(1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

  • Upload
    ombsac

  • View
    214

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    1/9

    HISTORIA MATHEIYATICA 2 (1975), 439-447

    THE MATHEMATICIAN, HE HISTORIAN,AND THE HISTORYOF MATHEMATICSBY JUDITH V, GRABINERSMALL COLLEGE, CALIFORNIA STATE COLLEGE,DOMINGUEZ HILLS

    The historian's basic questions, whether he is a historianof mathematics or of political institutions, are: what was thepast like? and how did the present come to be? The secondquestion--how did the present come to be?--is the central one inthe history of mathematics, whether done by historian or mathe-matician. But the historian's view of both past and present isquite different from that of the mathematician. The historianis interested in the past in its full richness, and sees anypresent fact as conditioned by a complex chain of causes in analmost unlimited past. The mathematician instead is orientedtoward the present, and toward past mathematics chiefly insofaras it led to important present mathematics. [a]

    IWhat questions do mathematicians generally ask about thehistory of mathematics? When was this concept first defined,and what problems led to its definition?" "Who first provedthis theorem, and how did he do it?" "IS the proof correct bymodern standards?" The mathematician begins with mathematicsthat is important now, and looks backwards for its antecedents.To a mathematician, all mathematics is contemporary; as Little-wood put it [A7, p. 813, the ancient Greeks were "Fellows ofanother College." True and significant mathematics is trueand significant, whenever it may have been done.The history of mathematics as written by mathematicians

    tends to be technical, to focus on the content of specificpapers. It is written on a high mathematical level, and dealswith significant mathematics. The title of E. T. Bell's TheDevelopment of Mathematics reflects the mathematician's view.The mathematician looks at the development of mathematics, asthe result of a chronologically and logically connected seriesof papers; he does not look at it as the work of people livingin considerably different historical settings.II

    How is the historian different? First, it goes withoutsaying that, in asking what the past was like, the historianwill be more concerned than the mathematician about the non-mathematical, as well as the mathematical past. More sur-prising is that even when dealing with strictly technical ques-tions, the historian may view things differently from the

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    2/9

    440 J .V. Grabiner HM 2

    mathematician.While the mathematician sees the past as part of the pres-ent, the historian sees the present as laden with archaeologicalrelics from the past; he sees everything in the present as hav-ing many and diverse roots in the past, and as the end of long,complex processes. Many things we take for granted are neitherlogical nor natural. They might even appear arbitrary, but theyare, instead, the products of particular historical situations.For example, the use of the letter epsilon, as in delta-epsilon proofs, appears arbitrary, but it in fact records theorigin of the use of inequalities in proofs in analysis. Theorigin was in the study of approximations, the notation Ire silon

    is Cauchys, and the letter seems to stand for error. dHistorians love this sort of explanation, and constantly searchfor ones like it. To take another kind of example, isnt itamazing that the standard7

    roof that /2 is irrational is overtwo thousand years old? [cAnother essential difference between the historian and themathematician is this: the historian of mathematics will askhimself what the total mathematical past in some particulartime-period was like. He will steep himself in many aspects ofthat mathematical past, not just those which have an obviousbearing on the antecedents of the particular mathematical de-velopment whose history he is tracing. [A2;A3;A4;A8] Let us seehow this feature of the historians approach can be of value tothe mathematician interested in the history of mathematics.Obviously it is easier to find the antecedents of present ideaswhen one knows where to look. The better one knows the past,the wider the variety of places he can investigate. In addition,through familiarity with specific types of sources, the historianknows where to find the answers to particular types of questions.By contrast, someone relatively unfamiliar with the time periodin question will not always understand what past mathematicianswere trying to do, and will find that the terms used then didnot always mean what they mean today. [d]Let me give some examples to clarify this general point.There is a widespread impression that eighteenth-centurymathematicians were very cavalier in their treatment of con-vergence, and it is sometimes % en said that they assumed thatonce they had shown that the n term of a series went to zero,the series converged. Did eighteenth-century mathematiciansin fact make this error? Hadnt they ever heard of the harmonicseries? My own sense of eighteenth-century mathematics saysthat eighteenth-century mathematicians werent that incompetent.They knew the divergence of the harmonic series [e]. Peoplelike Euler, DAlembert, Lagrange, and Laplace were not hopelesslyconfused. In fact, DAlembert and Lagrange investigated theremainders of specific infinite series and tried to find boundson the value of those remainders [fl. Why, then, did even these

