2
Editorial Scientific methods are the only credible way forward for nursing research What is the place of scientific methods in nursing research? It is very hard to imagine that anyone could argue against them or that anyone could argue exclu- sively for another approach to investi- gation in any field. Science rests upon the ability to measure. Measurement is the antidote to subjectivity: it settles arguments and suggests specific, new lines of inquiry. Subjectivity lies at the heart of non-scientific methods, and subjectivity is what scientific methods expressly aim to avoid. By scientific methods I mean, essen- tially, anything that involves measure- ment, objectivity and rigour, including randomized controlled trials (RCTs), surveys, taxonomies, systematic reviews and so on. Anything where the method used can be clearly explained, repeated and potentially, replicated. If these three features – explicability, repeatability and the potential for replication – are missing from a research approach, then that approach is not scientific; and that approach, I contend, has little, if any, place in nursing research. Therefore, all forms of research involving subjectivity – such as phenomenology, grounded the- ory and ethnography – are not scientific. To explain something means to tell someone else precisely how you did something. Scientific and non-scientific research can both pass this test. Expli- cability is crucial in science in order that the next feature may be apparent, rep- eatability: that is, the ability of someone else, based on your explanation, to do exactly the same as you did. Scientific research passes this test; non-scientific research does not. Only if something can be repeated is there any chance that the findings might be replicated or, indeed, refuted. A further feature of scientific research is that another investigator can make changes to what you did in order to improve upon what you did, deliber- ately, to find out something new. Non- scientific methods – which I’ll come to later – can be explained but are imposs- ible to repeat since they rely upon, even glorify themselves in, subjectivity. The chances of replication are negligible. As for refutation, I am not sure that it has ever happened in non-scientific research. Qualitative findings appear to be accep- ted without question; used to build a subsequent study; and a whole field of ‘knowledge’ builds up without ever being challenged. Measurement is only appropriate if it is reliable and valid. In scientific terms, validity is predicated upon reliability: if you are not measuring the same thing each time you make a measurement, then what you are using to measure what you are purporting to measure simply cannot be valid. However, those with a predilection for non-scientific methods make vague claims about reli- ability and validity – and even get them the wrong way round. For instance, I have heard qualitative researchers say that it is possible to have validity in qualitative research, without having reliability. This is simply not possible. If a method is not reliable it cannot be used by two people, or on two different occasions by the same person, to pro- duce the same results. Surely this should apply to qualitative methods every bit as much as it applies to scientific methods? If the method or measurement does not produce the same result for you and me, then how can the result mean the same thing to you and me? How can the results be valid? Subjectivity is accept- able up to a point: it stimulates debate and leads to new lines of enquiry. However, why dress up a method in quasi-scientific terms if it does not pro- duce the same result for two people? Explanations aside, it strikes me more and more that, in non-scientific re- search, reliability means ‘I think the same thing on two separate occasions’ and something is valid simply because ‘I think it’. Such an approach to research, which is totally internally valid, has absolutely no external validity, and external validity should be the gold standard for all research. Without exter- nal validity and the hope of generaliz- ability – even to a limited group of subjects, as with the RCT – there seems little point to the research. What are the alternatives to scientific methods? A whole range of qualitative methods are on offer: phenomenology, ethnography, postmodernism, discourse analysis, grounded theory, and all the rest. But, really, they’re all the same in the sense that they are all subjective: they start with loaded dice. There is nothing more dangerous than your own opinion in research, especially when it is untamed by objective, reliable and valid methods. The most extreme examples are qualitative research methods taking an ideological label. For example, when did a Marxist researcher not come to the conclusion that their research demon- strated class oppression? and likewise, when did a feminist researcher not come to the conclusion that patriarchal oppression was not at work? Those of us adhering to scientific methods are accused of ‘positivism’ and ‘reduction- ism’. It is a fact, however, that scientific methods have not been tried and found wanting in nursing research: instead, they have been found difficult and not tried. There is yet another criticism to be parried: that of decontextualization. Those of us using scientific methods not only take an unpopular stance, we apparently ‘decontextualise’ by follow- ing the scientific method. Can research be carried out any other way? The postmodernist-phenomeno-Marx- ist-feminstic-discourse analyst rightly tries to contextualize everything – not a criticism in itself – but claims that research cannot be decontextualized: there is nothing to be learned about the whole that cannot be learned from the whole and not from the parts – we are more than just the sum of our parts. Ó 2003 Blackwell Publishing Ltd 219

Editorial

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Editorial

Editorial

Scientific methods are the onlycredible way forward for nursingresearch

What is the place of scientific methodsin nursing research? It is very hard toimagine that anyone could argue againstthem or that anyone could argue exclu-sively for another approach to investi-gation in any field. Science rests uponthe ability to measure. Measurement isthe antidote to subjectivity: it settlesarguments and suggests specific, newlines of inquiry. Subjectivity lies at theheart of non-scientific methods, andsubjectivity is what scientific methodsexpressly aim to avoid.

By scientific methods I mean, essen-tially, anything that involves measure-ment, objectivity and rigour, includingrandomized controlled trials (RCTs),surveys, taxonomies, systematic reviewsand so on. Anything where the methodused can be clearly explained, repeatedand potentially, replicated. If these threefeatures – explicability, repeatability andthe potential for replication – are missingfrom a research approach, then thatapproach is not scientific; and thatapproach, I contend, has little, if any,place in nursing research. Therefore, allforms of research involving subjectivity –such as phenomenology, grounded the-ory and ethnography – are not scientific.

