32
What is the Philosophy of Language?

What is the Philosophy of Language?

  • Upload
    kynton

  • View
    96

  • Download
    2

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

What is the Philosophy of Language?. Philosophy of language is the study of philosophically interesting issues concerning language. Many of these issue involve the semantic (or “meaning”) properties of language. Semantic Properties. The French sentence ‘ il pleut ’ means that it’s raining. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: What is the Philosophy of Language?

What is the Philosophy of Language?

Page 2: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Philosophy of language is the study of philosophically interesting issues concerning language.

Many of these issue involve the semantic (or “meaning”) properties of language.

Page 3: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Semantic Properties

• The French sentence ‘il pleut’ means that it’s raining.

• That sentence is true if and only if it’s raining.• The French word ‘chien’ applies to dogs; dogs

satisfy ‘chien.’• The name ‘Victor Hugo’ refers to a certain

person; sentences containing the name are about Victor Hugo.

Page 4: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Interesting Features

Semantic properties/ relations are interesting for a number of reasons. Normally, we see the following patterns:• If Fred kicked George, then George exists.• If Fred kicked George, then there is someone

Fred kicked.• If Fred kicked George, and George is the

sneakiest Russian spy, then Fred kicked the sneakiest Russian spy.

Page 5: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Interesting Features

However,• ‘Sherlock Holmes’ means Sherlock Holmes, but

Holmes does not exist.• ‘Santa Claus’ means Santa Claus, but there isn’t

anyone whom ‘Santa Claus’ means.• ‘Ben Franklin’ means Ben Franklin, and Ben

Franklin is the inventor of bifocals, but ‘Ben Franklin’ does not mean the inventor of bifocals.

Page 6: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Interesting Features

Language can mean or be about thing that don’t exist.

Also, even when they are about things that do exist (Ben Franklin), they simultaneously are not about those very same things (the inventor of bifocals).

That’s all very weird.

Page 7: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Naturalizing Meaning

The weirdness of representation makes it difficult to see how it fits into “the natural order.”

As we’ll see, various proposals about why some things have meanings and others don’t, and why things that have meanings have the ones they do, haven’t worked out to everyone’s satisfaction.

Page 8: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Original vs. Derived Meaning

One strategy for dealing with the problem of linguistic representation is to say that words represent what our thoughts represent (since thoughts too can be about things and be true or false).

This pushes the problem back to how thoughts can represent, but maybe this is easier to explain.

Page 9: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Idea Theory

One theory popular in the Early Modern period in Europe was the idea theory. According to this theory, words stood for ideas and ideas represented things. Derivatively, words represented what the ideas they stood for represented.

Ideas were like mental pictures, and they represented the world by resembling it. (Obviously can’t work for words: ‘dog’ doesn’t resemble dogs.)

Page 10: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Problems for the Idea Theory

For a large number of reasons (that we’ll cover in detail next class), the idea theory went out of fashion.

Here’s just one such reason: if A resembles B, then B resembles A. But it’s not true that if A represents B, then B represents A. Therefore representation is not resemblance.

Page 11: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Verificationism

A subsequent view that became popular in early 20th Century Anglophone philosophy was called ‘verificationism.’

Roughly stated, the verificationist position was that words stood for experiences, and experiences represented what they verified. Here, an experience verifies X = whenever you have that experience, X is true.

Page 12: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Verificationism

So the meaning of ‘it’s raining’ would be the set of experiences such that if you were having those experiences, then it was raining.

We’ll consider verificationism in greater detail, but one objection worth thinking about is that it seems to count past-tense sentences as meaningless. What experiences that you now have can verify “Caesar crossed the Rubicon”?

Page 13: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Description Theory

Verificationism was a kind of description or definition theory. Some words stood for certain experiences, but other words were defined from the ones that stood for experiences.

This is another common strategy in lessening the amount of work we have to do to understand meaning. Some words “inherit” their meanings from others via definitions.

Page 14: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Description Theory

But the definition strategy is broader than verificationism. You can deny that words stand for experiences and still say that some (perhaps a great many) words get their meanings by definition. And maybe all of them do?

Part of the problem with the description theory has been that there are so few convincing definitions.

Page 15: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Causal-Historical Theory

The causal-historical theory, which I can’t go into great detail on here, is the view that my words don’t have their meanings because of the ideas/ experiences/ definitions that I associate with them, but rather they simply “inherit” their meanings from the people whom I learnt the words from. Mental representation is required for the original “attachment” of meaning (reference fixing) but not its preservation.

Page 16: What is the Philosophy of Language?

