13
Metaethics and Moral Neutrality Author(s): Alan Gewirth Reviewed work(s): Source: Ethics, Vol. 78, No. 3 (Apr., 1968), pp. 214-225 Published by: The University of Chicago Press Stable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2379712 . Accessed: 30/10/2012 07:23 Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at . http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp . JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected]. . The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics. http://www.jstor.org

2379712

  • Upload
    vdolghi

  • View
    11

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

2379712

Citation preview

Metaethics and Moral NeutralityAuthor(s): Alan GewirthReviewed work(s):Source: Ethics, Vol. 78, No. 3 (Apr., 1968), pp. 214-225Published by: The University of Chicago PressStable URL: http://www.jstor.org/stable/2379712 .Accessed: 30/10/2012 07:23

Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at .http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp

.JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range ofcontent in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new formsof scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].

.

The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Ethics.

http://www.jstor.org

DISCUSSION

METAETHICS AND MORAL NEUTRALITY

ALAN GEWIRTH

I AS IS suggested by its affinity with

4.~ "metalanguage," metaethics is a certain kind of second-order

logical discourse about first-order moral discourse. Since much of contemporary American and British moral philosophy consists in metaethics, philosophers con- cerned with understanding their disci- pline have tried to clarify difficulties in the concept of metaethics itself (there- by doing, I suppose, "metametaethics"). For there are troublesome questions about what kind of "second-order logi- cal discourse" constitutes metaethics. For example, Bentham's and Mill's contention that the principle of utility is implicitly assumed in most men's sin- gular moral judgments' is a second-or- der logical assertion, since it purports to analyze the implications of first-or- der moral judgments; yet many expos- itors of metaethics would deny that the assertion is a metaethical one. They might give as one reason that the utili- tarians' assertion aims at providing sim- ply a substantive generalization of the content of moral judgments, whereas metaethical discourse concerns itself rather with categorial logical and meth- odological questions, that is, questions about the most general rubrics under which fall the meanings of first-order moral terms and the methods of justi- fying first-order moral judgments. This is why the dramatis personae of meta- ethics have been such very general and

basic concepts as "natural," "non-natu- ral," "factual," "intuitive," "emotive," "prescriptive," "descriptive," and the like. Yet there are also difficulties in re- garding only such concepts as metaethi- cal ones, as against more specific con- cepts like "utilitarian" or "impartial."

Another reason that might be given for denying that the utilitarians' asser- tion is a metaethical one is even more controversial. For it is usually held that metaethical discourse must be "morally neutral." While what is meant by "mor- al neutrality" is often left unanalyzed, in the case of the utilitarians one im- portant thing that might be meant is that their assertion would have to fit, and be intended to fit, all men's moral judgments, both those of which the phi- losophers themselves approved and those of which, in principle, they disap- proved. (The word "moral" is here used in the general "positive" or "descrip- tive" sense in which it is opposed to "non-moral" rather than to ''immoral.'') But it is implausible to hold that the principle of utility is implicitly assumed in the moral judgments of such anti- utilitarian particularists as individual- istic egoists, racists, nationalists, and the like. It follows, therefore, that Bentham and Mill were tacitly exclud- ing such men's judgments from the range of those "moral" judgments which they held to imply the utilitarian principle; they were referring only to those moral judgments which they con-

214

DISCUSSION 215

sidered to be morally right, at least "in principle." (There is, of course, an im- putation of circularity here.) Hence, the philosophers' second-order assertion presupposed, and was limited by, their own first-order normative moral posi- tion; hence, their assertion was not morally neutral; hence, it was not metaethical.

