23
The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger Hans Ruin Published online: 11 September 2008 Ó Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008 Abstract The essay recapitulates the decisive steps in Heidegger’s development of the problem of human freedom. The interpretation is set in the context of a general matrix for how freedom is treated in the tradition, as both a theoretical ontological problem, and as practical appeal. According to some readers, Heideg- ger’s thinking is a philosophy of freedom throughout; according to others his ‘‘turning’’ implies abandoning the idea of human freedom as a metaphysical rem- nant. The essay seeks an intermediate path, by following his explicit attempts to develop an ontology based on the concept of freedom in the earlier writings, showing how this is the central theme in his confrontation and also his final break with German idealism, with Kant and with Schelling in particular, and with the prospects for a system of freedom. However, this break does not terminate his preoccupation with the problem of freedom, which is then transformed into the idea of thinking as a practice of freedom, as a way of reaching into ‘‘the free’’. Keywords Heidegger Á Kant Á Schelling Á Freedom Á The free Á Schu ¨rmann Die Leitfrage der Metaphysik gru ¨ndet auf der Frage nach dem Wesen der Freiheit (GA 31: 134). Modern philosophical thinking is inaugurated as a discourse on freedom and its place in nature. The stage of this constellation is set in the Meditations on first philosophy, where Descartes, establishes the distinction between material and spiritual substance, between extension and thought, by means of a demonstration of the autonomy of critical doubt. Thinking is essentially free, as opposed to nature which is bound by causal laws. In an introduction to Descartes from 1946, Sartre insists on how the Cartesian doubt and the subsequent definition of man as thought, H. Ruin (&) So ¨derto ¨rn University College, 141 89 Huddinge, Sweden e-mail: [email protected] 123 Cont Philos Rev (2008) 41:277–299 DOI 10.1007/s11007-008-9087-4

Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Article presents idea of freedom in the philosophy of Heidegger

Citation preview

Page 1: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

Hans Ruin

Published online: 11 September 2008

� Springer Science+Business Media B.V. 2008

Abstract The essay recapitulates the decisive steps in Heidegger’s development

of the problem of human freedom. The interpretation is set in the context of a

general matrix for how freedom is treated in the tradition, as both a theoretical

ontological problem, and as practical appeal. According to some readers, Heideg-

ger’s thinking is a philosophy of freedom throughout; according to others his

‘‘turning’’ implies abandoning the idea of human freedom as a metaphysical rem-

nant. The essay seeks an intermediate path, by following his explicit attempts to

develop an ontology based on the concept of freedom in the earlier writings,

showing how this is the central theme in his confrontation and also his final break

with German idealism, with Kant and with Schelling in particular, and with the

prospects for a system of freedom. However, this break does not terminate his

preoccupation with the problem of freedom, which is then transformed into the idea

of thinking as a practice of freedom, as a way of reaching into ‘‘the free’’.

Keywords Heidegger � Kant � Schelling � Freedom � The free � Schurmann

Die Leitfrage der Metaphysik grundet auf der Frage nach dem Wesen der

Freiheit (GA 31: 134).

Modern philosophical thinking is inaugurated as a discourse on freedom and its

place in nature. The stage of this constellation is set in the Meditations on firstphilosophy, where Descartes, establishes the distinction between material and

spiritual substance, between extension and thought, by means of a demonstration of

the autonomy of critical doubt. Thinking is essentially free, as opposed to nature

which is bound by causal laws. In an introduction to Descartes from 1946, Sartre

insists on how the Cartesian doubt and the subsequent definition of man as thought,

H. Ruin (&)

Sodertorn University College, 141 89 Huddinge, Sweden

e-mail: [email protected]

123

Cont Philos Rev (2008) 41:277–299

DOI 10.1007/s11007-008-9087-4

Page 2: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

places freedom—liberte—at the center of being, as the very condition of an

apparition of a world. Eventually, Sartre writes, Descartes will accredit only God

with the absolute freedom to constitute a world, but this is only a testimony to the

time bound aspect of his thinking. What Descartes is said to have revealed to us,

long before Heidegger in ‘‘Vom Wesen des Grundes’’, is the foundation of a

‘‘humanism’’, in the sense that ‘‘man is the being whose very apparition makes a

world exist’’ and ‘‘that the unique ground of being is freedom’’.1 The legitimacy of

this Cartesian-existentialist appropriation of Heidegger is a problem in itself which I

hall return to. For now Sartre’s remark can stand simply as an illustration of a

certain continuity within modern philosophy, from Descartes to Existential

phenomenology.

From its Cartesian inception we can also see how this question of freedom is

structured along what can be identified as two intersecting paths, that which

concerns what I will here speak of as, on the one hand the nature of freedom, and on

the other hand, that which concerns the demand of freedom, or simply freedom as a

demand, as appeal. I want to insist from the start on this distinction. For the question

of freedom always implies both of these aspects, even though it is not always

recognized as such. This can be elucidated as follows. When we think of the nature

of freedom we raise the metaphysical question concerning the what of freedom. In

Cartesian terms, this is the question of the essence of the human, which is what

leads him to posit a cognizing substance, which is free in the sense of not being

bound by the causal laws of nature. In this way, spirit is equated with freedom, as a

domain separated, if yet correlated with a non-free nature. But freedom is also, from

the very start of Descartes’ explorations, fixed as a demand on man and his thinking.

This is brought out very clearly in the opening statement of the First meditation,

where the necessity of abandoning the inherited views, at least once in a life, is

stated. In the Discourse on method, first part, he speaks likewise of the need of

freeing oneself from the mistakes and misconceptions that impede the natural light

of our reason. In this discourse the connection is thus established between freedom,

reason, and truth; only by freely practicing one’s rational capacity can man reach the

truth of being. Reason, as a natural, inborn light, does not automatically reach its

potential. Only by being cultivated freely, as a voluntary act, which wills its own

fulfillment, can freedom reach into its own, namely into the adequate comprehen-

sion of that which is. In this way, the Cartesian discourse on freedom is both a

definition of the essence of man and a demand that man seeks the completion of his

essence through his own choice, which is most dramatically exemplified in the

universal doubt, which leads to the constitution of a universal and free human self.

The duality of the question of freedom, as set up in this schematic way through

Descartes, is repeated with an even greater emphasis in Kant. Indeed—and as has

often been repeated—it can be said to organize the very structure of his thought.

Freedom as spontaneity is the very definition of thought and of understanding,

which organizes a passively received material of experience. As such it also belongs

to what is transcendental, in other words what marks the condition of possibility of

knowledge. Yet, as a fact of nature freedom cannot be localized, for nature appears

1 Sartre (1946, p. 25 (my translation)).

278 H. Ruin

123

Page 3: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

as a system of grounded, explicable, processes, in which freedom does not appear as

such. As the third antinomy in the Critique of pure reason seeks to demonstrate, we

can prove both the existence and the inexistence of absolute freedom or spontaneity,

and thus neither of them definitively. Even though the fact of freedom can never be

proven by ordinary rational argument, a transcendental freedom, i.e., the principal

possibility of absolute spontaneity, nevertheless functions as the supreme concept

on which the critical philosophy rests. And in the introduction to the SecondCritique Kant affirms that the reality of the concept of freedom is the corner stone in

the whole construction of the system of pure and speculative reason.2

Kant’s practical philosophy can be read as an investigation into what this fact of

freedom implies, a quest which culminates in the idea of a rational, grounded

morality of absolute universalizability, manifested in the categorical imperative. In

this way we can see how the problematic fact of freedom is developed into a

concept of freedom which calls upon and demands from the subject to become its

own lawgiver. The whole tension is contained in the definition of the free will as

autonomy, as self-rule, what Kant also speaks of as ‘‘positive’’ freedom, as opposed

to the ‘‘negative’’ sense of freedom as simply being unaffected. The point about this

causality is, however, that unlike the unconditional law of nature, it must be fulfilled

and brought about by the individual human subject. The antipode of this potential

autonomy, as something to be achieved, is heteronomy, the law of another. In the

1784 essay on Enlightenment, this situation is brought out with a strong rhetorical

emphasis, captured in the concept of Mundighet, of maturity.3 To become

enlightened is to leave immaturity, as the enslavement of one’s own reason; it is

to realize in full the freedom in oneself, and to become what one was meant to

become. Thus, in Kant the subject is essentially free, and at the same time, always at

risk of losing this freedom, which in order to be what it is, must be enacted and

achieved. Freedom defines the nature of subjectivity, and at the same time it

constitutes its task, always to be assumed anew.

