83
‘Cause we are living in a material world: on iconic turn in cultural sociology A Master’s Thesis written by Bc. Jitka Sklenářová MASARYK UNIVERSITY •FACULTY OF SOCIAL STUDIES •DEPARTMENT OF SOCIOLOGY Supervisor: doc. PhDr. Csaba Szaló, Ph.D. Brno, 2014

‘Causewearelivinginam aterial’world:’’ …fresh-eye.cz/wp-content/uploads/2014/06/sklenarova...‘Causewearelivinginam aterial’world:’’ oniconic’turnincultural’soc

  • Upload
    hakhanh

  • View
    213

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

 

 

 

   

 

‘Cause  we  are  living  in  a  material  world:    on  iconic  turn  in  cultural  sociology  

A  Master’s  Thesis  written  by  Bc.  Jitka  Sklenářová    

 

 

MASARYK  UNIVERSITY  •  FACULTY  OF  SOCIAL  STUDIES  •  DEPARTMENT  OF  SOCIOLOGY    

Supervisor:  doc.  PhDr.  Csaba  Szaló,  Ph.D.    

Brno,  2014  

 2  

 3  

Declaration  

I  hereby  declare  that  this  thesis  I  submit  for  assessment  is  entirely  my  own  work  and  

has  not  been  taken  from  the  work  of  others  save  to  the  extent  that  such  work  has  been  

cited  and  acknowledged  within  the  text  of  my  work.    

 

 

 

 

 

11th  May  2014  

 

 

Signature  

 4  

 5  

Acknowledgements  

“We  are  not  at  an  airport;  we  are  at  a  university.”  

I  would  like  to  thank  Csaba  Szaló  for  these  words,  for  his  inexhaustible  support  and  

trust,  and  for  influencing  my  life  in  many  positive  ways.  I  am  also  grateful  for    

the  international  and  friendly  environment  he  managed  to  create    

at  the  Department  of  Sociology.  

•  

Special  thanks  go  to  Werner  Binder  who  spent  many  hours  answering  my  questions.  

His  enthusiasm  and  inspirational  comments  were  of  great  importance  for  my  work.  

•  

I  also  appreciate  attention,  support,  and  suggestions  received    

from  Nadya  Jaworsky  and  Dominik  Bartmański.  

 6  

Table  of  Contents  

Abstract   8  

Abstract  (in  Czech)   9  

Introduction:  Call  for  a  new  sociology   11  

1.  Human  and  social  sciences  &  the  visual:  History  of  a  complicated  relationship   17  

1.1.   Semiotics  and  the  notion  of  a  discursive  world   18  

1.1.1.   Peirce’s  triad   19  

1.2.   Panofsky’s  image  interpretation   20  

1.2.1.   Iconology   21  

1.2.2.   Critique  of  Panofsky’s  method   25  1.3.   “Rhetorique  of  the  Image”   27  

1.4.   Consequences  of  the  linguistic  turn   29  

1.5.   Pictorial  turn   30  

1.6.   Iconic  turn   33  

1.6.1.   Iconic  difference   34  

2.  Iconicity  and  the  strong    programme  in  cultural  sociology   39  

2.1.   Strong  programme   40  

2.2.   Iconic  theory   42  

2.3.   The  power  of  icons   45  

2.4.   Icons  as  myths   48  

 7  

2.5.   Achievements  &  benefits  of  iconic  theory   51  

2.5.1.   Nobody  puts  images  in  a  corner  (anymore)   53  

3.  The  problem  of  two  iconic  turns   57  

3.1.   Boehm’s  iconic  turn   58  

3.1.1.   Focus:  genuinely  pictorial  aspects  of  the  image   59  

3.2.   Iconic  turn  of  the  strong  programme   61  

3.3.   Suggestions   62  

3.3.1.   Surface  &  depth  is  not  enough   63  

3.3.2.   Problem  of  pre-­‐reflexive  experience   65  

3.3.3.   Bohnsack’s  documentary  method   66  

3.3.4.   Binder’s  secular  icon   68  

4.  Conclusion   71  

References   75  

Index   82  

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

 

Number  of  characters:  149  487  

Reproduction  on  the  cover:    La  trahison  des  images  by  René  Magritte  (fragment)  

 8  

Abstract  

The  strong  programme   in  cultural   sociology  has   recently   taken  up   topics  of  visuality  

and  materiality  and  made  an  effort  to  include  them  into  one  theory.  The  iconic  theory  

suggested   in   Iconic   Power   (2012)   pursues   two  main   goals.   It   aims   at   overcoming   the  

duality  of  materialism  and  idealism,  two  approaches  that  have  in  the  sociological  theo-­‐

ry  until  now  been  fully  incompatible.  The  proposed  concept  of  icon  combines  an  aes-­‐

thetic  surface  and  a  meaningful  depth  of  a  cultural  object,  which  are  mutually  consti-­‐

tuted  and  intertwined.  Bringing  the  elusive  experience,  the  feeling  of  material  objects  

and  their  deep  cultural  meanings  together  seems  to  be  the  right  way  to  go  for  cultural  

sociology   that  has  dealt  with   collective   emotions   and   representations   since   its   birth.  

The  iconic  theory  also  makes  possible  the  emancipation  and  liberation  of  images  from  

the   textual   and   discursive   dominance   typical   of   the   sociological   thinking   in   the   20th  

century.  The  source  of  inspiration  for  the  new  theory  was  the  so  called  iconic  turn  in  

art  theory.  However,  there  seem  to  be  some  fundamental  disagreements  between  these  

two  approaches.  My  thesis  presents  the  newborn  iconic  theory  and  reflects  its  benefits  

and   pitfalls.   Furthermore,   drawing   on   the   background   of   developments   within   the  

scholarly  approach  to  images  and  on  the  currently  used  sociological  methods  of  image  

analysis   I  offer  possible  answers   to  the  questions  and  puzzles  raised  by  the  theory  of  

iconic  power.  

 9  

Abstract  (in  Czech)  

Kulturní  sociologie  se  nedávno  začala  zabývat  otázkami  vizuality  a  materiality,   jež  se  

pokusila  zahrnout  do  jedné  teorie.  Teorie  ikonicity  formulovaná  v  knize  Iconic  Power  

(2012)   sleduje  především  dva  cíle.  Prvním  z  nich   je  překonání   rozporu  mezi  materia-­‐

lismem  a  idealismem,  dvěma  nesmiřitelnými  myšlenkovými  směry,  které  se  doposud  v  

rámci  sociologické  teorie  nepodařilo  úspěšně  sjednotit.  V  navrhovaném  konceptu  iko-­‐

ny  se  vzájemně  konstituují  a  propojují  estetický  povrch  s  významovou  hloubkou  kul-­‐

turních  objektů.    Spojení  prchavé  zkušenosti  a  pocitů  zakoušených  při  kontaktu  s  ma-­‐

teriálními   objekty   a   jejich   hlubších   kulturních   významů   se   zdá   být   v   souladu   se  

směřováním  kulturní  sociologie,  která  se  již  od  počátku  zabývá  kolektivními  emocemi  

a   reprezentacemi.   Ikonická   teorie   rovněž  umožňuje   emancipaci   a  osvobození  obrazů  

zpod  diskurzivní  nadvlády  typické  pro  sociologické  myšlení  20.  století.  Zdrojem  inspi-­‐

race  pro  novou  teorii  byl   takzvaný   ikonický  obrat  v  teorii  umění.  Mezi   těmito  dvěma  

přístupy  se  nicméně  projevily  zásadní  neshody.  Ve  své  práci  představuji  nově  vytvoře-­‐

nou  ikonickou  teorii  a  reflektuji  její  přínosy  a  problematické  aspekty.  Na  pozadí  vývoje  

vědeckého  přístupu  k  obrazům  a  na  základě  v  současnosti  používaných  metod  obrazo-­‐

vé  analýzy  v   sociologii  navrhuji  možné  odpovědi  na  otázky  a  problémy  vyvstávající  z  

teorie  ikonické  moci.  

 

 10  

“A  book  is  changed  by  the  fact    that  it  does  not  change  even  when  the  world  changes.”  

Pierre  Bourdieu  quoted  in  Chartier,  1989  

 11  

Introduction:  Call  for  a  new  sociology  

Fourteen  years  ago,  Howard  Becker  was  asked  by  the  Contemporary  Sociology  Maga-­‐

zine,   what   sociology   should   look   like   in   the   (near)   future.   In   his   answer,   Becker  

(2000:  333)  took  the  question  literally;  by  that  move  he  managed  to  point  out  the  fact  

that  visual  materials  were  neglected  by  social  sciences  for  a  long  time  and  that  it  was  

time  for  us  to  change  such  an  attitude1.  In  fact,  the  ignorance  made  explicit  by  Becker  

does   not   exclusively   relate   to   the   visual,   but   applies   also   to   the  material   in   general.  

Sensual  experience  never  used  to  be  taken  into  account  for  the  explanation  of  mean-­‐

ing-­‐making  processes,  since  meaning  was  thought  of  as  emerging  in  text,  language  and  

discourse.  Obviously,  this  is  not  enough—there  is  more  to  life  than  discourses.  Such  a  

realization  could  explain  why  the  relevance  of  sensual  experience,  gained  by  encounter  

with  material  things  and  its  importance  for  how  we  make  sense  of  the  world,  has  nev-­‐

ertheless  won  further  discussion  in  the  last  two  decades,  especially  among  those  advo-­‐

cating  the  strong  programme  in  cultural  sociology.  The  effort  to  grasp  the  sensual  and  

                                                                                               

1  As  soon  as  I  have  engaged  in  the  problem  of  image  interpretation,  which  stood  at  the  very  beginning  of  my   work   presented   here,   I   also   encountered   opinions   stating   that   the   topic   was   not   “sociological  enough”.  During   disputes  with   professors,   colleagues   and   in   interaction  with   scholarly   texts   I   indeed  discovered  comments  questioning  the  very  idea  of  the  relation  between  sociology  and  the  visual.  I  had  to  conclude  that  there  was  a  broad  range  of  understandings  and  conceptions  of  the  role  of  the  visual  in  sociology,  ranging  from  using  it  as  a  mere  data-­‐collection  or  data-­‐presenting  method,  to  qualitative  ap-­‐proaches  and  interpretation  of  images,  to  the  theoretical  stance  of  cultural  sociology.  

 12  

material   side   of   social   life   has   resulted   in   an   attempt   to   establish   a   theory   of   iconic  

power.  

Dealing  with  such  elusive  entities  as  sensuality  or  emotionality  has  without  any  doubt  

been   always   a   tricky   issue   for   sociologists.   The   founding   fathers   of   social   sciences  

strived  to  avoid  everything  that  had  to  do  with  emotions  in  order  to  gain  an  unbiased  

view  of  reality.  Even  the  most  necessary  (in  our  culture,  at  least)  sense  of  sight  was  ex-­‐

cluded  from  inquiring  about  society.  “Real  scientists  were  objective  and  unsentimental,  

and  photographs   seemed   to  make  people   sympathetic,”   criticizes  Becker   sociologists’  

reluctance   to   use   images   in   their   journals   (2000:  333).  However,   the   21st   century   has  

brought   about   significant   changes   in   sociological   research;   most   notably   the   strong  

programme  has   re-­‐focused  sociological  attention   from  analyzing   the  effects  of  objec-­‐

tive   social   structures  on  actors  and  culture   to  considerations  about  autonomous  cul-­‐

ture  itself.  The  new  reading  (or  re-­‐reading,  as  the  protagonists  call   it2)  of  Durkheim’s  

Elementary  forms  of  religious  life  has  provided  the  new  cultural  movement  with  an  in-­‐

spiring  notion  of  society.  

“Durkheim’s  vision   in  the  Elementary  Forms  was  of  a  shared  cul-­‐tural  system  that  is  internalized  within  each  individual.  It  trumps  the  material  base  by  superimposing  upon  it  a  universe  of  arbitrary  but  deeply  meaningful  signs,  myths  and  determinations  of  action.  He   wrote:   ‘(...)   Collective   representations   very   often   attribute   to  the  things  to  which  they  are  attached  properties  which  do  not  exist  in  any  form  or  degree.  Out  of  the  commonest  object  they  can  make  a  very  powerful  and  very  sacred  being.  Yet,  although  purely   ideal,  the  powers  which  have  been  conferred   in   this  way  work  as   if  hey  were  real.  They  determine  the  conduct  of  men  with  the  same  inevi-­‐tability  as  physical  forces’”  (Alexander  and  Smith  2005:  8–9)    

It  was  thus  Elementary  Forms  that  furnished  cultural  sociology  with  a  toolbox  contain-­‐

ing  concepts  such  as  collective  representations,  meanings,  symbolism,  morality,  totem,  

rituals,  dichotomy  of  sacred  and  profane  etc.  But  even  after  establishing  the  research  of  

                                                                                               

2  “Readings  proliferate  that  are  unintended  and  unpredictable,  with  determinations  that  go  far  beyond  those  that  could  have  been  consciously  anticipated  by  the  maker  of  the  original  text.  Time  reverses  the  direction  of  influence.  New  contexts  of  interpretation  come  to  rewrite  texts  as  authors  and  theories  are  re-­‐narrated  for  present  relevance.”  (Alexander  and  Smith  2005:1)  

 13  

collective  discourses  based  on  narratives  and  introducing  the  concept  of  performativi-­‐

ty,  there  still  was  a  wish  “to  extend  this  new  understanding  one  step  further”  (Alexan-­‐

der  2008:  9).  The  broadening  of  sociological  horizons  crystallized  eventually  into  icon-­‐

ic  turn  (the  term  was  borrowed  from  the  German  art  historian  Gottfried  Boehm),  and  

respectively   into   iconic  theory,  which   is  seeking  after  an  answer  to  the  question  how  

meaning  manifests   itself   through  materiality   (Alexander  2010a:  12).  Becker’s   call   for  a  

new  sociology  which  would  get  more  visual  was  thus  surpassed—it  has  not  stuck  with  

vision  only  and  made  an  effort  to  integrate  the  other  four  senses  as  well.  In  short,  icon-­‐

ic  theory  promises  to  combine  the  sensual  and  the  material  in  a  way  that  allows  us  to  

sociologically  grasp  both  subjective  experience  and  collective  meanings  and  their  rela-­‐

tionship  at  the  same  time.  

It  seems  to  be  a   logical  step  in  the  development  of  the  strong  programme  to  shift   its  

focus  to  iconicity  recently.  The  aim  of  iconic  theory  continues  the  cultural  sociological  

line,  which  has  since  its  birth  paid  a  great  attention  to  the  study  of  collective  represen-­‐

tations  and  emotions.  The  problem  with  texts  is,  however,  that  they  cannot  raise  such  

strong  emotions  as  other  forms  of  human  experience.  The  main  goal  of   iconic  theory  

was  thus  the  inclusion  of  sensual  experience  of  material  stuff  into  sociological  theory.  

But   why   is   it   important   to   treat   materiality   sociologically?   How   does   iconic   turn  

change  our  understanding  of  social  phenomena?  What  problems  does  the  iconic  theo-­‐

ry   solve  and  what  problems   it  brings?  These  are   just   several  questions  and  problems  

that  I  deal  with  in  this  thesis.  My  argument  is  developed  and  divided  into  three  steps:  

First,  I  introduce  the  background  of  scholarly  development  in  the  field  of  image  inter-­‐

pretation,  which  made  certain  progress  despite  of  the  prevailing  approach  inspired  by  

turn  to   language  and  discourse   in  the  20th  century.   It   is  essential   to  begin  with  these  

developments  since  they  have  mostly  provided  inspiration  for  current  efforts  in  dealing  

with  iconicity.  In  the  second  chapter  I  introduce  the  newly  born  theory  of  iconic  power  

suggested  by   the   strong  programme,  highlight   its  main  points   and   ideas  and  outline  

the  main  benefits  it  has  brought  into  sociological  discourse.  In  the  last  chapter  I  point  

out   the   questions   emerging   from   the   first   notion   of   iconic   theory   and   the   problems  

concerning   its   future   direction.   Drawing   on   contemporary   research   based   on   art-­‐

 14  

theoretical   methods   of   image   interpretation   I   also   suggest   possible   solutions   to   the  

unresolved  issues  in  the  definition  of  iconicity.  

 15  

 16  

“Medium  is  the  message.”  

Marshall  McLuhan,  1964

 

 17  

1  Human  and  social  sciences  &  the  visual:  History  of  a  complicated  relationship  

The  search  for  meaning  as  well  as  the  effort  to  understand  the  processes  of   its  emer-­‐

gence  was   focused   exclusively  on   language   for  most  of   the   20th   century.  By   claiming  

that  all  philosophical  questions  are  basically  linguistic  problems  and  can  therefore  be  

solved  either  by   reforming   language  or  by  understanding  more  about   the  one  we  al-­‐

ready  use  (Rorty  1967:  3),  the  linguistic  turn  in  philosophy  was  launched.  But  as  Wag-­‐

ner  rightly  observed,  the  way  how  one  sees  the  world  inevitably  changes  “once  one  as-­‐

serts   that   all   relations   between   human   beings   and   the   world   are   constituted   by  

language“   (2008:  252).  Rorty’s  book  Linguistic  Turn  published   in   1967  caused  a  broad  

paradigm  shift  that  influenced  a  whole  set  of  human  sciences—from  linguistics,  semi-­‐

otics  and  rhetoric  to  art  and  media  studies  and  sociology.  It  resulted  not  only  in  asking  

different  questions,  but  also  in  ability  to  find  new  answers  and  opening  new  perspec-­‐

tives  on  social  life.  Suddenly,  society  became  a  text  and  nature  and  its  scientific  repre-­‐

sentations  “discourses”  (Mitchell  1994:  11).  

 18  

1.1. Semiotics  and  the  notion  of  a  discursive  world  However,   the  assumption   that   everyday   reality   is   constituted  by   language  was  by  no  

means  new   in   1967.   The   same  position  was   central   also   for   Saussure’s   structuralism,  

one  of  the  biggest  inspirations  for  linguistic  turn  as  well  as  for  the  whole  linguistics  in  

the  20th  century  up  to  now.  The  main  argument  in  Saussure’s  (1996)  theory  is  that  signs  

acquire  their  meanings  from  their  positions  and  mutual  relations  within  a  sign  system,  

i.e.  the  language  system,  which  he  favored.  His  semiology,  as  he  called  his  semiotics,  is  

based  on  a   “dyadic  sign  model”.   In   this  model,  sign   consists  of  signifier   (e.g.  a  word)  

and   signified   (i.e.   a  mental   concept   evoked   in   one’s  mind   by   hearing   or   reading   the  

word).  The  real  object  in  the  world,  which  the  sign  points  to,  is  called  referent  and  is  

not  a  part  of  the  dyadic  model.  The  crucial  assumption  here  is  that  the  relationship  of  

referent  and  its  sign  is  purely  arbitrary,  what  accounts  for  the  fact  that  there  are  differ-­‐

ent   signs   used   for   denoting   different   referents   in   different   languages.   Therefore,   the  

meaning  of  each  sign  must  be  conceptualized  as  context-­‐dependent,  i.e.  contingent  on  

positions  of  different  signs  within  the  sign  system.  As  a  result,   language  system  does  

not  provide  people  with  contact  to  reality;  language  is  reality,  since  everything  we  refer  

to  as   reality   is   just  a  convention,   a   result  of   the  process  of   signification.  Nothing  can  

exist  without  being  thought  of  and  we  cannot  think  of  any  referent  unless  it  exists  in  

language,  unless  there  is  a  concept  for  it.  Even  though  such  a  conclusion  might  seem  

extreme  today,  it  has  indeed  largely  influenced  the  course  of  human  and  social  scienc-­‐

es  for  decades,  Mitchell  thus  talks  about  “absorption  of  image  by  discourse”  (Mitchell  

1994:  28).  

If  there  were  any  attempts  to  push  the  image  topic  further,  they  would  generally  con-­‐

clude   that   images  were   themselves   linguistic   occurrences   or   demonstrated   that   they  

were   participating   in   the   signs’   systems   as  well   (Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:  105).   For  

Boehm,   the   latter  was   true   for   the  work   of   the   second   “father”   of   semiotics,  Charles  

Sanders  Peirce.  A  different  reading  is  proposed  by  Mitchell  who  highlights  Peirce’s  “re-­‐

sistance  to  taking  the  symbolic  (or  the  verbal)  as  the  foundational  moment  of  semiot-­‐

ics”  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  118).  This  argument  is  supported  by  the  fact  that  Peirce  

is  sometimes  considered  to  be  “a  visual  interpreter  of  language”  (Pietarinen  2012:  251).  

 19  

1.1.1. Peirce’s  triad  For  Peirce,  sign  is  a  kind  of  relation;  to  be  exact  it  is  a  triadic  relation  of  representation  

(Buczynska-­‐Garewicz   1979).  The   elements  of  his   “triadic   sign  model”   are   sign   (repre-­‐

sentament),  object   and  meaning   (interpretant).   An   object   is   always   represented   by   a  

sign,  but  since  representation  is  always  mediation,  the  central  point  belongs  to  the  in-­‐

terpretant3.   The   interpretant   is   always   general,   never   individual   and   constitutes   the  

ideal,   logical  meaning   of   the   sign.   Furthermore,   Peirce   emphasises   that   the   subject’s  

experience  of  a   sign   is   sensational  and   irreflexive,  while  meaning-­‐making   takes  place  

during  the  process  of  construction  of  interpretant  that  makes  sense  of  the  relationship  

between  sign  and  object  (Petrilli  1999).  

The  next  key  assumption  of  Peirce’s  semiotics  is  that  sign  is  always  determined  by  its  

object.   Therefore,   he   developed   a   typology   of   signs   based   on   a   triad   of   firstness,  

secondness,  and  thirdness4  that  organizes  signs  by  “closeness  to  their  object”  (Huening  

2006).  Whenever   a   sign   stands   for   its   object   through   some   quality   of   feeling   (Atkin  

2005),  it  is  called  icon  (or  likeness)  and  belongs  to  the  category  of  firstness.  “Icons  can  

represent   nothing   but   Forms   and   Feelings,”   wrote   Peirce5   (quoted   in   Buczynska-­‐

Garewicz  1979:  256).  Therefore,  icon  is  interpreted  as  a  possibility,  i.e.  a  mental  image,  

typical  of  its  similarity  or  analogy  to  the  subject  of  discourse  (Lattmann  2012).  Indices  

(or  indexes)  then  stand  for  their  objects  through  an  existential  or  physical  fact  (Atkin  

2005)  and  therefore  belong  to  the  sphere  of  secondness.  Symbols  as  thirdnesses  stand  

for   their  objects   through  convention,   the   relation   to   their  objects   is   therefore  purely  

habitual  or  defined  by  rules  (Peirce  1998:  5–7).  All  three  sign  categories,  nevertheless,  

overlap  in  actual  signs:  “Consider  a  photograph:  it  has  properties  in  common  with  its  

object,   and   is   therefore   an   icon;   it   is  directly   and  physically   influenced  by   its  object,  

                                                                                               

3  Interpretant,  contrary  to  a  widespread  belief,  is  neither  an  interpreter  nor  an  individual  mind  (Buczyn-­‐ska-­‐Garewicz  1979).  

4  Firstness  is  a  category  of  quality  of  feeling,  secondness  stands  for  actual,  concrete  and  temporary  being  and   thirdness   is   general,   timeless   and   independent   category   independent   on   subjective   thinking  (Buczynska-­‐Garewicz  1979).  