One Problem

One problem for the causal-historical theory is that sometimes words change their meanings (that is, they don’t inherit them from prior uses of those words)– and sometimes this change is unintentional and unobserved. Through a misunderstanding, ‘Madagascar’ has come to name an island off the coast of Africa. According to the causal-historical theory, this shouldn’t be so: the inheritance of meanings doesn’t care about understanding or misunderstanding.

Page 17: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Use Theory

Some words are very difficult to handle on the theories of meaning we’ve discussed– words like ‘not’ and ‘and.’

What mental picture does ‘and’ stand for? What experience? Can you define ‘and’ with other words? These questions are difficult, or impossible to answer.

Page 18: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Use Theory

One view is that ‘and’ means what it does because of how it’s used in inference.

From ‘A and B’ we can infer A and we can infer B. We can’t infer A from ‘A or B.’

From A and B, we can infer ‘A and B.’ We can’t infer ‘A and B’ from just A, however (cf. ‘A or B’).

Page 19: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Use Theory

The difficulty is to make this idea work for other expressions. Use theorists have certainly tried, but it’s difficult to explain, for example, what premises you can infer ‘x is a tree’ from, and what conclusions you can draw from ‘x is a tree.’ It seems saying this would require you to have a definition of tree (which, as I’ve said, is difficult to come by).

Page 20: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Infinite Meanings

Moving beyond theories of meaning, there are other issues in the philosophy of language.

One interesting one is how it’s possible that we can understand a potential infinity of novel utterances– sentences we’ve never heard before in our life.

Page 21: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Novelty

Before now you’ve never heard the sentence,

“Little purple gnomes, wearing red tracksuits, are disco-dancing on the ceiling of Run Run Shaw Tower.”

Still, you understand what it means without effort.

Page 22: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Infinity

And there are infinitely many meaningful sentences that you have yet to hear, but would understand immediately. Here’s the proof.

For any meaningful sentence that’s N words long, there is another meaningful sentence that’s N + 3 words long: take the original and append ‘Michael believes that’ to the front.

Page 23: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Compositionality

A much-favored solution among philosophers (and linguists and computer scientists) is called compositionality.

This is the claim that we can understand infinitely many sentences, because the meanings of sentences depend only on what their parts mean, and there are only finitely many parts (individual words).

Page 24: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Semantic Paradoxes

There are a number of paradoxes associated with semantic properties. We’ll be looking at them later in the semester, but here is one known as Grelling’s paradox.

First, we define the terms autological and heterological.

Page 25: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Autological Adjectives

An adjective is autological if and only if it applies to itself. Examples:

• ‘Short’ is short• ‘English’ is English• ‘Adjectival’ is adjectival• ‘Polysyllabic’ is polysyllabic

Page 26: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Heterological Adjectives

The heterological adjectives are all the rest, the ones that don’t apply to themselves:

• ‘Long’ is not long• ‘German’ is not German• ‘Nominal’ is not nominal• ‘Monosyllabic’ is not monosyllabic

Page 27: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Grelling’s Paradox

Here’s a question then: is the adjective ‘heterological’ heterological?

Suppose we say ‘yes.’ Then ‘heterological’ is heterological. By definition then, ‘heterological’ does not apply to itself. Thus ‘heterological’ is not heterological.

Page 28: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Grelling’s Paradox

Suppose instead we say ‘no,’ ‘heterological’ is not heterological. Then it does not apply to itself, so by definition ‘heterological’ is heterological.

The contradiction seems to arise from assuming the reasonable principle that if ‘red’ applies to x, x is red; if ‘big’ applies to x, x is big; and if ‘heterological’ applies to x, x is heterological.

Page 29: What is the Philosophy of Language?

Paradoxes of Vagueness

Paradoxes also seem to arise when we consider vague expressions– expressions that have borderline cases.

Many adjectives are vague– ‘bald,’ and ‘rich.’ are examples. Sometimes it’s not clear whether someone is bald or whether they’re rich. There are also non-vague adjectives, like ‘pregnant.’

Page 30: What is the Philosophy of Language?

No Sharp Boundaries

For vague terms, it seems there are no sharp boundaries. This means something like: if someone is bald, adding one hair to their head won’t make them not bald, and if they are not bald, taking one hair away won’t make them bald.

Page 31: What is the Philosophy of Language?

The Slippery Slope

But now consider this argument:1. Someone with 1 hair is bald.2. So someone with 2 hairs is bald [No Sharp

Boundaries]3. So someone with 3 hairs is bald [No Sharp

Boundaries]… So someone with 10 million hairs is not bald.

Page 32: What is the Philosophy of Language?

What do we do? We can’t believe that someone with 1 hair is bald AND that someone with 10 million hairs is not bald AND that there are no sharp boundaries.

But all three claims seems unimpeachable. If we reject No Sharp Boundaries, for instance, we have to say that its possible to go from bald to not bald by losing one hair!