The strikingly novel character of this claim that metaethics must be morally neutral has not, I think, received suffi- cient recognition. For if we define "metaethics" as dealing with categorial logical questions of the meaning of first- order moral terms and the methods of justifying first-order moral judgments, then metaethics is as old as moral phi- losophy, even though the idea of "lev- els" of discourse, or of discourse about discourse, may not always have been explicitly emphasized. When, for exam- ple, Aristotle said that "anyone who is to listen intelligently to lectures about what is noble and just . . . must have been brought up in good habits,"' and that to ascertain in particular cases the mean between extremes in which moral virtue consists "is not easy to determine by reasoning ... such things depend on particular facts, and the decision rests with perception,"3 he was making two important metaethical assertions about the conditions for justifying or at least acquiescing in moral principles and judgments. He was saying that the ac- ceptance of the first principle of moral- ity requires not an essentially cognitive process but a certain kind of antecedent habituation and that to grasp the cor- rectness of a particular moral judgment about morally good action requires di- rect insight rather than inference or calculation. Yet, in these and similar cases, Aristotle's metaethical discussion

was not morally neutral, for the moral principles and judgments with whose logical character he was dealing were not those upheld by anyone at all (such as Callicles or Thrasymachus) but, rather, those to which he himself ad- hered and which he set forth in central portions of the Nicomachean Ethics. In this respect, then, Aristotle's metaethi- cal discussions presupposed, and were largely or even exclusively concerned with elucidating, his own normative moral position.

The same point holds not only for such philosophers as Hume and Kant but also for much of twentieth-century moral philosophy prior to the emotiv- ists. When the intuitionists discussed the intuitions by which they held that the meanings of basic moral concepts and the truth of basic moral proposi- tions are grasped, they took as their "data" what they regarded as "the mor- al convictions of thoughtful and well- educated people."4 They did not think that the moral doctrines which, in their view, were untrue or incorrect, such as those of Hitler or Mussolini, were them- selves grasped by intuition; on the con- trary, they consigned such erroneous doctrines to the sphere of inadequately developed moral beings who were lack- ing in "thoughtfulness" and hence "blind" to their real obligations. This normative moral restrictiveness in meta- ethics was also found in such a naturalist as Dewey.5 It was only with the emotiv- ists (and such of their near-precursors as Santayana) that the explicit claim was made that their metaethical doc- trines fit all moral positions and are not restricted to those upheld as morally right by the emotivists themselves.6 But, of course, the emotivists held that, as philosophers, they had no way of ascer- taining what is morally right.

216 ETHICS

It is important not to confuse the sense of "moral neutrality" indicated above with another sense. The sense I have used above may be called "refer- ential"; and I shall want to say that a metaethical assertion or doctrine may, in the referential sense, be either moral- ly neutral (or positive) or morally non- neutral (or normative). To say that a philosopher's metaethical assertion is morally neutral in the referential sense means that he does not intend to re- strict the assertion's reference or appli- cation to that normative moral position which he may himself regard as morally right; he intends it, rather, to fit all normative moral positions, including those which he regards as morally wrong and those on which he holds no moral view at all. A philosopher's meta- ethical assertion is not morally neutral in this sense, then, but is, rather, nor- matively moral, if he restricts the refer- ence or applicability of his assertion to what he regards as the morally right normative ethics, if he intends to eluci- date the meanings or methods of only those uses or contents of moral judg- ments which he regards as morally right. For, in such a case, his metaethi- cal assertion implies or presupposes a specific normative moral position of his own: in presenting his explicit meta- ethical doctrine he is also presenting, at least implicitly, his own normative mor- al position as that to which alone his metaethical doctrine refers or applies. He is saying something like the follow- ing: "The meaning or use of those mor- al judgments which take a morally cor- rect position is of kind X." The itali- cized phrase is, of course, not morally neutral but, rather, normatively moral, for here the metaethicist is not merely mentioning a normatively moral char-

acterization; he is using it himself. When such a normatively moral use occurs explicitly or implicitly in what the metaethicist's assertion refers to, his assertion is not morally neutral.

Much of the controversy over whether metaethics is morally neutral has involved this referential sense. It is this sense that figures in such familiar "metametaethical" questions as: (1) How universal is the scope of a given metaethical doctrine? Is it intended by its author to refer, and does it in fact refer, to all normative moral positions or only to the one which he himself regards as morally right? (2) Is the metaethicist presupposing or presenting (at least implicitly) his own normative moral position when he sets forth his metaethical doctrine? (3) Does the metaethical doctrine have normative ethical implications? If the doctrine is true, then does it logically imply the truth, soundness, or acceptability of some normative moral judgment? For example, if the metaethical doctrine says that P is the only logically correct way to justify a normative moral judgment, then does this imply a restriction of the range of justifiable (and hence of "cor- rect") moral judgments?