5  Icon  is  a  possibility,  i.e.  a  mental  image,  typical  of  its  similarity  or  analogy  to  the  subject  of  discourse  (Lattmann  2012).  

 20  

and  is  therefore  an  index;  and  lastly  it  requires  a  learned  process  of  ‘reading’  to  under-­‐

stand  it,  and  is  therefore  a  symbol”  (Huening  2006).  

Peirce’s   semiology   is   important   for   the  study  of   images  exactly  because   it  did  not,   in  

contrast  to  the  one  introduced  by  Saussure,  assume  that  language  is  paradigmatic  for  

meaning   (Mitchell   1994).   For   when   one   considers   Saussure’s   theory   in   the   light   of  

Peirce,  one  is  “struck  by  Saussure’s  need  to  characterise  the  ‘signified’  in  pictorial  terms  

in   the   famous   diagram   of   the   sign”   (Boehm   and  Mitchell   2009:  118).  Mitchell   (ibid.)  

therefore  acknowledges  Peirce’s  effort  to  pave  the  path  for  a  broader  scholarly  recogni-­‐

tion  of  images,   later  known  as  pictorial  turn.  His  writings  were  also  acknowledged  as  

highly  inspirational  by  Erwin  Panofsky—an  art  historian  whose  methods  of  interpreta-­‐

tion  of  works  of  art  have  recently  experienced  considerable  comeback   in  many  disci-­‐

plines   interested   in   images.   There   are   barely   any   texts   dealing  with   the   image   topic  

that  would  not  refer  back  to  Panofsky.  The  fact  that  they  still  feel  compelled  to  take  a  

stand   on   his   theory   only  maintains   its   significance   for   contemporary   research.   Also,  

considering   the   lack   of   interest   that   sociology  has   paid   to   the   visual   during   the   20th  

century  (cf.  Bartmanski  2012b),  it  is  exactly  art  history  that  offers  us  the  chance  to  look  

for  sociologically  useful  concepts,  convenient  terminology  and  methods  of  interpreta-­‐

tion  in  its  field  of  interest.  

1.2. Panofsky’s  image  interpretation  “The   artist   knows   only   ‘what   he   parades’   but   not   ‘what   he   betrays6’”   (Panofsky  

2012:  480),  could  have  been  the  motto  of  Panofsky’s  thinking  about  art  and  its  forms.  

The  central  assumption  lying  in  the  very  core  of  his  theory  was  that  every  perspective  

is  historically  determined.  Notion  of  historicity  thus  became  his  point  of  departure  for  

every   interpretation.   Instead   of   asking   what   the   artist   wanted   to   express,   Panofsky  

tried   to   find  out  what   she  expresses  without  being  aware   of   it.  His  method   therefore  

carries  certain  resemblance  to  psychoanalysis,  for  it  tries  to  reveal  the  “cultural  uncon-­‐

                                                                                               

6  The  quote  was  taken  from  writings  by  Charles  S.  Peirce  whom  Panofsky  considered  to  be  “an  intellec-­‐tually  stimulating  American”  (Panofsky  2012:480).  

 21  

sciousness7”   in  order   to   find   “the  unintentional   and   subconscious   self-­‐revelation  of   a  

fundamental  attitude  towards  the  world  which  is  characteristic  in  equal  measure  of  the  

individual   producer,   the   individual   period,   the   individual   people,   and   the   individual  

cultural   community”   (Panofsky  2012:  479).   It   is  exactly   the   search   for  underlying  cul-­‐

tural  principles  that  demonstrate  themselves  in  art,  why  Panofsky’s  approach  is  some-­‐

times  referred  to  as  hermeneutics  of  the  visual8  (Binder  2012:  103).  

Panofsky   introduced  his  method  named   iconology   in   1939   together  with   a  model   for  

interpretation  of  pictures  based  on  three  levels  of  meaning,  i.e.  phenomenal  meaning,  

meaning  dependent  on  content  and  documentary  (or  intrinsic)  meaning.  In  this  classi-­‐

fication,   the   resemblance   to  Mannheim’s   three   kinds   of  meaning—objective,   expres-­‐

sive   and  documentary   (1951:  44)—is   by  no  means   accidental9.  Another   inspiration   of  

Panofsky  can  be   traced  back   to  Peirce’s   categories  of   firstness,  secondness   and   third-­‐

ness   based   on   feeling,   reacting   and   thinking   (Peirce   1998).   Based   on   these   levels   of  

meaning,   the   suggested   technique   was   supposed   to   enable   the   interpreter   to   grasp  

more  than  just  the  “‘physiognomic’  qualities  of  the  work  of  art,”  since  the  aesthetic  ex-­‐

perience  had  to  be  “supported,  controlled,  and  corrected  by  the  history  of  the  style,  the  

types,   and   the   ‘cultural   symptoms’”   (Bourdieu   2005:  224).   To   fully   understand   the  

character   of   individual   types   of   meaning,   the   most   convenient   way   is   to   introduce  

them  together  with  Panofsky’s  interpretative  model.  Also,  since  contemporary  scholars  

inquiring   about   images   almost   always   refer   back   to   Panofsky’s   thoughts,   in   order   to  

understand  these  critiques  it  is  essential  to  understand  his  approach  first.  

1.2.1. Iconology  The  method  of  iconological  interpretation  introduced  by  Panofsky  stems  directly  from  

the  notion  of  three  levels  of  meaning.  An  important  note  is  that  the  differentiation  of  

                                                                                               

7  Credits  for  this  metaphor  belong  to  Binder  (2014a).  

8  Panofsky’s  work  and  accent  on  underlying  structures  is  indeed  strongly  influenced  by  hermeneutics  of  W.  Dilthey  and  F.  Schleiermacher  (cf.  Holly  1984).  

9   Panofsky   adopted   Mannheim’s   “Weltanaschauungsintepretation”   (Eberlein   2003:179),   which   can   be  best  translated  as  “interpretation  of  the  world-­‐view”  and  which  is  known  also  as  the  documentary  meth-­‐od  (for  its  contemporary  use  in  picture  analysis  see  Bohnsack  (2007,  2009)).  

 22  

individual  meanings   used   in   the  model   is   only   theoretical   and   solely   analytical   and  

therefore   does   not   play   any   role   in   everyday   empirical   experience,   since   people   en-­‐

counter  all  of  three  levels  of  meaning  at  once  (Panofsky  2012).  

Figure  1:  Panofsky’s  (1955:  40–41)  synoptical  table  summarizing  three  independent  strata  of  meaning  and  their  respective  identification  and  interpretation.  

Object  of  interpretation  

Act  of  inter-­‐pretation  

Equipment  for  interpretation  

Corrective  principle  of  interpretation    (History  of  tradition)

I  Primary  or  natural  subject  matter:  A)  factual,    B)  expressional  (constituting  the  world  of  artistic  motifs).

Pre-­‐iconographical  description    (and  pseudoformal  analysis).

Practical  experience  (familiarity  with  objects  and  events).

History  of  style  (insight  into  the  manner  in  which,  under  varying  historical  conditions,  objects  and  events  were  expressed  by  forms).

II  Secondary  or  conventional  subject  matter,  constituting  the  world  of  images,  stories  and  allegories.

Iconographical  analysis.  

Knowledge  of  literary  sources  (familiarity  with  specific  themes  and  concepts).

History  of  types  (insight  into  the  manner  in  which,  under  varying  historical  conditions,  specific  themes  or  concepts  were  expressed  by  objects  and  events).

III  Intrinsic  meaning  or  content,  constituting  the  world  of  “symbolical”  values.

Iconological  interpretation.  

Synthetic  intuition  (familiarity  with  the  essential  tendencies  of  the  human  mind),  conditioned  by  personal  psychology  and  “Weltanschauung”.

History  of  cultural  symptoms  or  “symbols”  in  general  (insight  into  the  manner  in  which,  under  varying  historical  conditions,  essential  tendencies  of  the  human  mind  were  expressed  by  specific  themes  and  concepts).

 

 

The  first  step  in  Panofsky’s   iconological  method  (see  Figure  1)   is  pre-­‐iconographic  de-­‐

scription.  Its  focus  is  the  level  of  phenomenal  meaning,  whose  source  is  common  eve-­‐

 23  

ryday  knowledge  and  practical  experience10.  The  interpreter  thus  describes  factual  and  

expressive  matters  of  the  image.  Although  it  might  seem  that  at  this  level  of  interpreta-­‐

tion  no  special  background  knowledge  is  needed,  the  opposite  is  true,   for   it  even  the  

pre-­‐iconographical   description  must   already   contain   certain   classifications,   for   “it   is  

not   always   easy   to   recognize   what   is   portrayed   in   the   picture”   (Panofsky   2012:  471).  

Completing  the  descriptive  step  therefore  presupposes  using  a  corrective  principle  of  

history  of  styles,  which  informs  us  about  the  kind  of  expression  and  representation  of  

specific  objects  or  events  that  was  possible  in  different  historical  periods  and  contexts  

(ibid.:  480),   “otherwise   we   have   no   means   of   knowing   whether   we   must   apply   the  

norms  of  modern  naturalism  or  the  norms  of  medieval  spiritualism  to  this  suspension  

in  the  void”  (ibid.:  472).  

In  the  focus  of  iconographical  analysis,  which  is  the  second  step  of  Panofsky’s  method,  

is  meaning  dependent  on  content.  Therefore  it  is  motifs,  stories  and  allegories  consti-­‐

tutive  of  the  image  what  the  interpreter  takes  into  consideration.  Familiarity  with  lit-­‐

erature,  narratives  and  broader  historical  context  are  essential  knowledge,  since  in  dif-­‐

ferent   historical   periods   there   were   different   objects   used   for   expression   of   certain  

concepts11.  This  knowledge  provides  the  interpreter  also  with  a  corrective  principle  for  

iconographical  analysis,  i.e.  with  a  history  of  types  that  informs  us  “what  was  imagina-­‐

ble”  at  that  time.  For  Panofsky,  a  type  is  “a  depiction  in  which  a  specific  phenomenal  

meaning   is   so  closely  connected  with   the  meaning  dependent  on  content   that   it   im-­‐

mediately  signals  that  content”  (ibid.:  473–474)  .  

The  most  generalizing  part  of  Panofsky’s  model  is  the  last  one  called  iconological  inter-­‐

pretation.  In  this  step  is  iconographic  meaning  as  such  treated  as  a  “cultural  symbol,”  

as  an  expression  of  specific  culture  (Bourdieu  2005:  224),  in  order  to  find  intrinsic  (or  

documentary)  meaning   of   the   picture.   Documentary  meaning   is   unintentional,   sub-­‐

                                                                                               

10  The  parallel  of  phenomenal  meaning   to  Peirce’s   firstness   is   evident   in  Panofsky’s   reference   to  unre-­‐flected  everyday  experience.  As  Peirce  noted,  likenesses  should  not  be  interpreted  but  “presented  to  the  sense”  (1998:8).  11   Again,   there   is   an   analogy   with   Peirce’s   indexical   signs   (secondness)   on   Panofsky’s   second   level   of  meaning;  indication  “focuses  attention”  and  connects  itself  with  other  experience  (Peirce  1998:8).  

 24  

conscious,  and  “fundamental  attitude  towards  the  world,”  capable  of  expressesing  the  

Weltanschauung  characteristic   “of   the   individual  producer,   the   individual  period,   the  

individual  people,  and  the  individual  cultural  community12”  (Panofsky  2012:  479).  Thus,  

the  focus  is  not  on  what  the  image  says  but  rather  how  the  message  is  made.  In  other  

words,   iconology   seeks   “the   fundamental   principles,”   deep   cultural   structures   that  

made  the  image,  i.e.  structures  that  underlie  not  only  “the  choice  and  presentation  of  

motifs  and  production”  but  also  “the  production  and  interpretation  of  images,  stories,  

and  allegories”  (Bourdieu  2005:  224).  The  problem  of  interpretation  of  intrinsic  mean-­‐

ing   lies,   however,   in   the   fact   that   its   source   is   “the   world-­‐view   of   the   interpreter,”  

which   is   also   a   fundamentally   subjective   source   of   knowledge   (Panofsky   2012:  480).  

Therefore,  interpretative  “violence”  must  be  kept  within  certain  boundaries  set  by  both  

interpreter’s  synthetic  intuition  (Panofsky  1955:  40–41)  and  “historically  situated  factu-­‐

ality,”  i.e.  “a  sense  of  general  intellectual  history  which  clarifies  what  was  possible  with-­‐

in   the   world-­‐view   of   any   specific   period   and   any   specific   cultural   circle”   (Panofsky  

2012:  480).  

In  general,  Panofsky’s   iconology   can  be   seen  as   a  movement   “from  surface   to  depth,  

from  sensations  to  ideas,  from  immediate  particulars  to  an  insight  into  the  way  ‘essen-­‐

tial  tendencies  of  the  human  mind  were  expressed  by  specific  themes  and  concepts,’”  as  

Mitchell  (1994:  26)  put  it.  In  1951,  Panofsky  published  his  Gothic  Architecture  and  Scho-­‐

lasticism  (1989)  and  showed  that   the   iconological  movement   “from  surface   to  depth”  

was  applicable  not  only  for  the  analysis  of  pictorial  art.  Instead,  he  used  iconology  to  

analyse  a  whole  architectonic   style,   for  he  was  convinced   that   there  was   “an  obvious  

and   barely   random   similarity   between   gothic   architecture   and   scholastic”   (Panofsky  

1989:  8).  For  Panofsky,  his  similarity  was  not  a  mere  result  of  parallel  development  of  

both.  He  assumed  that   there  was  rather  a   relationship  of  cause  and  effect,   i.e.   it  was  

                                                                                               

12  The  unreflected  character  of  intrinsic  meaning  is  reminiscent  of  Peirce’s  notion  of  symbols  (thirdness-­‐es)   that  are  also  conventional  and  dependent  upon  habit   (1998:9).  Sign  as  a   triad   itself  belongs   to   the  sphere   of   thirdness   that   is   “general,   timeless,   and   independent   of   subjective   thinking”   (Buczynska-­‐Garewicz  1979).  

 25  

the   scholastic   culture   that  made   the  birth  of   gothic   possible.  As  Bourdieu13   summed  

up,  

“Panofsky  shows  that  culture  is  not  just  a  common  code,  or  even  a  common   repertoire   to   answers   to   common   problems,   or   a   set   of  particular  and  particularized  forms  of  thought,  but  rather  a  whole  body  of  fundamental  schemes,  assimilated  beforehand,  that  gener-­‐ate  (...)  an  infinite  number  of  particular  schemes,  directly  applied  to  particular  situations.  This  habitus  could  be  defined  (...)  as  a  sys-­‐tem  of  internalized  schemes  that  have  the  capacity  to  generate  all  the  thoughts,  perceptions,  and  actions  characteristic  of  a  culture,  and  nothing  else.”  (Bourdieu  2005:  233)

1.2.2. Critique  of  Panofsky’s  method  Comments   on   and   critiques   of   Panofsky’s   iconology   come   from   various   intellectual  

positions  and  criticize  or  appreciate  different  aspects  of  his  thought.  The  first  problem  

touches   upon   the   character   of   the   relationship   between   texts   and   images.   There   are  

those  who  suggest  that  Panofsky  did  not  pay  enough  attention  to  keep  the  boundary  

between  images  and  texts  and  thus  caused  the  shift  of  importance  to  the  side  of  textu-­‐

ality  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009).  Mitchell  (1994)  criticizes  Panofsky  for  having  signifi-­‐

cantly   reduced   the   power   of   images   and   trying   to   develop   a   universal   template   for  

“reading”  them  as  text.  Belting  (Belting  2002:  15)  uses  the  same  argument  as  Mitchell  

and  notes  that  Panofsky  wanted  to  explain  visuality  through  textuality.  In  contrast  to  

that,  Przyborski  and  Slunecko   (2012:  44)  point  out   that  Panofsky’s  method  offered   “a  

certain  emancipation  from  the  model  of  text”  and  therefore  gained  central  importance  

in  cultural  and  social  research.  Bredekamp  too  assumes  that  iconology  treats  language  

rather  as  the  visual’s  counterpart  than  as  and  also  as  “a  ‘superior  self’  as  is  suggested  by  

the   theory   of   ‘image-­‐as-­‐text’  which   follows   the   ‘world-­‐as-­‐text’  metaphor”   (1995:  366).  

He  appreciates  the  tendency  of  Panofsky’s  iconology  to  “recognize  pictorial  forms  not  

only  as  carriers  of  linguistically  transmitted  meaning,  but  also,  and  above  all,  as  factors  

that  disturb  it”  (Bredekamp  1995:  366).  To  sum  up,  the  ambiguous  character  of  the  re-­‐

lation  of  texts  and  images  within  Panofsky’s  method  is  neatly  made  explicit  in  Binder’s  

                                                                                               

13  In  the  French  translation  of  Gothic  Architecture,  Pierre  Bourdieu  also  used  the  famous  term  habitus  (as  “princip  that  directs  action”  (Panofsky  1989:18)  for  the  first  time.  

 26  

term  for  iconology;  hermeneutics  of  the  visual  simultaneously  hints  Panofsky’s  concern  

about  the  textual  as  well  as  the  visual.  

The   second   often   criticized   aspect   of   Panofsky’s   iconology   is   its   neglectance   toward  

spectators.   “Panofsky   remains  blind   to  his   own   role   as   individual   interpreter   and   ig-­‐

nores   the   potential   meanings   that   paintings  might   hold   for   other   recipients,”   notes  

Binder  (2012:  103).  However,  there  is  a  passage  that  addresses  exactly  the  problem  of  an  

individual  interpreter  and  reflects  her  subjective  position:  “the  source  of  the  interpreta-­‐

tion  of  intrinsic  meaning  is  effectively  the  world-­‐view  of  the  interpreter  (...)  this  source  

of   knowledge   is   fundamentally   subjective,”   (Panofsky   2012:  480).   This   excerpt   rejects  

also  the  demur  by  Didi-­‐Huberman,  who  insists  that  “we  cannot  ignore  the  fact  that  we  

encounter  the  image  in  the  present”  (quoted  in  Moxey  2008:  135).  His  other  objection  

seems  to  be  more  plausible—he  points  out  that  Panofsky  did  not  pay  attention  to  spec-­‐

tator’s  response  to  work  of  art  and  was  trying  to  analyse  and  explain  the  work  by  refer-­‐

ring  to   its  circumstances  that  were  thought  of  as  being  more  stable  and   less  opaque,  

i.e.  to  the  underlying  structures  (Moxey  2008:  134–135)  .  Imdahl  stresses  a  similar  point  

and   notes   that   spectator’s   experience   has   not   been   taken   into   account   by   Panofsky  

(Imdahl  2006).  He  also   ignored  “the  genuinely  pictorial  aspects  of   the   image,”  which  

create  social  meanings  that  are  not  accessible  by  language  but  are  equally  fundamental  

(Przyborski   and   Slunecko   2012:  44),  what   prevented  him   also   from  gaining   access   to  

the  deeper  meanings  of  abstract  art.  

Third,   Bartmanski   (2012b:  5)   criticizes   Panofsky   for   having   treated   images   as   if   they  

were  mere  reflections  of  deep,  underlying  structures,  and  thus  the  question  asked  was  

not   what   and   how   images   do,   but   what   makes   them   and   why.   On   the   contrary,  

Bohnsack  (2007:  28–31)  understands  the  move  from  iconography  to  iconology  as  a  pas-­‐

sage  from  the  question  of  what  is  made  to  how  it  is  made.  Hence,  Bohnsack  does  not  

pose   any   implicit   question  of   intentionality   or   purpose   and   allows   also   for   inclusion  

and  consideration  of  images’  effects  on  viewing  subject  in  his  analysis.  

Finally,  Panofsky  is  accused  of  being  concerned  with  “delimited,  mostly  pictorial  artis-­‐

tic  representations  and  conventional  symbols”  (Bartmanski  2012b:  5),  instead  of  paying  

attention   to   visuality   in   general.   Yet   others   recognize  his   effort   to   inquire  not   solely  

 27  

about   images   but   also   in   other   forms   of   art,   e.g.  music   and   architecture   (Przyborski  

and  Slunecko  2012).  

After  Panofsky,  another  significant  and  inspiring  effort  to  push  the  theory  of  the  image  

further  was  made  by  Roland  Barthes.  For  he  was  not  an  art  historian  but  linguist  and  

semiotician,   he   did   not   use  works   of   fine   arts   for   study.   Instead,   Barthes   (1977)   em-­‐

ployed  advertising  pictures  in  his  analysis,  and  by  that  he  took  a  step  toward  the  theory  

of  the  image  and  the  visual  in  its  currently  popular  form.    

1.3. “Rhetorique  of  the  Image”  Barthes’s  insightful  writings  about  myths  and  ideologies  continue  to  influence  and  in-­‐

spire  disciplines  from  media  studies  to  sociology  (e.g.  Alexander  2003,  2008  &  2010b).  

His  work  is,  nonetheless,  remarkable  also  from  the  point  of  view  of  image  interpreta-­‐

tion,  for  he  focused  his  analytical  effort  on  “reading”  the  visual.  Drawing  on  his  semio-­‐

logical  background,  Barthes  made  an  effort  in  decoding  the  messages  carried  by  imag-­‐

es.  He  chose  advertising  images  for  the  analysis,  since  he  was  convinced  that  the  signs  

contained  in  this  kind  of   images  are  used  intentionally  to  construct  the  desired  mes-­‐

sage  and  thereby  they  transmit  meanings  as  clearly  as  possible.  

On  one  hand,  Barthes  makes  a  distinction  between  image  and  text  based  on  their  qual-­‐

ities  and  the  way  how  they  create  meaning.  While  images  are  polysemous,  possess  pro-­‐

jective  powers  and  transmit  the  meanings  they  carry  simultaneously,  texts  are  sequen-­‐

tial,   have   a   repressive   value   and   are   able   to   limit   the   polysemy   of   images   (Barthes  

1977:  38–39)  .  On  the  other  hand,  he  suggests  that  it  is  possible  to  understand  images  

in  the  very  same  way  as  we  do  with  texts;  the  tendency  to  narrow  images  down  to  the  

textual  level    and  to  make  them  readable  implies  already  the  name  chosen  for  his  es-­‐

say:  Rhetorique  of  the  Image  (1977;  cf.  Bartmanski  2012b).  “An  image  is  more  persuasive  

than  writing,   its  meaning  hits  us  at  once,  without  being  put   in  order  and  distributed  

spatially.   It  makes  no   important  difference  any   longer,   though.  As  soon  as  the   image  

contains  meaning,  it  becomes  writing;  as  writing  it  requires  a  Lexis.”  (Barthes  2012:  253,  

italics  in  original)  

 28  

In  the  course  of  analysis  of  advertising  images,  Barthes  (1977)  distinguishes  three  types  

of   messages   one   can   find   in   a   single   photography:   linguistic   message,   coded   iconic  

message   and   analogical   representation14.   The   image   as   such   contains   the   latter   two  

messages  that  are,  however,  on  the  empirical  level,  i.e.  in  the  course  of  ordinary  read-­‐

ing,  not  separated;  "the  viewer  of  the  image  receives  at  one  and  the  same  time  the  per-­‐

ceptual  message  and  the  cultural  message”  (Barthes  1977:  35–37,  italics  in  original).  In  

other  words,   although  we   see  one   single   image,   it   is  necessary   to   analytically  distin-­‐

guish   between   literal   and   symbolic   image,  while   this   distinction   is   analogous   to   the  

one  between  signifier  and  signified  within  a  sign  (1.1).  