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    3/9

    HM2 Mathematician, Historian, History of Science 441

    men sometimes say the series converges when they had shownonly that the nth term goes to zero? Because, in the eighteenthcentury, the term converge was used in different ways; some-times, it was used as we use it; often, however, it was used tosay that the nth term went to zero or that the terms of the seriesgot smaller [g]. This conclusion, which I reached after read-ing numerous eighteenth-century papers, can be reliably verifiedby looking at the Diderot-DAlembert i?ncyclop&ie [h]. Themodern def inition of convergent series -- that the part ial sumsof the series have a lim it -- was established by Cauchy [B6 (2),vol. 3, p. 1141. It is hard to avoid reading this modern mean-ing back into eighteenth-century mathematics. But this linguis-tic point, once understood, makes sense out of much eighteenth-century work on infinite series.

    Another advantage of knowing the mathematical past is thatthe historian can construct a total picture of the background ofsome specific modern achievement. Rather than just looking atthe major papers on the same topic, he may find the antecedentsof some modern theories in unlikely places. A well-known ex-ample is the way the general definition of function came, notmerely out of attempts to describe the class of al l known al-gebraic expressions, but, more importantly, from the attemptsto characterize the solutions to the partial differentialequation for the vibrating string [i]. Another example may befound in the way Thomas Hawkins in his Lebesgue's theory ofIntegration [El43 has presented the ful l nineteenth-centurybackground, drawing on a wide variety of mathematical work be-sides earlier ideas on integration.For another example, consider Cauchys def inition of thederivative and the proofs of theorems based on that definit ion.In looking at the introductory sections of eighteenth-centurycalculus books, one finds a long string of definitions of de-rivatives, and debates about their nature -- debates stemmingfrom the attack on the foundations of the calculus by BishopBerkeley. One might well view each of these old definitionsand polemics as major contributors to Cauchys final formulation.However, what was more important than the explicit verbal def-ini tion Cauchy gave for the derivative are the associated in-equality proof-techniques he pioneered. And these techniquescame from elsewhere. The basic inequality property Cauchy usedto define the derivative came to him from Lagranges work onthe Lagrange remainder in the latters lectures on the calculusat the Ecole polytechnique [j]. The inequality proof-techniquesthemselves were developed largely in the study of algebraicapproximations in the eighteenth century [k].Let us now take up a characteristic of the historian whichwe have not yet considered. We expect the historian to know thegeneral history of a particular time as well as the mathematicsof that time. He should have a sense of what it was like to be

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    4/9

    442 J.V. Grabiner HM2

    a person, not just a mathematician, at that time. Sometimessuch knowledge has great explanatory value. One would not wantto treat the history of the foundations of the calculus with-out knowing about the attacks on the calculus by the theologianBerkeley [B3, ch. VI]; or the flowering of seventeenth-andeighteenth-century mathematics without reference to the con-temporary explosion in the natural sciences, especially Newton-ian physics [A6]. One cannot treat the growth of the Frenchschool of mathematics in the nineteenth century without men-tioning a major cause -- the founding by the French revolution-ary government of the Ecole polytechnique, providing employ-ment and a first-rate mathematical community for its facultand an excellent mathematical education for its students [l 5 ,.One would not want to explain the relative absence of women inthe ranks of nineteenth-century mathematicians without refer-ring to the lack of access to higher education for women inEurope at a time when mathematics was so sPecialized and ad-vanced that formal training was essential m].By virtue of his training, the historian has been exposedto a number of general historiographical questions and is usedto hearing them asked. For instance, there are theories of thenature of scientific change, like Thomas Kuhn's theory of scien-tific revolutions [A3]. Again, there are sociologically basedtheories like Robert Merton's analysis of priority controversiesin science [A13]. The historian of mathematics,without havingto become a disciple of Kuhn or Merton, can use such theoriesto help ask fruitful questions about the past of mathematics,and about the time period in which the mathematics occurred.He has the questions already at hand, and need not figure themout from first principles.

