believe, help to clarify and distinguish the presuppositions of structuralism and of hermeneutics regarding history. Traditional biblical criticism, based on the historical-critical method, has focused on history as the historical. This is clearly seen in form criticism's concern to estab- lish the Sitz im Leben of the text and in redaction criticism's concern to illuminate the situation of each community by examining the theology of each synoptic gospel.

Structuralism has not infrequently been criticized by biblical schol- ars (and others) as being ahistorical if not antihistorical. But, as Dan Via more realistically observes, any adoption and adaptation of structuralism by biblical studies "will entail, not a rejection of the historical method, but a relegating of it to a more marginal position than it has been enjoy- ing" (2; cf. McKnight:239,242). Structuralism reacts against concentra- tion on the diachronic by focusing on the synchronic. Structuralism responds primarily not to history as the historical but to history as the historic. For example, Lincoln's "Gettysburg Address" is recognized as historic, structuralists would point out, not primarily because of its place in the chronological syntagm of presidential addresses from George Washington to Ronald Reagan but because of its place in the paradigm of all presidential addresses, no matter when they were given. Likewise, the significance of a text, that which interests structuralists, is to be determined by its intertextual and intratextual relationships, not merely from its historical context. Oversimplifying in order to clarify our schema, we might say that fact is to significance as the historical is to the historic and as historical criticism is to structuralism.

Hermeneutics focuses on neither the historical nor the historic but on history as the historicity of human existence in the world. "For herme- neutic itself," states Robinson, "is rooted in man's historicness, namely, the call placed upon him to encounter the history of the past in such a way as not to deny his own existential future and present responsibility" (9). In fact, Heidegger's ontology, on which much of recent hermeneuti- cal thinking rests, suggests that the historical is founded upon historicity. Paraphrasing Heidegger, Achtemeier states, "Time itself is grounded in the structure of the self, so that the possibility of temporal existence, i.e., history, is itself grounded in the structure of the self" (39-40). Or, as paraphrased by Thiselton (184), "history is what it is by virtue of the historicality (Geschichtlichkeit) of Dasein, rather than because of the mere pastness of historical events and objects. Hence the focus of history lies not in the past but in the present."/19/ Paul Ricoeur, in speaking for hermeneutics as over against structuralism, states explicitly, "I will reserve the term 'historicity'-historicity of tradition and historicity of interpretation-for any understanding which implicitly or explicitly knows itself to be on the road of the philosophic understanding of self

Page 13: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

218 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

and of being" (55). For this reason, biblical exegesis in the Bultmannian tradition is primarily concerned not with the historical past but with the present and future historicity of human existence; it is not historical exegesis but exegesis pro nobis; it is, in the words of Ebeling, a "process from text to sermon"; it is "proclamation" (Ebeling:107; cf. Fuchs: 141)./20/

At least as applied in the field of biblical studies, both structuralism's focus on the historic and hermeneutics' focus on historicity may be seen as reactions against the excesses of the nineteenth and twentieth centu- ries' concern for the historical./21/ Structuralism has challenged tradi- tional historical criticism to respect the integrity of the text and to appreciate the presuppositions that enable texts to be written and to be read (e.g., Via). Hermeneutics has challenged traditional historical criti- cism to bridge the distance between "the two horizons," the horizon of the ancient text and the horizon of the contemporary reader (e.g., Palmer). Structuralism has sometimes accused hermeneutics of ignoring the interrelations and the constraints of the text as a linguistic product (e.g., Kovacs). Hermeneutics has sometimes accused structuralism of ana- lyzing the text in isolation from the living process of communication (e.g., Ricoeur).