In   order   to   be   able   to   “read”   and   understand   the   literal   or   perceptual   image,   all   we  

need  is  a  basic  knowledge  of  what  an  image  is  and  what  objects  it  depicts.  The  literal  

image  of  a  given  object  is  not  “arbitrary,”  it  is  denoted,  since  the  photograph  seems  to  

mechanically  represent  the  untransformed  reality,  and  therefore  to  be  a  message  with-­‐

out  a  code15.  At  the  same  time,  the  symbolic  or  cultural  image  contains  a  coded  iconic  

message—it  is  connoted.  What  is  more,  it  uses  the  literal  image  to  support  the  symbol-­‐

ic  message,  which  lifts  it  up  onto  a  higher  level  of  meaning—it  is  “a  system  which  takes  

over   the   signs   of   another   system   in  order   to  make   them   its   signifiers   in   a   system  of  

connotation,”  (Barthes  1977:  35–37)  or  to  put  it  differently,  it  is  a  myth.  Barthes  (2012)  

defines  myth  as  a  construction  consisting  of  form  and  concept  that  can  be  described  as  

equivalents  of  Saussurean  signifier  and  signified  within  a  sign.  Myth  is,  in  fact,  a  sign  of  

second-­‐order  operating  on   the   level  of  meta-­‐language,  while  using   the   sign   from  the  

first  order  as  its  form.  The  trick  is,  nevertheless,  not  new—the  relation  between  form  

and  concept  is,  as  well  as  in  Saussurean  model  of  a  sign,  not  naturally  given,  but  cul-­‐

                                                                                               

14  The  level  of  connotation  corresponds  to  Panofsky’s  level  of  iconography  (1.2),  while  the  denoted,  literal  meaning  has  its  analogue  in  Panofsky’s  level  of  phenomenal  meaning  (Bohnsack  2009:305).  

15  A  photograph  is  here  opposed  to  a  drawing,  which  is  already  a  coded  message;  “the  denotation  of  the  drawing   is   less   pure   than   that   of   the   photograph,   for   there   is   no   drawing   without   style”   (Barthes  1977:277).  Contrary  to  that,  the  current  scholarly  assumption  is  rather  that  a  photograph  has  “exactly  as  many  ways  to  picture  the  world  as  painting  had  before”  (Belting  2000:  163).  

 29  

turally   constructed16.   Mythical   concepts   can   therefore   build   themselves   up,   change,  

collapse  or  disappear;  since  they  are  historical,  history  can  also  defeat  them  quite  easily  

(Barthes  2012:  266).  

However,   Barthes’s   effort   in   “reading”   images   ends   on   the   level   of   connotations;   he  

considers   the   complexity   of   meaning   characteristic   of   images   unverbalizable  

(Bohnsack   2009:  308).  Having   deciphered   the   connotative  meaning   he   thus   turns   to  

the  textual  knowledge  and  follows  the  path  of  myth  and  its  deconstruction  instead.  

1.4. Consequences  of  the  linguistic  turn  Already  the  fact  that  above  mentioned  scholars  are  the  only  ones  who  provide  inspira-­‐

tion  for  contemporary  study  of   images  shows  how  far-­‐reaching  the  impact  of  the  lin-­‐

guistic  turn  was.  The  emphasis  was  put  on  “the  significance  of  language  and  interpreta-­‐

tion  for  human  social  life,  and  thus  for  the  study  of  human  social  life  as  well”  (Wagner  

2008:  247).    

Comprehending   the  world   as   language   that   resulted   in   a   search   for  meaning  within  

linguistic  occurrences  had  influence  also  on  scientific  attitude  toward  images.  The  re-­‐

sults  of  considering   language   to  be   the  ultimate  creative   force   (Alexander  and  Smith  

2003:  25)  had  a  deep  impact  also  on  sociological  methodology;  although  there  has  been  

a  considerable  progress  in  methods  of  interpretation,  pictures  have  been  broadly  mar-­‐

ginalized  (Bohnsack  2009:  297).  

A   strong   counter-­‐reaction   to   the   “language-­‐is-­‐everything”   approach   appeared   almost  

thirty  years  after  Rorty’s   turn,  at   the  peak  of  “postmodern”  era,  as  McLuhan’s  “global  

village”  came  true  and  the  culture  found  itself  dominated  by  images  (Mitchell  1994:  15).  

For  art  historian  W.  J.  T.  Mitchell,  the  need  for  a  shift  of  scholarly  interest  and  perspec-­‐

tive  was  fueled  by  the  fact  that  the  

                                                                                               

16   Barthes   actually   points   to   the   role   of   ideology   in   creating  myths   and  believes   that   they   are   created  intentionally   (1977,   2012).  However,   the   suggested   ideological   background   of  mythical   structures   only  proves  that  the  character  of  the  relation  between  myth’s  form  and  concept  is  conventional.    

 30  

“picture  now  has  a  status  somewhere  between  what  Thomas  Kuhn  called  a   ‘paradigm’  and  an   ‘anomaly’,  emerging  as  a  central  topic  of  discussion  in  the  human  sciences  in  the  way  that  language  did:  that  is,  as  a  kind  of  model  or  figure  for  other  things  (including  fig-­‐uration   itself),  and  as  an  unsolved  problem,  perhaps  even  the  ob-­‐ject   of   its   own   ‘science’,  what   Erwin  Panofsky   called   an   ‘iconolo-­‐gy’.”  (1994:  13)  

1.5. Pictorial  turn  Mitchell  was  convinced  that  there  was  a  certain  anxiety  concerning  images  in  texts  by  

Wittgenstein,  which  he   interpreted   as   iconophobia   and  need   to   “defend   ‘our   speech’  

against   ‘the  visual’”   (1994:  12–13)   .  He  understood  these  claims  as   indicators  of  a  new,  

pictorial  turn  that  was  taking  place  in  human  sciences:  

“(W)hile   the  problem  of   pictorial   representation  has  always  been  with  us,  it  presses  inescapably  now,  and  with  unprecedented  force,  on  very  level  of  culture,  from  the  most  refined  philosophical  specu-­‐lations  to  the  most  vulgar  productions  of   the  mass  media.  Tradi-­‐tional  strategies  of  containment  no  longer  seem  adequate,  and  the  need   for   a   global   critique   of   visual   culture   seems   inescapable.”  (Mitchell  1994:  16)  

In  other  words,  Mitchell  wanted   to  win  broader  attention   for   the  visual.  Methods  of  

“reading”  or  interpreting  images  that  were  already  at  hand  he  found  rather  unsatisfac-­‐

tory—though  they  dealt  with  spectatorship  and  various  forms  of  reading,  for  Mitchell  

it   was   unacceptable   to   explain   such   phenomena   “on   the   model   of   textuality17”  

(1994:  16).  Although  the  society  of  that  time  was  often  described  as  one  of  “spectacle”  

and   “surveillance”   (which   are   both   vision-­‐based  metaphors),   there   was   a   significant  

lack   of   knowledge   about   images   and  Mitchell   thus   complained   that   “we   still   do   not  

know  exactly  what  pictures  are,  what  their  relation  to  language  is,  how  they  operate  on  

observers  and  on   the  world   (...)”   (1994:  13).  Mitchell’s   goal  was,  however,  not  only   to  

emancipate  images  from  logos,  but  also  to  give  them  absolute  precedence  (1994:  28f.).  

What  is  also  important  and  distinctive  in  Mitchell’s  approach  is  the  fact  that  he  refused  

to  restrict  his  study  to  images  to  art  (Moxey  2008:  135).  

                                                                                               

17  Especially  critical  was  Mitchell  to  Panofsky’s  model  of  interpretation  (2005:49,  see  also  1.2.2).  

 31  

One  of  Mitchell’s   inspirations  was   the  book  Ways  of  worldmaking     (1978),  where   the  

American  philosopher  Nelson  Goodman,  at  that  time  strongly  influenced  by  Ernst  Cas-­‐

sirer’s  work,  discussed  the  role  symbols  play  in  the  processes  of  worldmaking,  i.e.  the  

creation   of   meaningful   worlds   ‘from   nothing’.   Borrowing   Goodman’s   vocabulary  

Mitchell  insists  that  pictures  enable  us  to  gain  access  to  events  and  practices  and  that  

they  are  “‘ways  of  worldmaking’,  not  just  world  mirroring”  (Mitchell  2005:xiv–xv)  .  That  

is  also  the  reason  why  for  Mitchell,  the  iconological  intepretation  in  its  form  as  intro-­‐

duced  by  Panofsky  is  not  a  way  how  to  disentangle  webs  of  meaning  contained  within  

images;  he  sees  it  rather  as  a  kind  of  ideology.  It  is  nothing  more  than  a  “system  of  nat-­‐

uralization,  a  homogenizing  discourse  that  effaces  conflict  and  difference  with  figures  

of   ‘organic   unity’   and   ‘synthetic   intuition’,”   he   assumes   (Mitchell   1994:  30).  What   is  

need  to  be  done,  then,  is  “to  unweave  this  tapestry”  of  “symbolic  forms,”  which  synthe-­‐

tize   vision,   and   space   as  well   as  world-­‐   and   art-­‐pictures   and  which  were   elaborated  

within  Panofsky’s   iconology—only  after  that  can  pictorial  turn  accomplish  Panofsky’s  

ambitions  for  a  critical  iconology  (Mitchell  1994:  19).  Therefore,  pictures  were  no  long-­‐

er  treated  as  mere  passive  reflections  of  reality;   the  accent  put  on  their  active  role   in  

worldmaking   (one  can  also  use   the   term  meaning-­‐making)  made   them,   in  Mitchell’s  

theory,  legitimate  participants  in  social  life18.  

The  rather  postmodern  character  of  Mitchell’s  picture  theory  becomes  also  evident  as  

soon  as  we  consider  how  deliberately  he  subjectivizes  and  personificates  pictures  and  

argues  that  they  have  desires  (which   is  already   indicated  by  the  book’s   title  What  do  

pictures  want?),  while  at   the  same  time   the  way  he  suggests   for  understanding   them  

reminds  of  Latour’s   (2005)  notion  of  objects’   agency:   “What  pictures  want   is  not   the  

same  as   the  message   they  communicate  or   the  effect   they  produce;   it’s  not  even   the  

same  as  what  they  say  they  want.  Like  people,  pictures  may  not  know  what  they  want,  

                                                                                               

18  In  order  to  show  that  even  though  people  tend  to  disrespect  those  who  believe  pictures  “are  alive  and  want   things”   (Mitchell   2005:  7)  and  no  one   thinks  pictures   should  be   treated   like  persons,   “we  always  seem  to  be  willing  to  make  exceptions  for  special  cases”  (ibid.:  31).  In  other  words,  “when  students  scoff  at  the  idea  of  a  magical  relation  between  a  picture  and  what  it  represents,  ask  them  to  take  a  photograph  of  their  mother  and  cut  off  the  eyes.”  (ibid.:9)  

 32  

they   have   to   be   helped   to   recollect   it   through   a   dialogue   with   others.”   (Mitchell  

2005:  46)  

The  most  problematic  part  of  Mitchell’s  approach  seems  to  be  his  method  for  finding  

out  what  effects  pictures  have  on  human  behavior,  since  there  is  none.  On  one  hand,  

he   claims  his   aim   is   “to  undermine   the   ready-­‐made   template   for   interpretative  mas-­‐

tery”  (2005:  49),  by  which  he  means  psychoanalytical,  materialist  or  Panofsky’s  model.  

On   the   other   hand,   he   does   not   offer   any   substitute   for   these   abandoned  methods.  

What   is  more,   the   insistence  on   considering  pictures   independently   of   language,   for  

they  have  “a  presence  that  escapes  our  linguistic  ability  to  describe  or  interpret”  (Mox-­‐

ey  2008:  135)  practically  deprives  him  of  the  possibility  to  say  (or,  in  this  case,  to  write)  

anything  about  them.  Also,  even  though  Mitchell  explicitly  states  that  he  wants  to  step  

back  from  questions  of  meaning  and  power  that  were  in  picture  analysis  usually  taken  

into  consideration,  his  effort  to  find  out  what  pictures  want  eventually  employs  exactly  

the   old,   criticized   methods   borrowed   from   linguistics,   semiotics,   hermeneutics   and  

rhetoric   (Mitchell   2005:  46).   Unfortunately,   a   certain  methodological   vagueness   pre-­‐

vents  Mitchell  from  offering  any  plausible  interpretation  or  understanding  of  pictures  

eventually;  he   sticks  with  mere   suggestions  of  possible  meanings  one  could   find  and  

subsequently  lets  the  reader  decide  which  one  she  prefers  (Mitchell  2005:  50).  How  are  

we  then  supposed  to  accept  such  bold  statements  as  “(i)mages  are  active  players  in  the  

game  of  establishing  and  changing  values”  (Mitchell  2005:  105),  if  everyone  is  allowed  

to   decide   freely   what   kind   of   message   he   wants   to   find   in   a   picture?   At   this   point  

Mitchell  seems  to  be  sinking  into  Baudrillardian  thinking  characteristic  of  “floating”  or  

“empty”   signifiers.   Supposed   that   values   are   shared,   collective   representations,   one  

should   be   able   to   identify   shared  meanings   that  would   be   portrayed   and   also   trans-­‐

ferred   by   images,   in   order   to   demonstrate   that   pictures   actually   have   the   power   to  

shape  peoples’  values.  Otherwise,  everything  we  are  left  with  is  just  an  ephemeral  im-­‐

pression   of   the   elusive   power   of   pictures   that   can  never   be   reduced   to   or   translated  

into   language.   It   seems   that   images  used   to  be   the  victims  of   rationalizing   linguistic  

turn;   after   Mitchell’s   postmodern   crusade   that   he—in   reaction   to   Panofsky—called  

critical   iconology,   language   became   the   defeated:   “If   traditional   iconology   repressed  

the  image,  postmodern  iconology  represses  language.”  (Mitchell  1994:  28f.)  

 33  

1.6. Iconic  turn  A  less  radical  approach  to  theorizing  about  images  was  suggested  in  the  1990s  by  Ger-­‐

man   art   historian  Gottfried  Boehm,  who  became   a  protagonist   of   a   so   called   “iconic  

turn”.  Boehm  spent,  according  to  his  own  words,  around  twenty  years  trying  to  answer  

one  question,  which  became  the  central  problem  of  his  research,  namely  “how  do  im-­‐

ages   create  meaning?”   (Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:  106).  Despite   the   fact   of   linguistic  

domination  during  much  of   the   20th   century,   studies   in   art  history  were   still   carried  

out.  However,  Boehm  is  rather  skeptical   to  the  widely  used  method  of   interpretation  

from  Panofsky  and  criticizes  him  for  having  caused  a  shift  of  balance  between  image  

and  text  “to  the  side  of  textuality”  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  107),  which  was  also  the  

point   of  Mitchell’s   (1994)   critique.   In   the   centre   of  Boehm’s   interest   is   the  puzzle   of  

non-­‐verbal  experience  provided  by  images,  which  was  logically  ignored  by  linguistical-­‐

ly   oriented   research.   Boehm   nevertheless   self-­‐reflexively   remarks   that   “image   is   not  

simply   some   new   topic,   but   relates   much   more   to   a   different   mode   of   thinking”  

(Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:  104).   The  motivation   for   his   iconic   turn  was   an   effort   to  

understand   images   as   iconic   “logos”,   in   the   sense   of   a   meaning-­‐generating   process  

(Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:  105).   In   other  words,   “iconic   turn   stems   from   the  notion  

that   images   evade   any   linguistic   logic   and   since   they   cannot  be  understood   through  

anything  else  they  have  to  be  understood  from  themselves”  (Binder  2013:  78).  

Therefore,  Boehm’s  vision  of   ideal   icono-­‐logy,  which  art  history  should  strive  for,  dif-­‐

fers   from  Panofsky’s   iconological   interpretation;  optimally,   it  would   seek   “the  under-­‐

standing   and   interpretation   of   the   logos   of   the   image   in   its   historical,   perception-­‐

oriented   and   meaning-­‐saturated   determinedness”   (Boehm   and   Mitchell   2009:  107).  

This  claim  makes  it  clear  that  Boehm’s  iconic  turn  is  not  based  on  a  “fundamental  op-­‐

position  to  the  linguistic  turn”  as  Mitchell’s  pictorial  turn  was19,  for  he  does  not  suggest  

repressing  the  language.  Rather,  based  on  his  notion  of  iconology  that  takes  into  con-­‐

sideration  the  embededness  of  images  in  various  contexts  (but  refuses  to  deduce  imag-­‐

es  from  these),  Boehm  tries  to  emancipate  images  from  language  and  also  accentuate                                                                                                  

19  “When  the  iconic  is  invoked,  it  never  implies  a  withdrawal  from  language,  but  rather  that  a  difference  vis  à  vis  language  comes  into  play.”  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  107,  italics  in  original)  

 34  

the   up   to   now   neglected   image   theory   (2009:  105–107).   On   the   other   hand,   Boehm  

(Boehm  2006)  also  insists  that  there  are  certain  categorical  differences  between  images  

and  texts  that  cannot  be  overcome,  since  words  can  never  grasp  exactly  what  an  image  

expresses.  The  closest  as  language  can  get  to  image  is  in  a  metaphor,  whose  structural  

qualities   are   comparable   with   those   of   images   (Boehm   2006:  26).   Since   a   metaphor  

carries  multiplicity  of  meanings  and  has  no  conclusion,  which  makes  it  a  linguistic  im-­‐

age,  it  cannot  be  translated  into  “normal”  language.  In  Roland  Barthes’s  words,  Boehm  

was   one   of   “those  who   think   that   signification   cannot   exhaust   the   image’s   ineffable  

richness”   (1977:  32).   On   the   other   hand,   contrary   to   Barthes   Boehm   and   others  

acknowledge  the  possibility  of  image  interpretation:  “What  a  sentence  can,  that  must  

be  also  for  pictorial  works  available,  however,   in  its  own  way”  (Boehm  2006:  31,  italics  

added).  

1.6.1. Iconic  difference  Boehm  stresses   that   the  use  of   the  terms   iconic  and  the   Iconic  within  his   iconic   turn  

has  nothing   in  common  with  Peirce’s  notion  of   icon  as  a  pictorial  sign20   (Boehm  and  

Mitchell  2009:  108).  For  Boehm,  the  term  iconic  marks  an  image21  simultaneously  as  an  

object  and  as  a  process  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  108),  since  his  goal  was  to  “under-­‐                                                                                                

20  Interestingly  enough,  at  the  same  place  Boehm  also  quotes  a  sentence  from  a  German  translation  of  Peirce’s  work  saying  that  an  icon  doesn’t  necessarily  take  up  a  visual  form  and  may  therefore  be  a  purely  imaginative   image   (Boehm   and   Mitchell   2009:108).   Consequently,   Mitchell   in   his   answer   corrects  Boehm’s  understanding  of  Peirce   and  writes:   “I  wonder   if   there   is  not   a  hidden  conceptual   resonance  between  Peirce  and  Imdahl  on  the  icon  as  a  ‘firstness’,  a  phenomenological  apprehension  of  immediate  sensuous  quali-­‐ties  as  the  foundational  moment  in  aesthetics,  epistemology,  and  semiotics,  not  to  men-­‐tion  in  Panofsky’s  version  of  the  first  stage  of  iconological  interpre-­‐tation  (the  pre-­‐iconographic  moment  of  sensuous  encounter).  I  don’t  know  Imdahl’s  work  very  well,  but  I  gather  that  his  concept  of  the  iconic  is   based   in   ‘the  direct  phenomenal   experience  of   the  plastic/formal   structure  of   an   artwork’,   a  notion  that  is  remarkably  similar  to  Peirce’s  iconic  ‘firstness’.”  (ibid:  119).  

21  Since  Boehm’s  work  is  written  mostly  in  German,  it  is  probably  convenient  to  start  with  a  clarification  of   two  basic   terms.  German   language  does  not  make  any  difference  between  English  terms   image  and  picture,  both  are  called  Bild.  As  Belting  Belting  2002:  15  notes,  pictures  should  be  seen  as  physical  imag-­‐es,  concrete  objects  of  representation,  which  make  images  appear.  This  (not  existing)  distinction  makes  translation  from  German  into  English  problematic,  since  it  always  poses  the  question  if  one  talks  about  material  picture  or   its  mental   representation  (concept  or  notion).  On  the  other  hand,   for  German  au-­‐thors  it  is  sometimes  convenient  to  be  able  to  use  only  one  term  for  “the  principle,  its  manifestation,  and  the  inner  representation”  (Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012:  40)  and  thus  they  often  neglect  the  distinction,  as   was   the   case   in   Boehm’s  Wiederkehr   der   Bilder   (Moxey   2008:  136).   However,   later   in   his   letter   to  Mitchell   Boehm   explained   his   perspective   and   also   from   the   broader   context   it   is   clear   that   Boehm  (2006)  refers  to  images  and  to  the  visual  in  general  (cf.  Moxey  2008).  

 35  

stand  images  in  view  of  an  implicit  processuality,”  for  which  he  developed  a  concept  of  

iconic   difference,  which  makes   it   possible   to   understand   images  without   any   help   of  

linguistic  or  rhetorical  models  and  devices  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  110).  Inspired  by  

Saussure’s  semiotic  difference22,  which  describes  the  fact  that  words  gain  meanings  not  

from  their  similarity  with  the  world  but  from  mutual  internal  oppositions  within  sign  

systems,   iconic   difference   marks   the   notion   that   “also   the   image   does   not   owe   its  

‘meaning’  to  similarity  with  the  real  world,  but  equally  to  purely  internal  visual  opposi-­‐

tions”  (Beyst  2010).  Thus,   image  becomes  a  self-­‐referential  system.  For  when  we  con-­‐

sider,  for  example,  abstract  art,  we  come  to  a  conclusion  that  it  is  actually  able  not  only  

to  produce  meanings  without  referring  to  any  object  in  reality  but  also  “to  surpass  the  

known  Real”   (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  106).   In  other  words,  Boehm  draws  a  differ-­‐

ence  between  mere  physical  seeing  and  viewing,  which  encompasses  the  construction  

of   meaning—as   he   puts   it,   “(t)he   view   triumphs   over   the   eye”   (Über   das   Auge   tri-­‐

umphiert  der  Blick.  (Boehm  2006:  25)).  

However,  Boehm  (Boehm  2006:  30)  himself  is  using  the  concept  of  iconic  difference  in  

(at  least)  two  diverse  ways,  as  Beyst  (2010)  pointed  out  (cf.  also  Binder  2013):  in  the  first  

definition  Boehm  stays  “on  the  surface”  and  defines  iconic  difference  as  a  relationship  

between  material  carrier  of  the  image  and  its  meaning,  between  the  lines  and  stains  of  

the   image  and  what  they  turn  out  to  show  as  something  meaningful,  or  between  the  

“figure   and   background”,   i.e.   the   details   of   the   image   and   its   whole.   In   the   second  

meaning,  iconic  difference  refers  to  the  relation  between  image  and  its  referent  in  real-­‐

ity  (Beyst  2010):  “content  that  means  something  absent  is  raised  by  iconic  difference,  in  

which   it   becomes   visible”   (Boehm  2007:  38).  On  one  hand,   “both   interpretations   are  

intertwined:  when  the  material  substrate  remains  visible,  the  representation  comes  to  

differ  from  the  model  in  the  real  world”  (Beyst  2010).  On  the  other  hand,  the  result  of  

the  fact  that  Boehm  does  not  distinguish  between  these  two  meanings  is  that  he  fails  

to  recognize  mirror  images  or  photographs  as  images,  and  misses  the  point  of  under-­‐

                                                                                               

22  Although  Boehm  explicitly  refers  to  an  analogy  of  his  iconic  difference  to  Heidegger’s  ontological  dif-­‐ference  (Boehm  2006:  30),  art  historian  Stefan  Beyst  (2010)  points  to  its  similarity  to  the  semiotic  differ-­‐ence  known  from  Saussure.  