1 I

Against this introductory background, I would now like to formulate the following

question: in what way and to what extent can the phenomenon of freedom in its binary

matrix be said to surface also in Heidegger’s writings? Let me first direct this question

in regard to SZ. The whole work is animated by a sense of crisis. From its inception, the

question which it seeks to answer has already been lost, and is in need of being

reawakened. In this process, thinking has to struggle against the inborn tendency of

man to lose himself to the world, to become absorbed by it in a way that produces

interpretations of his own mode of existence which blocks the very access to its central

concern, i.e., the meaning of being, or simply to fall prey to previously established

patterns of thinking. The possibility of falling, of inauthenticity, manifests itself both

with regard to history and tradition, and to the present. Only by practicing a stepwise

2 Kant (1968a, p. 16).3 Kant (1968b).

The destiny of freedom 279

123

Page 4: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

critical destruction of inherited patterns of thought can thinking bring about the

confrontation with what is to be thought, the disclosure, Erschlossenheit, Lichtung, or

simply the truth of Dasein, as the opening toward being in a temporalizing movement.

This precarious space of meaning is at once the ground of Dasein, its essential

determination, and yet it can become available to this Dasein only under certain

circumstances, namely that it assumes authentically its own finite and thrown

existence. In SZ the privileged mood or attunement of authentic disclosure is that of

anxiety. Partly following the analysis of Kierkegaard in The Concept of Anxiety,

Heidegger here describes anxiety as revealing Dasein to itself as a possibility to exist,

which in other terms is its ‘‘being free for the freedom of choosing and grasping

itself.’’—Freisein fur die Freiheit des Sich-selbst-wahlens und -ergreifens. But this

again is equivalent to choosing the world in which it is.4 The freedom outlined here is

thus essentially a freedom for, not a freedom from. It is a freedom for a world, in which

Dasein always already finds itself, as something it can assume, but it is also something

from which it can fall away or shun. And precisely due to its tendency to fall, Dasein

will be tempted to interpret its situation as grounded in the world, and not the other

way around, as itself the futural temporalizing disclosure in and through which the

world is manifested, or simply through which it ‘‘worlds’’, weltet.The concept of freedom outlined here is both near and distant from that of Kant.

Here the question is not with autonomy, as a unique form of causality distinct from the

causality of nature. Yet on another level it marks the continuation of the Cartesian-

Kantian problematic, as it tries in its own way to circumscribe the nature of life so as to

understand how it can have an experience of a world, and of its truth, that which

Heidegger in his Kantbuch will explore as the finite temporality of the self. But to

what extent is it reasonable to say that Heidegger’s thinking is also and genuinely a

philosophy of freedom? In his important study from 1988, Martin Heidegger.

Phanomenologie der Freiheit, Gunter Figal responded in a definitive manner to this

question. He stated there that ‘‘Heidegger’s thought remains to the end a thought of

freedom just as it is a thought of time’’.5 For Figal the entire analysis of Dasein as

disclosedness and eventually as truth can be reinterpreted as a way of understanding

what it means for Dasein to be free, and thus freedom can inversely be described as

Heidegger’s most fundamental concern.

Figal’s analysis remains convincing in many ways, and it brings to light a

dimension of Heidegger’s work which had not really been seen and understood as such

previously. Yet it does so at the cost of certain distinctions, which deserved to be raised

and discussed initially. The matter can be put in the following way. First we have the

question to what extent Heidegger explicitly seeks to elaborate something like a

philosophy of freedom, literally evoking this word and its particular implications.

Secondly we have the question to what extent Heidegger’s work can also be

interpreted and described as a philosophy of freedom, in other words, to what extent

freedom could be used as a heuristic concept in the course of an interpretation of

Heidegger’s work as a whole. It is the second question which Figal develops with such

good results, but at the expense of a more detailed exploration of the first question.

4 Heidegger (1927/1979, p. 188).5 Figal (1988, p. 275).

280 H. Ruin

123

Page 5: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

What I want to do here, therefore, and as a development of Figal’s analysis, is to

direct our eyes more specifically to the when and how, in the course of Heidegger’s

work, that the specific concept and problem of freedom emerges as an explicit

concern. What we find then, and this is my interpretational hypothesis, is that there

is indeed a phase in the course of Heidegger’s path of thinking during which he tries

to ground his entire philosophical aspiration on an understanding of freedom in a

qualified sense, but that he also abandons this attempt. This phase is manifested

primarily by two texts in particular, the essays ‘‘Vom Wesen des Grundes’’ and

‘‘Vom Wesen der Wahrheit’’, both from 1929. This attempt, as well as its eclipse, is

intimately linked to his intense engagement with German idealism in general, and

with Kant and Schelling in particular, a confrontation which follows upon the

completion of SZ. More specifically it begins with the 1929 lectures on Kant and the

question of Freedom, over the 1936 lecture course on Schelling, culminating with

the 1942 course on German idealism. Yet—and this is my subsequent point, which I

develop in the second part of this essay—even though Heidegger at a certain point

abandons the attempt to found the quest for the meaning of being literally on

freedom, the problem of freedom does not disappear from his horizon. Instead it can

be said to emerge as the hidden ethos of his thought, but as something that cannot be

adequately conceptualized as a theoretically expressed foundation, but which

remains in a qualified sense an appeal, to open thinking for ‘‘the free’’, das Freie.

Some years before Figal’s study, Reiner Schurmann had published his magistral

study original Le principe d’anarchie: Heidegger et la question de l’agir, in which he

elaborates the thought of the later Heidegger in the direction of showing how the very

idea of a human will and willing, is abandoned with the later thinking of the sending of

being. In recent years, and indeed all throughout the renewed discussion of the

philosophical implications of Heidegger’s political engagements in the thirties,

precisely this question of a certain philosophical anti-liberalism has become again a

central issue, not only among Heidegger’s categorical critics, but also for example in

the work of Lacou-Labarthe and Nancy. In a recent study, Bret Davis’ impressive

monograph Heidegger and the Will. On the Way to Gelassenheit, this thread is picked

up again, but here from the perspective of the question not primarily of freedom, but of

the will. Davis shows, in great detail, how the problem of willing is transformed

throughout the work of the thirties from the decision of Dasein toward the historical

decisions of being. But he also tries to go beyond Schurmann in pointing toward not an

eclipse of the individual will in favor of an impersonal sending of being, but toward a

transformed understanding of willing itself. My own analyses in part trace the same

trajectory as the study of Davis, but I follow more closely the precise transformation of

his understanding of freedom, and the genealogy of this question, in order to show in

what way Heidegger should indeed be read as a philosopher of freedom.

2 II

The 1929 essay ‘‘Vom Wesen des Grundes’’, together with the subsequent essay,

‘‘Vom Wesen der Wahrheit’’ are the two most important texts for a discussion of

Heidegger’s explicit approach to the problem of freedom, and also the first echo of

The destiny of freedom 281

123

Page 6: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

his confrontation with the Freiheitsschrift of Schelling. Indeed we could perhaps

speak of this text as the most schellingian of all of Heidegger’s writings. Here, more

than in any other of his writings, freedom emerges as a key operative term, around

which the argument is built. ‘‘Vom Wesen des Grundes’’ is to some extent an

extension and an appendix to the lecture course from the preceding year on the

metaphysical foundation of logic, in which the Leibnizian principle of ground, as a

principle of universal explicability is explored in its hidden presuppositions. It also

continues immediately the question raised in the 1928 inaugural lecture ‘‘Was ist

Metaphysik?’’. In the essay on the essence of ground, Heidegger moves from the

question of ground or reason to that of world, showing that the very positing of a

ground and the having of a world is founded on the transcendence of Dasein, its

going beyond and over in the direction of the world so as to disclose it, to let it

appear. In the inaugural lecture this movement has been defined as the ‘‘hinaussein

uber das seiende’’, a being-beyond beings, and also as a holding oneself in the

nothingness, in das Nicht. In SZ Sorge is defined in terms of its always ahead of

itself, of being toward beings. And Dasein is described as essentially an

understanding of being, in a pre-ontological mode. When the essay on the ground

speaks of transcendence it describes what the main work analyses in terms of

Dasein’s futural projection toward possibilities. In an important footnote to the text,