Evidently, in the responses of structuralism and hermeneutics to historical criticism and in the responses of structuralism and hermeneu- tics to each other, we are sometimes dealing with overreactions to over- reactions. In order to defuse this situation, it is helpful to remember Perrin's presentation of the historical, the historic, and historicity as three dimensions of history, three interrelated-not independent-ways of conceiving of history. Analogously, various approaches to textual meaning are to be viewed as interrelated; the focus of traditional biblical criticism on the historical is better supplemented than supplanted by the concern of stucturalism for the historic and that of hermeneutics for historicity./22/

For structuralism, the historic is determined by syntagmatic and especially paradigmatic inter- and intrarelationships of cultural phenom- ena, and syntagmatic and paradigmatic are the two dimensions of lan- guage. For hermeneutics, the bridge between an historical text and the historicity of a reader is formed by language. Yet structuralism and hermeneutics approach language, as they approach history, with differ- ent concerns and different presuppositions.

Langue, Parole, and Sprachereignis In somewhat oversimplified terms, we may say that structuralism

regards language as a system of signs and hermeneutics regards language as an event of disclosure. While these assumptions are not necessarily

Page 14: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 219

contradictory or exclusive, they do represent opposing points of view on the appropriate starting point of a discussion of language.

The foundations of structuralism's presuppositions about language were set by Saussure. As we noted above, the "crux of de Saussure's

theory . . . is the role of relations in a system . . ." (Wells:97). A linguistic sign itself (a word) is a relation, a relation between a signifier and a signi- fied; and language is a system of signs. In three key dichotomies, Saussure presented his answers to three questions concerning this language system: (1) what are the components of languages? (2) how should language be studied? (3) what are the dimensions of language? First, language in the broad sense (French langage) is comprised of the language-system (langue) and language-behavior or speech (parole)./23/ Langage is a social phenomenon; langue is its inherited or institutional element, parole its innovational element. Langue, language, is communal and passive; parole, speech, is individual and active. Second, according to Saussure, it is the task of the linguist to study langue and, primarily, to study it synchronically rather than diachronically, that is, as a system of "relations across a moment in time, rather than through time" (Lane:16-17). Diachronic analysis of language is the study of changes in language over time; synchronic analysis is the investigation of the structure of language.

Third, in focusing on langue synchronically, Saussure distinguished two dimensions of langue, two kinds of relationships that exist between the signs of the language-system: syntagmatic and paradigmatic./24/ Rela- tions of contiguity are syntagmatic; relations of similarity are paradigma- tic. Principles of selection are paradigmatic; principles of combination are syntagmatic. Consider, for example, the sentence: "She wrote an essay." Here "wrote" is related syntagmatically to "She" by following it and to "an essay" by preceding it, while, paradigmatically, "She" is related to "He" and "essay" to "poem." While the syntagm concerns the actual sentence, the paradigm concerns the potential sentences over against which the meaning of the actual sentence is made clear. Both the paradigmatic dimension, the "axis of simultaneity," and the syntagmatic dimension, the "axis of succession," are essential if language is to "mean" (signify) anything.

Language as a system of signs, language as the interrelation of syn- tagmatic and paradigmatic dimensions, is a basic presupposition of struc- turalism. Thus, without reference to Saussure, Propp focused on the syntagmatic aspects of the Russian fairy tale. In a conscious application of Saussure's linguistic model,/25/ Levi-Strauss focused on the paradig- matic aspects of the "language" of kinship and the "language" of myth. Levi-Strauss's work has been heralded as "the model for all subsequent attempts at the extension of linguistic theory beyond the borders of its own discipline" (Robey:3), and with this extension has come the exten- sion of the syntagmatic/paradigmatic distinction.