The referential sense of "moral neu- trality" must be distinguished from another sense, which I shall call "pred- icative." In the predicative sense, "neutrality" centers, not on the range of the normative moral judgments to which metaethical assertions are in- tended to refer, but rather on what the metaethical assertions predicate of these judgments. To say that a meta- ethical assertion is morally neutral in this predicative sense means only that the assertion does not itself directly make a normative moral judgment, in

DISCUSSION 217

that the predicate which the assertion assigns to its subject is not a norma- tively moral one. The predicate is of some other kind, logical, epistemologi- cal, psychological, ontological, or what- ever. When, for example, an intuition- ist says that all true moral propositions are and must be grasped by intuition, or when Dewey says that a "genuine practical judgment" requires the appli- cation of experimental methods, these assertions are morally neutral in the sense just indicated. For, while they may indeed be normative statements, they are only epistemologically or logically normative, not morally nor- mative, for the norms they directly up- hold or prescribe are epistemological or logical ones, not moral ones. Hence, while such metaethical statements are not morally neutral in the referential sense distinguished above, they are morally neutral in the predicative sense.7

To see somewhat more clearly the nature and implications of these two senses of moral neutrality, let us en- visage a metaethical statement as hav- ing two main parts. Its subject refers to the meaning or use of some moral term or judgment or the argument for some moral conclusion. Its predicate assigns to this meaning or use some metaethical property, such as "descrip- tive," "prescriptive," "empirical," or perhaps more particular terms specif- ically relevant to ethics. Now the dis- tinction between a morally neutral and a morally non-neutral metaethical state- ment may be put in terms of either its subject or its predicate. In terms of its subject, the metaethical statement is morally neutral if its subject refers to the meaning or use of any moral term or judgment or the argument for

any moral conclusion, without restric- tion to those moral judgments or uses which the metaethicist himself regards as morally right. If, on the other hand, the metaethicist does restrict in this way the reference of the subject of his metaethical statement, then his state- ment is not morally neutral. (The sense of "morally neutral" here is, of course, the referential one.) For when the metaethicist's statement is re- stricted in its reference to those moral judgments which he regards as morally right, then it implies his own normative moral position, as we saw above.

Let us now look at the distinction between a morally neutral and a mor- ally non-neutral metaethical statement in terms of its predicate. Here, to begin with, we must distinguish between a descriptive and a normative predicate. A descriptive predicate will be of the form: "The use of moral terms is of kind X," while a normative predicate will be of the form: "The use of moral terms ought to be of kind X."28 Now each of these forms of statement may be either morally neutral or morally non-neutral in the referential sense, depending on the intended reference of the phrase "use of moral terms." In addition, the descriptive form of state- ment is morally neutral in the predica- tive sense. But whether the normative form of statement is morally neutral in the predicative sense depends on whether the "ought" in the predicate is intended by the metaethicist to be a moral or a non-moral "ought." He may intend it only as a logical or an epis- temological "ought." But he may also intend it as a moral "ought," in which case he will mean that, if a moral judg- ment is to be used in a way that fulfils the requirements of what he considers

218 ETHICS

to be morally right or good, then it mor- ally ought to have certain features, such as sincerity or impartiality or concern for the interests of everyone alike. (Kant is one of many exemplars of such a morally normative metaethicist.) It will be noted that features of the kind just mentioned are more specific than "typical" metaethical terms, such as "descriptive" and "prescriptive." Yet there seems to be no reason why the more specific terms cannot be used in the analysis of the meaning or use of first-order moral judgments.

From the above distinctions, several conclusions follow. For one thing, the referential and the predicative senses of moral neutrality are mutually inde- pendent. A metaethical assertion may refer only to those moral judgments or arguments that the metaethicist regards as morally right, while the predicate which he assigns in his assertion may be logical or epistemological, rather than moral. Conversely, the meta- ethical assertion's predicate may be a moral one, while the assertion refers to all moral judgments, not only to those which the metaethicist himself regards as morally right. In the former case, the metaethical assertion implicitly makes a normative moral judgment, while in the latter case it explicitly makes such a judgment. In addition, of course, the metaethical assertion may be morally neutral, both referentially and predicatively.

