29
Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be; but as it isn’t, it ain’t. That’s logic.”

Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

  • View
    215

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.”

Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be; but as it isn’t, it ain’t. That’s logic.”

Page 2: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

PHIL 120: Introduction to Logic

Professor:Lynn [email protected]

Instructors:Lars EndenCheryl FitzgeraldMitch KaufmanJoe Ricci

Page 3: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

PHIL 120: Introduction to Logic

Course website:http://faculty.washington.edu/lynnhank/PHIL120.html

Syllabus and course requirementsPower point lecturesSample testsOffice hours and locations; e-mail addresses.Announcements

Course Text:The Logic Book, 5th edition. McGraw Hill.A solutions manual is available online.

Page 4: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

PHIL 120 Requirements

I. Attendance and participation in lectures and discussion sections, including assigned homework and pop quizzes (20%)

II. 5 tests (16% each)III. You may take 1 test over to raise the gradeIV. Practice, practice, practice… logic is not a

spectator sport!V. Ask questions!

Page 5: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Logic The study of reasoning The drawing of inferences: what follows

from what and what doesn’t follow We can talk in terms of ‘ideas’, ‘beliefs’,

and the like, but it’s more concrete to talk about ‘sentences’ – those entities that we use to express ideas, beliefs, and claims.

One focus: arguments A set of at least two sentences, one of which is

the conclusion and the other or others is/are reasons (premises) that support it.

Page 6: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Good arguments vs. bad arguments

1. All men are mortal.2. Socrates is a man.__________________3. Socrates is mortal.

This argument is truth-preserving. It is deductively valid.

If it is true that all men are mortal, and true that Socrates is a man, then it must be true that Socrates is mortal.

1. All men are mortal.2. Socrates is mortal.____________________3. Socrates is a man.

This argument is not truth preserving. It is deductively invalid.

Even if the premises are true, they do not guarantee the truth of the conclusion.

Socrates could be the name of any living thing.

Page 7: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Logic and humor

Page 8: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Good arguments vs. bad arguments

1. If you studied a lot, you did well in the logic course.

2. You studied a lot._________________________3. You did well in the logic

course.

This argument is truth-preserving. It is deductively valid.

It is not possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false.

1. If you studied a lot, you did well in the logic course.

2. You did well in the logic course.

____________________3. You studied a lot.

This argument is not truth preserving. It is deductively invalid.

It is possible for the premises to be true and the conclusion false.

Page 9: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The language SL

A symbolic language used to illustrate the logical structure of sentences, of sets of sentences, of arguments, and of other relationships between sentences

In sentential logic, the most basic unit is the simple declarative sentence.

Simple: no logical connectives Declarative: either true or false We assume bivalence

Page 10: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The language SL

The vocabulary of SL:1. Roman capital letters, A through Z, with or

without subscripts (e.g., S and S3) used to symbolize simple, declarative sentences

2. 5 (sentential) connectives: ~ (tilde)

& (ampersand)v (wedge) (horseshoe) (triple bar)The first is a unary connective.

The rest are binary connectives.3. Punctuation: ( ) and [ ]

Page 11: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The language SL

Every sentence of SL is either simple/atomic or compound/molecular.

Simple/atomic sentences have no connectives.

Compound/molecular sentences have at least one connective.

Meta variablesObject language and meta languageP, Q, R, and S are meta variables used to talk

about sentences of SL.

Page 12: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The recursive definition of SL

1. Every sentence letter is a sentence. 2. If P is a sentence of SL, ~P is a sentence of SL.3. If P and Q are sentences, then (P & Q) is a

sentence.4. If P and Q are sentences, then (P v Q) is a sentence.5. If P and Q are sentences, then (P Q) is a

sentence.6. If P and Q are sentences, then (P Q) is a

sentence.7. Nothing else is a sentence.

Page 13: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

What the recursive definition of SL does It tells us what will count as a sentence of SL It also tells us what will not. For example, these are not sentences of SL:

A & clause 3: & is a binary connective

B & C ? SL does not include ‘?’