Page 15: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

220 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

Whereas structuralism focuses upon the syntagmatic and paradig- matic dimensions of language (French langue) as opposed to speech (French parole), hermeneutics, and especially the new hermeneutic, con- centrates on language as language-event (German Sprachereignis). And whereas Saussurean linguistics is foundational for structuralism's view of language, Heideggerian philosophy is foundational for hermeneutic's view of language. For Heidegger, "language is the house of being"; "words and language are not wrappings in which things are packed for the commerce of those who write and speak. It is in words and language that things first come into being and are" (as quoted by Palmer:135). Language, then, is insufficiently accounted for as a system of arbitrary signs. Language originates not with human beings but with Being itself. Language is, in Achtemeier's paraphrase of Heidegger, "the response to Being, it is the act of being-open-to Being, of letting-be-manifest in response to the call of Being" (Achtemeier:48; cf. Robinson:48-49). Thus, for the new hermeneuticist Ernst Fuchs, "Language is not necessarily talk. Language is rather primarily a showing or letting be seen, an indi- cation in the active sense" (as quoted by Robinson:54). Language and reality, word and event, are inseparable, and it is their unity that is indi- cated by the term "language-event." To approach language as language- event is to presuppose that, quoting Achtemeier, "event and word are born together," "that an event needs the words, the language, it calls forth in order to be itself," and that "the language thus given birth illumines the reality that summoned it forth" (Achtemeier:90-91; cf. Robinson:46-48,57-58)./26/ Thus language as language-event is a living process of communication-or better, of illumination, since the "saving event" (Bultmann's Heilsgeschehen or Heilsereignis) is a "language event" (Ebeling's Wortgeschehen or Fuch's Sprachereignis) (Robinson: 57; see also 61-62). By contrast, language as a system of signs is a human product-though more an unconscious than a conscious one./27/

Structuralism's insistence on the importance of synchronic study of language, including cultural "languages," correlates with its concern for history as the historic. Hermeneutics' understanding of language as language-event correlates with its concern for history as the historicity of human existence in the world. For the new hermeneutic, language is the bridge between the historical and historicity. Central to Fuchs's hermeneu- tical program is the task of "exhibiting the historicness of existence as the linguisticality of existence" (as quoted by Robinson:55). Language, explains Achtemeier (91), "contains the possibilities of self-understanding, and therefore of human existence, as they have found expression in the past." "Language," summarizes Palmer (207), "is the medium in which the tradition conceals itself and is transmitted. Experience is not so much something that comes prior to language, but rather experience itself occurs in and through language. Linguisticality is something that permeates the

Page 16: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 221

way of being-in-the-world of historical man." Thus, and not so surprisingly, presuppositions concerning language

are intertwined with presuppositions concerning history for both herme- neutics and structuralism. Furthermore, these presuppositions influence the goals generally pursued by structuralists and hermeneuticists. Although both structuralism and hermeneutics, as we suggested above, are open to four analogous goals, structuralism's approach to language as a system of signs predisposes structuralism to aim toward exegesis, while hermeneutics' approach to language as language-event predisposes her- meneutics to seek existential understanding and to develop a philosophy and/or theology. This would seem to be the reason why Ricoeur (27-61; see also 62-78), for example, recommends structuralism as a method (or "science") of exegesis and hermeneutics as a philosophy. This tendency of particular presuppositions to favor particular goals seems also to be behind Culley's observation that structuralism focuses on the text and hermeneutics on the reader, for structuralism's approach to history as the historic predisposes structuralism to focus on the text in its literary or linguistic context, whereas hermeneutics' approach to history as the his- toricity of human existence in the world predisposes hermeneutics to focus on the reader in the context of his or her lived experience./28/ For both structuralism and hermeneutics as approaches to meaning, the con- text is crucial.

Structuralism, Hermeneutics, and Contextual Meaning

Structuralism, as a way of concentrating on the text, may be distin- guished from hermeneutics, as a way of concentrating on the reader; this is the simple but powerful suggestion of Culley's model. Yet structuralism shares with hermeneutics an awareness of the relation of the reader to the text, of the interpreter to the interpreted; this is the recurrent theme of Polzin's argument. Thus, as we noted at the beginning, Culley emphasizes a fundamental difference between structuralism and hermeneutics, whereas Polzin emphasizes a fundamental similarity between them. It has been my aim to consider both differences and similarities, both distinctions and commonalities, between these two approaches to meaning. I have suggested that structuralism and hermeneutics share a similar range of goals: that four terminal goals of structuralism-ideology (or philosophy), theory, structural exegesis, and narrative hermeneutics-are analogous to four terminal goals of hermeneutics-theology (or philosophy), theory, biblical exegesis, and existential understanding. I have suggested that structuralism and hermeneutics differ, however, in their presuppositions concerning history and language: that structuralism approaches history as the historic and language as a system of signs, and hermeneutics approaches history as historicity and language as language-event. Because

Page 17: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

222 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

of these presuppositions, literary or biblical structuralism focuses on intertextual and intratextual relationships and literary or biblical hermeneutics focuses on the text-reader relationship.

