PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    1/26

    Pragmatism was a philosophical tradition that originated in the United States

    around 1870. The most important of the classical pragmatists were Charles

    Sanders Peirce (18391914), William James (18421910) and John Dewey

    (18591952). The influence of pragmatism declined during the first two thirds of

    the twentieth century, but it has undergone a revival since the 1970s withphilosophers being increasingly willing to use the writings and ideas of the

    classical pragmatists, and also a number of thinkers, such as Richard Rorty,

    Hilary Putnam and Robert Brandom developing philosophical views that

    represent later stages of the pragmatist tradition. The core of pragmatism was the

    pragmatist maxim, a rule for clarifying the contents of hypotheses by tracing

    their practical consequences. In the work of Peirce and James, the most

    influential application of the pragmatist maxim was to the concept of truth. But

    the pragmatists have also tended to share a distinctive epistemological outlook, a

    fallibilist anti-Cartesian approach to the norms that govern inquiry.

    For much of the twentieth century, pragmatism was largely in eclipse. Few

    philosophers were familiar with the works of classical pragmatists such as

    Charles Sanders Piece and William James, and pragmatist ideas were not at the

    centre of debate. John Dewey, who had been a dominant philosophical figure in

    the 1920s was no longer a central figure. Analytical philosophers and their

    students had a central role in philosophy. It was not until the 1970s that interest

    in the writings of the Pragmatists became widespread and pragmatist ideas were

    recognized as able to make a major contribution to philosophy.

    Most of this entry is devoted to the ideas of the classical pragmatists, Peirce,

    James, and Dewey. But towards the end of the entry we shall explore what are

    sometimes called the new pragmatists. These are philosophers who revitalized

    pragmatism, developing ideas that evidently belonged to the pragmatist tradition.

    As well as the figures mentioned above, these include Philip Kitcher, Huw Price,

    and others (Misak 2007, Malachowski 2010. There has also been a growing

    interest in the connections between pragmatism and idealism: (Margolis 2010,

    Stern 2009, chapters 710).

    1. Pragmatism and pragmatism 2. The pragmatist maxim 3. Pragmatist theories of truth

    o 3.1 Peirce on truth and realityo 3.2 James on truth

    4. The pragmatist tradition

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraMaxhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraMaxhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTheTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTheTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PeiTruReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PeiTruReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#JamTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#JamTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#JamTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PeiTruReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraTheTruhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraMaxhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraPra
  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    2/26

    o 4.1 Skepticism and fallibilismo 4.2 Inquiryo 4.3 The pragmatist conception of experienceo 4.4 Representations

    5. Other pragmatists

    6. Conclusion Bibliography

    o Primary texts of the classical pragmatistso Collections of papers by classic and contemporary pragmatists.o Other references and supplementary reading

    Academic Tools Other Internet Resources Related Entries

    1. Pragmatism and pragmatism

    When William James published a series of lectures on Pragmatism: A New

    Name for an Old way of Thinking in 1907, he began by identifying The Present

    Dilemma in Philosophy (1907: 9ff), a fundamental and apparently irresoluble

    clash between two ways of thinking about things. He promised that pragmatism

    would show us the way to overcome this dilemma and, having thus shown us its

    importance, he proceeded, in the second lecture, to explain What PragmatismMeans.

    James's dilemma is a familiar one: it is a form of the question of how we can

    reconcile the claims of science, on the one hand, with those of religion and

    morality on the other. James introduces it by observing that the history of

    philosophy is to a great extent that of a certain clash of human temperaments,

    between the tough minded and the tender minded. The tough minded have an

    empiricist commitment to experience and going by the facts, while the tender-

    minded have more of a taste for a priori principles which appeal to the mind. The

    tender minded tend to be idealistic, optimistic and religious, while the tough

    minded are normally materialist, pessimistic and irreligious. The tender-minded

    are free-willist and dogmatic; the tough minded are fatalistic and sceptical.

    By the early twentieth century, never were so many men of a decidedly

    empiricist proclivity: our children are almost born scientific (1907: 14f).

    http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#SkeFalhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#SkeFalhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Inqhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Inqhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraConExphttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraConExphttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Rephttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Rephttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Conhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Conhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Bibhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Bibhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PriTexClaPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PriTexClaPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#ColPapClaConPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#ColPapClaConPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthRefSupReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthRefSupReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Acahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Acahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Othhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Othhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Relhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Relhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Relhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Othhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Acahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthRefSupReahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#ColPapClaConPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PriTexClaPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Bibhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Conhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#OthPrahttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Rephttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#PraConExphttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#Inqhttp://plato.stanford.edu/entries/pragmatism/#SkeFal
  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    3/26

    But this has not weakened religious belief. People need a philosophy that is both

    empiricist in its adherence to facts yet finds room for religious belief. But all that

    is on offer is an empirical philosophy that is not religious enough and a religious

    philosophy that is not empirical enough for your purpose (1907: 15f). The

    challenge is to show how to reconcile the scientific loyalty to facts with the oldconfidence in human values and the resultant spontaneity, whether of the

    religious or of the romantic type. We must reconcile empiricist epistemic

    responsibility with moral and religious optimism. Pragmatism is presented as the

    mediating philosophy that enables us to overcome the distinction between the

    tender-minded and the tough-minded: we need to show how adherence to tough-

    minded epistemic standards does not prevent our adopting the kind of worldview

    to which the tender-minded aspire. Once we use what he introduced as the

    pragmatic method to clarify our understanding of truth, of free will, or of

    religious belief the disputeswhich we despaired of settling intellectuallybegin to dissolve. For James, then, Pragmatism is important because it offers a

    way of overcoming the dilemma, a way of seeing that, for example, science,

    morality and religion are not in competition.