 36  

standing  image  as  a  combination  of  “iconic  identity,”  based  on  mere  visual  similarity  to  

reality,   as   well   as   “iconic   difference,”   which   refers   to   the   fact   that   although   visually  

similar,  images  are  not  similar  to  other  senses:  “whoever  wants  to  touch  his  mirror  im-­‐

age  stumbles  on  the  surface  of  the  mirror,  not  on  a  body,  and  knows  precisely  there-­‐

fore  that  he  is  dealing  with  an  image,  not  with  the  real  thing”  (Beyst  2010).  Despite  the  

confusion   caused   by   Boehm’s   vague   definition   (or   rather   because   of   it),   the   term   of  

iconic  difference  became  quite  encompassing  and  gained  a  broad  variety  of  meanings  

in  later  research.  One  of  the  possible  interpretations  builds  an  insurmountable  bound-­‐

ary   between   image   and   text   (see   Binder   2012:  102),   which   is   also   one   of   the   main  

thoughts  expressed  in  Boehm’s  work  as  well  as  in  other  contributions  in  his  anthology  

Was  ist  ein  Bild?  The  problem  of  the  relationship  between  text  and  image  is  also  cen-­‐

tral  in  Max  Imdahl’s  work.  

For  Imdahl,  image  has  a  unique  expressive  quality  that  mediates  meaning  and  that  also  

cannot   be   substituted   by   anything   else   (Imdahl   2006:  300).   In   other   words,   “in   art  

there  are  experiences  and  meanings  present,  that  one  cannot  gain  without  it”  (Greub  

2001:  20).   This   distinctive   characteristic   (unverwechselbare   Eigenart)   of   an   image   is  

considered  to  be  the  effect  of  its  iconic  meaning  structure  (ikonische  Sinnstruktur).  In  

order  to  grasp  image’s  distinctiveness,  Imdahl  suggests  a  new  method—iconic  (Ikonik),  

which   Panofsky   in   his   three-­‐leveled  model   left   out.  While   Panofsky’s  model   doesn’t  

allow  us  to  interpret  abstract  images  (or  leads  inevitably  to  the  conclusion  that  every  

abstract   image   is   trivial),   Imdahl’s   iconic   enables   the   spectator   or   interpreter   to   use  

creative  potential   and   fantasy   and  makes   and   effort   to   involve   the   experience  of   the  

spectator  (Imdahl  2006:  315–318).  The  notion  of  iconic  meaning  contains  a  reflection  of  

what  image  depicts  as  well  as  of  the  possibilities  of  image  as  such.  An  image’s  character  

differs   categorically   from   narrative   succession   and   also   from   empirical   event   experi-­‐

ence  and  does  not  allow  us  to  narrate  it.  This  specific  feature  is  called  scenic  simultane-­‐

ity  (ibid.:  308ff.).  In  other  words,  thanks  to  its  scenic  simultaneity,  an  image  provides  

the  spectator  with  a  unique  notion  of  the  interrelations  among  its  elements,  but  at  the  

same  time  simultaneity  makes  it  also  impossible  to  find  any  linguistic  substitution  for  

the  image’s  iconic  meaning  structure,  to  translate  it  into  any  language  expression  or  to  

narrate   it   as   a  process.   Scenic   simultaneity   is   therefore  opposed   to   linguistic   succes-­‐

 37  

siveness,  typical  of  texts.  Further  Imdahl  points  out  that  although  the  interpretation  of  

images  is  always  inevitably  linguistic,  it  still  cannot  fully  grasp  the  specific  simultaneity  

that  helps  us  understand  the  image,  i.e.  the  iconic  (ibid.:  310).  

Boehm  himself  made  a  similar  point  as  Imdahl  in  his  letter  to  W.J.T.  Mitchell,  where  

he  mentioned   “intelligence  of   images,”  which   is  based  on   “their   respective   visual   or-­‐

der.”  However,  as  from  the  rest  of  the  letter  becomes  clear,  even  twelve  years  after  the  

original  publication  of  Was  ist  ein  Bild?  the  image’s  specifics  remains  rather  unresolved  

and  somehow  mysterious;  we  still  do  not  know  how  we  should  understand  the  specific  

visual  order,  what  are   its  rules  and  what   is   the  role  played  by   individuality   in  under-­‐

standing   images   (Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:  110).   Some   ideas   of   Boehm’s   iconic   turn  

have  been   subsequently   adopted  by   the   strong  programme   in   cultural   sociology   and  

used  for  the  formulation  of  iconic  theory  (see  Alexander  2008,  2010,  2012,  Bartmanski  

2012).  Its  protagonists  have  nevertheless  made  some  changes  to  the  original  approach,  

e.g.  the  initial   inspiration  by  Panofsky’s  interpretation  (Boehm  2006)  was  turned  into  

an   explicit   categorical   rejection   (Bartmanski   2012:  5).   As   I   will   show   in   the   second  

chapter,   this   iconic   theory   formulates  new  problems,  or   rather   re-­‐formulates   the  old  

ones,  and  with   its  emphasis  of   the  emotional  aspect  of  contact  with   images  (and  the  

material  in  general)  reminds  of  Mitchell’s  (2005)  question  What  and  how  images  do?.  

 

 38  

“Stuff  matters.”  

Jeffrey  C.  Alexander,  2010  

 39  

2  Iconicity  and  the  strong    

programme  in  cultural  sociology  

In   this   chapter,   I   present   a   brief   introduction   to   the   cultural   sociological   notion   of  

iconic   theory.   Therefore   it   is   convenient   to   start  more   generally   and   to   provide   the  

reader  with  the  key  ideas  that  are  at  the  basis  of  the  strong  programme  in  cultural  so-­‐

ciology   as   it   was   formulated   by   Phillip   Smith   and   Jeffrey   Alexander   (Alexander   and  

Smith  2003).  The  core  ideas  and  concepts  used  by  this  relatively  young  approach  will  

be  touched  upon  in  order  to  show  how  and  why  it  was  fruitful  and  possible  to  shift  the  

attention  of  cultural  sociology  to  iconicity.  In  fact,  Alexander  and  others  have  recently  

made   a   significant   effort   to   adopt   and   reformulate   some   features   of   the   iconic   turn  

proposed  by  Boehm  and  also  to  include  them  into  the  core  fields  of  interest  for  cultural  

sociology.  This  new  point  of  departure  brought,  however,  not  only  opening  of  new  ho-­‐

rizons  for  us  and  the  opportunity  to  ask  fresh  and  different  question  about  social   life  

that  can  be  now  answered  in  a  different  way.  Quite  expectedly,  by  virtue  of  its  novelty  

and   focus   on   materiality,   which   is   for   sociology   an   extremely   undertheorized   field,  

iconic  theory  brings  also  many  questions  about  its  own  character,  concerning  its  rela-­‐

tion   to   the   German   iconic   turn   as   well   as   to   American   pictorial   turn   proposed   by  

Mitchell,  while  some  of  the  key  problems  seem  to  go  much  deeper  into  the  history  of  

 40  

scholarly  inquiry  about  images.  My  argument  will  be  thus  developed  in  following  steps:  

1)  I  briefly  present  the  main  ideas  of  the  strong  programme  by  Alexander  and  Smith  in  

order  to  shed   light  on  the  character  of   topics  and  research   interests  as  well  as  of   the  

nature  of  answers  it  suggests.  2)  I  introduce  the  theory  of  iconic  power  stemming  from  

the  main  ideas  of  the  strong  programme  and  its  main  goals.  3)  By  summing  up  Alexan-­‐

der’s  writings  about   iconicity  published  since  2008   I   suggest  a  notion  of  Alexandrian  

icon  and  its  distinctive  features.  4)  I  connect  the  notion  of  Alexander’s  icon  to  a  broad-­‐

er  network  of  cultural  sociological  concepts  and  show  why  iconic  power  is  believed  to  

provide  a  missing  link  in  the  social  theory  and  5)  I  sum  up  its  benefits.  The  emergent  

problems  and  puzzles  raised  by  the  iconic  theory  are  addressed  in  the  last  chapter.  

2.1. Strong  programme  In   the   founding  article  of   cultural   sociology,  Smith  and  Alexander  published  a   sharp  

polemic  aimed  at  hitherto  existing  sociological  understandings  and  studies  of  culture.  

In  answer  to  Alexander’s  (1988)  call  for  a  conception  of  robust  culture,  they  rejected  all  

opinions  suggesting  that  “culture  is  something  to  be  explained,  by  something  else  en-­‐

tirely  separated  from  the  domain  of  meaning  itself,”  that  “explanatory  power  lies  in  the  

study  of   the   ‘hard’   variables  of   social   structure,”   or   in  which   culture   is   “more  or   less  

confined   to  participating   in   the   reproduction  of   social   relations,”  and   introduced   the  

concept   of   cultural   autonomy   (Alexander   and   Smith   2003:  12–13).   While   the   former  

approaches  were   labeled  as  “weak”,   the  newly   introduced  theory  arguing  for  “a  sharp  

analytical  uncoupling  of  culture   from  social   structure”  was   referred   to  as   “strong”.   In  

other  words,  although  both  types  of  theory  are  devoted  to  studying  culture,  the  weak  

or  sociology-­‐of  approach  pays  attention  to  the  effects  of  collective  meanings,  explains  

how   meanings   are   created,   and   is   interested   in   how   the   structures   of   culture   are  

formed  by  other,  more  material,  less  ephemeral  structures.  Contrary  to  that,  the  strong  

programme  focuses  on  interpreting  collective  meanings  and  makes  collective  emotions  

and  ideas  central  “precisely  because   it   is  such  subjective  and  internal   feelings  that  so  

often  seems  to  rule  the  world”  (Alexander  2003:  5).  In  other  words,  culture  is  treated  as  

more  than  just  an  environment  for  social  action,  but  it  is  rather  considered  a  source  of  

 41  

motivation  working   through  “emotions,  classification,  and  collective  action”   (Alexan-­‐

der  and  Smith  2005:  13–14).    

The   new   interpretation   of   Durkheim’s   Elementary   Forms   equipped   the   strong   pro-­‐

gramme  in  such  a  significant  way  that  one  could  paraphrase  Alexander’s  claim  about  

cultural  turn  and  state  that  cultural  sociology  owes  everything  to  Durkheim  (ibid.:  12).  

It  is  not  only  the  conceptual  toolbox,  but  also  the  core  ideas  in  the  very  heart  of  cultur-­‐

al   sociology   that   stem   from   Elementary   Forms.   By   stressing   the   symbolic   nature   of  

modern  social  order  and  of  social  structure  constructed  by  deep  solidarities  based  on  

the  master  binary  of  sacred  and  profane,  the  sociological  focus  moved  explicitly  from  

“decoding  culture  as  text”  to  payig  attention  to  cultural  symbolic  forms  and  their  im-­‐

pact  on  society  (Alexander  and  Smith  2005).  

Since  the  way  how  culture  influences  peoples’  lives  remains  unreflected  in  everyday  life  

and  thus  also  inaccessible  from  a  common  sensical  perspective,  Alexander  sets  a  kind  

of  Freudian  goal  for  cultural  sociology.  It  should  make  an  effort  to  reveal  the  repressed,  

to  “bring  the  social  unconscious  up  for  view23”  (Alexander  2003:  4).  In  order  to  achieve  

this,  Alexander  and  Smith  proposed  a  method  of  structural  hermeneutics,  which  makes  

structuralism  and  hermeneutics  into  fine  bedfellows.  “The  former  offers  possibilities  for  

general  theory  construction,  prediction  and  assertions  of  the  autonomy  of  culture.  The  

latter  allows  analysis   to  capture   the   texture  and   temper  of   social   life.  When  comple-­‐

mented  by  attention   to   institutions  and  actors   as   causal   intermediaries,  we  have   the  

foundations   of   a   robust   cultural   sociology.”   (Alexander   2003:  26).   As   Emirbayer  

(2004:  8)  points  out,  the  fact  that  the  strong  programme  does  not  prefer  social  struc-­‐

ture  to  other  kinds  of  structures  and  acknowledges  cultural  autonomy  makes  it  useful,  

for  it  provides  us  with  the  opportunity  to  methodologically  isolate  cultural  structures,  

map  out  their  internal  patterns  and  logics,  examine  their  interplay  with  other  kinds  of  

structures  and  historical  processes,  and  to  see  “how  these  together  constrain  and  ena-­‐

ble  interaction”.  

                                                                                               

23   That   is   why   he   also   considers   cultural   sociology   to   be   a   kind   of   social   psychoanalysis   (Alexander  2003:4).  

 42  

Yet   even  Alexander’s   emancipation  of   culture   from  structure   suffered   from   the  pres-­‐

ence  of  a  residue  of  the  Marxist  way  of  thinking,  as  Emirbayer  (ibid.)  noticed.  By  draw-­‐

ing  distinction  between  “ideal”  culture  and  “material”  structure,  Alexander  was  actually  

reproducing  the  old,  materialist  binary  opposition  that  was  by  no  means  neutral.  How-­‐

ever,  his  recent  effort  made  in  the  field  of  iconicity  seems  promising,  since  it  endeav-­‐

ours  to  include  materiality  into  the  study  of  culture,  by  which  the  dualism  of  ideal  and  

material  should  be  overcome.  

2.2. Iconic  theory  Inspired  by  growing  interest  in  the  aesthetics  in  social  theory,  Alexander  (2008)  intro-­‐

duced  an  interpretation  of  Standing  Woman,  a  famous  sculpture  from  Alberto  Giaco-­‐

metti.  There,  according  to  his  own  words,  he  hoped  to  pursue  “the  old  romantic  dream  

of  reintegrating  art  and  life”  (2008:  10).  The  way  Alexander  deals  with  materiality  gives  

voice  to  the  sensual,  material  experience  of  art  (he  calls  it  iconic  experience);  however,  

he   immediately   extends   the   notion   of   such   experience   to   everyday   life.   In   the  main  

argument,   Alexander   articulates   the   assumption   that   material   experience   is   by   no  

means   limited  to  contact  with  art.  Quite  the  opposite,  materiality   is  essential   for  hu-­‐

man’s  experience  of   the  world24.  As  we  experience  material   surface  of   things,  we  can  

“feel”   it   “in   our   un-­‐conscious  minds   and   associate”   it  with  meanings,   i.e.  with   other  

personal  as  well  as  social   ideas  and  things  (Alexander  2008:  6).  Making  such  associa-­‐

tions   is   typical  of   and  pivotal   in   the  process  of   typification  as  defined  by  Berger  and  

Luckmann   (1991)   and  Alexander   is   thus   able   to   conclude   that  materiality   lies   at   the  

very  basis  of  social  life.  Furthermore,  since  human  experience  of  the  material  is  medi-­‐

ated  by  senses,  the  concern  of  iconic  theory  for  materiality  required  also  the  inclusion  

of  sensuality:  “In  the  iconosphere  of  society,  the  meanings  of  social  life  take  on  sensual  

                                                                                               

24  Although  such  a  statement  may  seem  rather  banal,  it  is  true  that  the  material  aspect  of  human’s  life  has  been  broadly  ignored  by  sociological  theory,  while  language  and  discourses  were  its  preferred  points  of  interest  at  the  same  time  (for  summaries  about  the  effects  of  Rorty’s  linguistic  turn  and  consequent  development   in   human   sciences   see   Boehm   and   Mitchell   2009,   Bartmanski   2012b,   Moxey   2008   and  Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012).  

 43  

form,   whether   by   sight,   hearing,   touch,   taste,   or   smell.”   (Bartmanski   and   Alexander  

2012:  11)  

Even  though  the  notion  of  iconic  experience  puts  a  striking  emphasis  on  sensuality  and  

materiality,   it  has  nothing  in  common  with  and  must  not  be  confused  with  material-­‐

ism.  The  iconic  turn  in  cultural  sociology  suggested  by  Alexander  (2010a)  categorically  

disapproves   of   all  materialistic   approaches   that   reduce  materiality   to  mere   things   of  

use-­‐value.  Therefore   is  Karl  Marx  one  of   three  modern  scholars,  whom  iconic   theory  

opposes;  his  concept  of  commodification  remains,  according  to  Alexander,  blind  to  the  

aesthetic  dimension  and  viewer’s  experience.  Drawing  on  Durkheim  and  the  manifesto  

of   the   strong   programme   (2.1),   Alexander   pursues   analytical   separation   of   meaning  

from  social  structure,  which  is  supposed  to  be  the  first  step  in  the  sociological  endeav-­‐

or   to   understand   the   iconic,   i.e.   “how  meaning,   soul,   and   spirit  manifest   themselves  

through  materiality”  (2010a:  11).  The  concept  of  iconicity  defies  also  the  notion  of  dis-­‐

entchantment   as   suggested   by  Max  Weber.  Quite   the   contrary,   the   theory   of   iconic  

power  suggests  that  we  do  not   live   in  perfectly  rational  and  emotionless   iron  cages25,  

but  rather  in  a  world  where  sensual  contact  with  material  things  that  trigger  emotions  

plays   an   essential   role   in   the   process   of  meaning-­‐making.   From   the   same   argument  

stems   also   the   critique   of   Walter   Benjamin’s   prediction   of   the   loss   of   aura,   which  

should   have   occurred   with   the   onset   of  modernity.   Nothing   like   that   has,   however,  

taken  place,  claim  Bartmanski  and  Alexander  and  suggest  rather  shifting  the  attention  

to  the  way  how  “iconic  aura  continues  to  inhabit  nonunique  items”  (2012).  To  sum  up,  

the   theory   of   iconic   power   aspires   to   bring   aura,   enchantment   and   fetish   back,   and  

hence  it  uses  Durkheimian  notion  of  totemism,  which  grants  economic  objects  meta-­‐

phorical  and  emotional  powers.  Elsewhere,  Bartmanski  (2012b)  regards  iconicity  to  be  

the  missing  link  that  enables  us  to  bring  totemism  back  into  social  theory.  

But  why  had  materiality  in  social  research  been  ignored  for  such  a  long  time?  Accord-­‐

ing  to  Alexander  (2010a),  it  was  because  of  the  tension  between  materialism  and  ideal-­‐

                                                                                               

25   In  criticising  Weber  has  been  Alexander  truly  consistent;  similar  argument  was  suggested  already  in  his  New  Theoretical  Movement  (1988).  

 44  

ism,  which  poses  a  problem  that  sociology  always  had  to  solve  or  avoid  (cf.  Alexander  

1988).  Earlier  scholars  seem  to  have  escaped  to  the  shelter  of  scientific  realism  in  order  

to  eschew  moralistic  and  aesthetic  fallacy  at  the  same  time  by  claiming  to  have  access  

to  the  thing  in  itself.  “It  is  this  realist  claim  that  lurks  beneath  Peirce’s  theory  of  iconic  

as  compared  with  symbolic  meaning,”  adds  Alexander26  (2010a:  20).  While  interpreting  

Peirce’s  concept  of  icon  as  “sign  by  resemblance”  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  119),  Al-­‐

exander  prefers  Saussure’s  theory  by  assuming  that  “(m)ateriality  is  non-­‐verbal  but  still  

conventional”  (Alexander  2008:  12).  At  the  same  time,  he  adopts  Durkheim’s  assump-­‐

tion  suggesting  that  morality  is  abstract  and  difficult  to  imagine,  and  therefore  has  to  

be  connected  to  a  concrete  object,  so  that  people  could  comprehend  spiritual  feelings  

(Alexander  2010a:  16).  

Materiality   is   thus   crucial   for   social   life,   since   “in  order   to   ‘express  our  own   ideas   to  

ourselves’  (…)  we  need  to   ‘fix  them  on  material  things  which  symbolize  them’”  (Alex-­‐

ander   and   Smith   2005:  8).   Therefore,   the   suggested   point   of   departure   for   studying  

iconicity  is  to  consider  materiality  as  constitutive  of  sociability  (Bartmanski  and  Alex-­‐

ander  2012).  Durkheim’s  (1976:  207)  notion  of  totem  as  “a  symbol,  a  material  expression  

of  something  else,”  as  a  collective  representation  of  the  sacred  that  classifies  things  as  

sacred  or  profane,  that  plays  an  important  role  during  rituals,  and  that  personifies  and  

represents  collective  identity  under  a  visible  form  (Alexander  2012),  is  fundamental  for  

the  cultural  sociological  concept  of  icon,  which  should  help  us  deal  with  the  key  ques-­‐

tion  how  meaning  manifests  itself  through  materiality  (Alexander  2010a:  12).  

                                                                                               

26    Peirce  seems  to  be  a  highly  controversial  theoretician.  While  Alexander  criticizes  his  realismus  and  “purely  pragmatic,   non-­‐conventionalist  materiality   of   the   icon   and   index”   (2008:12)   and  backs  up   this  critique  by  Mitchell’s  words,  Mitchell   acknowledges  Peirce   as  higly   inspirational   for  his   own   thought:  “Peirce’s  resistance  to  taking  the  symbolic  (or  the  verbal)  as  the  foundational  moment  of  semiotics,  and  his  insistence  on  the  phenomenon  of  the  ‘qualisign’,  the  sign  that  signifies  by  virtue  of  its  inherent  sen-­‐suous  qualities,   that  attracted  me.”   (Boehm  and  Mitchell   2009:118).  Moreover,  Peirce’s   claim  that   icon  and  index  are  not  based  on  experience  but  on  the  capacity  of  experience  (1.1.1)  is  similar  to  Alexander’s  notion  of  iconic  consciousness,  which  is  based  on  a  Kantian  disposition  (see  below).  

 45  

2.3. The  power  of  icons  The  most   recent   version   of   still   developing   iconic   theory   has   been   presented   in   the  

book   Iconic   Power,   where   Bartmanski   and  Alexander   (2012)   define   icons   as  material  

objects  with  symbolic  power.  Such  modern  totems  represent  social  sacred  or  profane  

(Alexander  2008:  9)  and  have  significant  impact  on  social  actors  who  encounter  them,  

since  people  do  not  just  stick  with  “understanding  them  cognitively  or  evaluating  them  

morally,”  but  they  also  feel  “their  sensual,  aesthetic  force”  (Bartmanski  and  Alexander  

2012:  1).  It  is  exactly  the  aesthetic  dimension  what  makes  icons  different  and  somehow  

special.  Once  we  encounter  an  icon,  we  feel  affected  by  it  not  only  in  a  strictly  material  

manner,   but   there   are   also   significant   sensual   and   highly   emotional   aspects   at   play.  

Even   though   such   empirical   iconic   experience   is   singular,   for  we   encounter   icons   as  

single  objects  or  things,  on  the  analytical  level  they  consist  of  two  components  that  are  

to  be  separated  (Alexander  2010a:  14).  

Icons  are  constituted  by  the  interplay  between  material  surface  and  meaningful  depth,  

where   the   latter   is  made   visible   by   the   former.   Alexander,   following   the   Saussurean  

structuralistic  notion  of   an   arbitrary   relation  between   signified   and   signifier,   regards  

the  relation  of  depth  and  surface  as  purely  conventional  as  well27  (Alexander  2008:  12).  