To explain something means to tellsomeone else precisely how you didsomething. Scientific and non-scientificresearch can both pass this test. Expli-cability is crucial in science in order thatthe next feature may be apparent, rep-eatability: that is, the ability of someoneelse, based on your explanation, to doexactly the same as you did. Scientificresearch passes this test; non-scientificresearch does not. Only if something canbe repeated is there any chance that thefindings might be replicated or, indeed,refuted. A further feature of scientificresearch is that another investigator canmake changes to what you did in orderto improve upon what you did, deliber-

ately, to find out something new. Non-scientific methods – which I’ll come tolater – can be explained but are imposs-ible to repeat since they rely upon, evenglorify themselves in, subjectivity. Thechances of replication are negligible. Asfor refutation, I am not sure that it hasever happened in non-scientific research.Qualitative findings appear to be accep-ted without question; used to build asubsequent study; and a whole field of‘knowledge’ builds up without everbeing challenged.

Measurement is only appropriate if itis reliable and valid. In scientific terms,validity is predicated upon reliability: ifyou are not measuring the same thingeach time you make a measurement,then what you are using to measurewhat you are purporting to measuresimply cannot be valid. However, thosewith a predilection for non-scientificmethods make vague claims about reli-ability and validity – and even get themthe wrong way round. For instance, Ihave heard qualitative researchers saythat it is possible to have validity inqualitative research, without havingreliability. This is simply not possible.If a method is not reliable it cannot beused by two people, or on two differentoccasions by the same person, to pro-duce the same results. Surely this shouldapply to qualitative methods every bit asmuch as it applies to scientific methods?If the method or measurement does notproduce the same result for you and me,then how can the result mean the samething to you and me? How can theresults be valid? Subjectivity is accept-able up to a point: it stimulates debateand leads to new lines of enquiry.However, why dress up a method inquasi-scientific terms if it does not pro-duce the same result for two people?

Explanations aside, it strikes me moreand more that, in non-scientific re-search, reliability means ‘I think thesame thing on two separate occasions’and something is valid simply because ‘Ithink it’. Such an approach to research,

which is totally internally valid, hasabsolutely no external validity, andexternal validity should be the goldstandard for all research. Without exter-nal validity and the hope of generaliz-ability – even to a limited group ofsubjects, as with the RCT – there seemslittle point to the research.

What are the alternatives to scientificmethods? A whole range of qualitativemethods are on offer: phenomenology,ethnography, postmodernism, discourseanalysis, grounded theory, and all therest. But, really, they’re all the same inthe sense that they are all subjective:they start with loaded dice. There isnothing more dangerous than your ownopinion in research, especially when it isuntamed by objective, reliable and validmethods. The most extreme examplesare qualitative research methods takingan ideological label. For example, whendid a Marxist researcher not come to theconclusion that their research demon-strated class oppression? and likewise,when did a feminist researcher not cometo the conclusion that patriarchaloppression was not at work? Those ofus adhering to scientific methods areaccused of ‘positivism’ and ‘reduction-ism’. It is a fact, however, that scientificmethods have not been tried and foundwanting in nursing research: instead,they have been found difficult and nottried.

There is yet another criticism to beparried: that of decontextualization.Those of us using scientific methodsnot only take an unpopular stance, weapparently ‘decontextualise’ by follow-ing the scientific method. Canresearch be carried out any other way?The postmodernist-phenomeno-Marx-ist-feminstic-discourse analyst rightlytries to contextualize everything – nota criticism in itself – but claims thatresearch cannot be decontextualized:there is nothing to be learned aboutthe whole that cannot be learned fromthe whole and not from the parts – weare more than just the sum of our parts.

� 2003 Blackwell Publishing Ltd 219

Page 2: Editorial

This is like going to a football matchand trying to work out the result byinvestigating how happy the spectatorsare. I daresay a great deal could belearned, but why not just measure thenumber of goals scored by each side andadd them up? Give or take a few visuallychallenged referees and linesmen, it’s afairly reliable test of who won, and it’sutterly valid once the referee has blownthe final whistle. Making such a meas-urement tells us the result in an instant;it cuts through spurious and subjectiveopinion; and it reaches a conclusionlong before the non-scientist has arrivedat the Nirvana of ‘saturation’.

I admit that non-science may have itsuses. For example, non-science can tell

us what suffering is like; however, onlyscience can tell us how to alleviate it.Science has cured diseases, while non-science can only look for new ways todeconstruct the experience. Science hastaken us to the moon, and back, whilenon-science can only dream of what themoon might look like. If nursing is tomake progress then we must decide ifwe wish to head for the moon or look atit from a distance. What applies toother fields of investigation involvinghuman subjects – medicine, psychologyand sociology, where the scientificmethod has served us well – appliesequally well to nursing. We must not setourselves aside, we must compete forour place at the high table of credibility

and the only way in which to do that isto carry out nursing research usingscientific methods.

Roger Watson BSc PhD RGN CBiol FIBiol

ILTMFRSA

Professor of Nursing, School ofNursing, Social Work and AppliedHealth Studies, University of Hull, UK

This editorial is based on the author’s

contribution to the debate on the motion

that ‘Scientific method is the only credible

way forward for nursing research’ held at

during the Royal College of Nursing of the

United Kingdom Research Conference at

University of Manchester Institute of Science

and Technology, Manchester, UK on 10

April 2003.

Editorial

220 � 2003 Blackwell Publishing Ltd, Journal of Advanced Nursing, 43(3), 219–220