    William James thus presented pragmatism as a method for settling metaphysical

    disputes that might otherwise be interminable. (1907: 28) Unless some practical

    difference would follow from one or the other side's being correct, the dispute is

    idle.

    [T]he tangible fact at the root of all our thought-distinctions, however subtle, isthat there is no one of them so fine as to consist in anything but a possible

    difference of practice. To attain perfect clearness in our thoughts of an object,

    then, we need only consider what conceivable effects of a practical kind the

    object may involvewhat sensations we are to expect from it, and what

    reactions we must prepare. (1907: 29)

    The lectures explained this with a memorable illustration of pragmatism in

    action. This shows how the maxim enables us to defuse an apparently insoluble

    (albeit trivial) dispute. On a visit to the mountains, his friends engage in aferocious metaphysical dispute about a squirrel that was hanging on to one side

    of a tree trunk while a human observer was standing on the other side:

    This human witness tries to get sight of the squirrel by moving rapidly round the

    tree, but no matter how fast he goes, the squirrel moves as fast in the opposite

    direction, and always keeps the tree between himself and the man, so that never a

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    4/26

    glimpse of him is caught. The resultant metaphysical problem now is this:Does

    the man go round the squirrel or not?(1907: 27f)

    James proposed to solve the problem by pointing out that which answer is correct

    depends on what you practically mean by going round. If you mean passing

    from north of him to east, then south, then west, then the answer to the question

    is yes. If, on the other hand, you mean first in front of him, then to his right,

    then behind him, and then to his left, before returning to being in front of him

    again, then the answer is no. Pragmatic clarification disambiguates the

    question, and once that is done, all dispute comes to an end. The pragmatic

    method promises to eliminate all apparently irresoluble metaphysical disputes.

    So James offers his pragmatism as a technique for clarifying concepts and

    hypotheses. He proposed that if we do this, metaphysical disputes that appear to

    be irresoluble will be dissolved. When philosophers suppose that free will and

    determinism are in conflict, James responds that once we compare the practical

    consequences of determinism being true with the practical consequences of our

    possessing freedom of the will, we find that there is no conflict.

    As James admitted, he explained the pragmatic method through examples rather

    than by giving a detailed analysis of what it involves. He did very little to explain

    exactly what practical consequences are. He made no claim to originality:

    Pragmatism represents a perfectly familiar attitude in philosophy, the empiricist

    attitude, although he acknowledged that it did so in a more radical and in a lessobjectionable form than it has ever yet assumed (1907: 31). It shared with other

    forms of empiricism an anti-intellectualist tendency (ibid), and it recognized

    that theories (and presumably concepts) should be viewed as instruments, not

    answers to enigmas. We identify the practical consequences of a theory,

    concept or hypothesis by describing its role as an instrument in thought, in

    inquiry and in practical deliberation.

    James also admitted that he was not the first to defend the principle of

    pragmatism. (1907: 29). The principle of pragmatism was the principle ofPeirce his friend and colleague of many years. Published in 1878 in a paper

    called How to Make our Ideas Clear (EP2: 124141), it lay entirely unnoticed

    by anyone for twenty years until James defended it before the Philosophical

    Union in the University of California in 1898. If we want a detailed formulation

    of pragmatism, we must go back to Peirce's original formulation, although we

    must also be mindful that the differences between the pragmatisms of Peirce and

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    5/26

    James may be greater than James acknowledged. And although the principle of

    Peirce was published in 1878, it didn't introduce the word pragmatism; it was

    only after James's 1898 address that pragmatism was used publicly in

    philosophy; and it was only after James's defence of pragmatism that it became

    famous.

    Pragmatism had been born in the discussions at a metaphysical club in Harvard

    around 1870 (see Menand 1998). Peirce and James participated in these

    discussions along with some other philosophers and philosophically inclined

    lawyers. As we have already noted, Peirce developed these ideas in his

    publications from the 1870s. And James's lectures in 1898 and later represented

    the next stages in the development of pragmatism. Both James and Peirce used

    pragmatism as the name of a method, principle, or maxim for clarifying

    concepts and hypotheses and for identifying empty disputes. As we shall see

    there were differences in how they understood the method and in their views of

    how it was to be applied.

    Later thinkers, for example John Dewey and C.I.Lewis, developed pragmatism

    further. Although they continued to refer back to Peirce's 1878 paper as the

    source of pragmatism, and they continued to regard concepts and hypotheses as

    functioning as instruments, they did not always think of pragmatism as

    denoting the principle of Peirce. Dewey once described pragmatism as the

    systematic exploration of what he called the logic and ethics of scientific

    inquiry. (LW: 15.24) Both Peirce and James combined their pragmatism with adistinctive epistemological outlook, one which rejected the Cartesian focus upon

    the importance of defeating skepticism while endorsing the fallibilist view that

    any of our beliefs and methods could, in principle, turn out to be flawed. This

    was tied to the study of the normative standards we should adopt when carrying

    out inquiries, when trying to find things out. Inquiry is an activity, and this sort of

    approach, in Dewey's hands, led to a rejection of there being a sharp dichotomy

    between theoretical judgments and practical judgments. Thus while Peirce and

    James used pragmatism in anarrowsense, as referring to Peirce's principle,

    others may have used it in a widesense as standing for a particular approach tounderstanding inquiry and the normative standards that govern it. Sections 2 and

    3 will be concerned, primarily, with pragmatism in the narrow sense. Then, in

    section 4, we shall explore some of the views that are associated with pragmatism

    in the wider sense.