    IIIOur description of the possible contributions of historiansand mathematicians to the writing of the history of mathematicshas required, as well, some description of what the history ofmathematics is like. Let us know turn to a different, but re-lated question. What value has the history of mathematics,whether done by historian or mathematician? Of course, there isan inherent fascination in any history,and work in the historyof mathematics certainly should be an element in the history ofhuman culture in general. But another essential use exists --for the mathematician -- in teaching and understanding mathematics.Historical background can help teach mathematics in threeways. First, the history can help the teacher understand the in-herent difficulty of certain concepts. A concept which tookhundreds of years to develop is probably hard, and the historicaldifficulties may well resemble student difficulties.Second, understanding how a mathematical idea arose can helpmotivate students. It helps answer questions like, "Why might

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    5/9

    HM2 Mathematician, Historian, History of Science

    somebody want to think about it in this particular way? [n].Isolated historical comments, of course, do not make history.What one would like to do for ones students -- and for thatmatter, for oneself -- is to give them a sense of how the wholesub j ect developed, and how the whole background of the subjectfits together. Such a sense would motivate not just one con-cept or proof, but the entire subject.Third, the historical background can help the student --or the mathematician -- see how mathematics fits in with therest of human thought; how Descartes the mathematician relatesto Descartes the philosopher; how the rise of German mathematicsin the mid-nineteenth century fits into the rise of Germanscience, technology, and national power at that time. To seepast mathematics in its historical context helps to see pre-sent mathematics in its philosophical, scientific, and socialcontext, and to have a better understanding of the place ofmathematics in the world.

    IVIf the history of mathematics is indeed to be used in theseways, we need more of it. There now exists a technical lit-erature which has established what the important results and

    their major antecedents are in many areas [o]. There is a neednow for more studies on the full historical background of manysubjects in modern mathematics -- the theory of functions of acomplex variable, for instance, or the rise of abstract algebra,or the philosophical and mathematical impact of non-Euclideangeometry. And the existing work needs to be made more availablethrough the offering of full-scale courses in the history ofmathematics , placingthemonographsof BoyerandHawkinsalong withthe general histories of mathematics on the library shelves,and ordering Archive for the History of the Exact Sciences andiiistoria Mathematics for the departmental library along with theBulletin and the Monthly. Finally, there are now too few his-torians of mathematics. The path for the historian of mathematicsis difficult; he needs the historians training, but also needsto know a great deal of mathematics. The history of science isitself a young and relatively small profession; the number ofhistorians of mathematics, because of the types of knowledgeneeded, is even smaller. Still the need for such people is ap-parent. Even if historians of mathematics were legion, however, thecontribution of mathematicians to the history of mathematicswould remain crucial. Mathematicians, of course, bring a higherlevel of mathematical knowledge to any historical task. His-torians of mathematics should certainly know the mathematicswhose history they are writing. But mathematicians are stillneeded -- and not just because they know the mathematics better.Historians need the mathematicians point of view about what is

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    6/9

    444 J .V. Grabiner HMZ

    mathematically important. The mathematicians work determineswhat it is that most needs a historical explanation. Only themathematician can tel l us which of a half-dozen contemporaryconcepts is really the crucial one, and which older conceptsare worth looking into again -- infinitesimals are one example(See Abraham Robinsons Non-Standard Analysis [C29], esp. ch.10) t Furthermore, the mathematician has a better idea of thelogical relationship between mathematical ideas, and can suggestconnections to the historian which might not be apparent fromthe historical record alone.We have seen that the mathematician and the historian bringdifferent skills and different perspectives to their common taskof explaining the mathematical present by means of the past.Therefore, as this conference by its existence declares, col-laboration between mathematicians and historians can be fruit-ful. The value of such a collaboration will be enhanced if eachcollaborator understands the unique contributions which can bemade by the other, The importance of the common task, I think,makes it well work the collective efforts.