For  if  we  already  knew  the  meaning  (of  an  art  piece,  for  example)  before  we  experience  

it,  the  point  of  aesthetic  experience  would  be  lost.  It  is  exactly  because  the  signifier  is  

not  determined  by  the  signified,  the  form  not  limited  by  the  concept,  the  surface  not  

restricted  by  the  depth,  that  imagination  can  work  on  the  principle  of  free  play28  (Alex-­‐

ander  2010a:  17);  as  Boehm  puts  it,  “(m)illions  of  people  would  not  be  visiting  museums  

                                                                                               

27   In  other  words,  Alexander   takes   a   stand  against  Peirce’s   signs’   typology   (especially   against   the   con-­‐cepts  of   icon  and  index,  see  above)  that  presupposes  a  motivated  relation  of  signified  and  its  signifier,  and  claims  that  such  a  theory  is  nothing  more  than  a  result  of  Western  philosophical  tradition,  which  is  used  to   fetishize   images  as   “natural”   signs.   In  order   to  avoid  such   idolatry,   “we  must  not   (…)  consider  material   shapes   literally,   even   if   it   is   the   textural   qualities   of   their   surfaces   that   give   them  distinctive  communicative  power”  (2008:12–13).  

28  On  the  other  hand,  in  the  mundane  everyday  experience  there  is  no  possibility  for  free  sensuous  in-­‐terpretations,   since   icons  and   their  meanings  are   typified.  That,  nevertheless,   changes  nothing  on   the  fact  that  the  relations  of  meaningful  depths  and  visible,  aesthetic  surfaces  are  conventional  (see  Alexan-­‐der  2010a:18).  

 46  

to  look  at  pictures  if  they  were  only  being  fed  what  they  already  knew  or  had  heard  at  

some  point”  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:  106).  

In   icons   that   function   like   signs,   aesthetic   shapes   become   “middles   of   semiotic   pro-­‐

cess,”  (Alexander  2010a:  11)  where  the  signifier  is  a  material  thing,  which  enables  us  to  

feel  the  signified.  Feelings  are  thus  activated  by  the  contact  with  surfaces,  but  simulta-­‐

neously  informed  by  the  meaning  structures  that  dwell  beneath  the  surfaces  (Alexan-­‐

der   2010a:  14).   Therefore,   it   is   the   aesthetic  material   form   that   seduces   the   spectator  

and  invites  her  to  experience   immersion   that  happens  when  the  sensual  contact  with  

icon’s   aesthetic   surface   brings   forth   sensual   experience   and   transition   of   meaning29  

(Alexander  2010a:  11).  

In  short,  immersion  is  a  movement  from  an  object’s  surface  to  its  depth,  a  dialectical  

process   between   “subjectification”   and   “materialization”   (Alexander   2008:  6).   Such   a  

“‘mystical’   experience”   lets   the   “distinction  between   subject   and   object”   dissolve   and  

the   duality   between   them  disappear   (Alexander   2008:  7).  Alexander   (2010a:  11)   likens  

icon’s  aesthetic  surface  to  a  vacuum  cleaner  sucking  the  spectator  into  meaning.  For  it  

is   hard   to   imagine   any   deep   cultural   meanings   one   would   find   inside   of   a   vacuum  

cleaner,  a  better  metaphor  would  probably  be  one  of  a  portal  which,  after  she  touches  

it,   sucks   the  viewer   in  on  one  side  and  subsequently   spews  her  out   in  a  different  di-­‐

mension,  that  is,  in  social  reality.  The  sensual  contact  with  surface,  “whether  by  sight,  

smell,   taste,   sound   or   touch,”   is   essential   for   the   transition   of  meaning,   since   “(t)he  

iconic  is  about  experience,  not  communication”  (Alexander  2010a:  11).  

This  notion  of  iconicity  reminds  very  much  of  Malcolm  Gladwell’s  bestseller  Blink.  In  

the   first   chapter   called  The   statue   that   didn’t   look   right,  Gladwell   (2007:  3–17)   tells   a  

story  of  a  kouros  bought  by  an  art  museum  in  California.  There  was  a  strong  contro-­‐

                                                                                               

29  In  his  narrative  analysis  of  guillotine,  Smith  quotes  a  notion  of  an  experience  (that  could  be  now  de-­‐scribed  as  iconic)  found  in  Freud’s  interpretation  of  Moses  of  Michelangelo  statue.  “According  to  Freud  cultural   objects   that   are   ‘unsolved   riddles   to   our   understanding   .   .   .’   and   refuse   a   simple,   consensual  explanation  are  often  those  which  produce  feelings  of  ‘awe’  (1955:  211).  They  have  a  ‘magical  appeal’  and  invite  us  to  discover  the  source  of  ‘a  power  that  is  beyond  them  alone’  (1955:  213).”  (Smith  2003:46)  Alt-­‐hough   implicit,   in   the  excerpt  one  easily   reveals   the   idea  of   surface  and  depth  distinction  as  well  as  a  hint  of  immersion.  

 47  

versy   concerning   the   origins   of   the   kouros:   while   special   tests   of   statue’s   material  

proved  its  old  age,  the  art  historian  and  experts  on  Greek  art  felt  repelled  by  that  stat-­‐

ue,   since   there  was   “something  wrong”  with   it—however,   they  could  not   tell  what   it  

was.  Eventually,  after  the  purchase  was  made  and  some  other  materials  testifying  kou-­‐

ros’s  origin  were  inspected,  it  turned  out  that  it  was  a  fake.  Many  art  historians  knew  it  

at   the   first  sight,   though.  How  could  they?  I  argue,  using  Alexander’s   terms,   that  the  

answer   lies   in   their  ability   to   “read”   the   iconic;  once   they  saw  the  statue,   they  knew.  

They  were  able  to  “understand  without  knowing,  or  at  least  without  knowing  that  one  

knows,”  which   is   the  characteristic  of   iconic  consciousness   (Alexander  2010a:  11).   It   is  

exactly  such  cases  what  allows  Alexander  to  describe  materiality  as  a  “non-­‐verbal  me-­‐

dium  for  symbolic  communication”  that  does  not  substitute  signs  but  offers  an  alterna-­‐

tive  for  using  them  (Alexander  2008:  12).  

However,   iconic  experience   is  not  exclusively  about  art—the  very  opposite   is   true,  as  

Alexander   (2008,   2010a,   2010b)   shows.  Mundane   iconic   experience   follows   the   same  

principles  as  the  one  of  art,  in  which  there  are  deep  meanings  expressed  through  aes-­‐

thetic  material   surfaces.  The   fact   that  social  value   is  signified  by  materiality  provides  

the  opportunity  for  sensual  contact  with  the  aesthetic  surface  forms,  whether  by  sight,  

smell,   taste,  sound  or  touch   in  everyday   life  as  well.  But  again,   it   is  not  the  aesthetic  

surface   alone   what   produces   “(t)he   thrills   and   fears”   one   experiences   during   an   en-­‐

counter  with  an  icon;  those  feelings  are  “informed  by  the  meaning  structures  that   lie  

beneath”  (Alexander  2010a:  14).  The  sensual  encounter  with  the  surface  then  draws  the  

subject  during  the  process  of  immersion  to  the  social  meanings  of  the  depth.  

For   being   able   to   “read”   the   deep  meanings  we   need   iconic   consciousness,   which   is  

closely  related  to  one’s  own  experience—the  viewer  must  understand  icons  “by  feeling,  

by  contact,  by  the  ‘evidence  of  the  senses’  rather  than  the  mind”  (Alexander  2010a:  11).  

In  this  point  lies  another  difference  between  art  and  mundane  experience  and  the  kind  

of  iconic  consciousness  needed  for  such  experience.  In  the  artistic  realm,  the  ability  to  

evaluate  and  experience  the  aesthetics  of  art  is  limited  and  has  to  be  gained  by  educa-­‐

tion;  however,  these  conditions  do  not  apply  for  the  surface  experience  of  things  in  the  

course   of   everyday   life   (Alexander   2010a:  14).   As   an   example,   Alexander   (Alexander  

2010a:  14)  suggests  that  everyone  is  able  to  recognize  and  evaluate  a  pretty  woman  or  a  

 48  

handsome   man,   because   everyone   simply   “knows”—and   all   one   needs   for   such   an  

evaluation   is   just  a  Kantian  disposition  to  be  moved.  During  mundane   iconic  experi-­‐

ence,  “self,  reason,  morality,  and  society”  are  defined  (Alexander  2010a:  18).  Icons  pro-­‐

vide  us  with  ontological  security,  which  stems  from  the  sense  of  being  a  part  of  “some-­‐

thing   bigger,”   something   that   transcends   the   single   actors,   that   is   “beyond   the  

comprehension   of   society  members”   and   that   allows   them   to   participate   in   it   (Bart-­‐

manski  and  Alexander  2012:  2).  That  makes  iconicity  one  of  the  bases  of  social  life,  for  

it  lets  us  be  part  of  the  group  and  also  makes  relationships  as  well  as  hierarchies  possi-­‐

ble  (Alexander  2008).  

2.4. Icons  as  myths  Alexander’s  articles  about  icons  (2008,  2010a,  2010b,  2012)  are  largely  based  on  critique  

of  Kant’s  categories  of  the  beautiful  and  the  sublime,  because  they  do  not  apprehend  

the   distinction   between   surfaces   and   depths;   therefore,   they   are   essentializing.   Kant  

seems   to  have   failed   to   recognize   the   constructed   character   of   aesthetic   surface   and  

concluded   that  women  are   beautiful   (simply   because   they   are  women)   and  men  are  

sublime.  Alexander’s  explanation  for  Kant’s  shortcoming  is  that  people,   in  the  course  

of  everyday  life,  experience  icons  in  naturalized  ways,  which  means  that  they  consider  

the   aesthetic   dimension   to   be   also   the   true   meaning   of   a   given   thing   (Alexander  

2012:  26).  That  is  also  the  reason  why  the  very  same  “aesthetic  essentialism”,  which  Al-­‐

exander  has  found  in  Kant’s  works,  still  plays  an  important  role  in  contemporary  popu-­‐

lar  culture  and  in  the  way  how  it  works  with  binary  oppositions  in  the  very  same  gen-­‐

dered  way   (2010b:  330).   In   other  words,   cultural   industry   produces   and   presents   the  

“surfaces”  of  female  celebrity-­‐icons  that  are  beautiful  and  those  of  male  icons  that  are  

sublime.  Since  surface  and  depth  are  on  the  empirical  level  intertwined,  these  aesthetic  

surfaces  are  consequently  used  for  naturalizing  moral  qualities.  Therefore  can  the  im-­‐

age  of  a  woman  be  constructed  as  one  of  a  “light,  delicate,  erotic”  princess,  while  a  man  

has   to  be  a  wise,   strong  and  courageous   (anti)heroe   (Alexander  2010b:  330–331).  Also  

Becker  appositely  noted  that  “people  do  not  experience  their  aesthetic  beliefs  as  merely  

arbitrary   and   conventional;   they   feel   that   they   are   natural,   proper   and   moral”  

(1974a:  773).  Breaking  the  required  image,  such  as  a  refusal  to  wear  skirts  if  you  are  a  

 49  

woman  or  having  long  nails  as  a  man,  which  is  actually  an  “attack”  on  aesthetics,  be-­‐

comes  (because  of  the  intertwinement  of  surface  and  form)  then  an  attack  on  a  morali-­‐

ty  (Becker  1974a:  773).  As  long  as  there  are  such  particular  social  meanings  that  seem  

to  “intrinsically  demand  some  specific  articulation  of  the  beautiful  or  the  sublime”  (Al-­‐

exander  2012:  26),  one  of   the  main  goals  of   the  newborn  theory  of   iconic  power   is   to  

overcome   the   essentializing   tendencies   of   ordinary   everyday   thinking.   By   providing  

answer  to  the  question  how  meaning,  soul,  and  spirit  manifest  themselves  through  ma-­‐

teriality?   (Alexander   2010a:  12),   we   should   be   able   to   reverse   the   process   and   to   de-­‐

naturalize   the  meanings   of   naturalized   cultural   constructions   (Bartmanski   and  Alex-­‐

ander  2012:  2).  

A   similar   issue   was   addressed   by   Alexander   already   in   his  Meanings   of   (Social)   Life  

(2003),  where  he  argued  that  naturalized  cultural  constructions  (or  myths,  in  Barthes’s  

terminology)  and  essentialized  interpretations  of  everyday  experiences  are  of  large  im-­‐

portance   for   society.   “We  need  myths   if  we  are   to   transcend   the  banality  of  material  

life.  We  need  narratives  if  we  are  to  make  progress  and  experience  tragedy.  We  need  to  

divide  the  sacred  from  profane  if  we  are  to  pursue  the  good  and  protect  ourselves  from  

evil.”   (Alexander   2003:  4)  However,   at   that   time   the   theoretical   emphasis   of   cultural  

sociology  was  still  put  on  language,  narratives  and  performances.  It  was  only  after  the  

recognition  of  materiality’s  role  in  social  life  that  icons  appeared  on  the  list  of  natural-­‐

ized  cultural   constructions.  Since   there   is   a   strong   similarity  between   the  concept  of  

myth  as   it  was  worked  out  by  Roland  Barthes  during   the   1950s   (1.3)   and  Alexander’s  

notion   of   icon   (and   Barthes’s   work   has   without   any   doubt   influenced   Alexander’s  

thinking,  for  he  quotes  him  quite  frequently),  in  the  following  I  compare  their  perspec-­‐

tives  and  make  explicit  the  parallels  between  the  concepts  of  myth  and  icon.  

The  notion  of  myth  draws  on  Saussurean  dyadic  sign  model;  Barthes’s  myth  consists  of  

form  and  concept,  which  stand   in  a  conventional,  culturally  constructed  relationship  

to  each  other.  Analytical  distinction  put  between  form  and  concept  has  its  equivalent  

in   Barthes’s   image   analysis   (1.3),   where   the   form   consists   of   literal,   denoted   image,  

while  the  concept   is  made  up  by  symbolic,  connoted   image.   It   is   the  same  idea   from  

which  Alexander’s  distinction  between  iconic  surface  and  depth  stems.  Therefore,  the  

myth   can   be   thought   of   as   the   deep   cultural   meaning   hidden   beneath   the   surface.  

 50  

Moreover,  one  mythical  concept  may  be  repeated  and  represented  by  a  number  of  dif-­‐

ferent  forms  (Barthes  2012:  259–261),  as  well  as  there  may  be  different  surfaces  for  the  

meaning  connoting  an  iconic  social  thinker  (e.g.  Foucault  and  Malinowski  as  demon-­‐

strated   by   Bartmanski   (2012a)).   Such   possibility   of   various   form-­‐substitutions   is   also  

illustrated   by   Barthes’s   claim   “(f)orm   is   empty,   but   present;  meaning   is   absent,   and  

therefore   full”   (2012:  270).  Also,   as  well   as   in   icon,   the   relation  between   the  denoted  

and  the  connoted  is  culturally  constructed  and  therefore  conventional,  e.g.  there  is  no  

“natural”  connection  between,  e.g.  a  sausage  and  the  idea  of  “Germanicity”  evoked  by  a  

sight  of  a  package  of  sausages  or  a  smell  of  them  etc.  The  iconic  surface  points  to  the  

meaning   and   eventually   seems   to   be   the  meaning   itself,   and   it   is   on   the   very   same  

principle   how   “the   denoted   image   naturalizes   the   symbolic   message”   (Barthes  

1977:  45).  The  process  of  naturalization  of  myth  has  in  Barthes’s  example  of  advertising  

pictures  considerable  persuasive  force,  since  the  literal  surface  of  a  photograph  makes  

the  impression  of  being  the  “evidence  of  this  is  how  it  was30”  (1977:  44,  italics  in  origi-­‐

nal).  

To  sum  up,  this  debate  leads  to  the  conclusion  that  icons  have  mythical  character,  for  

they  do,  as  well  as  myths,  have  the  power  to  naturalize  “arbitrary  meaning  structures”  

and   to   essentialize   “historically   contingent   aesthetic   forms”   (Alexander   2012:  26).   As  

Barthes   (2012:  269)  puts   it,   “(m)yth  begins  where  meaning  ends.”  Therefore  everyone  

who  endeavors  to  interpret  icons  runs  a  normative  risk  and  “must  beware  of  assuming  

that  a   ‘look’  naturally  expresses  anything,”  because   it  does  not   (Alexander  2010a:  20).  

However,  “iconic  consciousness  inevitably  makes  it  seem  that  way”  (ibid.).    

                                                                                               

30  The  current  approach  to  photographs  acknowledges  the  fact  that  they  make  “an  impresion  that  some-­‐thing  happened  this  way,”  but  at  the  same  time  they  actually  “represent  one  way  of  seeing,  one  perspec-­‐tive  of  the  reality,”  and  therefore  are  a  reductive  selection  of  reality  (Pilarczyk  and  Mietzner  2000:  345).  Becker  (1974b:  10)  makes  a  similar  point:  “As  you  look  through  the  viewfinder  you  wait  until  what  you  see  ‘looks  right,’  until  the  composition  and  the  moment  make  sense,  until  you  see  something  that  corre-­‐sponds  to  your  conception  of  what's  going  on.”    

 51  

2.5. Achievements  &  benefits  of  iconic  theory  To  begin,  when  looked  at  from  a  more  general  perspective,  the  theory  of  iconic  power  

poses   a   logical   step   in  Alexander’s   theoretical   effort  whose  beginnings   can  be   traced  

back  to  the  1980s.  In  his  essay  The  New  Theoretical  Movement  (Alexander  1988)  he  pre-­‐

sented  a  critique  of  hitherto  existing  social  theories  and  suggested  a  neo-­‐functionalist,  

synthetic  attempt  to  combine  Parsons’s  functionalist  theory  with  subjectivist  interpre-­‐

tative   approaches.   By   uniting   the   one-­‐sided  micro-­‐   and  macro   perspectives,   the   old  

dichotomy  of   individualistic   and   collectivist   approach  would  be  overcome.  Yet   there  

were  more  problems  and  theoretical  dilemmas  to  solve;  in  particular,  Alexander  dealt  

with  the  issue  of  reconciling  the  notion  of  freedom  and  order  in  society  that  was  close-­‐

ly   linked  to  the  question  of  rationality  of  social  actors.  “It   is  the  independence  of  the  

individual   that  makes   order   problematic,   and   it   is   this   problematizing   of   order   that  

makes  sociology  possible.  At  the  same  time,  sociologists  acknowledge  that  the  every-­‐

day  life  of  an  individual  has  a  patterned  quality.  It  is  this  tension  between  freedom  and  

order  that  provides  the  intellectual  and  moral  rationale  for  sociology,”  he  wrote  (Alex-­‐

ander  1988:  85).  

In   order   to   overcome   these   intellectual   challenges,  Alexander   formulated   a   basic   re-­‐

quirement,   namely   that   “action   and   structure   must   now   be   intertwined”   (1988:  77).  

Hence  he  suggested  a  new  theoretical  direction  that  made  an  effort  to  reconcile  both  

collectivist   and   individualist   approaches   by   postulating   structures   on   one   side   and  

non-­‐rational   actors,   driven   by   ideals   and   emotions,   on   the   other   side   (ibid.).   The  

source  of   ideals  and  emotions   is  culture,  an  independent  sphere  of  collectively  struc-­‐

tured  meanings  that  is  situated  between  structures  and  actors,  shapes  social  life,  inter-­‐

feres  with   it,  and  directs  what  happens   (Alexander  2003:  3).  Yet   it  was  already   in   the  

essay  from  1988  where  Alexander’s  call  for  a  “robust  conception  of  culture”  appeared,  

which  was  later  established  by  the  strong  programme  manifesto  (2.1).  The  strong  pro-­‐

gramme  has,  nevertheless,  in  the  first  decade  of  its  existence  mostly  focused  on  collec-­‐

tive   representations,   emotions,   morality   and   other   immaterial   issues.   Such   interests  

have,  however,  rather  contributed  to  the  reproduction  of  materialistic  distinction  be-­‐

tween  “ideal”  culture  and  “material”  structure  (Emirbayer  2004).  

 52  

Thus,   the  newborn   iconic   theory  with   its   effort   to   synthesize  materiality  and  culture  

seems  to  be  overcoming  of  materialism  and  idealism  and  hence  filling  up  the  “empty”  

spaces   that  have  been  until  now  dwelling   in   the  core  of  Alexander’s  bold   theoretical  

attempt  from  the  1980s.  It  is  also  noteworthy  that  the  way  how  Alexander  understands  

icon   mirrors   the   same   principles   that   analytically   distinguish   between   action   and  

structure.   In   other   words,   the   relation   of   iconic   surface   and   depth   that   intertwines  

form  and  content  is  analogue  to  the  distinction  of  action  and  structure.  

Second,  by  bringing  the  topic  of  aesthetics,  which  is  normally  a  concern  of  humanities  

into   sociology,   iconic   theory  managed   to   formulate   a   completely   new   research   pro-­‐

gramme  (Bartmanski  2012  even  talks  about  a  paradigm  shift).  To  be  sure,   the  shift  of  

sociological  attention  to  the  visual  and  material  has  opened  new  perspectives  for  theo-­‐

retical  effort  as  well  as  it  brought  new  questions,  disputes  and  research  topics.  

Third,  the  theory  of  iconic  power  succeeds  in  including  sensuality  and  emotions  linked  

with   the   experience   of   the   aesthetic   and  material   to   the   sociological   discourse.   The  

emphasis  put  on  culturally  produced  emotions  and  their  analytical  grab  and  analysis  

successfully  follows  the  direction  laid  out  both  by  Alexander  in  1988  (see  above)  and  in  

the  manifesto  of  the  strong  programme  (2.1).  By  stressing  the  importance  of  iconic  ex-­‐

perience   in  modern   life,   cultural   sociology   continues   to   walk   the   Durkheimian   line  

that  lies  at  the  very  heart  of  the  strong  programme,  for  it  managed  to  include  totem  in  

the  form  of  icon  to  the  contemporary  sociological  theory.  

Next,  iconicity  also  supplements  the  list  of  cultural  representations  that  used  to  consist  

of   narratives   and   performances   that   through   the   concepts   of   myths   and   rituals   re-­‐

searched   concrete   events   and   actions.   After   the   iconic   turn   in   cultural   sociology,  

iconicity   as   cultural   representation  was   included   and   the   concept  of   icon  was  devel-­‐

oped  for  analysis  of  materiality  (Binder  2013).  

Furthermore,   the   theory   of   iconic   power   compensates   by   its   concept   of   iconicity   for  

the   linguistic   one-­‐sidedness   of   structuralism   and   hermeneutics   (Binder   2014b).   The  

iconic  turn  has  caused  a  significant  expansion  of  the  opinion  that  the  relationship  be-­‐

tween  text  and  image  has  to  be  radically  rethought  (cf.  Binder  2013,  Bartmanski  2012b,  

Bohnsack  2007  &  2009,  Mitchell  1994  &  2005,  Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012).  Since  the  

 53  

issue  of   rethinking  of   the   relation  of   texts   and   images  within   the  discourse   of   social  

sciences  is  of  crucial  importance,  for  it  suggests  changing  of  the  language-­‐oriented  ap-­‐

proach  typical  for  human  sciences  in  the  20th  century  and  brings  certain  crucial  ques-­‐

tions  about  the  future  direction  of  sociological  approach  toward  the  visual.  