    2. The pragmatist maxim

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    6/26

    As we have seen, the pragmatist maxim is a distinctive rule or method for

    becoming reflectively clear about the contents of concepts and hypotheses: we

    clarify a hypothesis by identifying its practical consequences. This raises some

    questions. First: what, exactly is the content of this maxim? What sort of thing

    does it recognize as a practical consequence of some theory or claim? Second,what use does such a maxim have? Why do we need it? And third, what reason is

    there for thinking that the pragmatist maxim is correct? In this section, I shall

    examine Peirce's answers to some of these questions but, as we proceed, we shall

    also compare Peirce's answers to these questions with those offered by James.

    (See Hookway: 2012 passim)

    We can begin with Peirce's canonical statement of his maxim in How to Make

    our Ideas Clear.

    Consider what effects, which might conceivably have practical bearings, we

    conceive the object of our conception to have. Then, our conception of those

    effects is the whole of our conception of the object. (EP1: 132)

    William James cited this passage when introducing pragmatism in his 1906

    lectures, and Peirce repeated it in his writings from after 1900.

    For all his loyalty to it, Peirce acknowledged that this formulation was vague: it

    does not explain how we should understand practical consequences. We shall

    seek clarity by looking at one of Peirce's illustrative applications of his maxim,

    by noting some of his later reformulations, and by identifying the uses to which it

    was put in his writings.

    Peirce's first illustrative example (the simplest one possible (EP1: 132) urges

    that what we mean by calling something hardis that it will not be scratched by

    many other substances. I can use the concepthardin contexts when I am

    wondering what to do. Unless there are cases where something's being hard

    makes a difference to what we experience and what it is rational for us to do, the

    concept is empty. The principle has a verificationist character: our idea of

    anything isour idea of its sensible effects (EP1: 132) but the use of the phrase

    practical consequences suggests that these are to be understood as having

    implications for what we will or should do. This is clear from his later

    formulations, for example:

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    7/26

    The entire intellectual purport of any symbol consists in the total of all general

    modes of rational conduct which, conditionally upon all the possible different

    circumstances and desires, would ensue upon the acceptance of the symbol.

    (EP2: 346).

    We become clearer about the concept hard, for example, by identifying how

    there can be conceivable circumstances in which we have desires that would call

    for different patterns of action if some object were hard from those it would call

    for if the object were not hard. If I want to break a window by throwing

    something through it, then I need an object which is hard, not one which is soft.

    It is important that, as Peirce hints here, the consequences we are concerned with

    aregeneralones: we are to look for the laws that govern the behaviour of hard

    things and for laws that show how such modes of behaviour on the part of things

    can make a difference to what it is rational for us to do.

    James never worked out his understanding of practical consequences as fully as

    Peirce did, and he does not share Peirce's restriction of these consequences to

    those that affect intellectual purport or to general patterns of behaviour.

    Sometimes he writes as if the practical consequences of a proposition can simply

    be effects upon the believer: if religious belief makes me feel better, then that can

    contribute to the pragmatic clarification of God exists. It is connected to these

    differences that James looks upon Peirce's principle as a method formetaphysics:

    he hopes that the attempt to clarify metaphysical hypotheses will reveal that some

    propositions are empty or, more important, that, as in the squirrel example, someapparent disagreements are unreal.

    Peirce sees uses for his maxim which extend beyond those that James had in

    mind. He insisted that it was a logicalprinciple and it was defended as an

    important component of the method of science, his favoured method for carrying

    out inquiries. This is reflected in the applications of the maxim that we find in his

    writings. First, he used it to clarify hard concepts that had a role in scientific

    reasoning: concepts likeprobability, truth, and reality. We shall discuss his view

    of truth below. It also had a role in scientific testing. The pragmatist clarificationof a scientific hypothesis, for example, provides us with just the information we

    need for testing it empirically. Pragmatism, described by Peirce as a laboratory

    philosophy, shows us how we test theories by carrying out experiments

    (performing rational actions) in the expectation that if the hypothesis is not true,

    then the experiment will fail to have some predetermined sensible effect. In later

    work, Peirce insisted that the maxim revealed allthe information that was need

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    8/26

    for theory testing and evaluation (EP2: 226ff). The pragmatist clarification

    revealed all the information we would need for testing hypotheses and theories

    empirically.

    Peirce's description of his maxim as a logical principle is reflected in passages

    where he presents it as a development of a distinction that had been a staple of

    traditional logic texts, the distinction, familiar to readers of Descartes, between

    ideas that are clearand ideas that distinct(EP1: 126f). As Peirce described

    contemporary versions of this distinction, the highest grade of clarity,

    distinctness is obtained when we can analyze a concept (for example) into its

    elements by providing a verbal definition. Peirce complained that nothing new is

    ever learned by analyzing definitions, and we can learn from a definition only if

    we already have a really clear understanding of the defining terms. He announced

    that a higher grade of perspicuity was possible, one that supplemented the

    verbal definition with a detailed description of how the concept is employed in

    practice. This was provided by applying the pragmatist maxim.

    As well as treating the pragmatist maxim as part of a constructive account of the

    norms that govern inquiry, Peirce, like James, gave it a negative role. The maxim

    is used as a tool for criticism, demonstrating the emptiness of a priori

    ontological metaphysics. In section 3.1 we shall see how the pragmatic

    clarification of realitycould be used to undermine the flawed nominalistic

    conception of reality that led to the copy theory of truth, to Cartesian strategies

    in epistemology and the Kantian assumption that we can possess the concept of athing in itself. Such applications reflect Peirce's concern with logic: he uses the

    maxim to criticize concepts whose use can be an impediment to effective inquiry.