    NOTESa. By historian and mathematician I do not mean a

    classification according to the fie ld of a persons Ph.D., butaccording to his general point of view. For our present pur-pose, Dirk Struik and Thomas Hawkins are historians; E. T. Belland the authors of the Encyclopsdie der mathematischen Wissen-schaften [13] are mathematicians. In general mathematiciansand historians have, while writing the history of mathematics,in fact taken the different approaches I describe, though thereis no a priori reason they would necessarily have to do so.

    b. In an approximation to the sum of an infin ite series,an 18th century mathematician might take n terms and ask howlarge the error -- the difference between the nth part ial sumand the sum of the inf ini te series -- might be. The series con-verges in Cauchys sense when the difference can be made lessthan any assignable error. Compare his Cours d'analyse [B6(2),vol. 31 with his article in- the Comptes Rendus 37 (1853) [B6(l), vol. 12, pp. 114-1241.

    C. See Van der Waerdens Science Awakening [9, p. 1101and compare Aristotles Prior Analytics i 23, 41a, 26-27.d. In my article [A5] in the Am. Math. Mon. 81, 354-365,I have treated this point at length, especially with respectto changing standards of proof in analysis.e. The divergence of the harmonic series was proved in

    the late 17th century by Johann and Jakob Bernoulli, and, forthat matter, was shown in the 14th century by Nicole Oresme.For Oresme, see [3, p. 2931; for the Bernoullis, [16, pp. 320-241f. See J. dAlembert, RCflexions sur les suites et sur les

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    7/9

    HM2 Mathematician, Historian, History of Science 445

    racines imaginaires, " Opuscules Math&natiques, 1768, vol. 5,pp. 171-83, esp. p. 173. See also Lagrange, Thikrie desFonctions Analytiques, 2nd ed., 1813 in [B24, vol. IX,pp. 83-841.

    g. For examples of this usage, see dAlembert, op. cit.; L.Euler, De seriebus divergentibus in [Bll (l), vol. 15, pp. 586,5881; and Lagrange, Sur la rCsolution des equations numeriques,1772 [B24, II, p. 5411.

    h. See also dAlembert, Dictionnaire raisonng des math&a-tiques, which collects the mathematical articles from the Ency-clop&die, articles Convergence and Seri& ou suite. CompareG. S. Kluegel, Mathematisches Woerterbuch, 1803, articleConvergirend, Annaehernd . fr

    i. See [B23]; compare [16, pp. 351-681; and C. Truesdell,The rational mechanics of flexib le or elastic bodies, 1638-1788 in [Bl l (2), 11, Sect. 2 (1960)].

    See [AS pp. 361-631 and Leqons sur le calcul des fonc-tioni*(2nd. ed. 1806) in [B24], vol. X, p. 871.k. See Lagrange, Trait6 de la rkolution des squations

    numkiques de tous les degrk, 2nd ed., 1808, in [B24, vol. VIII,pp. 46-7, 1631. Compare dAlembert, opuscules mathgmatiques,1768, vol. 5, pp. 171-83.1. J. T. Merz, History of European Thought in the Nine-teenth Century, vol. I (1904), Dover reprint, 1965.

    m. See [B29]; L. Osen, women in Mathematics, M.1 .T. Press,1974; J. L. Coolidge, Six female mathematicians, ScriptaMath. 7 (1951), pp. 20-31.n. A view championed by Lebesgue. See Mays biography in

    H. Lebesgue, Measure and the Integral [B27, p. 51.0. A good introduction to the literature up to 1936, with

    extensive and humane annotations, is Sartons Study of the His-tory of Mathematics [7]. For a detailed, up-to-date, andextremely valuable guide see Mays Bibliography [6].