But, to borrow the terminology of Michael Polanyi, what is of focal awareness for the one is of subsidiary awareness for the other. Structural- ists know, sometimes more tacitly than explicitly, that to remove the text from its author-text-reader context is an abstraction; they insist, however, that this procedure is not arbitrary but essential, for it enables the reader to listen openly and fully to the text itself. Hermeneuticists know, some- times more tacitly than explicitly, that, if the reader is to hear and respond to the text, the text itself-in detail and as a whole and as a system of relationships forming of details a whole-this text must be allowed to speak in its own voice. In their most thoughtful moments, both structuralists and hermeneuticists realize, with Robert Funk, that "the text cannot speak for itself if it is not painstakingly exegeted in its own context, and it cannot be interpreted if it cannot be brought into intimate relation with contemporary modes of thought and experience" (Funk, 1964:181; see also Foust; Scholes:9-10).

But one cannot focus on everything at once./29/ In this the scholar, whether a traditional historical critic, a structuralist, or a hermeneuticist, is no better off than a child at a three-ring circus-and no worse off either. We do not regard the circus as primarily a frustrating experience for the child, nor need we regard the scholarly world as primarily such for ourselves. Yet, like the child whose head spins at the circus, we would do well to shift our focus occasionally, to allow our work to be refreshed by tacit knowledge coming to explicitness.

Structuralism focuses on "meaning of," on meaning in the context of intertextual and intratextual relationships. Hermeneutics focuses on "meaning for," on meaning in the context of the text-reader relationship. Because both structuralism and hermeneutics appreciate the importance of context to meaning, these two approaches to meaning should manifest a "preunderstanding" of each other, or, to change the figure, should perceive a common structure between themselves, and thus establish a creative relationship. Structuralism might guide hermeneutics away from a premature application of the text to the reader. from an immature abstraction of the text from the reader. Both structuralism and herme- neutics affirm that all textual meaning is contextual meaning. Perhaps both structuralists and hermeneuticists need to reaffirm that all inquiry is interrelated.

Page 18: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 223

NOTES

/1/ Compare (1) the model of a literary work (in the broadest sense of the term) as the interrelation of author, text, reader, world presented in Malbon, 1980:321-22; (2) the model of the "coordinates of art criticism" (work, audience, universe) presented by Abrams (especially 6); and (3) the "maps" for literary critics (central point: work; cardinal points: author, reader, information, lan-

guage) presented by Hernadi.

/2/ Polzin defines structuralism as an approach (1) to objects as whole, self-

regulating systems of transformations, (2) by means of hypothetical-deductive models, (3) with self-conscious awareness of the personal, operational structures of the subject making the approach (see especially 1-2). In his succeeding evalu- ations of what makes a structural analysis structural, however, Polzin focuses

primarily on the third element, the relationship of the analyzing subject to the

analysis (see especially 38,33-34). Polzin's purpose here-and his model-is "a structural analysis of structural analysis," not an evaluation of the relationship between structuralism and hermeneutics.

/3/ An earlier version of the following typology of structuralist goals was presented in Malbon, 1980:318-21.

/4/ Lane expresses these two categories not as ideology and methodology but as "theories" and "methods"; but note Lane's use of the terms "philosophies and methods" (17) and "ideology" (18).

/5/ I do not mean by this to ignore the possible distinctions between ideology and philosophy, but rather to refer, in general and with neutrality, to what Robert Scholes identifies and Robert Polzin affirms as "structuralism as a move- ment of mind" (Scholes:1; Polzin:iv,1).

/6/ Lane is here describing what he terms a "theory" as opposed to a "method." See note 4 above.

/7/ Cf. Scholes's discussion of "structuralism as a movement of mind" and "structuralism as a method" (1-12). See also Culley:169.