    A more vivid non-logical example of using the concept to undermine spurious

    metaphysical ideas was in showing that the Catholic understanding of

    transubstantiation was empty and incoherent (EP1: 131f). All we can mean

    by wineis something that has certain distinctive effects upon the senses, and to

    talk of something as having all the sensible characters of wine, yet being in

    reality blood, is senseless jargon.

    Why should the pragmatist maxim be accepted? Here another difference between

    James and Peirce emerges. James made no concerted attempt to show or prove

    that the principle of pragmatism was correct. In his lectures, he put it into

    practice, solving problems about squirrels, telling us the meaning of truth,

    explaining how we can understand propositions about human freedom or about

    religious matters. But in the end, inspired by these applications, we are

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    9/26

    encouraged to adopt the maxim and see how well things work out when we do

    so.

    Since Peirce presented the maxim as part of the method of science, as a logical

    or, perhaps better, methodological principle, he thought that it was important to

    argue for it. Indeed, after 1900, he devoted much of his energy to showing that

    the maxim could receive a mathematical proof. He used several strategies for

    this. In 1878, he relied upon the idea that beliefs are habits of action: when we

    form a belief, we acquire a disposition to act in some distinctive way. Applying

    the pragmatist maxim to the clarification of a proposition, he argued, involved

    describing the habits of action we would acquire if we believed it (EP1: 127f). In

    the lectures on pragmatism which he delivered at Harvard in 1903, he adopted a

    different strategy. He offered a detailed account of the cognitive activities we

    carried out when we used the method of science: these consisted in the three

    kinds of inference, inductive, deductive and abductive. His strategy then was to

    argue that the pragmatist clarifications brought to the surface all the information

    that was required for responsible abductive reasoning, and that our use of

    inductive and deductive arguments made no use of conceptual resources that

    could show that pragmatism was mistaken. (EP2: 225241; Hookway 2005)

    None of these arguments fully satisfied him, and the task of fine tuning these

    arguments and seeking for alternatives was his major philosophical concern of

    the last ten years of his life. Although he remained optimistic of success in this,

    he was never satisfied with his results.

    3. Pragmatist theories of truth

    These differences in motivation become clearest when we consider how both

    Peirce and James applied their pragmatist maxims to the clarification of the

    concept of truth. Peirce's account of truth is presented as a means to

    understanding a concept that was important for the method of

    science: reality(3.1); while James was ready to use his account to defend the

    pluralist view that there can be different kinds of truths (3.2).

    3.1 Peirce on truth and reality

    The final section of How to Make our Ideas Clear promises to approach the

    subject of logic by considering a fundamental logical conception,reality. It

    possesses a form of unreflective clarity: every child uses it with perfect

    confidence, never dreaming that he does not understand it. An abstract definition

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    10/26

    is also readily forthcoming: we may define the real as that whose characters are

    independent of what anybody may think them to be. But, he announces, we shall

    need to apply the pragmatic maxim if our idea of reality is to be perfectly clear.

    It is at this stage that the concept of truthenters the discussion: Peirce's strategy

    for clarifying the concept of reality is, first, to give an account of truth, and, then,to observe that the object represented in [a true proposition] is the real. So we

    have to turn to his remarks about truth to see how the kind of mind-independence

    captured in the abstract definition of reality is to be understood from a pragmatist

    perspective.

    Peirce's motivations are evident when he says that the ideas of truth and

    falsehood, in their full development, appertain exclusively to the scientific (in a

    later revision he altered this to experiential) method of settling opinion. This

    reflects a law which is evident from scientific experience: when different people

    use different methods to identify, for example, the velocity of light, we find that

    all tend to arrive at the same result:

    So with all scientific research. Different minds may set out with the most

    antagonistic views, but the progress of investigation carries them by a force

    outside of themselves to one and the same conclusion. This activity of thought by

    which we are carried, not where we wish, but to a foreordained goal, is like the

    operation of destiny. No modification of the point of view taken, no selection of

    other facts for study, no natural bent of mind even, can enable a man to escape

    the predestinate opinion. (EP1: 138)

    In the 1878 paper, his pragmatic clarification is quite tersely expressed:

    The opinion which is fated to be ultimately agreed to by all who investigate, is

    what we mean by the truth, and the object represented in this opinion is the real.

    That is the way I would explain reality. (EP1: 139)

    Peirce had presented this way of thinking about realityseven years earlier when

    he described it as the realist conception of reality (EP1:889). In doing this, he

    contrasts it with another nominalist conception of reality, which he thinks is

    flawed, but which many earlier philosophers had accepted. In a review of a new

    edition of the writings of Berkeleya philosopher who, according to Peirce, was

    in the grip of this misleading picturePeirce asks where the real is to be found,

    observing that there must be such a real because we find that our opinions (the

    only things of which we are immediately aware) are constrained. While

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    11/26

    acknowledging that there is nothing immediately present to us but thoughts, he

    continues:

    These thoughts, however, have been caused by sensations, and those sensations

    are constrained by something out of the mind. This thing out of the mind, which

    directly influences sensation, and through sensation thought, because it isout of

    the mind, is independent of how we think it, and is, in short, the real. (EP1: 88)

    We can then think of the real only as the cause of the (singular) sensations which,

    in turn, provide our sole evidence for beliefs about the external world, and this

    naturally leads to both nominalism about universals and skepticism about

    empirical knowledge. Peirce's pragmatist clarification of truth offers an

    alternative conceptualization of being constrained by reality. It is explained in

    terms of this fated agreement of convergence through the process of inquiry

    rather than in terms of an independent cause of our sensations. Although the

    nominalist theory is not clearly worked out here, it is clearly related to the

    intellectualist or copy theory of truth attacked by other pragmatists. It

    articulates a metaphysical picture that all pragmatists tried to combat. See (Misak

    2007, 69f) where Cheryl Misak emphasises that Peirce does not offer a

    traditional analysis of truth. Rather, he provides an account of some of the

    relations between the concepts of truth, belief, and inquiry, She describes this as

    a naturalistic understanding of truth, and calls it an anthropological account of

    how the concept is used.