Although  there  is  a  view  that  the  focus  on  everyday  iconicity,  in  the  way  how  it  is  used  

by  the  theory  of  iconic  power,  has  brought  not  much  more  to  cultural  sociology  than  a  

fresh,  new  opportunity  to  narrate  “colourful  stories  about  the  rise  of  icons  to  fame”  and  

to   show   what   their   impact   on   collective   identity   is   (Giesen   2012:  249),   drawing   on  

Bartmanski  (2012b)  I  argue  that  one  of  the  considerable  benefits  of  iconic  theory  is  the  

effort  to  overcome  the  preference  for  language,  which  marked  the  character  of  sociolo-­‐

gy  for  decades.  

2.5.1. Nobody  puts  images  in  a  corner  (anymore)  Human  and   social   sciences  of   the  20th   century   lived  and  developed   in  an  era  of   “ab-­‐

sorption  of  image  by  discourse”  (Bartmanski  2012b:  4).  Especially  after  Rorty’s  Linguis-­‐

tic  Turn   the  focus  of  scholars  was  mainly  (save  some  scarce  exceptions)  on  language,  

texts   and   discourses.   “Meanings   can   only   be   shared   through   our   common   access   to  

language”   (Hall   1997:  1),   was   a   predominant,   common,   and   widespread   belief.   The  

“epistemological  preference  for  words  to  images”  (Bartmanski  2012b:  5),  caused  by  the  

turn   to   language,  was   the   reason  why   social   research   remained   ignorant   to   pictures  

and  preferred  texts;  social  reality  in  its  scientific  form  thus  also  must  have  taken  on  the  

form  of  protocols,  i.e.  texts,  notes  Bohnsack  (2007:  22).  Furthermore,  with  the  assump-­‐

tion  that  meaning  was  constituted  by  language,  research  data  were  constructed31  in  the  

same,   linguistic   way   (ibid.,   see   also   Przyborski   and   Slunecko   2012).   As   a   result,   the  

“sensual  and  aesthetic  spheres,  visuality  included,  were  simply  not  considered  a  basis  

for  serious  sociological  scholarship,”  notes  Bartmanski  (2012b:  2).  

The  other  extreme  position  ensued  from  so  called  pictorial  turn  announced  by  W.  J.  T.  

Mitchell  (1.5).  While  trying  to  gain  more  attention  to  the  visual  culture,  Mitchell  was  

                                                                                               

31  The  term  “construction  of  research  data”  is  used  in  the  same  sense  as  formulated  by  Latour  (2005).  

 54  

determined  to  give  absolute  precedence  to  image  and  to  suppress  the  language.  Thus,  

although  he  asked  a  very  similar  question  as  cultural  sociology  does  (namely,  what  sort  

of  power  pictures  have  to  effect  human  emotions  and  behaviour?  (Mitchell  2005:  28),  his  

approach  did  not  offer  any  promising  nor  useful  alternative  for  social  sciences,   for   in  

his  radical  opposition  to  linguistic  turn  Mitchell  had  simply  gone  “too  far”  in  its  post-­‐

modernity.  As  a  result,  the  old,  established  duality  of  image  and  text  was  continuously  

reproduced.  On  one  hand,  there  was  a  modern  logocentrism  that  was  suppressing  sur-­‐

faces  and,  on  the  other  hand,  there  was  Mitchell’s  postmodernism  downplaying  discur-­‐

sive  meaning  (2012b).  

The  problem  with  privileging  either   text  or   image  and  condemning   the  other   is   that  

the  distinction  drawn  between  them  is  never  neutral;  in  fact,  it  can  be  rather  seen,  us-­‐

ing  Durkheimian   terms,  as  a  binary  opposition  of   sacred  and  profane,  as  Bartmanski  

puts  it.  He  also  claims  that  sociology  needs  a  new  perspective  in  order  to  overcome  this  

binary  and  to  bridge  the  two  competing  opinions.  The  inspiration  for  such  a  new  per-­‐

spective,  he  suggests,  can  be  found  in  the  strong  programme  in  cultural  sociology  in-­‐

spired  by  the  iconic  turn  that  gives  preference  to  neither32.  In  this  new  perspective,  the  

iconic   and   the  discursive   are   treated   as  mutually   constitutive,   equal  members  of   the  

process   of   meaning-­‐making.   Put   differently,   the   iconic   theory   recognizes   the   im-­‐

portance  of  visuality  and  its  influence  on  the  symbolic  order  of  society,  and  acknowl-­‐

edges   that   visuality   and   linguality   are   both   relevant  meaning-­‐makers   constitutive   of  

human  collective  representations  (Bartmanski  2012b:  2).  This  perspective  can  be  illus-­‐

trated  with  Alexander’s  critique  of  Harré’s  claim  that  “a  material  object  is  transformed  

to  a  social  object  by  its  embedment  in  a  narrative”  (quoted  in  Alexander  2010a:  12).  In  

line  with  the  iconic  theory  he  argues  that  it  is  the  sensuous,  visual  surface  of  the  thing  

that  leads  us  to  the  narrative.  As  Przyborski  and  Slunecko  sum  up,  “(w)e  not  only  dwell  

in  a  house  of  language  but  also  in  a  house  of  images.  Our  access  to  the  world  is  no  less  

structured  by  images  than  it  is  by  language”  (2012:  40).  

                                                                                               

32  Mitchell   himself   acknowledges   that   for   a   scientific   use   the   iconic   turn   proposed   by   Boehm  will   be  more  convenient  than  pictorial  turn.  Pictorial  turn,  he  writes,  takes  place  on  the  level  of  society,  while  iconic  turn  implies  the  scientific  use  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  2009:115).  

 55  

According  to  Bartmanski  (2012b),  the  impact  of  the  visual  on  the  symbolic  order  of  so-­‐

ciety  remains  after  many  years  of  ignorance  under-­‐theorized.  With  reference  to  Panof-­‐

sky   he   argues   that   previous   research   of   the   visual   was   concerned   with   “delimited,  

mostly  pictorial  artistic  representations  and  conventional  symbols33”  (2012b:  5).  Contra-­‐

ry  to  that,  contemporary  studies  of  iconicity  should  focus  on  the  interaction  of  surface  

and  depth  and  on  “connecting  discursive  meaning  with  the  perceptual  and  palpable”  

(Bartmanski  and  Alexander  2012:  2),  so  that  they  do  not  prefer  either  word  or   images  

and  by  that  will  not  reproduce  the  old  dualism,  for  both  language  and  image  play  an  

essential   role   in   establishing   a  meaningful   collective   life.   As  Mitchell   once   declared,  

“(v)ision  is  as  important  as  language  in  mediating  social  relations,  and  it’s  not  reduci-­‐

ble  to  language,  to  the  ‘sign,’  or  to  discourse.  Pictures  want  equal  rights  with  language,  

not  to  be  turned  into  language.”  (Mitchell  2005:  47)  It  seems  that,  at  least  in  the  per-­‐

spective  of  cultural  sociology,  the  attempt  to  liberate  pictures  from  discursive  hegemo-­‐

ny  proved  successful.  Nevertheless,  the  current  notion  that  scholarly  attention  should  

be  paid  not  only   to   language  but  also   to   the  visual—since   iconicity   is  as  well   as   text  

fundamentally   important   for   processes   of   meaning-­‐making—appears   to   be   the   last  

assumption  shared  both  by  the  cultural  sociological  iconic  theory  and  by  the  art  histor-­‐

ical  iconic  turn  (1.6).  

                                                                                               

33  This  argument  is,  however,  at   least   in  the  case  of  Panofsky,  not  valid;  his   iconological   interpretation  looking  for  underlying  principles  and  a  modus  operandi  of  art  production  was  aimed  at  interpretation  of  media  of  various  kinds  including  architecture  or  music  (cf.  Panofsky  1989,  Imdahl  2006,  Bohnsack  2009  and  1.2.2).  Furthermore,  the  claim  that  Panofsky  has  treated  images  as  mere  passive  reflections  of  “struc-­‐tures  of  power”  (Bartmanski  2012b:  5)  needs  to  be—not  only  with  the  respect  for  the  following  argumen-­‐tation—reconsidered.   From   Panofsky’s   writings   follows   that   iconological   interpretation  was  meant   to  transcend  the  iconographical  analysis,  which  was  only  the  second  and  only  step  in  his  method  (1.2.1)  that  was   concerned   with   representations   and   symbols   (cf.   Bohnsack   2009).   Elsewhere,   Bohnsack   also   ex-­‐plains   that   the  move   from   iconography   to   iconology   is   the   same  as   the  change  of  question  of  what   is  made  to  how  is  it  made,  not  in  the  sense  of  images  reflecting  some  structures  but  rather  in  the  sense  of  understanding  images  as  cultural  products  of  specific  era  and  specific  individuals  sharing  the  historically  and  culturally  specific  space  of  experience  (2007:28–31).  This  space  of  experience  is  based  on  tacit,  pre-­‐reflective  or  atheoretical  knowledge,  accessible  through  iconological  analysis,  and  produces  “characteris-­‐tic  meaning  that  documents  itself”  (Wesenssinn)  or,  to  use  a  more  popular  term,  habitus.  

 56  

“Pictures  have  the  same  quality,    in  the  sense  of  energy,  as  guns.”  

Horst  Bredekamp  interviewed  by  Wood,  2012  

 57  

3  The  problem  of  two  iconic  turns  

Theorists  of   the   iconic   turn  proposed  by  Boehm  as  well   as   cultural   sociologists  were  

given  voice  in  Iconic  Power,  a  book  with  the  goal  of  making  “the  study  of  material  life  

more   cultural”   (Bartmanski   and   Alexander   2012:  2).   But   once   familiar   with   the   ap-­‐

proach  of  art-­‐theoretical  iconic  turn,  when  one  starts  reading  the  book,  there  are  cer-­‐

tain  questions  that  keep  popping  up  in  her  mind.  How  much  do  these  two  perspectives  

actually  have   in  common?   Is   the   iconic   turn   in  cultural   sociology   indeed   inspired  by  

Boehm’s  iconic  turn,  as  Bartmanski  (2012b)  suggests?  And  what  are  the  differences  be-­‐

tween  these  two  approaches?    

Considering   the   incongruence   one   finds   when   reading   Iconic   Power,   it   seems   that  

Moxey   (2008:  136)   was   true   not   only   in   his   comparison   of   pictorial   and   iconic   turn:  

“Curiously  enough,  the  Anglo-­‐American  and  German  initiatives  often  appear  to  be  un-­‐

aware  of  each  other,  though  they  have  much  in  common.”  In  the  following  chapter,  I  

argue  that  there  is  a  similar  unfamiliarity34  emergent  between  the  notion  of  iconic  turn  

                                                                                               

34   Interestingly   enough,   Alexander   has   never   quoted   any   of   Boehm’s   work   (the   only   exception   is   the  introduction  to  Iconic  Power  that  was,  however,  written  in  cooperation  with  Bartmanski  2012).  This  fact  may  shed  light  on  some  fundamental  differences  between  “their”  respective  iconic  turns.  

 58  

in   the   form   proposed   by   Boehm   and   the   iconic   turn   suggested   by   the   strong   pro-­‐

gramme  with   the   purpose   of   comparing   the   two   rather   different   perspectives  made  

visible  by  Iconic  Power.  

Although  both  approaches  indeed  agree  on  the  importance  of  shifting  scholarly  atten-­‐

tion  to  the  visual,  which  has  been  deliberately  ignored  for  decades,  and  that  both  visu-­‐

ality   and   linguality   are   equally   fundamental   for  meaning-­‐making,   I  was  dealing  with  

the  question  how  is  it  possible  that  Bartmanski,  with  reference  to  the  iconic  turn,  sug-­‐

gests  to  overcome  the  duality  of  word  and  image,  while  Boehm  and  other  theorist  of  

iconic  turn  insist  on  their  categorical  difference?  Drawing  on  the  research  presented  in  

the  previous  chapters,  on  arguments  suggested  by  Bernhard  Giesen  (2012)  in  afterword  

to   Iconic  Power  and  also  on  current  efforts  made   in  picture  analysis,   I  argue  that  the  

crucial  differences  stem  from  one  simple  fact  that  was  already  pointed  out  by  Giesen:  

they  have  and  work  with  different  conceptions  of  iconicity.  

3.1. Boehm’s  iconic  turn  The  core  of  Boehm’s   theoretical  effort   is,   in   the   first  place,  strictly  art   theoretical.  As  

such,  the  method  used  for  analysis  of  visual  objects  draws  mostly  on  the  interpretative  

effort  made  by  Panofsky   (1.2)   that   is   constantly  kept   in  use  and   improved   to   fit   con-­‐

temporary  needs.  

The  iconic  turn  proposed  by  Boehm  insists  on  keeping  categorical  boundaries  between  

images   and   texts   because   it   recognizes   their   different   ontological   status.   Similar   as-­‐

sumption  can  be  found  in  the  work  of  Roland  Barthes,  who  mentions  projective  pow-­‐

ers  and  polysemy  of  images  that  are  opposed  to  repressive  value  of  texts.  From  his  per-­‐

spective,  texts  are  usually  used  to  “fix  the  floating  chain  of  signifieds  in  such  a  way  as  to  

counter  the  terror  of  uncertain  signs,”  i.e.  to  reduce  the  polysemy35  (Barthes  1977:  38–

39).  

                                                                                               

35  Barthes  also  differentiates  two  functions  of  text  in  relation  to  image:  anchorage  using  repressive  value,  and  relay  that  works  in  a  complementary  relation  to  an  image  Barthes  1977:  39–41  .  

 59  

For  Boehm,  too,  the  way  how  images  and  texts  create  meaning  is  different.  If  there  are  

any   structural   qualities   of   text   comparable   to   those   typical   of   image,   they   are   to   be  

found  in  metaphor,  which  is  characteristic  by  “incompleteness,  openness  and  ambigui-­‐

ty  of  the  form,”  (Boehm  2006:  26)  and  by  the  impossibility  to  translate  a  metaphor—

linguistic   image—into  normal   language.  Boehm  calls   the   specific  ability  of   images   to  

activate  passions  and  evoke  meaning  iconic  difference  (for  a  broader  discussion  of  the  

term  see  1.6).  Iconic  difference  constitutes  the  possibility  to  see  “something”  in  the  im-­‐

age,  something  different  than  strokes,  lines  and  stains  of  color;  it  “separates  the  visual  

surface  of  an  image  from  its  emerging  visual  depth”  (Binder  2012:  102,  my  italics).  Icon-­‐

ic  difference  can  also  be   (due   to   its   rather  vague  definition)   interpreted  as   “the   rela-­‐

tionship  between  the  material  presence  of  images  and  the  represented,  but  in  fact  ab-­‐

sent,  reality”  (Giesen  2012:  248),  which,   in  other  words,  means  that  the   image  “shows  

itself,  but  also  something  different”  (Binder  2013:  78).  Iconic  difference  thus  makes  im-­‐

ages  distinct  in  comparison  to  texts,  for  it  accounts  for  their  simultaneity,  which  pro-­‐

vides   images   with   specific   meaning   that   cannot   be   substituted   by   anything   else  

(Bohnsack  2007:  35).   It   is  also  due  to  their   iconicity  why  “(p)ictures  don’t  allow  us  to  

translate  them  fully  into  discursive  language.”  (Michel  2006:  64)  To  sum  up,  the  basic  

assumption  of  iconic  turn  is  that  images  are  categorically  different  from  linguistic  sys-­‐

tems  by  their  simultaneity  and  iconicity.  Thus,  if  we  want  to  treat  images  equally  fun-­‐

damental  for  creating  social  meanings  as  we  do  with  texts,  we  have  to  focus  on  these  

special  qualities.  Hence,  as  Moxey  (2008)  puts  it,  iconic  turn  considers  physical  proper-­‐

ties  of  images  as  important  as  their  social  function  and  stresses  the  independence  and  

autonomy  of  the  visual.  

3.1.1. Focus:  genuinely  pictorial  aspects  of  the  image  Therefore,   the  methods   suggested   by   proponents   of   iconic   turn   focus   exclusively   on  

the  “genuinely  pictorial  aspects  of  the  image”  (Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012:  44),  as  is  

the  case  of  Max  Imdahl’s  iconic36.  In  reference  to  Panofsky’s  method,  iconic  was  meant  

to  improve  the  model  suggested  for  iconological  interpretation.  For  Imdahl,  the  prob-­‐                                                                                                

36  The  following  description  of  Imdahl’s  iconic  draws  heavily  on  Bohnsack’s  (2009)  article  about  picture  interpretation  and  the  documentary  method.  

 60  

lem  of  iconology  was  that  it  searches  meanings  with  the  help  or  through  texts  (consid-­‐

er  the  iconographical  analysis  based  on  literary  and  textual  knowledge  (1.2.1)).  There-­‐

fore,   iconic   interpretation   begins   on   the   level   of   pre-­‐iconographical   description   and  

subsequently  does  not  proceed  to  the  level  of  meaning  dependent  on  content.  Instead,  

Imdahl  focuses  on  the  formal  composition  and  significance  of  forms,  trying  to  abstain  

from   textual   iconographical   knowledge.   The   methodological   suppression   of   textual  

knowledge  enables  Imdahl  to  treat  image  as  a  self-­‐referential  system37,  while  the  picto-­‐

rial   composition   itself   provides   him   with   access   to   iconic   meaning.   This   meaning  

(Sinnkomplexität  des  Übergegensätzlichen,  translated  as  “complexity  of  meaning  char-­‐

acterized  by  transcontrariness”)  escapes  verbal  expression38  and  can  only  be  described  

“in  direct  reference  to  the  picture”  (Bohnsack  2009:  308).  That  is  also  the  reason  why  

Imdahl   always   introduces   and   demonstrates   his   iconic   empirically   on   images  

(Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012:  44).  

A  similar  goal  to  come  up  with  an  interpretive  method  that  would  cease  to  explain  im-­‐

ages  through  texts  was  pursued  by  Mitchell  (1994),  who  suggested  a  new,  revised  ico-­‐

nology  called  critical  iconology.  However,  the  problem  with  Mitchell’s  iconology  is  that  

it  does  not  distinguish  between  pictures  and  visual  culture   (Belting  2002:  15).  To  un-­‐

derstand  why  it   is   important,   from  the  perspective  of   iconic  turn,  to  differentiate  be-­‐

tween  two-­‐  and  three-­‐  dimensional  works  of  art,  it  is  suitable  to  turn  to  Imdahl’s  work  

again.   In  his   text  about   iconic   (2006),  he  develops  an  argument  concerning   the  con-­‐

trast  between  the  medium  of  image  and  of  sculpture  or  object.  He  argues  that  the  ex-­‐

perience   induced  by  an   image  and  by  an  object   is   incomparable  at   least   in   three  as-­‐

pects.   First,   there   is   one   possible   view   for   an   image   but   an   indefinite   number   of  

                                                                                               

37  The  principle   is   similar   to  Boehm’s  concept  of   iconic  difference   that,   too,  assumes   that   images  gain  their  meanings  from  mutual  internal  oppositions.  

38   It   is   important  to  distinguish  between  the   impossibility  to  translate  the  exact  meanings  of  an  image  into  language  and  the  impossibility  to  interpret  or  talk  about  these  meanings  at  all.  For  example,  Barthes  expresses  the  opinion  that  we  cannot  describe  this  complexity  of  meaning,  which  he  calls  “obtuse”  and  which   exists   outside   the   language   system   (Bohnsack   2009:  308).   Contrary   to   that,   Imdahl   and   others  approve   of   the   possibility   of   interpretation:   “Though   images   can   never   be   completely   translated   into  language,  we  are  able  to  talk  about  images  and  share  our  experiences  with  them”  (Binder  2012:103).  This  assumption  is  also  crucial  for  a  scholarly  study  of  images;  as  Binder  (2013)  also  aptly  points  out,  if  we  do  not  develop  a  way  of  talking  and  writing  about  images,  we  will  become  mystics.    

 61  

possible  views  of  a  statue.  Hence,  second,  the  image,  its  view,  and  the  experience  of  it  

stay   the  same   for  ever,  while  with   the  sculpture   there   is  no  main-­‐view  and  no  main-­‐

experience  given.  Third,  the  imagination  is  in  both  situations  focused  differently:  when  

encountering   the   object,   the   consciousness   is   focused   on   the   present,   while   during  

viewing   the   picture   the   spectator’s   imagination   focuses   on   the   absent   (Imdahl  

2006:  319–324).  Now,  the  focus  on  the  absent,  which  is  created  by  iconic  difference  and  

therefore  distinctive  of   images,  becomes  one  of   the  principal  disagreements  between  

iconic   turn   introduced  by   art   theoreticians   and  between   the   second   iconic   turn,   an-­‐

nounced  by  cultural  sociologists.  

3.2. Iconic  turn  of  the  strong  programme  The   fact   that   there   are  different  matters   of   interest   formulated  by  proponents  of   re-­‐

spective   iconic  turns  becomes  clear  when  we  compare  the  main  questions  asked.  On  

one  hand,  there  is  the  problem  of  How  images  create  meaning?  (Boehm  and  Mitchell  

2009:  106).   On   the   other   hand,   we   have   a   question   How   meaning   manifests   itself  

through  materiality?  (Alexander  2010a:  12)  

Therefore,  the  focus  of   iconic  theory  suggested  by  the  strong  programme  lies  not  ex-­‐

clusively   on   images,   but   it   seems   to   encompass   everything39:   from   images   to   objects  

and  persons  to  events.  Obviously,  the  meaning  of  “iconic”  denotes  something  different  

in  comparison  with  Boehm;  in  fact,  the  word  is  used  in  a  common,  everyday  way,  and  

therefore  understood  as  “socially  eminent  status”  (Giesen  2012:  249).  Furthermore,  to-­‐

gether  with  the  emphasis  put  on  emotions  triggered  by  icons,  the  cultural  sociological  

notion   of   iconicity   becomes   rather   sensual   and   therefore   similar   to   aura,   continues  

Giesen.   “If   we   can   reduce   without   remainder   the   meaning   of   ‘iconic’   to   ‘auratic’   or  

‘charismatic,’  why  do  we  need  the  term?”  (Giesen  2012:  250).  

In  reaction  to  Giesen’s  critique,  Bartmanski  and  Alexander  (2012)  admit  that  the  prob-­‐

lem  how  to  define  iconicity  will  probably  become  a  contested  issue,  provided  that  the  

                                                                                               

39  While  Alexander  talks  about  his  “vitalist  vision,  with  its  omnivorous,  boundary-­‐crossing  aestheticism”  (2008:  11),  Giesen  in  his  critique  prefers  the  term  “colourful  multifariousness”    (2012:  249).  

 62  

concept   of   icon  will   gain   broader   attention  within   sociological   theory.   If   we   do   not  

want  to  evade  the  problem  of  defining  icon  (even  though  Sonnevend  (2012:  223)  argues  

that  due  to  various  substances  and  complex  interrelations  of   icons   it   is   impossible  to  

define  them  for  sociological  purposes),  two  elementary  problems  and  puzzles  remain  

to  be  solved.  The  first  main  question  for  us  to  ask  is,  whether  iconicity  should  refer  to  

visual   images   exclusively   or  whether  we   should  make   an   effort   in   encompassing   the  

whole   sensual   experience.   The   second   questions   deals   with   the   problem   of   “sacred-­‐

ness”  of  icons;  should  we  focus  on  mundane  objects  of  everyday  experience,  or  should  

the   iconic   theory  deal  only  with   “sacred,”  auratic   things?   (Bartmanski  and  Alexander  

2012:  11)  The  purpose  of  the  following  discussion  is  to  suggest  possible  solutions  to  the-­‐

se  crucial  problems.  Drawing  on  the  approach  of  art  theoretical  iconic  turn,  Panofsky’s  

iconology   and   Bohnsack’s   documentary  method   for   analyzing   pictures,   I   argue   that  

future  approach  to  iconicity  should  stick  with  its  visual  definition.  Subsequently,  I  also  

demonstrate  the  benefit  of  combining  both  visuality  and  sacredness  in  the  definition  of  

icon  in  Binder’s  approach.  