/8/ For example, Ehrmann:viii; Lane:17-18; Patte, 1976:19; Spivey:144; Wilder, 1974:11. Among the more positive, or at least neutral, discussions of structuralism as an ideology are Scholes:1-7; Gardner:213-47; McKnight: 295-312; Detweiler:202-4,207.

/9/ This distinction between theory and analysis is paralleled by, for exam- ple, Patte and Patte's distinction between "theory" and "practice" or "fundamen- tal research" and "applied research" (1); Patte's distinction between the search for "universal structures" and the search for "structures which characterize each specific narrative" (1980a:7); Detweiler's distinction between "theory" and "application" (3-4,103,124); Barthes's distinction between "poetics" and "criti- cism," as discussed by Culler (30-35).

/10/ This appears to be the case with Spivey:135; Robey:3; Culler (following

Page 19: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

224 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

Barthes):30-all of whom are commenting in the context of literary structural- ism. Cf. also Calinescu:5,9,16, on "poetics" (see note 28 below).

/11/ See Polzin:34. Patte's discussion of "five types of structuralist research" (1980a:7-9) may be understood as a development of the various relationships between theory and analysis: analysis in disregard of theory (Patte's type 1), theory in isolation from analysis (type 2), analysis for the sake of theory, whe- ther inductive or deductive (types 3 and 4), and analysis in the light of theory (type 5, "structural exegesis").

/12/ The term "methodology" is somewhat problematic. Whereas methodol- ogy does seem an appropriate term in opposition to ideology, that which sub- divides into theory and analysis might more appropriately be labeled methodology/method.

/13/ Cf. Patte, 1976:3-6, on "exegesis" and "hermeneutic." See also Patte and Patte:vii,94; and Patte, 1980a:22.

/14/ My diagram of goals, although developed independently of Pettit's tree of options (54), may be fruitfully compared with it. However, Pettit's tree of options serves as an evaluative tool (54-64): according to Pettit, theory fails- generative theory more drastically so than descriptive theory, and straight analy- sis is uncontrolled, thus only systematic analysis is workable; there is only one real option for structuralism.

/15/ See Glucksmann's five levels of the "problematic," or conceptual frame- work, of structuralism-or of any theoretical system, listed according to "descending levels of abstraction rather than a hierarchy of determinacy" (10): (1) epistemology [cf. structuralism as an approach to meaning], (2) philosophy [cf. philosophy (or ideology)], (3) theory [cf. theory], (4) methodology [cf. analy- sis], (5) description [cf. structural exegesis]. Glucksmann stresses that "each coher- ent thought system includes the five mentioned in some form" (10).

/16/ See Patte and Patte's diagram of "the path taken by Levi-Strauss" and the path they follow to the "semantic universe" (15-16).

/17/ As an analogous example we note that, although Daniel Patte shares with Edgar McKnight the structuralist goal of "narrative hermeneutics," Patte (1980b) underscores a fundamental difference in their philosophical and theolog- ical presuppositions: McKnight, according to Patte, affirms the reality of the world as an extralinguistic reality and revelation as immanent, while Patte, fol- lowing Greimas, affirms the reality of the world as a linguistic reality and reve- lation as transcendent.

/18/ Robinson (52), Cobb (229-30), and McKnight (77-78) would, presum- ably, consider existential understanding the ultimate goal of the new hermeneu- tic but biblical exegesis the ultimate goal of Bultmann. To be sure, exegesis of the text is more central (and essential) for Bultmann than for Ebeling and Fuchs, but Bultmann's approach to the text is motivated by his concern for the reader's (or hearer's) existential appropriation of it, and for Bultmann biblical

Page 20: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 225

exegesis that does not result in existential understanding is incomplete. For further examples of penultimate and ultimate hermeneutical goals,

consider Heidegger (penultimate: textual exegesis, ultimate: philosophy; see Palmer:141,161) and Ebeling and Fuchs (antepenultimate: biblical exegesis, pen- ultimate: existential understanding, ultimate: theology; see Achtemeier:85,87).

