48

Binder2

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

 

Citation preview

Page 1: Binder2
Page 2: Binder2
Page 3: Binder2
Page 4: Binder2
Page 5: Binder2
Page 6: Binder2
Page 7: Binder2
Page 8: Binder2
Page 9: Binder2
Page 10: Binder2
Page 11: Binder2
Page 12: Binder2
Page 13: Binder2
Page 14: Binder2
Page 15: Binder2
Page 16: Binder2
Page 17: Binder2
Page 18: Binder2
Page 19: Binder2
Page 20: Binder2
Page 21: Binder2
Page 22: Binder2
Page 23: Binder2
Page 24: Binder2
Page 25: Binder2
Page 26: Binder2
Page 27: Binder2
Page 28: Binder2
Page 29: Binder2
Page 30: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 1

More and More About Less and Less:

Notes Toward a History of Nonfigurative Architecture

“It’s just the simple thing that’s hard, so hard to do.”

– Bertold Brecht

Pier Vittorio Aureli

In recent years, structural complexity, formal redundancy, and image seem to have

become the new Vitruvian triad embraced by the majority of contemporary architects.

The result of this has been a figural excess in architecture, of which the city as res

publica – the public and thus common thing par excellence – is the victim. Given this

figural excess, it is possible – even necessary – to propose a nonfigurative architectural

language; that is, an architecture essentially reduced to a public grammar for inhabitable

space. This proposal is not advocated in the ideological terms of another style for

architecture. Quite the contrary. The idea of the nonfigurative proposed here is defined

through the reconsideration of a possible archaeology of modern architecture. With a

series of archetypal examples from the past, one can demonstrate how the possibility of a

nonfigurative architecture is not new but is already latent within a reading of architectural

history – a reading in which the unfolding of such a history is understood not as the

change of styles or accumulation of more and more complexities and contradictions, but

rather as a series of constructive denials. These denials can be interpreted within the

evolution of modernity in terms of the rise of the “generic” condition of urban space. The

term generic defines the common character associated with a number of persons or

Page 31: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 2

things. Since modernity has always stressed, as the core of its project, the possibility of

an uprooted and reified subjectivity, it has held up the generic attributes of life as the

common political character of society.1 It is possible to argue that, by denying formal

redundancy, the latent project of nonfigurative architecture was parallel to the reduction

of inhabitable space to the common forms of the generic city. As much the idea of a

nonfigurative architecture implies the process of reification2 that has invested the city

since the beginning of modernity, for this precise reason nonfigurative architecture may

also point toward an understanding of what public architecture is within modern

civilization.3

The modern definition of nonfigurative architecture is derived from a drawing made by

Archizoom in 1968 as a scheme for a homogenous habitat condition, which, a few years

1 This is what is defined today as “Biopolitics,” a constitution of political subjectivity where what is at stake is the management of life and its forms of reproduction. In this sense it is possible to say that fundamental urban categories that shape the political economy of the contemporary city such as labour force reproduction and sustainability can be seen as the ultimate source of the “generic” attributes of the urban condition. 2 It is important to remember that beyond its traditional meaning of expropriation of subjectivity, the term reification come from the Latin word res, which means thing in the sense of something that is graspable as a public thing (res-pubblica). As such the word reification means the necessary dynamic process that constitute a public sphere, that is the movement from the interiority of being, to the externality relationships, the thingness of the world. A fundamental re-evaluation of reification as territory for a new political form of public sphere, has been advanced by the Philosopher Paolo Virno. See: Paolo Virno, Quando Il verbo si fa carne. Linguaggio e natura umana (Turin: Bollati Boringhieri), 111-142. 3 This text is an attempt to rethink the idea of the “generic” in architecture but in different terms than those in which this category has been theorized in recent years, especially after Rem Koolhaas’s canonical text “Generic City.” Seen within the perspective of the historical unfolding of modernity and capitalism, the “Generic City” that is the condition of the permanent cultural and social uprooting that affects urban space is not the collateral effect of modernity, but modernity’s fundamental political project. This political project started with the secularization of politics, the beginning of modern forms of sovereignty in the 17TH century, and the rise of liberalism in economics and politics. In this sense, the generic certainly embodies what Bertold Brecht would have defined as the “Bad New.” Yet it is the task of a critical theory to discern within the characters of the generic the possibilities of political and cultural emancipation without a return to something like “authenticity,” and “originality,” which in today’s extremely reified means of production can only exist as caricatures of a lost aura. As such, the generic must be addressed without useless enthusiasm or hopeless despair, but with the awareness that any conception of the public sphere that wants to address what is truly common today has to be formulated from within the reified nature of the modern and contemporary (generic) city.