    3.2 James on truth

    Claims about truth had a much more central role in James's work and he was

    even prepared to claim that pragmatism wasa theory of truth. And his writings

    on this topic rapidly became notorious. They are characteristically lively, offering

    contrasting formulations, engaging slogans, and intriguing claims which often

    seem to fly in the face of common sense. We can best summarize his view

    through his own words:

    The true is the name of whatever proves itself to be good in the way of belief,

    and good, too, for definite assignable reasons. (1907: 42)

    The true, to put it very briefly, is only the expedient in the way of our thinking,

    just as the right is only the expedient in the way of our behaving.Expedient in

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    12/26

    almost any fashion; and expedient in the long run and on the whole, of course.

    (1907: 106)

    Other formulations fill this out by giving a central role to experience:

    Ideas become true just in so far as they help us to get into satisfactory

    relations with other parts of our experience. (1907: 34)

    Any idea upon which we can ride ; any idea that will carry us prosperously

    from any one part of our experience to any other part, linking things

    satisfactorily, working securely, saving labor; is true for just so much, true in so

    far forth, true instrumentally. (1907: 34)

    This might be taken to suggest that beliefs are made true by the fact that they

    enable us to make accurate predictions of the future run of experience, but otherpassages suggest that the goodness of belief can take other forms. James

    assures us that it can contribute to the truth of a theological proposition that it has

    a value for concrete life (1907: 40); and this can occurbecause the idea of God

    possesses a majesty which can yield religious comfort to a most respectable

    class of minds (1907: 40). This suggests that a belief can be made true by the

    fact that holding it contributes to our happiness and fulfilment.

    The kind of passages just noted may lend support to Bertrand Russell's famous

    objection that James is committed to the truth of Santa Claus exists (Russell1949: 772). This is unfair; at best, James is committed to the claim that the

    happiness that belief in Santa Claus provides is truth-relevant. James could say

    that the belief was good for so much but it would only be wholly true if it did

    not clash with other vital benefits. It is easy to see that, unless it is somehow

    insulated from the broader effects of acting upon it, belief in Santa Claus could

    lead to a host of experiential surprises and disappointments.

    4. The pragmatist tradition

    So far, we have concentrated on the pragmatist maxim, the rule for clarifying

    ideas that, for both Peirce and James, was the core of pragmatism. When we

    think of pragmatism as a philosophical traditionrather than as a maxim or

    principle, we can identify a set of philosophical views and attitudes which are

    characteristic of pragmatism, and which can lead us to identify as pragmatists

    many philosophers who are somewhat sceptical about the maxim and its

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    13/26

    applications. Some of these views maybe closely related to the maxim and its

    defence, but we shall now explore them rather as distinctive characteristics of the

    pragmatist tradition. The first of the themes that we shall consider is

    epistemological, and it picks up on Hilary Putnam's claim that one mark of

    pragmatism is the combination of anti-skepticism and fallibilism.

    Like some other philosophers, the pragmatists saw themselves as providing a

    return to common sense and the facts of experience and, thus, as rejecting a

    flawed philosophical heritage which had distorted the work of earlier thinkers.

    The errors to be overcome include Cartesianism, Nominalism, and the copy

    theory of truth: these errors are all related.

    4.1 Skepticism and fallibilism

    The roots of the anti-sceptical strain can be found in an early paper of Peirce's,Some Consequences of Four Incapacities (EP1: 2830). He identifies

    Cartesianism as aphilosophical pathology that lost sight of the insights that

    were both fundamental to scholastic thought and also more suited than

    Cartesianism to the philosophical needs of his own time. The paper begins by

    identifying four characteristics of the sort of modern philosophy that is

    exemplified by Descartes' writings. In each case, Descartes self-consciously

    made a break with the scholastic tradition, and, in each case, the outlook that he

    rejected turns out to be the outlook of the successful sciences and to provide the

    perspective required for contemporary philosophy. The first, and most important,of these characteristics was the method of doubt: [Cartesianism] teaches that

    philosophy must begin with universal doubt. We are to try to doubt propositions

    and we should retain them only if they are absolutely certain and we are unable

    to doubt them. The test of certainty, as Peirce next points out, lies in the

    individual consciousness: trial through doubt is something that everyone must do

    for him or her self. And the examination of our beliefs is guided by reflection on

    hypothetical possibilities: we cannot trust our perceptual beliefs, for example,

    because we cannot rule out the possibility that they are produced by a dream or

    by wicked scientists manipulating our brains. (See Hookway 2012, chapters 2,3.)

    The initial pragmatist response to this strategy has several strands. It is a strategy

    that we cannot carry out effectively, and there is no reason to adopt it anyway.

    Peirce begins his response by claiming that any attempt to adopt the method of

    doubt will be an exercise in self-deception because we possess a variety of

    certainties which it does not occur to uscanbe questioned. What is produced

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    14/26

    will not be a real doubt and these beliefs will lurk in the background,

    influencing our reflection when we are supposed to be suspending judgment in

    them. Peirce urges that we should not pretend to doubt in philosophy what we

    do not doubt in our hearts. We should doubt propositions only if we have a real

    reason to do so. It is necessary to separate some different threads here.