It also follows from the above dis- tinctions that both morally neutral and normatively moral metaethics are logi- cally possible. There is nothing in the concept of metaethics, defined in the "second-order logical" terms used above, that rules out either moral neu- trality or moral non-neutrality in either

the referential or the predicative senses. It might be thought that the word "logical" in the definition means that the predicates of metaethical state- ments can be only logical, not moral, ones, so that metaethical statements cannot be morally non-neutral in the predicative sense. If, however, meta- ethical logical discourse may include the analysis of the implications of par- ticular moral judgments which the meta- ethicist accepts as morally right (as in my example of the utilitarians above), then such logical analysis may come up with conclusions which make norma- tively moral assertions. For the con- clusions simply generalize the norma- tive moral predicates already accepted by the metaethicist in the singular moral judgments from which he begins. The utilitarian metaethicist, for ex- ample, will conclude not only that all "non-vitiated" moral judgments do in fact rest on the principle of utility but also that they morally ought to rest thereon; for his acceptance of the prin- ciple is not divorced from his accept- ance of the normative moral judgments which he holds to imply the principle.

II

About a decade ago, I wrote an es- say devoted to such questions about metaethics, which was published in Mind (and to which I shall here refer as "G").9 This essay has recently been criticized by L. W. Sumner in a paper in Ethics (to which I shall here refer as "S").10 His chief criticism is that my argument in G "contains a fallacy, that there is something seriously amiss with [my] method" (S, p. 99; italics here and in all other quotations are in the originals). The alleged fallacy seems to be a modal one: according to

DISCUSSION 219

Sumner I argued from merely factual- historical premises to a necessary con- ceptual conclusion, or, more specifical- ly, from the fact that some metaethi- cists have failed in their attempts at morally neutral metaethics to the con- clusion that morally neutral meta- ethics is logically impossible. Thus, Sumner says that, even if I had suc- ceeded "in showing that certain theo- ries thought to be morally neutral by their authors are not so," this would be only "a quasi-historical claim about the status of certain theories which had been thought to be metaethical in character. . . . And, if we take moral neutrality to be an essential defining feature of metaethics, then he has shown that some theories ordinarily thought to be metaethical are in reality not metaethical at all. To say all this is only to criticize the practice of some supposed metaethicists; it is not to say anything about the possibility of meta- ethics at all. One does not show that something cannot be done by showing that someone or some group has tried it and failed" (S, p. 99). Hence, Sum- ner concludes, "no amount of pointing out inconsistencies in the practice of some of those commonly taken to be metaethicists can show that metaethics is impossible or that there are concep- tual difficulties in the normative-meta- ethical distinction" (S, p. 100).

I wish to make the following com- ments on this criticism and on some related ones:

1. In my aforementioned essay, I nowhere tried to show, or said I would try to show, that metaethics in general, as a morally neutral doctrine, "cannot be done" or "is impossible." What I tried to show is that a certain kind of metaethics is impossible, namely, that

which, while claiming to be morally neutral in the referential sense, still tries to differentiate what constitutes morally right or good judgments or actions from those which are not mor- ally right or good. The impossibility here derives from the inconsistency of the following pair of claims: (a) that one's metaethical conclusion refers without differentiation to all moral judgments; (b) that this same meta- ethical conclusion draws distinctions between what is morally right and morally wrong and refers directly only to what is morally right. But I certainly did not say that all metaethics neces- sarily incurs this inconsistency. A meta- ethics which tries to make such norma- tively moral differentiations I called a "normative" one, and I distinguished it from a "positivistic" metaethics which tries to make its analyses fit equally, without differentiation, all kinds of normative ethics, both those approved and those not approved by the metaethicist. Of this positivistic metaethics, I wrote: "no normative ethical judgment of his [the metaethi- cist's] own is presupposed by his engag- ing in such analysis, for his use of 'ethics' does not uniquely reflect his own evaluations" (G, p. 192). I re- peated this point in my summary of conclusions at the end of the essay: "When the metaethicist analyzes what for him is positive ethics as well as normative ethics [i.e., the ethics of which he does not himself approve as well as that of which he does approve], with the aim of ascertaining what meanings are common to these, then no specific normative ethical judgment of his own is presupposed or implied thereby; from his standpoint his meta- ethics is compatible with different or

220 ETHICS

opposed normative ethics" (G, p. 205; see also p. 193).