Heidegger even says that the entire first part of SZ is in fact nothing but a concrete

uncovering of transcendence.6 That Dasein transcends means that it has always

already engaged itself in beings. Transcendence in this sense is not a qualification

that belongs to Dasein, Heidegger writes, it is not something that can be appended to

it or not, but it is what constitutes selfhood, just as the being-in-the-world, with

which it is at one point equated.7

It is in the continued elaboration of his theme that Heidegger reaches a point

where freedom is suddenly introduced as yet another name for the phenomenon of

transcendence. Taken together with the previous statement, that SZ was in fact a

meditation on transcendence, it implies that at least at this point he was prepared to

see SZ as one long elaboration of the problem freedom. He writes: that which

according to its essence accomplishes something like this concern is what we call

freedom. The stepping over—Uberstieg—toward the world is freedom itself.8

Freedom is not, he insists, to be thought of as a different kind of ground, but the

origin of ground in general. Freedom is a freedom for the ground.9 This is also

described in terms of enabling a responsibility, for oneself and for the world, and for

being. But what kind of ground is the ground of freedom? On the very last page of

the essay, Heidegger’s reading of Schelling surfaces explicitly as he states: that this

freedom is the abyss—the Abgrund—of Dasein.10 This means that it does not

support or explain Dasein, but it is what places Dasein before itself in its possibility

for being and thus before its finite choice. This situation is what he here also equates

6 Heidegger (1967, p. 162).7 Ibid., p. 139.8 Ibid., p. 163.9 Ibid., p. 165.10 Ibid., p. 174.

282 H. Ruin

123

Page 7: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

with the fate of Dasein, its Schicksal. As a ground, freedom withdraws in favor of

that towards which Dasein will have to project itself.

In the later editions of this text we have also Heidegger’s subsequent remarks,

many of which are explicitly self-critical. In a remark to the above passage he notes,

e.g., that here again we have the ‘‘vain attempt to think Dasein in neglect of the truth

of being in its turning’’. And in a final note he writes that freedom has nothing to do

with grounds, little less with causes and causings. From the perspective of his later

thinking we can see why many of his formulations in this text will appear

problematic. When Sartre in his Cartesian-existentialist reading of the text

mentioned earlier, summarizes it to be saying that the freedom of man is the only

ground of being, he brings out precisely one such aspect of the text, which to

Heidegger would be unacceptable, since it would seem to posit the freedom or

subjectivity as an ontological foundation. But it all hinges of course on how this

grounding is understood, and in this respect we can also say that Heidegger is

somewhat unfair to his earlier attempt, as he is also to some extent unfair in his

complete disavowal of existentialism in his subsequent writings (notably the ‘‘Letter

on Humanism’’). If freedom is understood as a foundation, if yet in its abysmal

character, then we recognize a repetition of the aspirations of German idealism, to

create a system of freedom, where freedom functions as a first principle. But

Heidegger’s aspiration already at this point should be read as directed elsewhere,

toward freedom as the opening toward that which is, what Figal speaks of as ‘‘the

opening of thought which escapes thought’’ die sich dem Denken entziehendeOffenheit des Denkens selbst.11 It is tempting to speak of it as a ‘‘transcendental

freedom’’, a principle underlying all manifestations of being. But this conceptual

detour does not really bring us closer to its reality, but simply places it in a

convenient and established conceptual paradigm. The abyssal freedom as the

transcending opening toward the world is not a philosophical principle in any

conventional sense. It is something lived and experienced, which at the same time in

itself withdraws from a conceptual grasp. For it is an attempt to indicate the very

happening of experience as at the same time a task to assume. Freedom, Heidegger

writes here, is a freedom for the ground, and transcendence is explicitly described as

a ‘‘happening of transcendence’’ (Geschehen) as a configuration—sichbilden—of a

space where the factical Dasein can emerge in the midst of beings, an

einbruchspielraum fur das jeweilige faktische sichhalten des faktischen Daseininmitten des Seienden im Ganzen.12 From this formulation alone it is clear that what

is sought, already in this text, is an understanding of freedom not as a foundation for

being, in the sense of its ultimate explicability, but rather as the neutral event

through which Dasein is situated before and amongst beings. Still, as it stands,

freedom is here the thinker’s last word, which is not questioned and critically

interpreted in terms of some more fundamental notion. At least in this sense, it

emerges here as a ground, as an ultimate logos.

In the following year 1929 Heidegger composes the essay ‘‘Vom Wesen der

Wahrheit’’. Up to a certain point this text also recapitulates the analysis from Sect. 44

11 Figal (1988, p. 364 (my translation)).12 Heidegger (1967, p. 170).

The destiny of freedom 283

123

Page 8: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

of SZ, in which truth as correspondence and correctness is led back to a more originary

openness, more fundamental than that of the statement. But instead of leading this

openness back to Dasein’s disclosedness, as is the case in SZ, this opening of oneself

to what is binding is here described as a being-free, a freisein, which furthermore is

said to point toward the hitherto non-comprehended essence of freedom.13 And

hereafter he concludes that the essence of truth as correctness is indeed the freedom of

man.

In a central section of the text he also develops what he understands by freedom.

The analysis follows closely what has already been established in the previous

essay, but it also adds important elements. Freedom as openness is what lets the

present being be what it is. Thus freedom reveals itself as a letting-be, a Sein-lassen,

not, he says, as a neglect, but as a letting oneself be engaged by, a sicheinlassen aufdas seiende. And in a marginal note from 1943 he adds: not negatively, but as a

preserving, gewahren, Wahrniss, and not as an ontically directed effecting of

something, but rather a heeding, Achten.14 To let be in this sense of freedom is to

expose oneself, as a stepping into the disclosure of beings. Deeper than the common

distinction between a negative and positive freedom, i.e., a freedom from and

freedom for, it signifies the involvement in and with the disclosure of beings. This is

also what Heidegger wants to understand by existence, not a moral concern with

oneself, but precisely this exposure to the disclosure, Entborgenheit des Seienden.

Unlike the common understanding of freedom as a possession of man, in virtue of

which he can make his choices, freedom in this sense is rather what possesses man.

And in a movement which implicitly recapitulates another theme from Schelling,

Heidegger insists that the possibility of falsehood, and of neglect to let beings be, is

likewise grounded in freedom. It should not be regarded as simply the neglect of

man in regard to original truth.

These two essays together constitute what could be described as Heidegger’s

explicit attempt to construct an ontology of freedom, wherein it shines forth as itself

the root of all shining, of all appearance of beings. For a time thus, the phenomenon

of freedom does indeed stand at the focal point of his philosophical aspirations.

How should we view this attempt in retrospect? Is freedom just another and

transitory word for what is and should be designated otherwise? Or is it the other

way around? Is freedom the truth of this event, of truth itself? In other words, does

Heidegger’s philosophy justly constitute a phenomenology of freedom, up until the

end, as suggested by Figal? I do not think that we should expect that this question

has a definitive answer, as if there was a correctness to be achieved here, and if the

continued sequence of basic words for being constitute a rational chain of grounded

groundings. What we can explore, however, is the continued elaboration of the

problem of freedom as it takes the form of historical confrontations with the work of

Kant and Schelling. From these philosophical encounters we can learn where a

critical ontological interpretation of freedom can lead. In the end it can also help us

understand why ‘‘freedom’’, like so many other fundamental concepts along

Heidegger’s path, is eventually abandoned.

13 Heidegger (1967, p. 186).14 Ibid., p. 188.

284 H. Ruin

123

Page 9: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

3 III

The essay on the ‘‘Essence of truth’’ is composed parallel to the ambitious lecture

series on The Essence of human freedom.15 As the title of this lecture course

indicates, it is clear that at least during this stage of his life, Heidegger’s

philosophical focus is directed toward the hidden resources and implications of

freedom, in order to reach some kind of decision concerning its ontological

potential. Initially the question is posed whether or not freedom can be said to

constitute a particular concern within the totality of philosophy. And as a response it

is stated, that freedom is indeed a concept that leads to and implies the problem of

philosophy as a whole. Heidegger’s approach is here very systematic, discussing to

begin with the inherited distinction between a negative and a positive freedom. It is

Kant who is said to bring the question of freedom to its full metaphysical

significance. From him we have the distinction between negative and positive

freedom, and also between positive freedom in the cosmological and practical sense,

and in their interdependency. Both of these definitions of freedom, Heidegger

argues, fall back on a notion of cause. In Kant, freedom will be explored in the

perspective of Ursachesein.16 Thus we are invited, Heidegger, concludes, to explore

the metaphysical tradition, which permits beings to shine forth as causes. What then

is the being of the causal? This remark opens a hundred page long exploration into

the metaphysical tradition, centered around the basic Aristotelian concepts of being,

as ousia, energeia, and dynamis and back to the analysis of being as time in SZ. The

interpretative movement implies that the question of freedom cannot be separated

from the context of metaphysics. It belongs in this context, both as independency

and as spontaneity, and can therefore only be elucidated within a more general

consideration of the question of the meaning of being. We can thus note a difference

in his reference to this concept in regard to the contemporary 1929 essays on the

essence of ground and truth respectively, where freedom is simply deployed as an

operative concept, in order to found from anew the these two fundamental questions

of metaphysics. In the lecture course he works instead from two directions; on the

one hand showing how freedom is connected to, and intertwined with, the general

conceptual framework of metaphysics as a whole; on the other hand, also using it as

a critical lever to upheave this entire tradition.