Page 32: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 3

later, would become the plan of their famous theoretical project “No-Stop City.”4

Archizoom subtitled this scheme “Proposal for a Non-Figurative Architectural

Language.” The drawing was executed with a typewriter and depicts an abstract field of

dots and X’s. The geometry that orders the disposition of the dots and X’s is

provocatively simple: the orthogonal spacing of the typewriter itself. The dots and X’s

represent the architecture of a city. Or better yet, they represent the basic condition

required for a city to exist: the minimum infrastructure for living, according to which the

city reproduces itself. Read in this way, X’s are columns occurring every 50 meters. The

remaining infrastructure fits within the grid of plug-ins occurring every five meters.

According to this logic, Archizoom defined other elements in a nonfigurative

architectural language: a wall occurs every 10 meters, a bed every 20 meters, an elevator

every 25 meters, etc. The overall layout illustrated an urban field governed by the

minimum welfare necessary to guarantee the reproduction of those living and working in

it. The drawing stripped the city of any architectural attribute, such as figures, and

mercilessly rendered it in all its infrastructural and biopolitical objectivity. Archizoom

sarcastically defined this type of city as “a bathroom every 50 square meters.”

The drawing itself, and the way it was made, presents an interesting and provocative

paradox. On the one hand, it declares the end of architecture and the futility of making

formal and spatial figures on an infrastructural order that is irreducible to any figure. On

the other, by conveying this message through the quintessentially architectural

organization of the grid, Archizoom exaggerates ad absurdum the strict orthogonal logic

4 For a complete illustration of Archizoom No-Stop City see: Andrea Branzi, No-Stop City: Archizoom Associati (Orleans: Editions HXY, 2006). For an in-depth critical study of the project see: Roberto Gargiani, Archizoom. Dall’onda Pop alla Superficie Neutra (Milan: Electa, 2007).

Page 33: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 4

underlying classical archetypes of modern architecture from Filippo Brunelleschi’s Santo

Spirito to Mies van der Rohe’s Barcelona Pavilion. In these latter examples,

orthogonality, defined by the logic of the grid, is the treatment of space in terms of the

perception of physical space. This orthogonality defines a sphere in which the experience

of the subject is subsumed and reproduced by means of a measurable, modular, and thus

objective order of things. The extreme evolution seen in Archizoom’s project can be

interpreted as an act of transferring the process of subsumption from the realm of

physical space perception to the realm of bio-political management in which the grid is

not simply rows of columns that define the concept of physical space but the rational and

isotropic distribution of infrastructure that defines all reproduction.

This drawing therefore forces us to reconsider the idea of the generic and its rational

attributes as something different from the stylish minimalist architecture with which it

has often been associated. The notes that follow address the possibility of a nonfigurative

architecture that extends far beyond the Archizoom project and set it within the evolution

of publicness, which can be understood as the progressive reificiation of human

subjectivity in the historical development of modernity.

Grid

The grid and its derivative formal orders are the most important nonfigurative attributes

of the city. Throughout history, the grid has proved to be a powerful form of spatial

indexing. It evolved from a simple geometrical organization of the aesthetic field, to the

Page 34: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 5

complex urban layout of ancient and modern cities, to geographical surveys, to financial

ledgers, to visual displays, to housing prefabrication, to computational systems, etc.5