In view of this repeated insistence by me that there can be a positivistic, mor- ally neutral metaethics, I am mystified by Sumner's repeated assertions that in my essay I "want to show that no metaethical theory is or can be morally neutral"; "Gewirth, then, is committed to arguing that no metaethical theory can be morally neutral" (S, pp. 96, 97). The only passage in my essay that might conceivably support this inter- pretation of my intention is one that occurs on the next to last page (and which Sumner does not quote): "Far from being independent of one another, metaethics is included in normative ethics, and differences in metaethics en- tail differences in normative ethics" (G, p. 204). But, as a glance at the next (last) page of my essay would have shown, the position represented by this passage is, but one of four different logical relations that I tried to estab- lish as holding between metaethics and normative ethics: "From the standpoint of a normative ethics which places the criterion of ethical value in specific psychological conditions, the meta- ethical analysis of the meanings and methods of ethical judgments in terms of psychological conditions may pre- sent an alternative criterion of ethical value, so that the metaethical analysis does make a normative ethical differ- ence. In this situation, from the stand- point of such a normative ethics there is a mutual implicative relation between it and metaethics" (G, p. 205). I at once went on, however, to show that this is not the only relation between normative ethics and metaethics: "This logical relation between normative ethics and metaethics may not, how- ever, obtain either when the normative

ethics in question places the criterion of value in something other than spe- cific psychological conditions or when the metaethics deals with questions of meaning in a very general way" (G, p. 205).

The difference between these two kinds of logical relations between nor- mative ethics and metaethics may be illustrated as follows. Suppose the nor- mative ethicist says that, for a moral judgment to be morally good, certain psychological conditions X (e.g., a "good will") must motivate or accom- pany the judgment; and suppose a metaethicist says that all moral judg- ments are motivated or accompanied by certain quite different psychological conditions Y which are such that they exclude a "good will." In such a case, the metaethicist is denying something that the normative ethicist is affirming, for while the latter is saying that "all morally good moral judgments are characterized by X," the metaethicist is saying that "no moral judgments are characterized by X." Hence, the meta- ethical position makes a normative ethical difference, for it declares that the instantiation of a certain normative ethical criterion is impossible.

Suppose, on the other hand, that the metaethicist does not in this way as- sert the contrary of the normative ethical doctrine, either because the metaethicist talks about the psycho- logical conditions of moral judgments in a much more general way (which would not involve denying any specific normative ethical doctrine about the psychological conditions of morally good judgments) or because the norma- tive ethical doctrine's criterion of mor- al value refers to something other than psychological conditions (e.g., to con- sequences). In such a case, the meta-

DISCUSSION 221

ethical position does not make any nor- mative ethical difference.

Besides these two alternatives, the conclusions I presented at the end of my essay also listed two other alterna- tive possibilities in the relation between metaethics and normative ethics; I have already mentioned these above as the distinction between "positivistic" and "normative" metaethics, the for- mer being morally neutral in the refer- ential sense, and the latter not. It ap- pears, then, that as against the various qualifications I drew in my quadruple list of conclusions, Sumner has attrib- uted to me a single, unqualified con- clusion. In ignoring the complexities of my actual position, he also misdirects his criticisms. If someone claims to have shown that some X is Y and some X is not Y. then to try to refute him on the ground that he has not simply shown that no X at all can be Y, when he never undertook to show the latter, is to commit the fallacy of ignoratio elenchi.