3.3. Suggestions    Although  there  is  probably  no  art  historian  or  theoretician  who  would  not  know,  refer  

to  or  oppose  Panofsky’s  method  of  iconological  interpretation  of  works  of  arts,  in  the  

sociological   field  has  Panofsky   remained   relatively   unnoticed.  The   importance   of   his  

work  is  mirrored  in  the  vocabulary  used  by  scholars  dealing  with  arts,  namely  in  cogni-­‐

zant  and  unified  use  of  terms  pre-­‐iconography,  iconography,  and  iconology.  Therefore  

it   is   rather   confusing   to   adopt   only   the   “surface”  without   its   “depth”,   i.e.   to   use   the  

terms  independently  on  their  (almost  traditional)  meaning  in  the  way  as  cultural  soci-­‐

ology   in   its   iconic   theory   did.   As   a   consequence,   Alexander   (2008)   treats   the   icon-­‐  

words  completely  arbitrarily  and  mixes   iconic  with   iconographic  etc.  When  Panofsky  

gets   quoted,   it   is   only   for   the   sake   of   a   general   critical   reference   to   the   iconological  

method40.  However,   it   seems   that   greater   familiarity  with   Panofsky’s  writings  would  

                                                                                               

40  Bartmanski  writes:   “(I)f  visual   research  was  systematically  conducted  at  all,   it   focused  on  delimited,  mostly   pictorial   artistic   representations   and   conventional   symbols   (e.g.   Panofsky).   Its   key   descriptive  and  explanatory  category  was   ‘reflection’.  From  the  so-­‐defined  scientific  vantage  point,   the  visible,  ex-­‐

 63  

not  only  prevent  the  terminological  inconsistencies  and  limit  the  use  of  icon-­‐  terms  to  

images,  which  are  just  a  tip  of  the  iceberg.  

Until  now,  as  Bartmanski   rightly  notes,   “sociology  has  evidenced  hardly  any  concern  

for  iconicity”  (2012:  11),  and  therefore  its  methods  for  dealing  with  pictures  are  still  “in  

infancy”   (Bohnsack   2009:  317).   The  main   benefit   of   giving   voice   to   Panofsky   and   his  

successors  is  that  it  can  provide  us  with  more  elaborated  methods  for  gaining  access  to  

and  interpretation  of  images.  “If  we  distinguish  just  between  surface  and  depth,  we  risk  

plunging   immediately   to   the   iconological   dimension,”   warned   Giesen   (2012:  248)  

against  too  simplistic  and  reductive  division  of  analytical  components  of  icons.  Let  us  

take  a  closer  look  at  this  statement.  

3.3.1. Surface  &  depth  is  not  enough  The   fact   that   Alexander’s   analytical   perspective   on   icon   draws   heavily   on   Barthes  

makes  him  to  miss  some  important  achievements  of  art  theory.  In  Alexander’s  concept  

of  icon  we  find  an  interplay  of  two  constituents,  namely  of  surface  and  depth.  This  ana-­‐

lytical  division  is  based  on  Barthes’s  notion  of  myth,  as  I  demonstrated  above  (2.4).  In  

other  words,  iconic  surface  stands  for  mythical  form  and  iconic  depth  for  the  content  

or  meaning  of  the  myth.  Moving  from  the  theoretical  level  to  practical  image  analysis,  

the  Barthesian  form  has  its  equivalent  in  the  literal,  denoted  message,  while  the  mes-­‐

sage  filling  up  the  content  is  connoted.  Now,  translated  into  terms  of  Panofsky’s  icono-­‐

logical  method,  analyzing  the  denoted  message  corresponds  to  the  pre-­‐iconographical  

description  on  the  level  of  phenomenal  meaning,  and  decoding  of  the  connoted  mes-­‐

sage  is  analogue  to  Panofsky’s  iconographical  analysis  of  meaning  dependent  on  con-­‐

tent,  which  is  based  on  the  textual  knowledge  (in  this  point  we  recognize  the  assump-­‐

tion  about   the  mutual   relationship  of   image  and  word  or,   in  other  words,  of   surface  

and   depth).   Hence,   the   conceptual   problem   with   icon   becomes   obvious—what   has  

been  left  out  is  the  level  of  intrinsic  or  documentary  meaning  that  can  be  achieved  on-­‐

                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                                     

pressive,   aesthetic   entities   designed   by   individuals   and   groups   typically   ‘reflected’  motives   and   struc-­‐tures  of  power  and/or  ‘mirrored’  conditions  of  their  possibility.  Put  differently,  the  seen  was  constructed  mostly  passively.  The  focus  was  on  why  and  what  made  images,  not  on  how  and  what  images  themselves  do  or  can  generate  in  turn.”  (2012b:  5)  

 64  

ly  by  iconological  interpretation.  Although  Giesen  (2012)  argues  that  the  surface-­‐depth  

division  causes  an  immediate  passage  to  the  iconological  dimension,  after  the  compar-­‐

ison  of  writings  by  Panofsky,  Barthes   and  Alexander,   a   conclusion   suggested  by  Ralf  

Bohnsack  seems  more  plausible:  “On  the  basis  of  Roland  Barthes’  theory  of  semiotics,  

there  seems  to  be  no  successful  way  to  develop  a  method  for  the  interpretation  of  pic-­‐

tures  which   is   relevant   for   the  social   sciences  and   is  able   to   transcend   the  surface  of  

iconographical   or   connotative   meanings.”   (Bohnsack   2009:  308)   Bohnsack   also   sup-­‐

ports  this  claim  by  pointing  at  Barthes’  notion  of  “obtuse”  meaning  that  transcends  the  

level  of  connotative  meaning,   is  characteristic   for   images,  and  exists  outside   the   lan-­‐

guage  and   therefore   remains   inarticulable   and   inexpressive  by  words  and   interpreta-­‐

tion.  Analytical   distinction  of   surface   and  depth  does   thus  not   go  deep   enough,   and  

practically  prevents  us  from  talking  about  and  interpreting  the  obtuse  meaning  charac-­‐

teristic  of  images.  To  support  this  argument,  I  revise  Alexander’s  account  of  icons  tak-­‐

en   from  his   Iconic  Experience   in  Art  and  Life   (2008)  and  Celebrity-­‐Icon   (2010b)  using  

Panofsky’s  terminology.  

In   the  analysis  of  Giacometti’s  Standing  Woman,  Alexander  begins  with  an  extensive  

description  of   the  statue’s   surface,  which  reminds  of  Panofsky’s  pre-­‐iconographic  de-­‐

scription.   Afterwards   he   introduces   Giacometti’s   biography,   while   quoting   his   diary  

and  other  resources  documenting  changes  in  artist’s  methods  and  worldview.  This  se-­‐

cond  step  is  thus,  by  its  embedment  in  narrative,  analogue  to  iconographical  analysis  

based   on   literary   knowledge.   A   very   similar   approach   is   used   in   the   example   with  

Audrey  Hepburn’s  Little  Black  Dress.  Here  we  are  offered  with  a  collection  of  stories  

connected  to  the  famous  actress,  the  famous  movie  and  the  famous  dress.  The  iconic  

character  of  the  dress  is  illustrated  by  strong  feelings  of  thrill  experienced  and  noted  by  

Hepburn’s  fans  who  have  encountered  garments  once  owned  and  worn  by  the  actress.  

The  sensual  surface  of  the  icon  draws  us  into  the  depth  and  enables  us  to  feel  the  icon-­‐

ic  meaning.  In  both  cases,  however,  the  icons  described  by  Alexander  are  embedded  in  

discourse,   which   bestows   them   with   deeper   meaning   (Binder   2012:  102).   In   other  

words,   if   the  dress  would  not  have  starred  in  Breakfast  at  Tiffany’s,   the  experience  of  

wearing  it  would  not  have  been  the  same.  The  problem  of  this  approach  is  that  without  

narratives,  Alexander’s   icons  become  mere  stuff.   If  one  does  not  know  the  movie,  he  

 65  

can  barely  experience  immersion  when  he  encounters  the  Little  Black  Dress,  for  he  will  

encounter  a  little  black  dress;  the  same  applies  to  the  statue  of  Standing  Woman.  

However,  if  we  limit  our  notion  of  iconic  experience  to  images  and  define  iconicity  as  

their  unique  quality,  we  may  proceed  with  the  analysis  further,  drawing  on  the  ability  

of   images   to  create  visual  depth  on   the  principle  of   iconic  difference.  Only   then   it   is  

possible  to  claim  that  “the  emergence  of  iconic  depth  is  never  completely  arbitrary,  but  

rather   tied   to   the   iconic  properties  of   the  surface”   (Binder  2012:  102).   In  other  words,  

icons-­‐images  have  the  power  to  elicit  emotional  reactions  even  if  the  viewer  does  not  

know  the  context  to  which  their  surface  points  to  (consider  Binder’s  example  of  iconic  

photographs  from  Abu  Ghraib  (2013),  or  Nick  Ut’s  famous  Napalm  Girl).  But  we  should  

not  stick  with  mere  wrapping  of  the  sensual  experience  of  an  icon  into  related  narra-­‐

tives,   for  this  approach  terminates  on  the  iconographical   level  of  analysis  and  cannot  

transcend  it:  “What  we  can  achieve  (…)  is  a  range  of  colorful  stories  about  the  rise  of  an  

“icon”  to  fame  and  its  impact  on  collective  identity”  (Giesen  2012:  249).  

3.3.2. Problem  of  pre-­‐reflexive  experience  Bartmanski   notes   that   the   unresolved   questions   that   should   be   answered   by   iconic  

theory  are  “How  exactly  does  the  visual  inform  what  we  know  and  shape  what  we  be-­‐

lieve?  How  contingent  is   its  elusive  power  on  other  aspects  of  social   life?”  (2012b:  13).  

The  underlying  assumption  of  these  questions,  namely  that  images  condition  our  en-­‐

tire  worldview  (Weltanschauung)  and  that  they  not  only  conserve  and  transmit  it,  but  

also  help  to  mediate  and  negotiate  it  (Przyborski  and  Slunecko  2012:  40),  is  shared  also  

by   recent   sociology   influenced  by  Boehm’s   iconic   turn  and  dealing  with   images.  The  

problem   is   that  one  cannot  directly  ask  people  about   their  perception  of   images,   for  

such   a   question  would   be   based   on   the   assumption   that   they   are   able   to   formulate  

their   habitualized   knowledge   (ibid.:  47).   Put   differently,   iconic   experience   is   pre-­‐

reflexive,   i.e.   below   the   level   of   explication   (Bohnsack   2009:  299)—this   assumption  

corresponds  to  the  notion  of  sensual  iconic  experience,  which  is  based  on  understand-­‐

ing  by  “feeling”  described  by  Alexander  (2010a).  According  to  Becker,  such  emotional  

effects  of  works  of  arts  are  produced  by  shared,  social  conventions  and  customs  (Beck-­‐

er  1974a:  771).  Belting  calls  this  a  phenomenon  of  period  eye,  by  which  he  expresses  the  

 66  

fact  that  the  way  how  people  view  works  of  arts41  is  closely  bound  up  with  conventions  

of  perceiving  of  our  own  time  that  cannot  be  explained  by  mere  physiological  vision42  

(Belting  2000:  161).  However,  different  conventions  of  perceiving  are   limited  not  only  

temporarily,   but   also   culturally,   for   people   from   different   cultural   contexts   do   not  

share   the   “way   of   viewing”   (e.g.   reaction   of   the  Arab  world   to  Mohammed   cartoons  

compared  with  Abu  Ghraib  photographs  (Binder  2012:  114)).  In  order  to  achieve  under-­‐

standing  in  a  communication  via  images,  there  is  a  necessary  condition  of  being  “able  

to   read  visual   images   in   roughly   similar  ways”   (Hall   1997:  4).  People  use  conventions  

for  understanding   images  unreflexively,   “just   as  we  may  not   know   the   grammar   and  

syntax  of  our  verbal   language  though  we  speak  and  understand   it”   (Becker   1974b:  6).  

The  unreflexive  character  of  understanding  is  recognized  also  by  Alexander,  when  he  

writes   that   iconic  knowledge   is  based  on  experience—one   “simply  knows”.  However,  

he  grounds  the  ability  of  “simply  knowing”  in  one’s  disposition  to  be  moved  and  does  

not  address   this   issue  any   further.  By   that  he   rather  evades   the   issue  of  atheoretical,  

aesthetic   experience,  which   thus   remains   a   challenging   question   iconic   theory   in   its  

cultural  sociological  form.  

3.3.3. Bohnsack’s  documentary  method  The  point  of  departure   formulated  by  Bohnsack   is  congruent  with   the  basic  assump-­‐

tions   of   iconic   turn:   social   reality   is   constituted   by   images   that   have   the   capacity   to  

provide   orientation   for   action   and   everyday   practice,   since   typification   is   based   on  

mental  images  that  depend  on  iconic  knowledge  (2009).  However,  the  understanding  

“through  the  medium  of  iconicity  is  mostly  pre-­‐reflexive,”  and  therefore  belongs  to  the  

level  of  atheoretical  or  tacit  knowledge,  which  is  imparted  by  iconicity,  text  and  prac-­‐

tice  (ibid.:  299).  On  one  hand,  the  access  to  tacit  knowledge  is  provided  by  the  transi-­‐

tion  from  iconography  to  iconology  in  Panofsky’s  analysis  that  enables  us  to  reveal  the  

instrinsic,  documentary  meaning—Wesenssinn  (i.e.  characteristic  meaning  that  docu-­‐

                                                                                               

41  The   reference   to   art  does  not,  however,   prevent  us   from  assuming   that   the   same  hold   true   also   for  viewing  in  general.  

42  The  period  eye  phenomenon  reminds  of  Boehm’s  distinction  between  seeing   (as  a  physical  process)  and  viewing  (as  a  meaning-­‐making  activity)  (1.6.1).  

 67  

ments  itself),  or  habitus.  The  problem  with  Panofsky’s  method  is  that  it  was  not  meant  

exclusively   for   analyzing   images   but   rather   aimed   at   different   media.   On   the   other  

hand,  if  we  want  to  analyze  only  images,  we  can  proceed  from  the  pre-­‐iconographical  

description  in  a  way  suggested  by  Imdahl  (3.1.1)  and  transcend  the  iconographical  level  

by  analyzing  the  composition  and  formal  structures  in  a  medium  of  picture.  Imdahl’s  

iconic  treats  images  as  self-­‐referential  systems  and  avoids  explaining  pictures  by  texts,  

while  the  main  focus  lies  on  formal  structures  of  images,  which  are  considered  docu-­‐

ments  for  “the  natural  order”  produced  by  actors  themselves  (Bohnsack  2009:  316).  The  

goal  of  Bohnsack’s  documentary  method  remains  the  same  as  the  one  of  iconology—it  

aims  at  the  level  of  tacit  knowledge  and  documentary  meaning  and  endeavors  to  gain  

access  to  the  space  of  experience  of  picture  producers.  A  central  element  of  this  space  

is  then  individual  or  collective  habitus.  

Panofsky’s  “habitus  could  be  defined  (...)  as  a  system  of  internalized  schemes  that  have  

the  capacity   to  generate  all   the   thoughts,  perceptions,  and  actions  characteristic  of  a  

culture,   and   nothing   else,”   wrote   Bourdieu   (2005:  233).  With   the   concept   of   habitus  

one  can  then  explain  both  the  reception  and  the  production  of  images,  for  it  emerges  

on  the  underlying  principles  characteristic  of  a  given  culture  and  epoch.  A  similar  view  

expressed  Boehm  by  claiming  that  “images  are  bodies  that  are  subject  to  historical  de-­‐

terminants  and  effects  as  well  as   forces  generating  images  and  claiming  recognition,”  

(2012).  The  assumption  that  reception  is  part  of  habitus  confirmed  Michel  in  his  study  

(2006).  Since  images  are  open  and  contain  no  inherent  meaning,  the  meaning  emerges  

in  the  process  of  understanding,  during  which  the  form  and  the  content  are  put   in  a  

relation.  This  understanding   is  directed  by  a  convention  of  a  specific  group  and  thus  

socially  embedded  he  concludes  (Michel  2006:  20).  

The  problem  with  Bohnsack’s  method  is  that  the  search  for  habitus  through  the  analy-­‐

sis  of  surface  qualities  of  an  image  leads  us  to  the  sphere  of  tacit  knowledge,  which  is  

informed   by   images   and   its   central   element   habitus.   Asking   how   the   visual   shapes  

what   we   believe   thus   seems   to   lead   to   pre-­‐reflexive   experience   (reception),   conven-­‐

tions  and  production  of  images  (photographs,  to  be  exact,  since  Bohnsack’s  method  is  

aimed  at  them),  which  all  stem  from  atheoretical  knowledge  and  are  part  of  the  habi-­‐

tus.  The  genuinely  social  aspect  of  icons  as  defined  by  Bartmanski  and  Alexander,  the  

 68  

power  to  generate  strong  collective  feelings  and  catalyze  action  while  having  impact  on  

collective   identity,   is   then   left  out.  At   this  point,   the  approach   to   icons  suggested  by  

Werner  Binder  (2012,  2013)  seems  promising.  

3.3.4. Binder’s  secular  icon  First  of  all,  Binder  pays  attention  to  the  origins  and  meanings  of  the  word  icon.  On  one  

hand,   it  denotes  pictures  and   images,   i.e.   it   is   connected   to  vision,  and  on   the  other  

hand  it  is  a  religious  symbol,  an  object  of  modern  rituals.  Further  he  shows  that  visual-­‐

ity  and  sacredness  were  fused  not  just  in  the  religious  icons  of  past  time;  quite  the  con-­‐

trary,   he   finds   a   fusion   of   the   same   elements   in   contemporary   secular   icons   (Binder  

2012:  101–102).  That  leads  him  to  define  and  treat  icons  as  visual  representations  of  the  

sacred43.  

The  notion  of  visual  character  of  icons  allows  Binder  to  adopt  methods  of  image  analy-­‐

sis  suggested  by  art  theory  and  Bohnsack,  which  take  into  account  the  pictorial  aspects  

of  an  image.  “The  prerequisite  of  iconic  depth  is  of  course  the  iconic  difference.  Only  

because  the  image  has  the  power  to  reveal  something  else  is  the  emergence  of  an  icon-­‐

ic  depth  possible.”  (Binder  2012:  107)  Thus,  special  qualities  of  the  surface  allows  for  the  

creation  of  immaterial  depth,  which  is  “created  by  an  interaction  of  spectator  and  ma-­‐

terial   surface,   by   the  dialectic   of   ‘immersion’   and   ‘materialization,’   informed  but  not  

determined  by  discourses”  (ibid.).  To  sum  up,  there  are  two  important  elements  to  this  

understanding  of  secular  icon.  The  visual  surface  allows  us  to  employ  the  methods  for  

image   analysis   based   exclusively   on   formal   and   compositional   qualities   of   an   image,  

which  suppresses  the  textual-­‐based  knowledge  of  context.  At  the  same  time,  the  analy-­‐

sis  of   iconic  depth  takes  discourses  and  rituals   into  consideration  and  allows  for  em-­‐

bedment  of  meaning  of  the  secular  icon  in  the  context  made  up  by  narratives  and  prac-­‐

                                                                                               

43  The  use  of  cultural  sociological  master  binary  of  sacred  and  profane  is  by  no  means  consistent  in  the  literature.  Alexander  (1990)  interpreted  sacred  as  good  and  profane  as  evil,  which  does  not  correspond  to  Durkheim  (1976)  who  distinguishes  between  pure  and  impure  sacred  (good  and  evil)  in  opposition  to  profane.  Elsewhere   (2010a),  he  uses   the  same  distinction   translated   into  aesthetic   terms,  when  the  sa-­‐cred-­‐good   is   thought   of   as   the   beautiful   and   the   profane-­‐evil   becomes   the   sublime.  However,   Binder  interprets  Durkheim’s  binary  as  the  opposition  between  sacred  as  collective  versus  profane,  mundane  as  individual.   Contrary   to   that,   Alexander’s   understanding   is   always   collective,   distinguishing   between  sacred  as  extraordinary,  transcendental,  auratic  etc.  and  mundane,  everyday  (2008).  

 69  

tices.  Thus,  in  this  approach  the  aesthetic  qualities  and  the  social  aspects  of  a  secular  

icon  are  separated  for  the  sake  of  respective  analysis,  but  combined  and  intertwined  in  

interpretation.  

“Secular  icons,  due  to  their  specific  visual  surface,  create  an  iconic  depth  that  allows  them  to  become  symbols   in  modern  rituals.  To  be  sure,  it  is  always  the  properly  socialized  spectator  and  the  civil  discourses   that   endow   an   image   with   deeper   public   meanings.  However,   the  emergence  of   iconic  depth   is  never  completely  arbi-­‐trary,   but   rather   tied   to   the   iconic   properties   of   the   surface.”  (Binder  2012:  102)    

 70  

 

 71  

4  Conclusion  

Whether   scholars  were   “bored  with   the   ‘linguistic   turn’”   (Moxey   2008:  131)   or   simply  

inspired   and   excited   by   the   aesthetic   experience   of   the  material   world   that   encom-­‐

passes  us,  the  accent  put  on  materiality  by  the  strong  programme  in  his  iconic  theory  

represents   an   important   step   toward   giving   voice   to  material   objects   that   shape   and  

influence   collective   identity   and   social   action.   The   effort   to   include  materiality   into  

sociological   theory  has  brought  sociological   thinking  closer  to  everyday   life,   for   it   fo-­‐

cuses   not   only   on   aesthetic   experience   of   art   but   also   on   common  mundane   experi-­‐

ence,  in  which  iconic  consciousness  gained  by  experience  plays  a  central  role.  Without  

doubt,  the  idea  to  make  sensational  experiences  part  of  serious  sociological  interest  is  

similarly  groundbreaking  as  pioneering  work  of  Mitchell  or  Boehm  in  art   theory  was  

years  ago.  To  suggest  a  cultural  sociological  iconic  theory  is  to  declare  emancipation  of  

scholarly  interest  from  its  discursive  limits,  to  offer  new  possibilities  for  gaining  access  

to  social  reality,  and  thus  open  new  horizons  for  research  as  well.  By  giving  voice  to  the  

visual   and   the  material   we   can   extend   our   understanding   of   how   cultural  meanings  

work;   they  are  not  anymore   transmitted  and   reproduced  only  by  narratives  and  per-­‐

formances.   The   inclusion   of  material   environment   into   sociological   theory   is   also   of  

considerable   importance   with   respect   to   Alexander’s   general   theoretical   effort.   The  

notion  of  icon  as  he  understands  it  reproduces  the  analytical  distinction  of  action  and  

 72  

structure  and  by  concentrating  both  on  materiality  as  well  as  sensuality  it  enables  his  

to  bridge  the  old  Marxist  opposition  and  incongruence  between  materialism  and  ideal-­‐

ism.  

