9
Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing enquiries@alevelphilosoph y.co.uk

Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Problems with calculation Can we know the consequences of an action? Bentham: –the principle of utility ‘approves or disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish … happiness’ –It is much easier to work out the consequences that actions ‘tend’ to have –We needn’t pursue the felicific calculus every time

Citation preview

Page 1: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Utilitarianism: objectionsMichael Lacewing

[email protected]

Page 2: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Hedonist act utilitarianism

• Act consequentialism: Actions are morally right or wrong depending on their consequences and nothing else. An act is right if it maximises what is good.

• Value theory: The only thing that is good is happiness.

• Equality: Everyone’s happiness counts more than anyone else’s.

Page 3: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Problems with calculation

• Can we know the consequences of an action?

• Bentham: – the principle of utility ‘approves or

disapproves of every action whatsoever, according to the tendency which it appears to have to augment or diminish … happiness’

– It is much easier to work out the consequences that actions ‘tend’ to have

– We needn’t pursue the felicific calculus every time

Page 4: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Mill’s secondary principles

• Mill: happiness is ‘much too complex and indefinite’ a standard for us to apply directly to actions in many cases

• But humanity has worked this out over time, giving our moral rules (‘secondary principles’)– ‘Don’t steal’: because it tends to produce more

unhappiness than happiness• If two secondary principles conflict, then we

should appeal to the greatest happiness principle

Page 5: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Individual liberty and rights

• No type of action is ruled out as immoral– Torturing a child for fun is wrong,

even in circumstances where this gives more happiness than not torturing the child

– What makes it wrong is not that this balance of happiness is unlikely

• Happiness isn’t always good?

Page 6: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Individual liberty and rights

• Moral rights place restrictions on how people can treat each other– Right to life: other people mustn’t kill

me– Right to liberty: I may act as I choose

as long as this respects other people’s rights

– Rights must be respected even when this does not maximize happiness

• But do we have any moral rights?

Page 7: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

The value of motives and character

• Utilitarianism doesn’t recognize the moral value of either our motives for acting or virtuous character traits

• Mill’s reply: utilitarianism says these are not relevant to whether an action is right, but that does not mean they are morally irrelevant

• A good motive or virtue is one that tends to produce morally right actions

• It is important to be made happy by maximizing happiness

Page 8: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Particular relationships• Everyone’s happiness counts equally.

My happiness, and the happiness of those I love, has no special weight in guiding my actions– This is too idealistic (demanding)– This wrongly condemns partiality

• Visiting a friend in hospital; rescuing one’s wife from drowning – just a means to maximize happiness?

Page 9: Utilitarianism: objections Michael Lacewing

Particular relationships• Friendship requires that the friend

is valued as the individual person that they are, and that we act out of love for them

• Benefiting a friend is morally good• Therefore, utilitarianism is false – it

is not wrong not to maximize happiness