In her canonical essay on the grid, the art historian Rosalind Krauss emphasizes that the

nonfigurative form became a central theme of modern art precisely because its

conventional geometric order was best suited for manifesting the nonrepresentational and

antinarrative ethos of modernity.6 For Krauss, the grid constitutes a realm that can be

understood only in terms of aesthetic decisions because its coordinates define a realm that

is antithetical to the way things appear in “real” space. She claims, for example, that the

grid used by Renaissance painters as a mathematical frame for constructing perspectival

views cannot be considered a modern grid because perspective was intended to reproduce

the real. Yet it is possible to counter that the science of perspective was not only intended

to reproduce the real as it appeared in primary perception, but also to abstract primary

perception in the measurable space of mathematical management. In turn, such

mathematical management generated a new type of real space

Historically, the grid is assumed to represent the least “complex” formal order.

The grid has no directionality, no expressivity, and supposedly no symbolic content: it is

what it does, and in that sense, it claims for itself a formal logic of neutrality. Because of

its approximation of an isotropic distributive order, the grid has often been used to

convey the ultimate essence of neutrality, yet this neutrality – as its historical

development in the arts, in architecture, and in urbanism makes clear – is far from being

5 For a comprehensive history of the grid see: Hanna B. Higgins, The Grid Book (Cambridge: MIT Press, 2009). 6 Rosalind Krauss, “Grids” first published in October n. 16 (1979); reprinted in The Originality of the Avant-garde and Other Modernists Myths (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1985), 9–22.

Page 35: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 6

politically neutral. The disarming simplicity of the grid belies the ineffable multiplicity it

attempts to frame and tame. An example of this is the Spanish engineer Ildefonso Cerdà’s

plan for the reform and extension of Barcelona, and his subsequent treatise, The General

Theory of Urbanization (1867). Cerdà proposes the organizational principle of the grid

not only as a morphological ordering but also as a means of rationally managing the even

distribution of social welfare and thus the reproduction (and control) of labor.7

The nature of the grid and the forms that derive from its use as a structuring principle

signal the essential consideration at the core of the project of modernity. Modernity’s

promise of a “public truth” based on universal values such as individual freedom and

equality could only be conceived with the reification of the subject and its space of

inhabitation. At first this reification was the result of the formalization of universal

reason, which made it possible to understand the process of human cognition as a

concrete thing. But as Cornelius Castoriadis has pointed out, the same formalization of

reason was redefined in terms of the idea of administrative logic, or the presumed

rationality of capitalism itself.8 The development of the Western city since the 15TH

century was a fundamental factor in this process of subjectification. Not only physical

objects, but also treatises, drawings, representations, maps, and texts were deployed to

produce a new, universal, rational human subject in terms of urban space and form.

7 Cerdà’s project manifests the biopolitical terms of the urban project in which the political is radically absorbed by the governance of space in terms of its management. See: Pier Vittorio Aureli, “Toward the Archipelago: Defining the Formal and the Political in Architecture,” Log 11 (2008). See also: Ildefonso Cerdà, The Five Bases of the General Theory of Urbanization, ed. Arturo Soria y Puig, trans. Bernard Miller and Mary Fons i Fleming (Madrid: Electa Espana, 1999), 81. This book is a partial translation of Ildefonso Cerdà, Teoría General de la Urbanización (Barcelona: 1867). 8 Cornelius Castoriadis, The World in Fragments (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1997). The Frankfurt School made a similar conclusion about the fate of rationality. See: Theodor W. Adorno, with Max Horkheimer, Dialectic of Enlightenment, trans. Edmund Jephcott (Stanford: Stanford University Press, 2002).

Page 36: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 7

Because this process was seen as irreducible to infallible and stable configurations, the

use of simple forms such as those derived from the paratactic logic of the grid gained

relevance. In spite of architecture’s periodic immersion in the culture of complexity

(from the complex geometries of the Baroque, to the decorative patterns of Art Nouveau,

to the current fetishism for parametric formalism and its resulting iconic buildings), at

crucial moments the grid always emerges as the substratum that prevents a freefall into

chaos. For this reason, in architecture the grid is not merely what something looks like.

The grid should be understood as an idea of formal reduction that can structure or simply

help to map the complexity of the modern city.