/19/ Cf. Achtemeier (125) on Fuchs and Palmer on Dilthey (Palmer:111, 116-18) and on Gadamer (Palmer:176-93) as well as Palmer's own "Thirty Theses on Interpretation" (242-53), especially theses 8 and 24-30. See also Ricoeur:16-19.

/20/ Wilder's critique of the new hermeneutic's concentration on historicity (1964:205), of its foundation "on a violent acultural and anticultural impulse" (1964:204), is well taken. See also Cobb's discussion of the existentialist (includ- ing the new hermeneutical) view of history (the historical) as external to faith.

/21/ From the point of view of the new hermenuetic, see Fuchs:237-39. On the reaction against historicism in twentieth-century literary criticism generally, see Calinescu:1-3,12,15-16.

/22/ As Funk notes in a warning to the new hermeneutic, "historical criticism as an integral element in the interpretation of the text is subject to pre- understanding. But the pre-understanding that is brought to the text is itself (both humanly and) historically situated and must itself be submitted to histori- cal criticism" (1964:195).

/23/ The terms language-system and language-behavior are Lyons's expres- sion (13) of Saussure's langue/parole distinction.

/24/ "Paradigmatic" is actually Louis Hjelmslev's term, but it is more com- monly employed (and less ambiguous) than Saussure's term "associative (Lyons:12).

/25/ Pettit (68) considers Levi-Strauss's work "as a development of the linguis- tic model rather than as an application of it." This evaluation appears to reflect Pettit's observation-and disapproval-of Levi-Strauss's move beyond interpre- tation to philosophy or ideology.

/26/ For a critique of the new hermeneutic's view of language (Does lan- guage express reality directly? Is existentialist language about language as abstract and objectifying, in another direction, as that which it rejects?), see Dillenberger (151) and Wilder (1964:211-12).

/27/ With this distinction between language "product" and language "process," compare Ricoeur's discussion of the word as "structure" and the word as "event" (79-96; see also 62-78). Patte suggests that both emphases are found within struc- turalism (1980a:9-12), and the inclusion of both structural exegesis and narrative hermeneutics within my typology of structuralist goals indicates my agreement at that level. However, at the level of presuppositions about language, I regard the language "product" orientation as more distinctive of structuralism and the language "process" orientation as more distinctive of hermeneutics.

Page 21: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

226 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

/28/ See also Calinescu's discussion of "Hermeneutics or Poetics," in which what I have isolated as goals and as presuppositions are not delineated. At times Calinescu's discussion of poetics vs. hermeneutics appears to parallel my discussion of goals: poetics is opposed to hermeneutics as theory is opposed to analysis (5,9,16) or perhaps as structural exegesis is opposed to narrative hermeneutics (16-17). At other times Calinescu's discussion of poetics vs. hermeneutics appears to parallel my discussion of presuppositions: poetics is opposed to hermeneutics as structural- ism's focus on language as a sytem of signs is opposed to hermeneutic's focus on

language as language-event (13-15) and as structuralism's focus on history as the historic is opposed to hermeneutic's focus on history as historicity (13,15-17).

/29/ The collection of papers and responses that comprises The New Herme- neutic (edited by Robinson and Cobb) illustrates the human drama of this state- ment.

REFERENCES

Abrams, M. H. 1953 The Mirror and the Lamp: Romantic Theory and the Criti-

cal Tradition. New York: W. W. Norton.

Achtemeier, Paul J. 1969 An Introduction to the New Hermeneutic. Philadelphia:

Westminster Press.

Bovon, Francis 1974 "French Structuralism and Biblical Exegesis." In Structural

Analysis and Biblical Exegesis: Interpretational Essays, trans. by Alfred M. Johnson, Jr., pp. 4-20. Pittsburgh Theo-

logical Monograph Series, no. 3. Pittsburgh: Pickwick Press.

Calinescu, Matei 1979 "Hermeneutics or Poetics." Journal of Religion 59:1-17.

Cobb, John B., Jr. 1964 "Faith and Culture." In The New Hermeneutic, ed. by James

M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 219-31. New York: Harper & Row.