The second strategy is introduced suddenly. After having established the

conceptual connections to the tradition, Heidegger states with emphasis, that

freedom is no longer to be seen only as a way that leads to the guiding question of

metaphysics as a whole, but instead, that this guiding question is indeed founded on

the question of the essence of freedom.17 And at this point he writes, close to the

argument in the essay on truth: that when we seek freedom as the ground of

possibility of man, then freedom is more original than man. Man is only the keeper,

Verwalter, of freedom. Thus freedom should no longer be thought of as the property

(Eigenschaft) of man, but man as the possibility of freedom. For man is the being in

15 Heidegger (1982/1994).16 Ibid., p. 29.17 Ibid., p. 134.

The destiny of freedom 285

123

Page 10: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

which the understanding of being happens, and thus the possibility of truth. At this

moment, he can thus turn the Kantian question around, and ask if the problem of

causality is not indeed the problem of freedom, instead of the other way around

(a question which the previous essay on the essence of ground had essentially

already answered in the positive).

From here on, the reading of Kant amounts to a detailed critical engagement which

seeks to show how and why Kant is unable to grasp freedom in its full radicality. To

begin with, Kant is unable to reach a full understanding of causality, for he lacks an

understanding of Dasein and of temporality. The very notion of causality is bound to

the being of present-at-hand (Vorhandensein), and thus the being of man is displaced

and betrayed, ins Gegenteil verkehrt. That Kant speaks of a different kind of causality

does not solve the issue, for he nevertheless lacks the proper ontological ground for

pursuing the problem of freedom. The same conclusion is then drawn from an

examination of how Kant understands action, Handlung, which is ultimately

subsumed under the concept of producing an effect, a Wirken which shows the limited

ontological horizon of the problem of freedom in Kant.18

In the last part of his extensive analysis, Heidegger traces what he calls the

second route to freedom in the Kantian system, i.e., the practical concept of

freedom. Its premise is an understanding of man as rational animal and as person,

with a responsibility for himself. The reality of this practical freedom is a fact, and

yet it can never be demonstrated by reason alone. This is the somewhat paradoxical

situation, which for Kant is solved by stating that the objective reality of freedom is

secured through the practical laws of reason. Thus practical freedom will emerge as

the existence of a will, understood as a capacity to act according to a principle.19

But as Heidegger shows, in a somewhat ironic tone of voice, the principle of the

categorical imperative, which according to Kant should somehow be self-evident,

and as such a proof that pure reason can also be practical, in fact lacks all self-

evidence, and recoils back as a question of how it can manifest itself as a fact.20 The

answer is not, as Kant sometimes pretends, that it is evident to anyone, but that it

lies in the telos of a genuine will that wills itself as will that it should also require

this principle. The essence of the practical freedom thus becomes: self-legislation,

pure will, autonomy, self-responsibility as the essence of the person and as the

human in man.21

So the final verdict becomes that what is never discovered by Kant is freedom as

the ‘‘condition of possibility of the disclosure of being of beings, understanding of

being’’.22 Yet, such a thesis cannot—thus Heidegger ends the course—be the matter

of a theoretical-scientific treatise. Instead it implies an understanding in concepts

which always and necessarily in advance includes (einbegreift) the one who

understands, ihn in der wurzel seines daseins in anspruch nehmen, i.e., which claims

and appeals to man in the root of his existence. This is a claim to become more

18 Ibid., p. 199.19 Ibid., p. 275.20 Ibid., p. 287.21 Ibid., p. 296.22 Ibid., p. 303 (my translation).

286 H. Ruin

123

Page 11: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

essential in the genuine will of his existence. ‘‘Why?’’, he asks. ‘‘For no less and no

greater as for: to become essential in the real willing of one’s own essence’’ (Wofur?Fur nichts geringeres und nicht hoheres als dafur: wesentlich zu werden imwirklichen wollen des eigenen Wesens).23 This is a remarkable statement in several

respects. Most importantly, from the perspective of our own initial question

concerning the relation between freedom as ontological problem versus freedom as

appeal, we can see how it emphatically establishes freedom as essentially a demand,

but a demand so radical that it in the end even sets a limit for the very possibility of

its theoretical representation.

4 IV

In the introduction to the essay on The essence of ground, Heidegger mentions

Schelling’s famous Freiheitsschrift from 1809 as an important contribution to the

question of the ground, and towards the end of that text we saw the echo of his

reading of Schelling in the reference to the abysmal (Ab-grund) nature of freedom.

Likewise in the essay on truth, the idea of a common and indifferent evanescent

origin of truth and falsity could be seen to reproduce in different terms the

speculative core of Schelling’s text. Six years later, in the summer of 1936,

Heidegger finally takes on this text in full, in his masterful critical exposition,

resulting eventually in the volume Schellings Abhandlung uber das Wesen derMenschlichen Freiheit (1809), published as a book by Niemeyer in 1971, with the

lecture manuscript edited by Hildegaard Feick in collaboration with Heidegger

himself. This exposition is also an attempt to come to an Auseinandersetzung with

Schelling and with German idealism as an historical epoch, whose speculative force,

in Heidegger’s view, reaches its apex in this particular text.

Unlike the discussion with Kant 6 years earlier, Heidegger is here closer to his

interlocutor. At least initially he mirrors Schelling’s own aspirations, also when

Schelling would seem to be more far removed than Kant from a contemporary

philosophical concern, in particular in view of his understanding of the divine and

the role of pantheism, which reverberates throughout the whole treatise. To some

extent this greater proximity issues from a greater interpretative violence, whereby

the text of Schelling is made to speak to the concern defined by Heidegger himself.

But I think we could perhaps also see it as an effect of Schelling’s lesser

philosophical weight in the present, which, like in the case of Holderlin, permits a

freer reading and appropriation on Heidegger’s part. This greater proximity can be

illustrated quite clearly from the outset, when Heidegger states that Schelling’s text

has nothing to do with the common concern with freedom, as the freedom of the will

of man. For here he says, freedom does not appear as ‘‘a property of man,’’ but the

other way around, that man is the property of freedom. The essence of man is

grounded in freedom, as itself a fundamental determination of being.24 Through this

23 Ibid., p. 303.24 Heidegger (1971b/1995, p. 11). This work was later also published in the Gesamtausgabe as vol. 42,

but the page references here are to the original version.

The destiny of freedom 287

123

Page 12: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

speculative turn, which is nowhere articulated as such by Schelling, Heidegger has

already from the start brought the text literally into the philosophical space which he

claimed it was impossible to recover from a reading of Kant.

On the next page he makes another very important point, which also reinstates

the significance of freedom as demand, in that he states that philosophy itself is only

possible as freedom, and that its very accomplishment constitutes a highest act of

freedom.25 Both of these propositions respond to the aspiration encoded in

Schelling’s text, namely to think the totality from the point of view of freedom, as

itself a culmination of that freedom. But whereas this is articulated by Schelling in

terms of the divine kernel in nature, which operates its teleological development in

and through the spirit of man, Heidegger here recovers it in an ontological and

atheistic, or rather a non-theistic discourse. For Heidegger, Schelling’s constant

reference to the divine, as well as the theological framework of his whole discourse,

is not something he leaves aside or seeks to discard as a time bound aspect of the

treatise. Instead he insists that all philosophy is essentially theology. Why? Because

it seeks to understand—to grasp in logos—the totality of beings in its ground, and

that it knows this ground: as god, theos. This, he says, is even the case with

Nietzsche. In asking for the totality of beings, philosophy speaks the language of

theology. Indeed, it is and has always been an onto-theology. Schelling’s treatise,

precisely when it speaks of the divine in nature, locates itself at the center of the

metaphysical question, and we should therefore read it as an attempt to speak to the

question: What is the totality of beings in its ground? This is a condensed and

forceful interpretation, which at once does violence to, and makes available

Schelling’s question from the highest possibility of our present philosophical

situation.