A history of the development of this concept can be made by looking at five radical

“architectural” interpretations of nonfigurative architecture, each of which introduces an

architectural proposition that has made neutrality and the orthogonal not a style but a

strategy for coming to terms with the development of the modern city.

Orders

Following examples of the stacked orders in ancient Roman architecture such as the

Coliseum, Leon Battista Alberti was the first architect in modern times to claim that the

column must only support the architrave and that the arch is an opening in a wall. For

Alberti, the planar condition of the wall is the absolute element of architecture, and the

system of orders developed by the column is ornament.9 In this way, the even geometry

of a grid made of vertically stacked orders is independent from the structure of the

9 Leon Battista Alberti, De re Aedificatoria, ed. Giovanni Orlandi and Paolo Portoghesi (Milan: Edizioni del Polifilo, 1966), 520–521.

Page 37: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 8

building itself. This is visible in Alberti’s most famous building, the Palazzo Rucellai

(1446–51), which he conceived in dialogue with Michelozzo’s design for the Palazzo

Medici in Via Larga (1445–60).10 At that time, the Medicis were consolidating their

power over Florence, destabilizing the republican politics of the city and extending their

control over civic institutions. The building of a new palazzo in the city center

materialized this political development. The heavy stone masonry of the Palazzo Medici

facade consciously mirrored that of the medieval Palazzo Vecchio, the seat of Florentine

communal power. Moreover, the imposing geometry of the square palazzo block with its

internal courtyard required the demolition of an entire neighborhood, which emphasized

the confrontational stance of the new building toward the intricate structure of the city.

Opposing such a naked display of power politics, Alberti’s Palazzo Rucellai offered a

simple facade that unites several preexisting houses, all belonging to a single family.

Alberti used stone masonry in a polemical fashion: unlike the Palazzo Medici, Palazzo

Rucellai is flat and framed by the addition of stacked orders. The extreme flatness of the

masonry overlaid by the grid of columns creates an impression of the building as a

modular plane rather than a massive block. Alberti transforms the archetype of the

Roman Coliseum into a wrapper with a civic orientation: rather than design an isolated

block, he rationalized the interface between street and building, wrapping the latter in a

repetitive and simple surface that seems infinitely extendable despite the uneven

geometry of the block itself. The function of the façade’s explicit flatness, which insists

on its role as mere ornament, is to mediate between private property and public space

through a rational, measurable order and not through the overall figure of the building

10 On the politics of Alberti’s Palazzo Rucellai see: Massimo Bulgarelli, Leon Battista Alberti, 1404–1472. Architettura e Storia (Milan: Electa, 2008), 34–72.

Page 38: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 9

itself. For this reason, the Palazzo Rucellai is the archetype of a new, modern, bourgeois-

mercantilist way of dealing with public space: not through confrontation but through

negotiation. The rational basis for this negotiation is the grid, which in the façade of

Palazzo Rucella, ideally extends the even order of the private palazzo towards the city

space.

Composition

A radical evolution of Alberti’s approach was elaborated by Jean-Nicolas-Louis Durand

in his Precis des Lecons d’architecture (1802),11 where the French architect introduced

for the first time the theme of composition. The Précis is divided into three parts. The

first is devoted to “architectural elements,” the second to “composition in general,” and

the third to “architectural genres.” In the first part, Durand isolates and presents each

element of a building – walls, atriums, stairs, vestibules, and so on – subdividing these

architectural elements into formally independent units. The isolation of each element

leads to the second operation: composition. Durand proposed the idea of composition in

order to overcome the methodological straightjacket of spatial distribution. For Durand

distribution was the art of creating order according to predefined habits of dwelling. As

such, it had a limited capacity to deal with the huge variety of possible architectural

genres – what today we would call “programs.” Composition, on the other hand, proposes

a combinatory principle whereby the positions of architectural elements can be changed

according to the kind of program addressed, and can occur in both plan and section. In

order to allow this formal flexibility, Durand proposed to subject the composition of all

11 Jean-Nicolas-Louis Durand, Précis des leçons d’architecture données à l’École royale polytechnique, 2 volumes (Paris: 1802-05).