    First, there is something unnatural about the Cartesian strategy. Inquiries

    normally occur within a context: we address particular issues, relying on a body

    of background certainties that it does not occur to us to question. The Cartesian

    suggestion that we should begin by trying to doubt everything appears to be an

    attempt to step outside this context, relying upon no beliefs that we have not

    ratified though reflective inquiry. Sometimes we may have to question some of

    our assumptions, but our practice is not to do so unless there is a positive reason

    for this. Second, the Cartesian strategy requires us to reflect upon each of our

    beliefs and ask what reason we have for holding itthe sceptical challenges are

    then used to question the adequacy of these reasons. This is at odds with our

    normal practice. Many of our familiar certainties are such that we cannot offer

    any concrete reason for believing them, certainly not one that is wholly

    convincing. We tend to treat our established beliefs as innocent until proved

    guilty. We need reasons for our beliefs when we propose to change them, or

    when they have been challenged. It is doubt that needs a reason, and we trust our

    everyday beliefs until given a positive reason for doubting them. The mere lack

    of a conclusive reason for belief does not itself provide us with a reason for

    doubt. The Cartesian strategy adopts an unorthodox, revisionary understanding

    of reason for beliefand reason for doubt.

    Descartes, of course, might have conceded this, but responded that the revision is

    required because, once we allow error to enter our corpus of beliefs, we may be

    unable to escape from its damaging effects. His was a time of controversy about

    how we should go about fixing our opinions, and he was sensitive to the number

    of false beliefs he had acquired from his teachers. The pragmatist response here

    is to question some of his assumptions about how we reason and form our

    beliefs. First, Descartes' picture is too individualist and to make singleindividuals absolute judges of truth is most pernicious:

    In sciences in which men come to agreement, when a theory has been broached,

    it is considered to be on probation until this agreement has been reached. After it

    is reached, the question of certainty becomes an idle one, because there will be

    no one left who doubts it. We individually cannot reasonably hope to attain the

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    15/26

    ultimate philosophy which we pursue; we can only seek it, therefore, for

    the communityof philosophers. (EP1: 29)

    Peirce also questions Descartes' understanding of reasoning, suggesting that he

    holds that we must rely on a single thread of inference that is no stronger than

    its weakest link:

    Philosophy ought to imitate the successful sciences in its methods, so far as to

    proceed only from tangible premises which can be subjected to careful scrutiny,

    and to trust rather to the multitude and variety of its arguments than to the

    conclusiveness of any one. Its reasoning should not form a chain which is no

    stronger than its weakest link, but a cable whose fibres may be ever so slender,

    provided they are sufficiently numerous and intimately connected. (EP1: 29)

    Where the Cartesian begins from the concern that unless we begin from premisesof which we can be absolutely certain we may never reach the truth, the

    pragmatist emphasises that, when we do go wrong, further discussion and

    investigation can hope to identify and eliminate errors. The possibility of error

    provides us with reason to be contrite fallibilists, aware that any of our opinions

    may, for all we know, require revision in the future, but it does not provide us

    with any reason for skepticism. The focus of epistemological inquiry should not

    be on showing how we can possess absolute certainty; instead, we need to

    understand how we can possess methods of inquiry that contribute to our making

    fallible progress. Inquiry is a community activity, and the method of science hasa self-correcting character. Such are the checks and balances that we can be

    confident in our cognitive activities.

    William James makes similar observations. In The Will to Believe, he reminds

    us that we have two cognitive desiderata: we want to obtain truth; and we want to

    avoid error (James 1897: 30). The harder we try to avoid error, the more likely it

    is that we will miss out on truths; and the more strenuous we are in searching for

    truths, the more likely we are to let in errors. The method of doubt may make

    sense in the special case where an enormous weight is given to avoiding error,even if that means loss of truth. Once we recognize that we are making a

    practical decision about the relative importance of two goods, the Cartesian

    strategy no longer appears to be the only rational one. What reason is there to

    give primary weight to reducing the risk of error?

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    16/26

    In his lectures on Pragmatism, James defends a kind of epistemic conservativism

    that accords with the idea that we do not needreasons for our beliefs when there

    are no challenges to them to be defeated. He describes how, in the normal case,

    we have an established body of views and opinions, and issues about what to

    believe arise when a new experience puts them under strain. We will accept anew opinion when it preserves the older stock of truths with a minimum of

    modification, stretching them just enough to make them admit the novelty, but

    conceiving that in ways as familiar as the case leaves possible. Thus a true idea

    marries old opinion to new fact so as ever to a show a minimum of jolt, a

    maximum of continuity. (1907: 345) Once again, our beliefs possess a kind of

    inertia: we need positive reasons to disturb them; but in order to preserve them,

    all that is required is that we have no reason to abandon them.

    James's remarks lead on to the views defended by Dewey in The Quest for

    Certainty. In developing his views about truth, James saw his antagonist as the

    rationalist or intellectualist. The rationalist seeks substantive a priori knowledge

    of the nature of truth or of reality, knowledge that is cut off from the exigencies

    of practice. The traditional distinction betweenknowledgeand opinionsuggested

    that opinion, the useful guide to conduct and practice, is second rate when

    compared with the secure certainties provided by the philosophers. Rational

    certainties are supposedly risk-free: untainted by the contingencies of experience,

    such knowledge is testament to our capacity to grasp the necessary structure of

    the world. The desire for certainty is part of a perspective that gives little weight

    to the needs of practice. For the rationalist, the operation of inquiry excludes any

    element of practical activity that enters into the construction of the object

    known. For the pragmatist, the needs of practice are allowed to contribute to the

    constitution of objects.