Much commentary is then devoted to the problem of system, in German idealism

in general, and in Schelling in particular. Kant’s legacy appears as the need to find

and construct a system in which man, god and world can be comprehended in a

synthetic unity, as a discourse on the totality of beings, within which man stands, as

its highest articulation. The means to accomplish this in Schelling is the intellectual

intuition, which Heidegger insists, is no unrealistic romantic fantasy, but the name

for the actual work of the spirit on itself, so as to bring its place within the totality of

beings to transparency.26 If freedom is the fundamental name for being, then the

system of the totality of beings must be a system of freedom. This is Schelling’s

great aspiration, which occupies him for the greater part of his life, just as it is the

inner aspiration of German idealism as a whole.27 Heidegger quotes a passage from

Schelling’s Munich lectures from 1827 in which he says: ‘‘A system of freedom, in

great lines, in the same simplicity, and yet as a total counter image to the

spinozistic—that would really be the highest’’.28 But this aspiration is also what is

doomed to fail, Heidegger says. Indeed, Schelling himself has already anticipated

this life long failure when he in the Freiheitsschrift says that according to an old

25 Ibid., p. 12.26 Ibid., p. 57.27 Cf. also Heidegger’s further remarks on the system on p. 109f.28 Ibid., p. 25.

288 H. Ruin

123

Page 13: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

saying the concept of freedom should be incompatible with that of a system. The

reason for this, Heidegger adds, is that ‘‘Freedom excludes the recourse to a

grounding. The system on the other hand demands a completed grounding’’.29 Seen

in this way, freedom is precisely that which cannot, indeed which is essentially

incapable of, serving as a ground for a system. And later on in the course Heidegger

also insists that ontology in his sense is not a system, as a discipline or a piece of

learning, but that it constitutes the question for the truth and ground of being, and

theology for us, he continues, is the question of the being of this very ground.30

How then does Schelling try to solve the problem, how does he attempt to

inscribe freedom into a system so as not to obliterate it in this very attempt? It is at

this point that the theological turn of the text occurs, when Schelling argues that

there must be such a system, such a perspective on the totality, if not elsewhere, then

in divine reason. From this point the treatise takes the perspective of the divine. It

begins to think the totality as divinity, but not as distinct from man, but on the

contrary as a way of conceptualizing from the highest possible point the position of

man in nature. One particular passage, Heidegger says, captures in poetic density

the entire movement of the treatise, where Schelling speaks of man as both the

principle of darkness and of light, and of his will as the ‘‘in eternal longing hidden

kernel of god,’’ of a God who once conceived will as nature.31 God is in us and we

are in God, and God becomes known through us. This pantheistic position

Heidegger also affirms in his own way, as he writes that we can only see what we

are, and that we are that to which we also belong. But this belonging is only

actualized to the extent that we confirm it (bezeugen), which is what happens in

Dasein. The connection here is clear to a theme which is central in Beitrage, on

which he is working at the same time, namely that only in belonging (zuhoren) to

being can being become present to us, precisely in its happening as an event of

belonging.32

Despite the inner failure to construct a system of freedom, what Schelling is

said to have rightly seen is the necessity to move beyond the separation of nature

as necessity and man as freedom. This is not a theme which should be treated as

a problem to be solved by philosophy (in the way perhaps Kant struggles with

it). Instead it should be recognized as the center of philosophy itself, from within

which it thinks. In Kant we stop before the two regions and their possible

mediation. For Schelling the task is to see how freedom runs through all domains

of being, only to reach a particular acuteness in man.33 His defense of pantheism

in this respect is consistent, Heidegger says, and there is no contradiction

29 Ibid., p. 26.30 Ibid., p. 79.31 The full quotation reads: ‘‘Im Menschen ist die ganze Macht des finstern Prinzips und in eben

demselben zugleich die ganze Kraft des Lichts. In ihm ist der tiefste Abgrund und der hochste Himmel,

oder beide Centra. Der Wille des Menschen ist der in der ewigen Sehnsucht verborgene Keim des nur

noch im Grunde vorhandenen Gottes; der in der Tiefe verschlossene gottliche Lebensblick, den Gott

ersah, als er den Willen zur Natur faßte’’, ibid. p. 65, on p. 35 in Schelling (1997).32 Cf., e.g., Heidegger (1989, p. 421) passim. For a more detailed analysis of Beitrage and the problem of

belonging as an historical-ontological category, see Ruin (2005a), and also Chapter 8 in Ruin (1994).33 Heidegger (1971b/1995, p. 73).

The destiny of freedom 289

123

Page 14: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

between pantheism and freedom, as was intensively debated at the time,

following Jacobi’s famous attack on Lessing in 1785 for ‘‘spinozism’’ (which

later also led him to criticize Schelling). For the genuine feeling for freedom

(Gefuhl) demands the belonging of man to the totality of beings, which is

another word for pantheism, and indeed the rightly understood pantheism even

presupposes human freedom.34 Schelling is the first to have tried to move beyond

a conception of nature as that which has to be overcome in order for freedom to

develop, and to try to bring freedom and nature together. This complete and

general concept of freedom is Schelling’s genuine contribution, over Kant and

Fichte, in Heidegger’s view.

But—and this ‘‘but’’ is the point where Heidegger’s whole discussion turns

around and leaves the violent but genuinely sympathetic reconstruction, and

begins to take its distance—but, in doing so Schelling also displays his

indebtedness to Leibniz, and the Monadology in a way that eventually points to

the incapacity of his thinking to provide a genuine alternative to the previous

tradition. The critical argument goes as follows: Schelling’s philosophy of nature

issues from the attempt to incorporate nature into freedom, and to think the

totality of beings from its perspective. From this ambition he is led to posit the

original determination of being as Wollen, as will. Will is original being,

according to Schelling, Wollen ist Ursein.35 In this he continues the Leibnizian

monadology, which is also echoed in Hegel, when the idea is placed at the peak

of his logic. Wollen ist das ursprungliche Wesen des Seins, willing is the original

essence of being, according to Schelling.36 It is with this statement that all is

suddenly decided. To put it somewhat drastically: here Heidegger parts ways, not

only with Schelling, but with German idealism as a whole, which in this

conception has revealed its interiority, as an apotheosis of the will. In this form, a

system of freedom becomes possible, once original being had been conceived as

will. And even though Schelling is presented by Heidegger as someone who

through his discourse on good and evil also wants to move beyond this purely

formal concept of freedom as original willing, it does not suffice.

In his concluding remarks, Heidegger states that the real importance of

Schelling’s treatise lies in its introduction and the first four sections, which discuss

the problem of the system and the basic comportment to philosophy. But in the end

Schelling does not reach much further than Kant in his understanding of freedom,

which remains unbegreiflich.37 And this has to do with the fact that freedom places

us in an actualization of being, not simply its representation. This enactment of

being, however, is not a blind process, but a wissendes Innestehen im Seienden imGanzen, das es auszustehen gilt, a knowing standing within beings in totality, so as

to endure it. And Heidegger continues to state that this awareness of freedom will

become ‘‘certain of its own highest necessity’’, because it alone is what ‘‘makes

possible that man can encounter a destiny, so as to take it upon himself, and carry it

34 Ibid., p. 106.35 Ibid., p. 114 (quotation from Schelling (1997, p. 350)).36 Ibid., p. 115.37 Ibid., p. 195.

290 H. Ruin

123

Page 15: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

beyond himself’’.38 In other words, as Heidegger reaches the end of this

monumental confrontation, he returns to essentially the same point as at the end

of his reading of Kant, namely that freedom is that which is understood to the extent

that we expose ourselves to its reality, which is the reality of standing historically

before the totality of being as destiny. But his sense of freedom is not only

something which neither Kant, nor Schelling, was able to articulate, but also

something which they could not articulate as such, since it necessarily withdraws

from a proper philosophical and conceptual grasp.

Heidegger’s genuine and explicit engagement with freedom as a fundamental

philosophical concept and theme coincides with his Auseinandersetzung with

German idealism during the thirties, a work which is also carried over into the

lectures on Nietzsche and Holderlin. When he returns again to Schelling’s essay and

to the epoch of German idealism in a 1941 lecture course on The metaphysics ofGerman Idealism, his confrontation with Nietzsche has already led him to posit this

whole epoch as a figure within the overall transformation of being. Our

confrontation with Schelling, he writes there, has shown that being is here posited

as presence and in modern terms as subjectivity, and as will. Furthermore, this is not

something unique to Schelling, but a testimony to the presenting of being itself.39

But through the questioning from the other beginning (what is there understood as

equivalent to the leaping into the truth of being), he writes, that all of this is

superceded, uberwunden.40 Also in the Letter on Humanism, his treatment of Hegel

and Schelling in conjunction is likewise sharp and definitive. They are both said to

think being as a will that wills itself, as knowledge and love, ‘‘And in this will the

will to power is already hiding.’’41 Period. Here the verdict has fallen. It is to some

extent a curious verdict. What was once conceived as the great promise of this

movement and its inheritance, is thereby definitively transformed into a fixed period

and a culmination of a fate.