Page 39: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 10

architectural elements to a radical, simple, and unequivocal method: the ordering of

architectural elements through the use of the grid. Walls would be placed on the parallel

axes of the grid, columns on the intersections of the axes, and openings such as doors or

windows between the axes. Thousands of different combinations could be made, each ad

hoc, to accomodate any program. For this reason, Durand’s method of design was not

only a radical attack on the strict hierarchical distribution of Baroque architecture, in

which formal complexity prevented programmatic and spatial flexibility, but also a

radical secularization of architectural form: composition accommodated the increasing

diversification of programmatic concerns that characterized the rise of the bourgeois city,

a city whose subsequent evolution Durand anticipated with the intrinsic flexibility of his

method.12 Composition allowed each element to have a potentially different position in

each application; the only fixed law of architecture was the combinatory logic of the grid.

While in Alberti’s Palazzo Rucellai the grid made by stacking the orders was still a two-

dimensional surface mediating between public and private space, in Durand’s Precis, the

grid became a spatial system that involved the three-dimensional totality of architectural

composition. Durand’s plans are devoid of poché, for they are made only by simple walls

and columns. Flexibility requires the extreme simplicity not only of the architectural

elements themselves but also of their combinations. The nonfigurative character of

Durand’s grid revealed the combinatory logic of composition: no element was fixed but

rather each was made relative to a specific use and thus accommodated a myriad of

“architectural genres.”

12 See: Sergio Villari, J.N.L. Durand (1760–1834): Art and Science of Architecture (New York: Rizzoli, 1990).

Page 40: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 11

Durand’s idea of composition suggests that the reduction of form to a grammar of

simple elements addresses the increasing proliferation of urban institutions such as

markets, hospitals, museums, etc. – the increasing unpredictability of the city’s

programmatic situations. Far from being just the outcome of aesthetic concerns, the

“abstraction” produced by a building’s combinatory performance, made efficient by

eliminating the figural infill of the poché, is the result of the reification of the city due to

the “liberalization” of its functions and activities. Durand’s focus on the grid as a

compositional template not only frames and thus tames the liberalization of city space, it

is also the only element that could orchestrate the design of everything from a single

room to an entire city without requiring the predefinition of all the stages between those

two poles.

Plan

The integration of the room and the entire city into the same compositional logic is

further radicalized by Ludwig Hilberseimer in his famous theoretical project for the

modern metropolis, the Hochhausstadt (1924).13 In this project for a vertical city

Hilberseimer takes a polemical stand against not only the utopian images proposed by

Expressionist architecture, but also Le Corbusier’s Contemporary City for Three Million

Inhabitants (1922). In his well-known proposal, Le Corbusier seems to arrange different

building types according to the figures of classical architecture: the spatiality of the

typical Parisian classicist square evoked by the space between the Cartesian skyscrapers;

the layout of the Palace of Versailles evoked by the Redents; the communitarian form of

the abbey cloister reinterpreted in the Immeuble Villas; and, finally, the outline of 13 See: Ludwig Hilberseimer, Grosstadt Architektur (Stuttgart: Hoffmann, 1927).

Page 41: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 12

Michelangelo’s plan for St. Peter’s in the form of the main train and air terminal at the

city center.14 Moreover, Le Corbusier clearly uses diverse building typologies, from the

most monumental at the center to the more suburban at the periphery, and separates

residential space from work space. Hilberseimer, on the other hand, uses only one

building type: a hybrid of blocks and slabs in which all civic activities, such as

production, living, and commerce, are superimposed rather than zoned in different

locations. Thus the form of the city emerges from the repetition of a single element or

type, and reflects the logic of the most conventional geometry possible – that of the grid.

The circulation system of the Hochhausstadt is then uniformly extended in all directions

by the superimposition of train lines, metro lines, trams, roads, and pedestrian streets in a

tartan pattern. For Hilberseimer, typological diversification no longer seems to be an

issue. Due to the extreme social mobility brought about by changing labor conditions in

the modern metropolis, living standards are reduced to the hotel room, which is contained

in an absolutely uniform slab superimposed atop a plinth comprising workshops and

office space. Distributive zoning and diverse typologies disappear because the inhabitants

of Hochhausstadt live, work, and move everywhere.