2. Sumner's criticism also raises the issue of the proper method of examin- ing the potentialities of philosophic theses in general and of metaethical theories in particular. In trying to as- certain whether metaethics is or can be morally neutral, should one proceed "conceptually," by examining the "con- cept" or "notion" of metaethics, or "factually" (or "historically"), by examining the actual statements of metaethicists? It might be thought that Sumner is clearly right in holding that, if one is going to try to prove that meta- ethics as a morally neutral study is logi- cally impossible, then only the concep- tual approach is appropriate. For a con- clusion having such a modal predicate as "impossible" can be derived only from premises which state that something is necessary or impossible; but factual

premises, unlike conceptual ones, tell us only what is actual or possible, not what is necessary or impossible.

My answer on this point is that in the part of my argument where I was trying to establish that what I called norma- tive metaethics necessarily makes a normative ethical commitment (so that it is impossible that it be morally neu- tral in the referential sense), there were required, and I used, both the conceptual and the historical ap- proaches as well as a third, mixed ap- proach. For I had to show (a) that on a certain definition or conception of metaethics it necessarily follows that metaethics is not morally neutral and (b) that the actual practice of many analytic philosophers of ethics con- forms to this definition. I also had to show (c) that this conformity is not merely accidental but results rather from certain basic "demands of their subject-matter."

a) Having distinguished between the "normative" and the "positive" mean- ings or uses of the word "ethics" (as referring to those rules of conduct of which the user, respectively, approves and does not approve), I wrote that "from these distinctions, the following emerges as an analytic consequence: When a metaethicist analyses ethics in a way which aims to fit indifferently what are for him both the positive and the normative senses of 'ethics,' then no normative ethical judgment of his own is presupposed by his engaging in such analysis, for his use of 'ethics' does not uniquely reflect his own evaluations. When, on the other hand, a metaethicist analyses ethics in what is for him the normative sense of 'ethics,' then his engaging in such analysis does pre- suppose a normative ethical judgment of his own, for his use of 'ethics' does

222 ETHICS

reflect his own evaluations" (G, p. 192). Here, then, I proceeded in terms of two different concepts or definitions of metaethics, one positivistic and the other normative, and from these I drew certain conclusions about moral neu- trality which follow necessarily. But, strangely enough, although Sumner briefly summarizes my above distinc- tions and even the conclusions I drew from them (S. p. 97), he nowhere shows any awareness that this part of my dis- cussion presents precisely that kind of conceptual analysis which he says is required but absent from my essay.

b) Having made these conceptual points, however, I then went on to emphasize that this "conceptual" ap- proach must be supplemented by a "factual-historical" one: "We must now show that these consequences actually apply to the practice of current meta- ethicists. For it is not enough to estab- lish these assertions as analytic, since as such they might reflect only our own idiosyncratic definitions" (G, p. 192). If one wants to be able to claim that one's conceptual conclusion refers to the actual doctrines or practice of metaethi- cists, then to the major "conceptual" premise ("All cases of normative meta- ethics necessarily presuppose the meta- ethicist's own specific normative moral position") there must be joined a minor "historical" premise ("Such and such admitted instances of contemporary metaethics are cases of normative metaethics"). Without the latter, how can one be sure that there are any actual instantiations of that morally normative metaethics which is a possi- ble alternative to positivistic meta- ethics? In other words, just as the claim that all metaethics is morally neutral has been interpreted both as a con- ceptual and as a historical statement,

so too the refutation of the claim must be historical as well as conceptual.

c) It was also important to show that this instantiation of the conceptual con- sequence by the actual practice of con- temporary metaethicists was not ac- cidental but reflected an awareness on the part of many of them that for their task to be fulfilled completely they would have to deal with what for them was ''normative ethics" as well as "positive ethics": "What is important is not merely the particular terms we have used [conceptual approach] nor even that they fit the empirical facts, i.e. the actual practice of metaethicists [historical approach], but also that the latter seem to be driven, as it were, to a concern with normative ethics as against positive ethics by the demands of their subject-matter. Their task is incomplete so long as they deal with the moral language of cannibals and missionaries, Capones and Schweitzers, as if they were morally on a par" (G, p. 192). In other words, that many metaethicists go in for normative meta- ethics, and hence make normative moral differentiations between the morally right and the morally wrong, is just as understandable and well-nigh inevi- table as that philosophers of science want to make their doctrines of the nature of scientific method fit the pro- cedures of astronomers and physiolo- gists rather than those of astrologists and phrenologists." Yet this still leaves open the possibility, which I empha- sized, that some metaethicists might not want to take this step into norma- tive metaethics.