What conclusion should we draw from this summary reading of Heidegger’s

confrontation with German idealism when it comes to the role of freedom in

Heidegger’s own thinking? This is now our question. One possible answer could be:

since the preoccupation with freedom in the previous tradition has led precisely to a

metaphysics of the will, then freedom also, and its illusions of autonomy and

subjectivity, can henceforth be discarded. The fact that Heidegger never again

returns to the problem, and hardly even refers to very concept of freedom in his

subsequent texts, could be interpreted to support such a claim. Yet from my

concluding remarks on his interpretations of Kant and Schelling, we could also—

and indeed, I think we should—draw a different conclusion. For what was stated at

the end of each of these interpretations was not that freedom was not fundamental,

38 Ibid., p. 196. The full quotation reads: ‘‘Dieses Wissen der Freiheit wird seiner hochsten

Notwendigkeit gewiß, weil es allein jene Aufnahmestellung ermoglicht, in der stehend der Mensch

imstande ist, als ein Geschichtlicher einem Schicksal zu begegnen, es auf sich zu nehmen und uber sich

hinweg zu tragen.’’39 Heidegger (1991, p. 187).40 Ibid., p. 189.41 Heidegger (1967, p. 360).

The destiny of freedom 291

123

Page 16: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

but that the nature of this foundation was such that it could only be understood on

the condition that the subject is somehow drawn into its demand as something to

endure, rather than simply understand. In other words, we were left with freedom as

the name for that which not only withdraws from a representational mode of

thought, but which must refuse this representation in order to be and appear as what

it is. This refusal is something which somehow remains to be enacted also in

ourselves, whereby we refuse to be captured by the will to conceptually dominate

our own fundamental existential predicament. From this perspective, the failures of

German idealism would not be that it sought to build a philosophy on and around

the phenomenon of freedom, but that its representatives were all ultimately led to

posit this ground as a founding will, and thus to betray what was perhaps also their

own deepest philosophical motive.

5 V

In Reiner Schurmann’s important study Heidegger on Being and Acting: fromprinciples to anarchy, which was mentioned above, there is a chapter on how we

should view the transformation of the problem of the will in Heidegger. He starts

out from the established opinion, that we find in SZ a partly voluntaristic discourse,

centered on decision, on becoming a self through an act of will, a discourse which,

following the turning (understood as a gradual transformation during the first half of

the thirties), is replaced by its opposite, a refusal of the will, a will not to will,

manifested instead in the comportment of letting-be, Gelassenheit. But this account,

he continues, needs to be complemented by a more sustained meditation on the

problem of decision, Entscheidung. Referring to the essay on The Origin of theWork of Art, and also to the Nietzsche interpretation, Schurmann recalls how the

fundamental words for being are presented by Heidegger precisely as ‘‘decisive’’

events. The history of metaphysics itself can be followed as a series of such

decisions, taken by no one in particular, but as result of which things are then

necessarily thought of in new ways. Schurmann speaks of these decisions as

‘‘economic’’ decisions, separating them from anything that can or could be willed

by individuals. ‘‘Just as thrownness precedes every project, so an essential,

disjunctive, historical-destinal, economic, aletheiological, non-human, systematic

decision precedes all human or voluntary decisions, all comportment.’’42

The question then arises how to comport oneself with regard to these decisions

already taken in and by being so to speak. For Schurmann, in his reading of

Heidegger, ‘‘it can only mean to follow the context-setting will in its epochal

decline, to dismiss it as the last metaphysical stamp, as the being of entities, as the

mark of our age’’. Citing Arendt, he says that ‘‘the will acts like ‘a kind of coup

d’etat’, as a force which seeks to establish the self as permanent and time as

lasting.’’ In action it manifests itself as principal acting, which is the very

manifestation of the hubris of modernity. For Schurmann, Heidegger presents a

42 Schurmann (1987, p. 247). I will here refer to the revised English version of the original Le principed’anarchie: Heidegger et la question de l’agir (Paris: Seuil, 1982).

292 H. Ruin

123

Page 17: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

response to the question of acting and what is do be done, in insisting, as he does in

the 1955 text on Gelassenheit, that we will non-willing. Heidegger urges, he writes,

the downthrow of epochal principles that are already foundering, a downthrow that

must be understood otherwise than willful, decisive, resolute or efficacious. This

kind of non-willing and releasement, are more subversive today than any project of

the will. Outlining and presenting this alternative is also the whole point behind the

title of the book, ‘‘from principles to anarchy’’.

In this program for a willing the non-willing, the problem of freedom first seems

to be absent. Schurmann does not address it, and Heidegger, in his later writings

does not openly invite such a discussion. On the contrary, it would seem natural to

assume that the very idea of freedom as autonomy, and as principled self-regulation,

belongs to the manifestation of a certain age, in which being shines forth precisely

as will and as a ground to be given, as explicability and mastery. If the principal

decisions and epochal transformations have always already been taken, if the very

figure of man, of humanity and its humanisms, are conceived in advance, beyond

any possible individual human decision, then the very idea of man as ‘‘free’’, as

essentially free, and even as called upon to become more and more free, would

obtain an almost ludicrous appearance, as simply the ideological effect of an age,

which thus demonstrates its incapacity to think its own predicament. What remains

for thinking to contemplate is not to continue to dream the dream of freedom but to

learn instead to understand the historical structures that have produced its

phantasms. It is to engage in an investigation of the conceptual transformations

of being and its epochs, and to comply in thinking with its sending, its fate.

In the final section of Nietzsche II, Heidegger would seem to confirm such a

conclusion when he writes: ‘‘The recollection in the history of being thinks this

history as the always distant arrival of a settling (Austrag) of the essence of truth, in

which the essence of being itself inceptually happens (ereignet).’’ Here being is

conveyed as that which gives itself for reflection, and as the possessor of what is

most proper to the thinker, and even as having itself a ‘‘freedom’’, in virtue of which

it ‘‘gives’’ itself.43 From the perspective of the discovery of a history of being, as a

series of sendings, of Geschick, the possible autonomy of man would seem to loose

its interest. Is this, then, the truth of the fate of freedom in Heidegger, that in the end

freedom is fate, a fate with which Dasein must simply comply?44

Heidegger’s later work contributed, on the one hand, to a more general suspicion

with regard to the relevance and pertinence of freedom, as demonstrated in the

suspicion vis-a-vis existentialism in structuralist thought, and in various forms of

anti- and a-humanisms which emerged during the sixties. Politically it carried with

it a suspicion with regard to the discourse of liberalism in general, which relies as its

foundation, on the primacy of the autonomous individual. On the other hand, and

starting already with Habermas’ early critical confrontation in 1953, precisely this

aspect of his thinking has generated a strong critical reactions among many of his

43 Heidegger (1961, p. 482).44 For an analysis of the destinal in Heidegger, which unites the theme of Schicksal with the earlier

analysis of historicity in SZ, and which also shows how Heidegger’s understanding of destiny is by no

means ‘‘fatalistic’’, see Ruin (2007, pp. 15–34).

The destiny of freedom 293

123

Page 18: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

contemporary readers (and non-readers!).45 It has been argued in different ways that

it is precisely this anti-liberal aspect of his thinking which led to his inability to

reflect critically on the emergence of European fascism, as well as his inability to

reconsider in retrospect his misguided political orientation. I will not try to rehearse

this debate here, but the point of my argument has a bearing on its outcome, since it

is concerned with exploring a certain sense of what I would dare to call an original

liberalism in Heidegger’s thinking.

If there is indeed a risk implied by Heidegger’s thinking in this respect today, it is

not a political risk, but rather a philosophical risk, which manifests itself in regard to

the reading of his own work, which always risks falling back into a kind of

doctrinary systematics. In its doctrinary form, the history of being becomes a system

of history, indeed a strange kind of post-idealistic system of freedom, as the system

of the freedom of beings itself, in the form of a history of its consecutive

manifestations, which is then repeated as a body of historical knowledge. More

generally, it leads to the temptation of a mode of thinking, which finds its highest

goal in a distanced categorization of its own present in terms of specific historical

sendings, and thus approaches the point of a kind of melancholic fatalism, in which

the fate of the West has already been fulfilled in the state of technological nihilism.