In Le Corbusier’s hierarchical City for Three Million, programmatic diversity is attained

by means of formal alternatives. In Hilberseimer’s Hochhausstadt, programmatic

diversity is addressed by assembling all of the elements of the city – domestic space,

office space, roads, railway lines, etc. – into one gridded composition that can be repeated

14 Le Corbusier, “Une Ville Contemporaine,” in Oeuvre Complète, 1910-1929 (Zurich: Les Editions d’architecture, 1964), 34–43. Gabriele Mastrigli has proposed a close reading of the “classical” figures that it is possible to identify in Le Corbusier’s Contemporary City for Three Million Inhabitants. See: Gabriele Mastrigli, In Praise of Discontinuity, or “La Leçon de Rome,” in Berlage Institute, Power: Producing the Contemporary City (Rotterdam: NAI Publisher, 2007), 113–124.

Page 42: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 13

ad infinitum. Form is no longer seen as representation but as process. In the

Hochhausstadt, form is devoid of any figurative or individualistic feature, guaranteeing it

will perform in the most rational, uniform way. The city is reduced to its reproductive

conditions. Its image may seem frighteningly monolithic, but it also appears to be serene,

because it has eliminated any formal anxiety through the radical deployment of a generic

type.

Surface

The continuous surface of Archizoom’s No-Stop City seems to have been developed as

an exaggeration ad absurdum of Hilberseimer’s Hochhausstadt. In both plans, the city is

envisioned as a stacking of technical elements without regard for their further formal

articulation. But where Hilberseimer uses building blocks, Archizoom dissolves the built

structure of the city into its constitutive infrastructural elements – column, elevator, wall,

etc. – by envisioning the city as a vast, artificially lit, air-conditioned interior. Differences

such as inside and outside, landscape and city, production and consumption, living and

working, are collapsed into one equipped surface that is extendable in all directions along

the grid, the most generic order possible. Here the grid is neither a visual element nor a

functional one, nor even a circulation system. It is simply the most conventional ratio

possible in order to distribute the necessary elements of the city without resorting to any

architectural gesture. The city is what it does: it is a continuous ambiance made by

repetitive conditions of light, communication, air-conditioning, mechanized

transportation, and all of the social connections – material and immaterial – that are

needed in order to make a city work and reproduce itself. Thus No-Stop City formalizes

Page 43: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 14

the conditions that make the city. Neither a proposal for a new city nor a utopian

transformation of the existing city, No-Stop City is a conceptual X-ray of the existing

capitalist metropolis, in which the conditions for reproduction are no longer localized in

specific sectors, such as the factory, housing, and recreation spaces, but proliferate

everywhere. With this scenario, the iconoclastic form of No-Stop City can be understood

as a merciless memento mori for architecture as a shape-maker and producer of

difference.

Within the objective conditions of the metropolis, formal complexity becomes

ideological, becomes a false consciousness that pretends to explain the functioning of the

city with futile formal gestures. The form of No-Stop City does not pretend to erase these

formal gestures; on the contrary, it cynically maintains them, integrating them into the

system, albeit as helpless arbitrary elements. Any formal difference is subsumed within

the sameness of the city.15 With No-Stop City, the history of nonfigurative architecture

appears to have arrived at its logical conclusion. But it is precisely the Hegelian act of

coming to the awareness of this unavoidable conclusion that offers the possibility of a

new beginning. In the aftermath of the history of nonfigurative architecture, a

nonfigurative form is no longer the demiurgical design of everything, but the limit that

attempts to release everything from its design. A possible postscript to the history of

nonfigurative architecture is to think of nonfigural form no longer as a vehicle for its own

extension but as a frame, as a limit of itself. Form as limit.

15 An example of this subsumption of difference is Rem Koolhaas’s theoretical project, “City of the Captive Globe,” 1972. Conceived as a parody of Manhattan, the project is an allegory of the lobotomy that the city’s infrastructural order – the grid – imposes on iconic architectural expression. See: Rem Koolhaas, Delirious New York (New York: Monacelli Press, 1995), 294–95.