Culler, Jonathan 1973 "The Linguistic Basis of Structuralism." In Structuralism: An

Introduction, ed. by David Robey, pp. 20-36. Wolfson College Lectures, 1972. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Culley, Robert C. 1974 "Structural Analysis: Is it Done With Mirrors?" Interpreta-

tion 28:165-81.

Detweiler, Robert 1978 Story, Sign and Self: Phenomenology and Structuralism as

Literary-Critical Methods. Semeia Supplements. Philadel- phia: Fortress Press; Missoula: Scholars Press.

Page 22: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 227

Dillenberger, John 1964 "On Broadening the New Hermeneutic." In The New Her-

meneutic, ed. by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 147-63. New York: Harper & Row.

Dundes, Alan 1968 "Introduction to the Second Edition" of Morphology of the

Folktale, by V. Propp, xi-xvii. Austin and London: Univer- sity of Texas for The American Folklore Society, Inc., and the Indiana Research Center for the Language Sciences.

Ebeling, Gerhard 1964 "Word of God and Hermeneutic." In The New Hermeneu-

tic, ed. by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 78-110. New York: Harper & Row.

Ehrmann, Jacques 1970 "Introduction" to Structuralism, ed. by Jacques Ehrmann,

pp. vii-xi. Garden City: Doubleday, Anchor Books.

Foust, Ronald 1981 "The Aporia of Recent Criticism and the Contemporary

Significance of Spatial Form." In Spatial Form in Narrative, ed. by Jeffrey R. Smitten and Ann Daghistany. Ithaca and London: Cornell University Press.

Fuchs, Ernst 1964 "The New Testament and the Hermeneutical Problem." In

The New Hermeneutic, ed. by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 111-63. New York: Harper & Row.

Funk, Robert W. 1964 "The Hermeneutical Problem and Historical Criticism." In

The New Hermeneutic, ed. by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 164-97. New York: Harper & Row.

1966 Language, Hermeneutic, and Word of God: The Problem of Language in the New Testament and Contemporary Theology. New York: Harper & Row.

Gardner, Howard 1972 The Quest for Mind: Piaget, LDvi-Strauss and the Struc-

turalist Movement. New York: Alfred A. Knopf. Glucksmann, Miriam

1974 Structuralist Analysis in Contemporary Social Thought: A Comparison of the Theories of Claude Levi-Strauss and Louis Althusser. International Library of Science. London and Boston: Routledge & Kegan Paul.

Hernadi, Paul 1976 "Literary Theory: A Compass for Critics." Critical Inquiry

3:369-86.

Page 23: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

228 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

Jacobson, Richard 1974 "The Structuralists and the Bible." Interpretation 28:

146-64.

Kovacs, Brian W. 1978 "Philosophical Foundations for Structuralism." Semeia 10:

85-105.

Lane, Michael 1970 "Introduction" to Introduction to Structuralism, ed. by

Michael Lane, pp. 11-39. New York: Basic Books.

Levi-Strauss, Claude 1969 The Elementary Structure of Kinship. Trans. by R. Need-

ham. Boston: Beacon Press. 1969-81 Introduction to a Science of Mythology. Trans. by John

Weightman and Doreen Weightman. Vol. 1: The Raw and the Cooked. Vol. 2: From Honey to Ashes. Vol. 3: The Origin of Table Manners. Vol. 4: The Naked Man. New York: Harper & Row.

Lyons, John 1973 "Stucturalism and Linguistics." In Structuralism: An Intro-

duction, ed. by David Robey, pp. 5-19. Wolfson College Lectures, 1972. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

McKnight, Edgar V. 1978 Meaning in Texts: The Historical Shaping of a Narrative

Hermeneutics. Philadelphia: Fortress Press.

Malbon, Elizabeth Struthers 1979 "Mythic Structure and Meaning in Mark: Elements of a

Levi-Straussian Analysis." Semeia 16:97-132. 1980 "'No Need to Have Any One Write'?: A Structural Exegesis

of 1 Thessalonians." In Society of Biblical Literature 1980 Seminar Papers. pp. 301-35. Missoula: Scholars Press for SBL. Revised form to appear in Semeia 27.