Then when this melancholy revolts against its own pathos and turns around—

perhaps in an explicit anti-heideggerianism—in a gesture of absolute affirmation of

precisely the same situation, it often simply ceases to think, and loses itself to the

present and its transitory concerns, in a superficial post-modernist posture.

The risk inherent in Heidegger’s attempts to develop a post-metaphysical

reflection coincides with its highest speculative expressions. This is clearly the case

with Beitrage, where he speaks of the so called inceptual thinking as a thinking in

which the very notion of self must be understood not as the result of a voluntary

action of an ego, but as the ‘‘enownment of belonging to the call’’ (Sect. 30), to

quote the English translation. In this and numerous formulations the attempt is made

to call Dasein back to a reflection, in which it can recognize itself as ungrounded,

handed over to itself by being itself. At this highest speculative point of Heidegger’s

discourse, the risk is run, and must perhaps be run, that the subject piously bends

down before the reality of its non-autonomy, and that it in its philosophical practice

satisfies itself with recapitulating the historical steps whereby it has been

constituted.

How and to what extent can such a thinking nevertheless still be spoken of as a

form of resistance and of action? Schurmann is right in pointing out the

‘‘subversiveness’’ of Heidegger’s later thinking, also in its most apparently fatalistic

formulations. But the nature of this subversiveness needs to be articulated more

sharply, or perhaps one should rather say, that it need to articulated always anew, in

order ultimately to free Heidegger’s own discourse from sinking down into yet

another ossified system of thought. And for this purpose I think it is important to

continue to explore his mode of reflection precisely as a peculiar form of praxis, as a

form of action, and to see more specifically in what way this continues to be guided

by a notion of freedom, also after this specific word has ceased to function as an

45 Habermas (1953).

294 H. Ruin

123

Page 19: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

explicit and guiding theme in its own right. We remain responsible in the face of a

tradition, also when our relation to this tradition is reformulated in terms of a

response to its sending and its address. As Bret Davis writes in relation to how the

question of the will is formulated by Schurmann: ‘‘where would the impetus to

voluntary renunciation of volition come from?’’46 Similarly, the question of

freedom and individual responsibility does not simply disappear just by transposing

the event of decision concerning the meaning of being from Dasein to being itself.

6 VI

What then is the guiding motive of the kind of reflection, this besinnende Denken,

which Heidegger seeks to practice in his continued meditations on thinkers and

themes from Beitrage onwards?47 Does this question have one answer? Is not the

very question suspicious, as it signals the search for an effect, or a result, from that

thinking which explicitly—if we are to take seriously what he declares in the Letteron Humanism, that this thinking is without effect, that es hat keine Wirkung.48 But

also in the same paragraph he adds that this thinking has a sachhaltigerverbindlichkeit, a stronger connection to the matter, than the validity of science,

for it is freer, freier, as it lets being be. In other words, that which accomplishes

nothing can still be recognized as a work of freedom, as an accomplishment of

freedom itself, indeed it finds its very legitimacy precisely in being more free than

that which has a result. This is an extraordinary statement in view of the problem

which concerns us here. The same point is made in the lecture on ‘‘What is

philosophy?’’ Which Heidegger presented at the seminar in Cerisy-la-Salle in 1955,

where he speaks of the tradition of philosophy, as a ‘‘free direction of a path, on

which we can ask: what is that—philosophy?’’ The tradition does not appear in the

form of a compulsion, for ‘‘to transmit (uberliefern), delivrer, is a freeing, namely in

the freedom of the dialogue with what has been.’’49 Later on in the same lecture

Heidegger states that to take up this tradition is essentially to respond to it, and to

assume the tradition in this way is what in SZ is designated by the term

‘‘destruction.’’ By this term, he says, I did not intend a dispersal or obliteration of

the past, but a dismantling and placing to the side the ‘‘only historical’’ statements of

philosophy. Destruction means: to open our ear, to be free—freimachen—for that

which speaks to us as the being of beings in the tradition.

This remark I read as the indication of a fundamental ethos of Heidegger’s

thinking, and it is therefore so much more noteworthy, that it insists precisely on the

liberating force of philosophical thought. If we begin to look further into the

statements in which he, so to speak, motivates his whole endeavor it is striking to

what extent one particular formulation returns again and again in the later texts:

namely that the task of thinking is to lead us to ‘‘the Free’’, ins Freie. In Sect. 204 of

46 Davis (2007, p. 207).47 For a more detailed analysis of the specific theme of ‘‘Besinnung,’’ see Ruin (2005b).48 Heidegger (1967, p. 358).49 Heidegger (1966, p. 8).

The destiny of freedom 295

123

Page 20: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

Beitrage he speaks of a need that should bring about that the second beginning leads

the first into ‘‘the free’’—ins Freie—so as to overcome it. In the subsequent section

the free is described in terms of openness, and a keenness of creating, as well as

what is unprotected, an exposure which brings things to the fore. From the same

year as the lecture on What is Philosophy?, dates the lecture series Der Satz vomGrund in which the question from 1929 is raised again, 25 years later. Here he

writes of the sending of being (Geschick des Seins) as an address from out of which

all human discourse emanates. Spruch, he says, is in latin Fatum, but what is meant

here is no ‘‘fatalism,’’ because as this word reaches us it carries with it the free of the

Zeit-spiel-raum, and only thereby frees man into ‘‘the free of his fated possibil-

ities.’’50 Already in the lectures on Schelling’s Freiheitsschrift analyzed above, he

had said in the introduction, that through the interpretation of a historical text—in

this case Schelling’s essay—‘‘when we begin to understand, it departs from us and

into the movement of the happening (Geschehnis) of the philosophy of German

idealism, and reveals its inner law, which is what we have to grasp in order to reach

into the free.’’51 Immediately after this he also added that we do not overcome or

become free from history only by turning our backs on it. What is essential turns

back, and the question is rather if a time is prepared for it and strong enough for it.

Together these passages—which are only a few examples of this often repeated

trope—point toward a conception of philosophical work which remains guided by a

certain understanding of freedom, not primarily as agency or independence, i.e., not

as classifiable according to a standard distinction between a positive and a negative

freedom, but as a kind of responsive openness to what is.52 To reach the free as an

interpretative goal, as in the Schelling book, is obviously not to liberate oneself

from the matter of the past, but to reach a point where one is able to encounter it.

But what is the nature of this free encounter, as opposed to a supposedly bound

encounter, guided by prejudices or misconceptions? From a traditional point of view

we know what the answer is, namely truth or correctness. Freedom is freedom for

truth, and truth is also what—ideally—sets us free. But a traditional concept of truth

as correctness is discharged from the very beginning here. And yet it is in an

exposure to the event of disclosure that this openness finds its telos also for

Heidegger. But this disclosure or event does not have, indeed it cannot have the

character of a fixed and certain belief, for then it collapses again into an objectifying

posture. Instead it can only be understood as the ability to prevail in the exposure to

the gift of disclosure, indeed to the gift of time itself, to the Es gibt envoked in the

lecture ‘‘Zeit und Sein’’ from 1962.53 Ultimately, this is what marks and constitutes

the work of freedom. To step into the free is to step into the exposed and uncertain

possibility of an experience, in which one’s previous conceptions, including those of

oneself, is placed at risk. This is also the inner, and not always apparent ethos of

50 Heidegger (1971a, p. 158).51 Heidegger (1971b/1995, p. 5).52 Bret Davis expresses a similar point when he writes, ‘‘were modern man to be wholly and seamlessly

confined to his historical essence of willful subjectivity, the ‘will’ to non-willing would forever

reduplicate the problem it aims to ‘overcome’’’, Davis (2007, p. 214).53 Heidegger (1969/1988).

296 H. Ruin

123

Page 21: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

Heidegger’s thinking and writing: to bring reflection to a point where it can ‘‘permit

things to be’’, and to ‘‘stand open for the secret,’’ as the two basic aspects of

philosophical comportments are described in the seminal text on Gelassenheit.54 In

the course of such a meditation we place ourselves at risk, in the sense that we open

our ears to what speaks from tradition, and from being itself. As it exposes itself to

the force of the address of being, thinking will have to renounce its beliefs in

mastery of itself and its own fate, and instead release itself for the destiny inherent

in its own finite situation. But this kind of reflection is not the abandonment of

freedom as such, only of its illusion in the form of a completed autonomy. Instead it

is the work of a freedom always to be achieved anew, in the practicing of

philosophical questioning as the interminable dialogue with what is. In this sense,

Heidegger’s thought can rightly be called a philosophy of freedom, a philosophy of

freedom not in the subjective genitive as a philosophy about freedom, but rather in

the objective; as a philosophy from freedom, as an attempt to respond to its difficult

and evanescent demand.