    DISCUSSIONThe discussion began with three comments by Dieudonn6.

    First, he raised a technical point regarding convergence in theeighteenth century. He claimed that there are many examples tobe found among the works of eighteenth-century mathematicianswhere divergent series are given a sum. Secondly, Dieudonn6commented regarding the relationship between mathematics and fac-tors external to its development. He stated that, for example,the general history of the seventeenth century had no connectionwith Fermats theory of numbers. Further, in spite of the factthat Descartes, Leibniz, and Cantor were al l philosophers andmathematicians, mathematicians in general are not philosophers;they do mathematics. And thirdly, Dieudonng asserted that simplybecause the choice of notation may be motivated by circumstancesexternal to mathematical reasoning, does not, however, make this

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    8/9

    446 J .V. Grabiner HM2

    fact significant. He firmly held that such motivating circum-stances have no significance.In her response to Dieudonnes first point, Grabineremphazized her basic agreement with Dieudonne. Of course it istrue, she agreed, that mathematicians in the eighteenth centuryused divergent series; she had not intended to dispute that fact(See for instance De seriebus divergentibus in [Bll (1)vol. 15,PP. 586-588). She re-emphasized her claim that some (and notall) historical discussions of inf ini te series can be illuminatedby considering the two definitions of convergence used in theeighteenth century.Kahane emphasized the difference between definitions ofconvergence and proofs of convergence. He claimed that alreadyin 1807, Fourier had in mind a defin ition of convergence basedon partial sums, i.e., before Cauchy. [This definition is tobe found in Fouriers basic paper on heat conduction submittedto the Academy of Sciences of Paris in 1807. The manuscript isin the library of the Ecole des Ponts etchausseesand was laterpublished in 1822 as part of his Thgorie analytique de la chaleur-- Ed.]. It would have been possible, stated Kahane, for Fourierto give proof of convergence, but he did not do so. Actually,when Cauchy attempted to prove the convergence of Fourier series,he committed several notable errors, one of which was to mistakeabsolute convergence for condit ional convergence. Ironically,this proved to be helpfu l, by providing a motivation for Dir-ichlet to press on, concluded Kahane.

    In regard to Dieudonnes second comment, Edwards beganby pointing out that precisely in Fermats time, the redis-covery and translation of the texts of Diophantus occurred. Hebelieved that the events in the general cultural history of theera were extremely relevant to the development of the theoryof numbers by Fermat. Hawkins further noted that at least inthe past many mathematicians were interested in philosophy.

    Dou continued in this vein. To him, mathematics is be-coming separated from the world, and this is dangerous formathematics, Even with the Greeks, Dou claimed, mathematicswas a real part of life, something to live with. In recent times,there has been a move to separate mathematics and philosophy,and consequently there has arisen a severe need to bridge thegap between the two. Whereas the choice of notation may be ir-relevant to mathematics, its philosophy is not.Putnam concluded this line of thought by noting that thephilosophy of mathematics from Plato on has always been of greatimportance not only for mathematics, but for epistemology andmetaphysics as well. Mackey concluded the discussion with a com-ment on the pedagogical value of the history and philosophy ofmathematics to students of mathematics. In Mackeys opinion,both of these approaches to mathematics can be illuminating, butone must question the level of accuracy required. Neither the

  • 7/29/2019 (1975) the Mathematician, The Historian, And the History of Mathematics

    9/9

    HM2 Mathematician, Historian, History of Science 447

    historians nor the philosophers detailed accuracy is bene-ficial pedagogically. Mackey expressed interest in history,but felt that because of the pressures of his discipline, hecould not be interested in too detailed a history.