1982 "Galilee and Jerusalem: History and Literature in Markan Interpretation." CBQ 44:242-55.

198? "Ta Oikia Autou: Mark 2:15 in Context." NTS, in press.

Palmer, Richard E. 1969 Hermeneutics: Interpretation Theory in Schleiermacher,

Dilthey, Heidegger, and Gadamer. Evanston: Northwest- ern University Press.

Patte, Daniel 1976 What Is Structural Exegesis? Guides to Biblical Scholar-

ship, New Testament Series. Philadelphia: Fortress Press. 1980a "One Text: Several Structures." Semeia 18:3-22. 1980b "Structuralism and Hermeneutics: A Review Article." Reli-

gious Studies Review 7:60-70.

Page 24: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

Malbon: Structuralism 229

Patte, Daniel and Patte, Aline 1978 Structural Exegesis: From Theory to Practice. Philadel-

phia: Fortress Press.

Perrin, Norman 1974 The New Testament: An Introduction. New York: Har-

court, Brace, Jovanovich.

Pettit, Philip 1975 The Concept of Structuralism: A Critical Analysis. Berke-

ley and Los Angeles: University of California Press.

Polanyi, Michael 1958 Personal Knowledge: Towards a Post-Critical Philosophy.

Chicago: University of Chicago Press.

Polzin, Robert M. 1977 Biblical Structuralism: Method and Subjectivity in the

Study of Ancient Texts. Semeia Supplements. Fortress Press; Missoula: Scholars Press.

Propp, Vladimir 1968 Morphology of the Folktale, 2d ed. Trans. by Lawrence

Scott. Rev. and ed. by Louis A. Wagner. Austin and London: University of Texas for The American Folklore Society, Inc., and the Indiana Research Center for the Language Sciences.

Ricoeur, Paul 1974 The Conflict of Interpretations: Essays in Hermeneutics.

Ed. by Don Ihde. Evanston: Northwestern University Press.

Robey, David 1973 "Introduction" to Structuralism: An Introduction, ed. by

David Robey, pp. 1-4. Wolfson College Lectures, 1972. Oxford: Clarendon Press.

Robinson, James M. 1964 "Hermeneutic Since Barth." In The New Hermeneutic, ed.

by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 1-77. New York: Harper & Row.

Saussure, Ferdinand de 1959 Course in General Linguistics. Ed. by Charles Bally,

Albert Sechehaye, and Albert Riedlinger. Trans. by Wade Baskin. New York: McGraw-Hill.

Scholes, Robert 1974 Structuralism in Literature: An Introduction. New Haven

and London: Yale University Press.

Spivey, Robert A. 1974 "Structuralism and Biblical Studies: The Uninvited Guest."

Interpretation 28:133-45.

Page 25: Structural Ism, Hermeneutics And Contextual Meaning

230 Journal of the American Academy of Religion

Thiselton, Anthony C. 1980 The Two Horizons: New Testament Hermeneutics and

Philosophical Description with Special Reference to Hei- degger, Bultmann, Gadamer, and Wittgenstein. Exeter: The Paternoster Press.

Via, Dan O., Jr. 1975 Kerygma and Comedy in the New Testament: A Structural-

ist Approach to Hermeneutic. Philadelphia: Fortress Press.

Wells, Rulon S. 1970 "De Saussure's System of Linguistics." In Introduction to

Structuralism, ed. by Michael Lane, pp. 85-123. New York: Basic Books.

Wilder, Amos N. 1964 "The Word as Address and the Word as Meaning." In The

New Hermeneutic, ed. by James M. Robinson and John B. Cobb, Jr., pp. 198-218. New York: Harper & Row.

1974 "Semeia: An Experimental Journal for Biblical Criticism- An Introduction." Semeia 1:1-16.

Wittig, Susan 1975 "The Historical Development of Structuralism." Soundings

58:145-66.