7 VII

Freedom is never entirely lost, nor can it once and for all be achieved. It remains

always the task of the individual and the community, to have the courage to expose

itself to the evanescent ground which can never be fixed and mastered, but which

only manifests itself in and through a destructive, releasing dialogue, which can

permit it to appear as an already there, in its freedom, as the free, and precisely

therefore in its fate, as a given space of decision. Only by freeing ourselves for the

situation in which we already stand can we genuinely act, and not simply reproduce

a grip which already holds us. This is the truth of the thought of Gelassenheit, as it

also seeks to place us ‘‘in the free.’’ This kind of meditation may appear

fundamentally a-political, in the sense of being defaitistic, yielding or compliant.

But it is also essentially political, for it releases man from his belief in fixed

individuality and of its freedom as a fixed property, and brings him before a

community and its historical situation. In its implication, if not stated as such by

Heidegger, it marks an openness to the other, not simply as acceptance, but as to the

possibility of a dialogue, as a wakefulness to what may show itself as binding. To

will freedom is to will the disclosure of being, but also to will the freedom of the

other, as Simone de Beauvoir writes in her essay Pour un morale de l’ambiguitefrom 1947, a text which could be read as response to the Letter on Humanism. It is a

text which takes up several of its themes, refusing also to display an ethics in the

sense of a given set of rules or principles, and insisting on the connection between

ethics and the opening of existence toward being, thus offering a more fruitful

appropriating response to Heidegger than Sartre’s neo-cartesianism.55

Freedom must be continuously questioned, as a phantasm and illusion of

modernity, but this questioning will have to continue to be performed precisely in

54 Heidegger (1959/1992).55 Beauvoir (1947).

The destiny of freedom 297

123

Page 22: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

the name of—freedom. At the end of his lecture course on Der Ister, from 1942,

Heidegger summarizes his reading of Holderlin by stating that in the Stromdichtungwe should not listen for symbols of something else, nor for the expression of an

individual, but that Holderlin thinks and poetizes in a vein which is hardly audible

for the present preoccupation with subjectivity.56 In order to hear this poetry, and

the domain, the Ort, from which it speaks, we must leave behind all attempts to

connect or correlate it to specific realities, in order—again—to reach into the free,

das Freie, in whose domain the poetic is. Holderlin asks Giebt es auf Erden einMaas? Is there a measure on earth? And he responds Es giebt keines—there is none.

Heidegger reads this as saying that there is no fixed measure to simply rely on, no

principle of control. For all attempts to fix and operate the measure will inevitably

lead to a total destruction of measure, and to nothingness, Nichtigkeit. On the other

hand, if we remain in thoughtless and without the wakefulness of a prufendeAhnens, an experimenting anticipation, then no measure will present itself. We need

therefore a certain strength in order to be struck by what is conveyed in the poetry.

The poet himself follows this law, Heidegger writes, and quotes a strophe from ‘‘DieWanderung’’: Zum Traume wirds ihm, will es Einer/Beschleichen und straft den,der/Ihm gleichen will mit Gewalt./Oft uberrascht es den, Der eben kaum es gedachthat.57 It becomes a dream, it veils and punishes the one who wants to control it with

violence—and often it surprises the one who has hardly even thought about it. This

law of the wandering poet, who does not believe that the measure is there to

establish, but who seeks it out, in his thinking and writing, and thus in his action, to

permit the measure to shine forth, this law could also be read as the demand of

freedom. It carries with it the courage to be surprised, and to be exposed to oneself

as another.

We have followed here how Heidegger in the texts immediately following upon

SZ strives to create a phenomenological ontology on the basis of human freedom as

transcendence, in close if yet critical proximity to German idealism, and to

Schelling in particular. This period is one in which his thinking can justly and non-

controversially be described as a ‘‘philosophy of freedom’’ in the sense given to it,

e.g., by Figal. But the more debatable issue is how the emergence of the non-

voluntaristic schema of the later writings is to be understood, and what the

implications of the history or sending of being are for to the sense of human

freedom. Here I have shown how this later constellation grows, stepwise through the

detailed critical engagement with the writings of Kant and Schelling in particular.

More specifically it became clear that the decisive point of disagreement is not

human freedom as such, but the inevitable failure of trying to construe an

ontological freedom as a foundation. For what this attempt implies is not

automatically a forgetfulness of being, but also a forgetfulness of freedom itself,

in the sense of its more original manifestation as demand and appeal. When the non-

foundational freedom is made into a foundation it inevitably lead to a metaphysics

of the will. But the solution to this aporia is not to abandon will and freedom, but to

think them in their character of what it means to stand open for the event of being

56 Heidegger (1984, p. 203).57 Ibid., p. 206.

298 H. Ruin

123

Page 23: Hans Ruin The destiny of freedom: in Heidegger

and of truth. As such the phenomenon of human freedom and transcendence is

handed over by Heidegger, not simply as a discarded illusion, nor as a higher order

possession, now secured within the movement of the history of being, but as a task,

as the highest task, indeed the most difficult, but also the most joyful.

References

Davis, Bret. 2007. Heidegger and the Will. On the Way to Gelassenheit. Bloomington: Indiana University

Press.

de Beauvoir, Simone. 1947. Pour un morale de l’ambiguite. Paris: Gallimard.

Figal, Gunter. 1988. Martin Heidegger. Phanomenologie der Freiheit, 275. Frankfurt am Main:

Athenaum.

Habermas, Jurgen. 1953. Mit Heidegger gegen Heidegger Denken. Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung.

25.7.53.

Heidegger, Martin. 1927/1979. Sein und Zeit. Tubingen: Niemeyer

Heidegger, Martin. 1959/1992. Gelassenheit. Pfullingen: Neske.

Heidegger, Martin. 1961. Nietzsche II. Pfullingen: Neske.

Heidegger, Martin. 1966. Was is das—die Philosophie? Pfullingen: Neske.

Heidegger, Martin. 1967. Wegmarken. Frankfurt am Main: Klostermann.

Heidegger, Martin. 1969. Sur Sache des Denkens. Tubingen: Niemeyer.

Heidegger, Martin. 1971a. Der Satz vom Grund. Pfullingen: Neske.

Heidegger, Martin. 1971b/1995. Schellings Abhandlung uber das Wesen der Menschlichen Freiheit(1809). Tubingen: Niemeyer.

Heidegger, Martin. 1982/1994. Vom Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit, Gesamtausgabe, vol. 31. Frankfurt

am Main: Klostermann.

Heidegger, Martin. 1984. Holderlins Hymne ‘‘Der Ister’’ Gesamtausgabe, vol. 53. Frankfurt am Main:

Klostermann.

Heidegger, Martin. 1989. Beitrage zur Philosophie (Vom Ereignis), Gesamtausgabe, vol. 65. Frankfurt

am Main: Klostermann.

Heidegger, Martin. 1991. Die Metaphysik des deutschen Idealismus, Gesamtausgabe, vol. 49. Frankfurt

am Main: Klostermann.

Kant, Immanuel. 1968a. Kritik der Praktischen Vernunft. In Werke: Akademie-Textausgabe, vol. 5.

Berlin: De Gruyter.

Kant, Immanuel. 1968b. Antwort auf die Frage: Was ist Aufklarung? In Werke: Akademie-Textausgabe,

vol. 8. Berlin: de Gruyter.

Ruin, Hans. 1994. Enigmatic origins: Tracing the theme of historicity through Heidegger’s works.

Stockholm: Almqvist & Wiksell.

Ruin, Hans. 2005a. Contributions. In Blackwell companion to Heidegger, ed. H. Dreyfus, and

M. Wrathall. Oxford: Blackwell.

Ruin, Hans. 2005b. Prudence, passion, and freedom: On Heidegger’s ideal of Besinnung. Giornale diMetafisica XXVIII: 29–52.

Ruin, Hans. 2007. Ein geheimnisvolles Schicksal—Heidegger und das griechische Erbe. In MartinHeidegger Gesellschaft Schriftenreihe, 15–34, vol. 8. Frankfurt am main: Klostermann.

Sartre, Jean-Paul. 1946. La liberte cartesienne. In Descartes, Discours de la methode. Paris-Geneve:

Traits.

Schelling, Friedrich. 1997. Uber das Wesen der menschlichen Freiheit. Hamburg: Felix Meiner Verlag.

Schurmann, Reiner. 1987. Heidegger on being and acting: From principles to anarchy. Bloomington:

Indiana University Press.

The destiny of freedom 299

123