Page 44: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 15

Limit

If the idea of form as limit means the diachronic sequence followed so far must be

slightly altered, it would be useful to conclude this brief history of the nonfigurative by

considering the work of Mies van der Rohe, who made “silence” his dogma. Unlike many

architects of his generation, Mies had little to do with political activism. Apart from some

experimental design at the beginning of his career and some sporadic and strategic social

proclamations, Mies focused on architecture as a “distanced” accomplishment of its

purpose: to frame space. Yet, as several critics have pointed out, the silent forms through

which Mies pursued this goal are far from idealistic. Especially in his American corporate

projects, Mies allowed the attributes of industrial technology – the famous I beams used

in the Seagram Building facade, for example – to enter and envelop his architecture. The

reification that emerges in Hilberseimer’s method of allowing the objective forces of

capital to redefine the city and the cynical detachment with which Archizoom addresses

the generic form of the postindustrial city are both apparent in Mies’s work. Again, the

neutrality of the grid seems to be the most effective ordering system for resisting the

semantic cacophony of the city while analogically and literally reflecting in the glass

facade the constitutive elements of that urban context. Neither an architecture of hope nor

of celebration, Mies’s buildings remain stubborn yet docile and simple orthogonal forms

within the complex space of the modern metropolis. As has been noted, their apparent

indifference to context is paradoxically their true contextual quality, which reflects, in the

most literal and objective terms, precisely what one cannot see: the generic space of

Page 45: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 16

exchange and reproduction behind the appearance of figural diversity.16 The “silence” of

Mies’s architecture has often been interpreted by historians and critics as reflecting and

incorporating the uprooting nature of modernity while defining a critical distance from

it.17 These interpretations range from the aesthetic of renunciation proposed by Manfredo

Tafuri, who saw in Mies’s American projects the explicit interiorization of the abstraction

of social life itself in the form of a paradoxical formal autonomy per via negativa, to

Massimo Cacciari’s reading of Mies’s abstraction (and of modern architecture) as a

conscious image of fulfilled nihilism; to Michael Hays’s use of Mies as an act of critical

architecture posited as both a radical detachment from all that is outside architecture and

reflecting the conditions that permit such distance; to Detlef Mertins’ rendering of Mies’s

redeeming use of technology.18 Yet, with the notable exceptions of the German critic

Fritz Neumeyer19 and Oswald Mathias Ungers,20 these canonical readings seem mostly to

have focused on the Miesian motif of the building envelope, while giving less importance

to the element that defined all of Mies’s projects: the careful placement of buildings

through the use of the plinth. From his early suburban houses in Germany to his corporate

office complexes in the US, the simple, bounded form of the plinth is the precondition for

16 See: Manfredo Tafuri, Proggetto e Utopia (Bari: Laterza, 1973), 64. 17 See: Sven-Olov Wallenstein, The Silences of Mies (Stockholm: AXL Books, 2008). 18 See: Tafuri, Progetto e Utopia; Manfredo Tafuri and Francesco Dal Co, Modern Architecture, trans. Erich Robert Wolf (New York: Rizzoli, 1980); Massimo Cacciari, Architecture and Nihilism: On the Philosophy of Modern Architecture (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1993); Michael Hays, “Critical Architecture: Between Culture and Norm,” Perspecta 21 (984); Detlef Mertins, “Mies’s skyscraper ‘project’: towards the redemption of technical structure,” in Detlef Mertins ed. The Presence of Mies (New York: Princeton Architectural Press, 1994), 49–67. 19 Fritz Neumeyer, “Space for Reflection: Block versus Pavillion,” in Franze Schulze, Mies van der Rohe, Critical Essays (New York: The Museum of Modern Art, 1989), 148–71. 20 Oswald Mathias Ungers, “Mies van der Rohe and Toronto,” in Lotus, 112 (2002 March), 108–31. Ungers has read Mies’s use of the plinth in his North American complexes, such as the Toronto Dominion Center, as an attempt to design a city form from within the limited boundaries of the architectural artifact. Addressed in this way, the plinth becomes the element that transforms the limits of the architectural artifact into its fundamental contribution to the city form.