Not only did I use both the concep- tual and the historical approaches in my essay, but Sumner does so also in his, although with seeming unawareness of his use of the latter. That he uses

DISCUSSION 223

the conceptual approach is obvious, and emphasized by him. One of his chief uses of the historical approach comes after he has distinguished two defini- tions of metaethics, on one of which it is morally neutral and on the other not. Sumner recognizes that a cogent choice between these, if it is to be relevant to what metaethicists do, requires a con- sideration of their actual practice: "the important question still remains: are any of the positions of those commonly called metaethicists morally neutral?" (S, p. 104). I conclude, then, that Sum- ner was somewhat overhasty both in his analysis of my procedure and in his way of contrasting it with his own. He does not, however, use what I have called the "mixed" approach, so that his own positive argument (or, rather, suggestion) is left quite inconclusive.

3. Sumner seems to think that meta- ethics must either be or not be morally neutral, that only one of his two "defi- nitions" of metaethics is acceptable (S, p. 104). The trouble with this attempt to arrive at one simple conclusion is that it fails to take account of the complexi- ties of the actual situation, that is, the actual practice of those whom he as well as I would call metaethicists. If "meta- ethics" is defined in the "second-order logical" terms given above (which are common to most of the explicit defini- tions given by metaethicists), then it emerges that many metaethical doc- trines are not morally neutral, espe- cially in the referential sense. Once this is granted, the only necessary incoher- ence would come from the claim that these doctrines were morally neutral. If this claim is dropped as an essential part of "metaethics," the way is clear to see not only the continuity of past and present metaethics but also the

relations between positive and norma- tive metaethics.

What is especially important in this connection is that the analytical devices of metaethics are indispensable tools for the normative ethicist who wishes to clarify the meanings and methods that enter into his own normative moral position. Such a use of metaethics by a normative ethicist would emphatically not be morally neutral in the referen- tial sense distinguished above; but it would be a great loss if this non-neu- trality were to be considered a bar to his doing metaethics at all. If all meta- ethics had to be morally neutral by definition, then the normative ethicist's inquiry into the meanings and logic of his own normative moral doctrines could not be called "metaethical." This, however, would obscure the important similarity and continuity between his analytical, logical inquiries and those engaged in by positivistic metaethicists. I conclude, then, that the basic assump- tion of Sumner's project is unsound philosophically as well as historically.

4. I now wish to deal with a further point of Sumner's discussion. Referring to my citations from Hare, Falk, Toul- min, Duncan-Jones, and Hampshire, where I argued that their statements showed that they were doing normative, not positive, metaethics, Sumner writes: "The particular point that Gewirth challenges in each of these cases is the claim that all moral judgments, as such, are in some sense universalizable" (S, p. 98). He then comments that "it is at least not obvious whether or not uni- versalizability is part of the meaning of the term 'moral' in its positive sense. Gewirth has given no argument to show that it is not" (S. p. 99). For if uni- versalizability is a universal feature of all moral judgments (in the positive

224 ETHICS

sense of "moral"), then the metaethical assertion that moral judgments must be universalizable is itself morally neutral in the referential sense, and metaethi- cists who appeal to universalizability to elucidate what is "moral" are not mak- ing a normative moral commitment of their own.

It must be noted, however, that the phrase I used in reporting the doctrines about morality presented by the meta- ethicists in question was that, according to them, moral judgments must be "im- partial or universalizable" (G, p. 195; quoted in S, p. 98). The relation be- tween universalizability and such traits as impartiality, mutuality, universal- ism, and egoism is still a subject of much dispute. But the passages I quoted seemed clearly to interpret uni- versalizability as a normative moral trait. Consider, for example, this pas- sage from Duncan-Jones: "a man can- not be making a moral judgment un- less his attitude is free from partiality for particular places, ages, and social groups, and from self-partiality" (But- ler's Moral Philosophy, p. 172, quoted in G, p. 196). By this requirement for a judgment's being a "moral" one, not only would the individualistic egoist's judgments be debarred from being called "moral," but so too would be those of nationalists, racists, tribalists, upholders of proletarianism, and nearly all other particularistic codes. Now philosophers may propose all sorts of restrictions on the meanings of terms.