~ & ~ must be used before a sentence

(clause 2); and & must connect 2 sentences

(clause 3)

Page 14: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

What the recursive definition of SL does It tells us what will count as a sentence of

SL These are sentences of SL:

A & B (clause 3) (B & B) & B (clause 3) ~~B (clause 2)

A v B (clause 4) A B (clause 5)

A B (clause 6)

Page 15: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

Roman capital letters A through Z (with or without subscripts) to symbolize simple declarative sentences:

‘Mary went to the store’ (we could symbolize as M).‘John went to the store’ (we could symbolize as J).

These are NOT simple declarative sentences:Either Mary went to the store or John did.Mary did not (or didn’t) go to the store.

Page 16: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘Mary did not (or didn’t) go to the store’ The logic of this sentence is:

‘It is not the case that Mary went to the store’ ~ symbolizes ‘it is not the case that’ So, using M for ‘Mary went to the store’,

we use ~M to symbolize ‘It is not the case that Mary went to the store’

Sentences whose main connective is the tilde are called negations.

Page 17: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The characteristic truth table for the ~

P ~~PP

T F

F T

Page 18: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘Mary and John went to the store’ This is a compound/molecular sentence to be

translated as: ‘Mary went to the store and John went to the

store’ We can use M to symbolize ‘Mary went to the

store’, and J to symbolize ‘John went to the store’ We use the & for ‘and’ So we have:

M & J

Page 19: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The characteristic truth table for the &

PP QQ P & QP & Q

T T T

T F F

F T F

F F F

Page 20: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

Sentences whose main connective is the & are called conjunctions and each of the sentences connected by the & is called a conjunct. We can refer to them as the right or the left conjunct.

We use & as a connective in all cases in which the compound sentence is only true if both of its component sentences are true.

This is the case for:‘Mary went to the store but John did too’the logical structure of which is:‘Mary went to the store and John went to the store’

Page 21: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘Mary went to the store but John did not’ Is paraphrased as: ‘Mary went to the store and it is not the case

that John went to the store’ M can symbolize ‘Mary went to the store’ And & is used for but. So far we have: M & ~J can symbolize ‘it is not the case that John

went to the store’ So we have:

M & ~J

Page 22: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘Either Mary went to the store or John did’ Is translated as: ‘Either Mary went to the store or John went

to the store’ We use the v to symbolize ‘either/or’ If we use M to symbolize ‘Mary went to the

store’ and J to symbolize ‘John went to the store’ we symbolize the whole sentence as:

M v J

Page 23: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The characteristic truth table for v

PP QQ P P v v QQ

T T T

T F T

F T T

F F F

Page 24: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

Because ‘either/or’ and the v assume the inclusive sense of ‘or’ (at least one is true), we will need to do more if we believe a sentence makes use of the exclusive sense of ‘or’ (at most one of the two) and should be symbolized to reflect this.

On a restaurant menu, for example, the phrase ‘either soup or salad is included’ reflects the exclusive sense of ‘or’.

Context may tell us that a claim comes to ‘Either Mary went to the store or John did, but not both’

Page 25: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘If Mary went to the store, John did’ ‘If Mary went to the store, then John went

to the store’ M: Mary went to the store J: John went to the store We use to symbolize ‘if, then’ So we have:

M J

Page 26: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The characteristic truth table for the

PP QQ P P QQ

T T T

T F F

F T T

F F T

Page 27: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences The reasoning behind the Consider the following claim:

If the operation is a success, the patient survives. The condition, ‘the operation is a success’, is a

sufficient but not a necessary condition for the patient’s survival.

The docs decided not to operate and the patient survived… they discovered they were wrong about the need for an operation…

If the claim was ‘Only if the operation is a success, the patient survives’, then the operation’s success would require the patient’s survival for the claim to be true … but that is not what ‘If’ by itself entails.

Page 28: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

Using SL to symbolize sentences

‘Mary went to the store if and only if John did’

‘Mary went to the store if and only if John went to the store’

We use for ‘if and only if’ So we have:

M J ‘P if and only if Q’ is equivalent to: (If P then Q) and (If Q then P)

Page 29: Tweedledum: “I know what you’re thinking, but it isn’t so. No how.” Tweedledee: “Contrariwise, if it was so, it might be; and if it were so, it would be;

The characteristic truth table for the

PP QQ P P QQ

T T T

T F F

F T F

F F T