    4.2 Inquiry

    As has already been suggested, pragmatist accounts of the normative standards

    we should follow in arriving at beliefs about the world are cast in terms of how

    we can carry out inquiries in a disciplined, self-controlled way. They provide richaccounts of the capacities we must possess in order to inquire well and the rules,

    or guiding principles, that we should adopt. A canonical statement of this is

    found in Peirce's classic paper The Fixation of Belief. Inquiry is a struggle to

    replace doubt with settled belief and Peirce argues that the only method of

    inquiry that can make sense of the fact that we are disturbed by inconsistent

    beliefs and that we should reflect upon which methods are correctis the Method

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    17/26

    of Science. The method of science is an experimental method, and the

    application of the pragmatist maxim reveals how hypotheses can be subject to

    experimental test. A knower is an agent, who obtains empirical support for her

    beliefs by making experimental interventions in her surroundings and learning

    from the experiences that her actions elicit. Peirce's writings provide asophisticated and historically informed account of just how the method of science

    can work (see Levi 2012).

    Dewey's conception of inquiry, found in hisLogic: the Theory of Inquiryis richer

    and more radical (ED2: 16979). He sees inquiry as beginning with a problem;

    we are involved in an indeterminate situation. And inquiry aims for the

    controlled or directed transformation of an indeterminate situation into one that is

    so determinate in its constituent distinctions and relations as to convert the

    elements of the original situation into a unified whole. (ED2: 171) As John E

    Smith has put it, Peirce aimed at fixing belief, whereas Dewey aimed at

    fixing the situation. (1978:98) It is important here that it is the situation that

    is objectivelyindeterminate, and it is the situation that is transformed during the

    course of the inquiry; Dewey is rejecting the common assumptions that all that

    change are our beliefs about the situation, and that describing the situation as

    problematic or indeterminate is simply a way of saying that wedo not have a

    clear grasp of it. We begin in a situation where we don't know our way around,

    and inquiry comes to an end when we do. The pattern of inquiry that he

    describes is common to practical problem solving, common sense investigations

    of our surroundings, scientific inquiry, the information gathering of animals and

    so on. Dewey recognizes that when we first face a problem, our first task is to

    understand our problem through describing its elements and identifying their

    relations. Identifying a concrete question that we need to answer is a sign that we

    are already making progress. And the logical forms we use in the course of

    inquiry are understood as ideal instruments, tools that help us to transform things

    and resolve our problem. The continuities he finds between different kinds of

    inquiry is evidence of his naturalism and of his recognition that forms of

    scientific investigation can guide us in all areas of our lives. All the pragmatists,

    but most of all Dewey, challenge the sharp dichotomy that other philosophers

    draw between theoretical beliefs and practical deliberations. In some sense, all

    inquiry is practical, concerned with transforming and evaluating the features of

    the situations in which we find ourselves.

    Dewey's work developed these ideas about inquiry. Shared inquiry directed at

    resolving social and political problems or indeterminacies was central to his

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    18/26

    conception of the good life and to his account of the democractic ideal. Others,

    closer to Peirce than to Dewey, identify scientific inquiry as the model of

    democratic problem solving (see Bernstein 2010: chapter three, Talisse 2008,

    Misak 1999, Westbrook 1991.

    4.3 The pragmatist conception of experience

    As is evident from the pragmatist maxim, pragmatism is a form of empiricism.

    Our ability to think about external things and to steadily improve our

    understanding of them rests upon our experience. However, the pragmatists all

    adopted accounts of experience and perception that were radically different from

    the views of most earlier modern philosophers such as David Hume and

    Descartes (see, for example, Smith 1978: chapter three). The established view

    linked experience to what is sometimes called the given: we are the passive

    recipients of atomistic, determinate and singular sensory contents, the kinds of

    things that are sometimes called sense data. Experience provides the material for

    knowledge and conceptualization, but it does not itself have a content that is

    informed by concepts, practical needs, or anything else non-sensory. Our only

    contact with the external world is through receiving such experiences that, we

    suppose, are caused by external things; but since these sensory inputs are our

    only source of knowledge of the external world, we have no direct sensory

    awareness of external things. It is no surprise that this way of thinking about

    experience can easily lead to skepticism about the external world.

    In different ways, Peirce, James, and Dewey all argued that experience is far

    richer than the tradition had supposed, and that earlier philosophers were

    mistaken in their belief that we could identify experiences or sense data as

    separable constituents of cognition. We can begin with James's radical

    empiricism, of which he said that the establishment of the pragmatist theory of

    truth [was] a step of first-rate importance in making [it] prevail (1909: 6f). The

    connection with pragmatism is evident from the fundamental postulate of

    radical empiricism: the only things that shall be debatable among philosophers

    shall be things definable in terms drawn from experience. But this requires thatexperience be far richer than earlier philosophers had supposed. First, he

    announced that the relations between things, conjunctive as well as disjunctive,

    are just as much matters of direct experience, neither more nor less so, than the

    things themselves. And, second, he concludes that the parts of experience are

    held together from next to next by relations that are themselves parts of

    experience. The directly apprehended universe needs, in short, no extraneous

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    19/26

    trans-empirical connective support, but possesses in its own right a concatenated

    or continuous structure.

    This suggestion is echoed in Peirce's account of perception. He too emphasizes

    the continuous character of perceptual experience, and also adds that we directly

    perceive external things as external, as other, that we can perceive necessary

    connections between events, and that experience contains elements of generality.