Page 46: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 17

nearly all of Mies’s designs. If, as Neumeyer has argued, the pavilion-like quality of

Mies’s buildings seems to have followed Schinkel’s attempt to elevate the freestanding

architectural object as an analogous form encompassing the bourgeois occupation of

space (as opposed to the imperial claims of Baroque architecture) then the plinth seems to

give to this appropriation a self-defined limit. This is evident in projects such as the Riehl

House (1907), the Barcelona Pavilion (1929), the Seagram Building (1954–58), and the

New National Gallery in Berlin (1962–68). By putting emphasis on the building site, the

plinth inevitably makes the site a limit for what it contains. The isotropic order of

industrialization evoked by the building envelopes is contrasted by their siting, framed by

the plinth. Moreover, the way the plinth reorganizes the connection between a building

and its site not only affects one’s experience of what is placed on the plinth, but also –

and especially – one’s experience of the city that is left outside the plinth. One of the

most remarkable things felt by anyone climbing a Mies plinth, whether in New York or in

Berlin, is the experience of turning one’s back to the building in order to look at the city.

Suddenly, and for a brief moment, one is estranged from the flows and organizational

patterns that animate the city yet still confronting them. In this way Mies’s plinths

reinvent urban space as an archipelago of limited artefacts. While the materiality and

composition of Mies’s envelopes reproduce the attributes of the generic city, their

placement on the plinth presents these attributes no longer as ubiquitous, but as sensual

and finite objects. While Mies’s buildings assume the generic attributes of production, his

insistence on framing and limiting proposes these attributes not as norms, but as

architectural states of exception that force the generic to conform to the finite form of

location.

Page 47: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 18

One can ask whether in the age of “biopolitics” and “geopolitics,” where political

subjectivity is constantly reformulated in ever more complex and impalpable terms, the

bodily experience of form and location can make sense at all. But this is precisely the

point. Today a possible and radical counteraction to the ubiquity of the management of

space in all its forms can only be proposed by reaffirming in the most radical terms the

most graspable junctures through which space must be made. The nonfigurative gesture

of the plinth seems to open an analogical crack in urban space even as it has been

totalized by the managerial forces of the modern city. The plinth introduces a stoppage

into the smoothness of urban space, thus evoking the possibility of understanding urban

space not as ubiquitous, pervasive, and tyrannical, but as something that can be framed,

limited, and thus situated as a thing among other things. While buildings assume the

ineffable attributes of production, the plinth limits these attributes to a finite location.

Moreover, unlike the wall, a form like the plinth is a frame that does not simply separate

or isolate; it recuperates in subtle ways the difference that the modern city has subsumed

within its generic space: the symbolic possibility of confrontation.

Unlike Alberti, Durand, Hilberseimer, and Archizoom, Mies is concerned not only with

the universality and repeatability of this form but also with its limit, with the finitude of

its location. The possibility of a nonfigurative architecture is thus reinvented by

absorbing the compulsion to repeat which is the essential trait of capitalist civilization

while increasing architecture’s function as a frame, as a limit both to itself and to the

Page 48: Binder2

Aureli 7/6/12 19

forces and interests it represents. Mies not only developed a particular model of

architecture, he also introduced a particular attitude toward the city.

Today, against the ubiquity of design, this attitude toward framing and limiting needs to

be developed both as literal material form of architecture, but also as a political principle

of design. Not open-ended growth, but limiting should be conceived as the fundamental

meta-project of that gives form to architecture’s responsibility towards the city. There is

no question that the idea of limit implies issues that go far beyond the scope of

architecture and its project, and involves the complex ecology of political and economic

space. Yet like the archetypes we have seen before, the task of architecture is to reify, that

is to transform into public generic, and thus graspable common things, the political

organization of space of which architectural form is not simply the consequence, but also

one of the most powerful and influential political example. In this way the absoluteness

of architecture, its being a finite form, is not simply the tautological claim of its literality

as object, but it is also the example for a city no longer driven by the ethos of expansion

and inclusion but by the positive idea of limits.