One  of   the  main  benefits  of   iconic   turn   in  cultural   sociology   is,   after  all,   the   shift  of  

scholarly   attention   it   brought.   This   does   not  mean   sociologists  will   cease   to   analyze  

discourses  and  start  to  study  society  through  images;  the  most  important  thing  about  

the  change  of  perspective   is  that  they  will  not  grant   language  epistemological  prefer-­‐

ence  over   images  anymore.  Although  it  might  sound  odd  and  quite  against  our  com-­‐

monsensical  experience,  the  visual  has,  in  the  view  of  social  science,  only  recently  be-­‐

come  equally   important   for  social   life  as   language.  Sociological  analysis  of  pictures   is  

still  quite  young  and  therefore  dependent  on  interpretive  methods  developed  and  used  

by  art  theory  and  history.    

Emancipating   images   from  discursive  domination,  however,   does  not  mean   that   one  

can  analyze  and  interpret  images  in  the  same  way  as  texts.  This  is  the  key  message  we  

receive  from  the  proponents  of  iconic  turn,  art  theorists  gathered  around  Boehm.  Con-­‐

trary  to  the  claim  that  the  meanings  of  images  and  texts  are  mutually  intertwined,  both  

iconic  turn  as  well  as  pictorial  turn  stresses  the  necessity  to  analytically  separate  imag-­‐

es   from  textual  resources  during   interpretation.  What  we  gain  by  this  separation   is  a  

focus  freed  from  connotations  and  other  literary  meanings  that  enables  us  to  analyze  

image  on  the  basis  of  its  genuinely  pictorial  aspects.  Unlike  texts,  images  transmit  their  

meanings   simultaneously,   so   the  viewer   receives   the  whole   set  of   information  at  one  

and  the  same  time.  Furthermore,  images  are  open  and  ambiguous,  what  leaves  a  great  

room  for  interpretation  that  actually  never  reaches  its  end,  for  there  is  no  final  mean-­‐

ing  contained  within  an  image.  And  since  the  meanings  gained  from  images  are  histor-­‐

ically  and  culturally  dependent,   the  methods   suggested  by  art  history  and  art   theory  

endeavors   to   gain   access   to   the   broader   context   in  which   images  were  made,   to   the  

space  of  experience  shared  by  specific  individuals  within  specific  groups  and  societies  

in   a  specific   time.   The   original   method   of   iconological   interpretation   suggested   by  

Panofsky  has  in  one  of  its  steps  taken  literary  knowledge  into  consideration.  Imdahl’s  

method  called  iconic  enables  the  interpreter  to  reach  the  level  of  documentary  mean-­‐

ing   exclusively   by   analysis   of   compositional   and   formal   qualities   of   an   image.  

 73  

Bohnsack’s  documentary  method  aimed  at  photography  interpretation  draws  on  both  

methods  and  seeks  for  the  habitus  of  picture  producers.  To  sum  up,  there  is  a  lot  for  us  

to   learn,  especially   from  art  history  and  theory.  Since  sociology   lacks  years  of  experi-­‐

ence  in  dealing  with  images,  it  is  advisable,  especially  if  it  wants  to  integrate  the  aes-­‐

thetic  dimension   into   its   theory,   to   look   for   inspiration   in  other   fields  of  human  sci-­‐

ences.   Familiarity  with   concepts   and  methods   of   art   theory   could   help   us   develop   a  

strong  sociological  theory  of  iconicity.  

As  I  showed  above,  today’s  reality  is  different;  there  are  rather  controversies  than  unity  

regarding   the   iconic   theory   in   cultural   sociology.   There   are   voices   declaring   almost  

every  material  thing  an  icon,  while  others  rather  stick  with  its  traditional,  strictly  visual  

definition.  The  problem  of  missing  definition  makes  the  iconic  theory  quite  vague  and  

omnivorous  and  the  study  of  iconicity  rather  uncoordinated.  As  I  also  demonstrated,  it  

holds  current  analyses  on  the  iconographical  level  and  does  not  allow  us  to  transcend  

it.  My  suggestion  draws  on  Bohnsack’s  methodology,  on  its  application  in  cultural  so-­‐

ciological  image  interpretation  by  Binder  and  prefers  a  narrower  use  of  the  iconic  term.  

I  argue  that  the  term  should  remain  reserved  for  visual  media  in  their  specific,  sacred  

form.  What  we  gain  by  this  definition  of  icon  is  the  possibility  to  grasp  both  the  aes-­‐

thetic  experience  bound  to  iconic  surface  and  the  meaningful  depth  partly  informed  by  

discourses  and  social  practices.  In  this  visual  and  sacred  (or  to  use  Binder’s  term  secu-­‐

lar)  icon,  the  creation  of  iconic  depth  is  directly  linked  to  and  enabled  by  its  aesthetic  

properties.  In  other  words,  if  we  want  to  get  deeper  in  the  analysis  of  iconicity  and  to  

transcend   the  everyday,   commonsensical   experience  and  perspective  of   social   actors,  

paying  attention  to  the  formal  rules  and  conventions  of  the  composition  of  an  image  

seems  to  be  a  fruitful  way  to  go.  On  the  other  hand,  there  is  no  need  to  reject  the  use  

of  iconographical  analysis  that  searches  for  the  context  based  in  narratives.  

Even  if  the  iconic  turn  suggested  by  cultural  sociology  does  not  eventually  manage  to  

encompass  successfully  the  whole  sphere  of  materiality,  the  shift  of  scholarly  attention  

to  the  visual  is  itself  a  great  achievement.  As  Rorty  (1967:  2)  remarked  wisely,  “no  such  

revolution  is  in  vain.  If  nothing  else,  the  battles  fought  during  the  revolution  cause  the  

combatants  on  both  sides  to  repair  their  armor,  and  these  repairs  eventually  amount  to  

a  complete  change  of  clothes.”  

 74  

 75  

References  

Alexander,  J.  C.  1988.  “The  New  Theoretical  Movement”  Pp.  77–101,  in  Handbook  of  

Sociology,  edited  by  N.  J.  Smelser.  Newbury  Park,  California:  Sage  Publications  Inc.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  1990.  “The  Sacred  and  Profane  Information  Machine:  Discourse  about  the  

Computer  as  Ideology”  Archives  de  sciences  sociales  des  religions.  35:  161–171.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2003.  “Introduction:  The  Meanings  of  (Social)  Life:  On  the  Origins  of  a  Cultural  

Sociology”  Pp.  3–10  in  The  meanings  of  social  life.  A  cultural  sociology,  edited  by  J.  C.  

Alexander.  Oxford,  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2008.  “Iconic  Experience  in  Art  and  Life:  Surface/Depth  Beginning  with  

Giacometti’s  Standing  Woman”  Theory,  Culture  &  Society.  25:  1–19.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2010a.  “Iconic  Consciousness:  The  Material  Feeling  of  Meaning”  Thesis  Eleven.  

103:  10–25.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2010b.  “The  Celebrity-­‐Icon”  Cultural  Sociology.  4:  323–336.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2012.  “Iconic  power  and  performance:  the  role  of  the  critic”  Pp.  25–35  in  Iconic  

power.  Materiality  and  meaning  in  social  life,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander,  D.  Bartmanski,  

and  B.  Giesen.  New  York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

 76  

Alexander,  J.  C.  and  P.  Smith.  2003.  “The  Strong  Programme  in  Cultural  Sociology:  

Elements  of  a  Structural  Hermeneutics”  Pp.  11–26,  in  The  meanings  of  social  life.  A  

cultural  sociology,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander.  Oxford,  New  York:  Oxford  University  

Press.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2005.  “Introduction:  the  new  Durkheim”  Pp.  1–37  in  The  Cambridge  companion  to  

Durkheim,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander  and  P.  Smith.  Cambridge,  UK,  New  York:  

Cambridge  University  Press.  

Atkin,  A.  2005.  “Peirce  on  the  Index  and  Indexical  Reference”  Transaction  of  the  

Charles  S.  Peirce  Society.  XLI:  161–188.  

Barthes,  R.  1977.  “Rhetoric  of  the  Image”  Pp.  32–51  in  Image,  Music,  Text,  edited  by  S.  

Heath.  New  York:  The  Noonday  Press.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2012.  Mythen  des  Alltags.  Vol.  4338,  Berlin:  Suhrkamp.  

Bartmanski,  D.  2012a.  “How  to  become  an  iconic  social  thinker:  The  intellectual  

pursuits  of  Malinowski  and  Foucault”  European  Journal  of  Social  Theory.  15:  427–453.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2012b.  “The  word/image  dualism  revisited:  Towards  an  iconic  conception  of  

visual  culture”  Journal  of  Sociology:  1–18.  

Bartmanski,  D.  and  J.  C.  Alexander.  2012.  “Materiality  and  meaning  in  social  life:  

toward  an  iconic  turn  in  cultural  sociology”  Pp.  1–12,  in  Iconic  power.  Materiality  and  

meaning  in  social  life,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander,  D.  Bartmanski,  and  B.  Giesen.  New  

York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

Becker,  H.  S.  1974a.  “Art  As  Collective  Action”  American  Sociological  Review.  39:  767–

776.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  1974b.  “Photography  and  sociology”  Studies  in  the  anthropology  of  visual  

communication.  1:  3–26.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2000.  “What  Should  Sociology  Look  Like  in  the  (Near)  Future?”  Contemporary  

Sociology.  29:  333–336.  

Belting,  H.  2000.  Konec  dějin  umění.  Vol.  22,  Praha:  Mladá  fronta.  

 77  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2002.  Bild-­‐Anthropologie.  Entwürfe  für  eine  Bildwissenschaft,  München:  W.  Fink.  

Berger,  P.  L.  and  T.  Luckmann.  1991.  The  social  construction  of  reality.  A  treatise  in  the  

sociology  of  knowledge,  Harmondsworth:  Penguin.  

Beyst,  S.  2010.  Gottfried  Boehm  and  the  image.  Iconic  or  semiotic  turn?  http://d-­‐

sites.net/english/boehm.htm  (25  Apr  2014).  

Binder,  W.  2012.  “The  Emergence  of  Iconic  Depth.  Secular  Icons  in  a  Comparative  

Perspective”  Pp.  101–116,  in  Iconic  power.  Materiality  and  meaning  in  social  life,  edited  

by  J.  C.  Alexander,  D.  Bartmanski,  and  B.  Giesen.  New  York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2013.  Abu  Ghraib  und  die  Folgen.  Ein  Skandal  als  ikonische  Wende  im  Krieg  gegen  

den  Terror,  Bielefeld:  transcript.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2014a.  “Interpretation  of  Images.”  Advanced  Methods  of  Interpretation  in  Cultural  

Sociology.  Lecture  conducted  by  Masaryk  University,  Brno.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2014b.  “Structural  Hermeneutics  I.”  Advanced  Methods  of  Interpretation  in  

Cultural  Sociology.  Lecture  conducted  by  Masaryk  University,  Brno.  

Boehm,  G.  2006.  “Die  Wiederkehr  der  Bilder”  Pp.  11–37  in  Bild  und  Text,  Was  ist  ein  

Bild?,  edited  by  G.  Boehm.  München:  W.  Fink.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2007.  Wie  Bilder  Sinn  erzeugen.  Die  Macht  des  Zeichens,  Berlin:  Berlin  University  

Press.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2012.  “Representation,  Presentation,  Presence.  Tracing  the  Homo  Pictor”  in  

Iconic  power.  Materiality  and  meaning  in  social  life,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander,  D.  

Bartmanski,  and  B.  Giesen.  New  York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

Boehm,  G.  and  W.  J.  T.  Mitchell.  2009.  “Pictorial  versus  Iconic  Turn:  Two  Letters”  

Culture,  Theory  and  Critique.  50:  103–121.  

Bohnsack,  R.  2007.  “Zum  Verhältnis  von  Bild-­‐  und  Textinterpretation  in  der  

qualitativen  Sozialforschung.”  Pp.  21–46,  in  Bild  und  Text.  Methoden  und  

Methodologien  visueller  Sozialforschung,  edited  by  B.  Friebertshäuser.  Opladen:  

Budrich.  

 78  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2009.  “The  interpretation  of  pictures  and  the  documentary  method.”  Historical  

Social  Research.  34:  296–321.  

Bourdieu,  P.  2005.  “Postface  to  Erwin  Panofsky,  Gothic  Architecture  and  Scholasticism”  

Pp.  221–242,  in  The  premodern  condition.  Medievalism  and  the  making  of  theory,  edited  

by  B.  W.  Holsinger.  Chicago:  University  of  Chicago  Press.  

Bredekamp,  H.  1995.  “Words,  Images,  Ellipses.”  Pp.  363–372,  in  Meaning  in  the  visual  

arts.  Views  from  the  outside  :  a  centennial  commemoration  of  Erwin  Panofsky  (1892-­‐

1968),  edited  by  I.  Lavin.  Princeton:  Institute  for  Advanced  study.  

Buczynska-­‐Garewicz,  H.  1979.  “Peirce’s  Method  of  Triadic  Analysis  of  Signs”  Semiotica.  

26:  251–259.  

Durkheim,  É.  1976.  The  elementary  forms  of  the  religious  life,  London:  Allen  and  Unwin.  

Eberlein,  J.  K.  2003.  “Inhalt  und  Gehalt:  Die  ikonografisch-­‐ikonologische  Methode”  Pp.  

175–197,  in  Kunstgeschichte.  Eine  Einführung,  edited  by  H.  Belting,  H.  Dilly,  W.  Kemp,  

W.  Sauerländer,  and  M.  Warnke.  Berlin:  Reimer.  

Emirbayer,  M.  2004.  “The  Alexander  School  of  Cultural  Sociology”  Thesis  Eleven.  79:  5–

15.  

Giesen,  B.  2012.  “Afterword”  Pp.  247–251,  in  Iconic  power.  Materiality  and  meaning  in  

social  life,  edited  by  J.  C.  Alexander,  D.  Bartmanski,  and  B.  Giesen.  New  York:  Palgrave  

Macmillan.  

Gladwell,  M.  2007.  Blink.  The  power  of  thinking  without  thinking,  New  York:  Back  Bay  

Books.  

Goodman,  N.  1978.  Ways  of  worldmaking,  Indianapolis:  Hackett  Pub.  Co.  

Greub,  T.  2001.  Las  Meninas  im  Spiegel  der  Deutungen.  Eine  Einführung  in  die  Methoden  

der  Kunstgeschichte,  Berlin:  Reimer.  

Hall,  S.  1997.  “Introduction”  Pp.  1–12  in  Culture,  media,  and  identities,  Representation.  

Cultural  representations  and  signifying  practices,  edited  by  S.  Hall.  London,  Thousand  

Oaks,  Calif:  Sage  in  association  with  the  Open  University.  

 79  

Holly,  M.  A.  1984.  Panofsky  and  the  foundations  of  art  history,  Ithaca,  N.Y:  Cornell  

University  Press.  

Huening,  D.  2006.  Symbol,  index,  icon.  

http://csmt.uchicago.edu/glossary2004/symbolindexicon.htm  (06  May  2014).  

Imdahl,  M.  2006.  “Ikonik.  Bilder  und  ihre  Anschauung”  Pp.  300–324  in  Bild  und  Text,  

Was  ist  ein  Bild?,  edited  by  G.  Boehm.  München:  W.  Fink.  

Latour,  B.  2005.  Reassembling  the  social.  An  introduction  to  actor-­‐network-­‐theory,  

Oxford,  New  York:  Oxford  University  Press.  

Lattmann,  C.  2012.  “Icons  of  novel  thought:  A  new  perspective  on  Peirce’s  definition  of  

metaphor  (CP  2.277)”  Semiotica.  2012.  

Mannheim,  K.  1951.  Essay  on  the  sociology  of  knowledge,  London:  Routledge  &  Kegan  

Paul  LTD.  

Michel,  B.  2006.  Bild  und  Habitus.  Sinnbildungsprozesse  bei  der  Rezeption  von  

Fotografien,  Wiesbaden:  VS,  Verl.  für  Sozialwiss.  

Mitchell,  W.  J.  T.  1994.  Picture  theory.  Essays  on  verbal  and  visual  representation,  

Chicago,  Ill.  [u.a.]:  University  of  Chicago  Press.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2005.  What  do  pictures  want?  The  lives  and  loves  of  images,  Chicago:  University  

of  Chicago  Press.  

Moxey,  K.  2008.  “Visual  Studies  and  the  Iconic  Turn”  Journal  of  Visual  Culture.  7:  131–

146.  

Panofsky,  E.  1955.  Meaning  in  the  Visual  Arts.  Papers  in  and  on  Art  History,  Garden  

City:  Doubleday.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  1989.  Gotische  Architektur  und  Scholastik.  Zur  Analogie  von  Kunst,  Philosophie  

und  Theologie  im  Mittelalter.  Vol.  225,  Köln:  DuMont  Buchverlag.  

-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐-­‐.  2012.  “On  the  Problem  of  Describing  and  Interpreting  Works  of  the  Visual  Arts.”  

Critical  Inquiry.  38:  467–482.  

 80  

Peirce,  C.  S.  1998.  “What  is  a  Sign?”  Pp.  4–11,  in  The  essential  Peirce.  Selected  

philosophical  writings.  Bloomington,  Ind,  London:  Indiana  University  Press.  

Petrilli,  S.  1999.  “Review  article:  About  and  beyond  Peirce”  Semiotica.  124:  299–376.  

Pietarinen,  A-­‐V.  2012.  “Peirce  and  the  logic  of  image”  Semiotica.  2012.  

Pilarczyk,  U.  and  U.  Mietzner.  2000.  "Bildwissenschaftliche  Methoden  in  der  

erziehungs-­‐  und  sozialwissenschaftlichen  Forschung"  Zeitschrift  für  qualitative  

Bildungs-­‐,  Beratungs-­‐  und  Sozialforschung.  1:343–364.  

Przyborski,  A.  and  T.  Slunecko.  2012.  “Learning  to  Think  Iconically  in  the  Human  and  

Social  Sciences:  Iconic  Standards  of  Understanding  as  a  Pivotal  Challenge  for  Method  

Development”  Integrative  Psychological  and  Behavioral  Science.  46:  39–56.  

Rorty,  R.  1967.  “Introduction:  Metaphilosophical  Difficulties  of  Linguistic  Philosophy”  

Pp.  1–39,  in  The  Linguistic  Turn.  Recent  essays  in  Philosophical  Method,  edited  by  R.  

Rorty.  Chicago:  The  University  of  Chicago  Press.  

Saussure,  F.  d.  1996.  Kurs  obecné  lingvistiky,  Praha:  Academia.  

Smith,  P.  2003.  “Narrating  the  Guillotine:  Punishment  Technology  as  Myth  and  

Symbol”  Theory,  Culture  &  Society.  20:  27–51.  

Sonnevend,  J.  2012.  “Iconic  rituals:  Towards  a  social  theory  of  encountering  images”  Pp.  

219–232,  in  Iconic  power.  Materiality  and  meaning  in  social  life,  edited  by  J.  C.  

Alexander,  D.  Bartmanski,  and  B.  Giesen.  New  York:  Palgrave  Macmillan.  

Wagner,  P.  2008.  Modernity  as  experience  and  interpretation.  A  new  sociology  of  

modernity,  Cambridge:  Polity.    

 81  

 82  

Index  

 

A  

Alexander  11,  23,  25,  32,  33,  34,  35,  36,  37,  38,  39,  40,  41,  

42,  43,  44,  45,  47,  48,  50,  54,  55,  56,  57,  59,  60,  61  

Atkin  ............................................................................  16  

B  

Barthes  ...........................  22,  23,  24,  29,  43,  44,  51,  53,  55  

Bartmanski  ...  17,  22,  23,  32,  37,  38,  39,  41,  42,  43,  45,  46,  

47,  48,  50,  51,  54,  55,  57,  59  

Becker  ....................................................  10,  11,  42,  44,  57  

Belting  ...................................................  21,  24,  29,  53,  58  

Benjamin  ......................................................................  37  

Berger  ...........................................................................  37  

Beyst  .............................................................................  30  

Binder  ...  5,  7,  17,  21,  22,  28,  30,  46,  52,  53,  54,  57,  58,  59,  

60,  63  

Boehm  ...  7,  11,  15,  16,  21,  28,  29,  30,  31,  34,  37,  38,  39,  47,  

50,  51,  52,  53,  54,  57,  58,  59,  61,  62,  66  

Bohnsack  .  7,  18,  22,  23,  24,  25,  46,  48,  52,  53,  54,  55,  56,  

57,  58,  59,  60,  62,  63  

Bourdieu  .................................................  9,  18,  20,  21,  59  

Bredekamp  .............................................................  21,  49  

Buczynska-­‐Garewicz  ........................................  15,  16,  20  

C  

Cassirer  ........................................................................  26  

D  

Didi-­‐Huberman  ..........................................................  22  

Dilthey  ..........................................................................  17  

Durkheim  ..............................................  11,  35,  37,  38,  60  

E  

Eberlein  .......................................................................  18  

Emirbayer  ..............................................................  36,  45  

F  

Foucault  .......................................................................  43  

Freud  ............................................................................  40  

G  

Giesen  .......................................  46,  51,  52,  54,  55,  56,  57  

Gladwell  .......................................................................  40  

 83  

Goodman  ....................................................................  26  

Greub  ...........................................................................  31  

H  

Hall  ........................................................................  46,  58  

Harré  ............................................................................  47  

Holly  .............................................................................  17  

Huening  .......................................................................  16  

I  

Imdahl  .................................  22,  29,  31,  48,  52,  53,  59,  62  

K  

Kant  ..............................................................................  42  

Kuhn  .............................................................................  25  

L  

Latour  .....................................................................  27,  47  

Lattmann  .....................................................................  16  

Luckmann  ....................................................................  37  

M  

Malinowski  ..................................................................  43  

Mannheim  ..............................................................  17,  18  

Marx  .............................................................................  37  

McLuhan  .................................................................  13,  25  

Michel  ....................................................................  52,  59  

Mietzner  ......................................................................  44  

Mitchell  ...  14,  15,  16,  20,  21,  25,  26,  27,  28,  29,  31,  34,  37,  

38,  40,  46,  47,  48,  53,  61  

Moxey  ..................................  22,  26,  27,  29,  37,  50,  52,  61  

P  

Panofsky  ....  6,  16,  17,  18,  19,  20,  21,  22,  23,  25,  26,  27,  28,  

29,  31,  32,  48,  51,  52,  54,  55,  56,  58,  59,  62  

Parsons  ........................................................................  44  

Peirce  ...........................  6,  15,  16,  17,  18,  19,  20,  29,  38,  39  

Petrilli  ..........................................................................  16  

Pietarinen  .....................................................................  15  

Pilarczyk  ......................................................................  44  

Przyborski  ............................  21,  22,  29,  37,  46,  47,  52,  57  

R  

Rorty  .....................................................  14,  25,  37,  46,  63  

S  

Saussure  .................................................  14,  15,  16,  30,  38  

Schleiermacher  ............................................................  17  

Slunecko  ..............................  21,  22,  29,  37,  46,  47,  52,  57  

Smith  ..........................................  11,  25,  34,  35,  36,  38,  40  

Sonnevend  ...................................................................  54  

W  

Wagner  ...................................................................  14,  25  

Weber  ..........................................................................  37  

Wittgenstein  ...............................................................  25