But when the restrictions they propose for "moral" are so extensive that they confine the term's applications to a uni- versalist or egalitarian code, then it seems difficult to interpret these restric- tions as being neutral toward the vari- ous conflicting codes usually called "moral."

Of course, the metaethicist may rep- resent himself as a "revisionist," as not reporting or describing how "moral" is actually used but, rather, as pre- scribing how it ought to be used. In this case, however, the metaethicist would no longer be a "positivist" in the sense indicated above, and there would not be the logical barrier urged by those who hold that a metaethical assertion can never be morally normative. For, suppose that the metaethicist holds that his proposed revision is only logically normative, not morally. This would mean that his metaethical assertion is morally neutral in the predicative sense indicated above. But would it also be morally neutral in the referential sense? It might be difficult to give a decisive answer to this question. Nevertheless, if it turned out that the reference of the metaethicist's revised sense of "moral" coincided with the range of what he, or the members of his cultural group, re- garded as morally right or good, then there would be strong ground for sus- pecting that his metaethical assertion was not morally neutral in the referen- tial sense.

UNIVERSITY OF CHICAGO

NOTES

1. J. Bentham, Principles of Morals and Legisla- tion, chap. i, sec. xii; J. S. Mill, Utilitarianism, chap. i, esp. par. 4.

2. Nicomachean Ethics i. 4. 1059b4; trans. W. David Ross (New York: Oxford University Press, 1954).

3. Ibid. ii, 9. 1 09b21,

4. See H. A. Prichard, "Does Moral Philosophy Rest on a Mistake?" in W. Sellars and J. Hospers (eds.), Readings in Ethical Theory (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1952), p. 156 n.; W. D. Ross, "The Meaning of 'Right' " and "What Makes Right Acts Right?" in Sellars and Hospers, ibid., pp. 171, 177 n., 184, 192.

DISCUSSION 225

5. See J. Dewey, "The Construction of Good," in Sellars and Hospers, ibid., pp. 275 ff.

6. For the emotivists' claims that their metaethi- cal doctrines are morally neutral, see A. J. Ayer, Language, Truth and Logic (2d ed.; London: V. Gollancz, 1948), p. 103; C. L. Stevenson, Ethics and Language (New Haven, Conn.: Yale Univer- sity Press, 1944), pp. 1, 110; R. Robinson, "The Emotive Theory of Ethics," Aristotelian Society Supplementary Volume, XXII (1948), 93.

7. It seems to be this predicative sense of moral neutrality that W. K. Frankena has in mind when he writes that "an inquiry into the meaning and logic of moral discourse may be normative without being moral" (see his "On Saying the Ethical Thing," Proceedings and Addresses of the American Philosophical Association, XXXIX [1965-66], 23).

8. Cf. ibid., pp. 22 ff.

9. A. Gewirth, "Meta-ethics and Normative Eth- ics," Mind, LXIX (1960), 187-205.

10. L. W. Sumner, "Normative Ethics and Meta- ethics," Ethics, LXXVII (1967), 95-106.

11. I have elsewhere discussed in detail this par- allel between normative metaethics and philosophy of science, as well as the severe limitations of the analogy (which Sumner repeats [S, p. 101]) where- by it is said that as (positivistic) metaethics is to normative ethics, so is philosophy of science to science (see A. Gewirth, "Positive 'Ethics' and Normative 'Science,"' Philosophical Review, LXIX [1960], 311-30).

12. I have discussed these questions in "The Gen- eralization Principle," Philosophical Review, LXXIII (1964), 229-42, and in "Categorial Con- sistency in Ethics," Philosophical Quarterly, XVII (1967), 289-99.