    As with James, this is supported by a phenomenological account of our

    experience, and, again as with James, it is supported by a system of pragmatist

    metaphysics, a general account of the sorts of things and features that the

    universe contains.

    Dewey's account of experience contributes an additional twist. Like Peirce, he

    thought that experience was full of inference. Experience is a process through

    which we interact with our surroundings, obtaining information that helps us to

    meet our needs. What we experience is shaped by our habits of expectation and

    there is no basis for extracting from this complex process the kind of thin given

    beloved of sense datum theorists. We experience all sorts of objects, events and

    processes, and we should not follow philosophers who seek to impose a

    distinction between the thin uninterpreted data of experience and the inferential

    processes which lead us to interpret what we experience as books, people and so

    on. The dichotomy between the passive given of experience and the rich results

    of our active conceptualization is not supported by our experience. It is yet

    another of the philosophers distortions.

    4.4 Representations

    Having discussed pragmatist emphases upon the activity of inquiry and the

    richness of experience, we should turn to their views about the nature of thought.

    It has been common for philosophers to assume that the content of a thought,

    judgment, or other mental state is a kind of intrinsic property that it possesses.

    Perhaps it offers a picture or idea of some state of affairs, and we can identify

    this content simply by reflecting upon the thought itself. All pragmatists haverejected this idea, and all have held that the content of a thought or judgment is a

    matter of the role it fills in our activities of inquiry. The content of a thought or

    belief is to be explained by reference to what we do with it or how we interpret it.

    I shall illustrate this by considering three particular pragmatist views.

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    20/26

    First, all of the classic pragmatists identified beliefs and other mental states

    as habits. According to Peirce, our beliefs Guide our desires and shape our

    actions (EP1: 114). The content of a belief is not determined by its intrinsic

    phenomenal character; rather, it is determined by its role in determining our

    actions. This was reflected in Peirce's formulations of his pragmatist maxim. Inorder to be clear about the content of a concept or hypothesis, we must reflect

    upon its role in determining what we should do in the light of our desires and our

    background knowledge. In Robert Brandom's happy form of words, the

    philosopher makes explicit aspects of our practice that are implicit in our habits

    and dispositions. The role of tacit habits of reasoning and acting in fixing our

    beliefs and guiding our actions is a theme that recurs in the work of all of the

    pragmatists.

    The second illustration concerns a passage in which James defended his account

    of truth by urging that it was the concept used in successful science. He identified

    the traditional view that, for early scientists, the clearness, beauty and

    simplification provided by their theories led them to think that they had

    deciphered authentically the eternal thoughts of the Almighty. By contrast,

    contemporary scientists held that no theory is absolutely a transcript of reality,

    but that any of them may from some point of view be useful . A scientific

    theory was to be understood as an instrument: it is designed to achieve a

    purposeto facilitate action or increase understanding (James 1907: 33). For

    James and Dewey, this holds of all our concepts and theories: we treat them as

    instruments, as artefacts to be judged by how well they achieve their intended

    purpose. The content of a theory or concept is determined by what we should do

    with it.

    The third illustration comes from Peirce's general theory of signs, which offers an

    account of the contents of thoughts as well as of public signs and language.

    Peirce insisted that the sign-relation was triadic: a sign or thought is about some

    object because it is understood, in subsequent thought, as a sign of that object.

    The subsequent thought is its interpretant. In understanding or interpreting a

    sign, we will probably draw inferences from it, or undertake actions that arerational in the light of the sign and the other information we possess.

    Interpretation is generally a goal directed activity. In such cases, our action or the

    conclusion of our inference is the interpretant; interpretation is not primarily a

    matter of intellectual recognition of what a sign means. The theory is complex

    and I will not explore it further here, beyond emphasizing, once again, that the

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    21/26

    content of a thought is determined by the ways in which we can use it in

    inference and the planning of action.

    5. Other pragmatists

    It would be wrong to conclude that pragmatism was restricted to the United

    States or that the only important pragmatist thinkers were Peirce, James and

    Dewey. As is documented by Thayer, there were pragmatists in Oxford, in

    France and, especially, in Italy in the early years of the twentieth century (Thayer

    1968, part III, Baldwin 2003: 889). Moreover we can mention several other

    important American pragmatists, for example Josiah Royce. Commonly thought

    to be an idealist opponent of James and a critic of pragmatism, Royce

    increasingly came to be influenced by Peirce's work on signs and on the

    community of inquirers and was acknowledged as a fellow pragmatist by Peirce

    himself. C.I.Lewis, the teacher of Quine and of several generations of Harvard

    philosophers developed a philosophy that was a sort of pragmatist Kantianism.

    Murray Murphey has identified him as the last great pragmatist (Murphey

    2005). In books such asMind and the World Order(1929), he defended a

    pragmatist conception of the a priori, holding that our choices of laws of logic

    and systems of classification were to be determined by pragmatic criteria (Lewis

    1923, 1929; Murphey 2005: chapters four and five). Of comparable importance

    was George Herbert Mead (see Mead 1934). Close to Dewey, Mead contributed

    to the social sciences, developing pragmatist perspectives upon the relations

    between the self and the community.

    Dewey's longevity meant that pragmatism remained a philosophical force in the

    United States well into the twentieth century. The influx of philosophers from

    Europe in the late 1930s and early 1940slogical empiricists, members of the

    Frankfurt School, and othersled to Pragmatist ideas becoming marginalized in

    the mid-century by providing new and exciting ideas when the pragmatist

    tradition may have begun to grow stale. Even then it retained some force. The

    work of Frank Ramsey at Cambridge (Ramsey 1926) in the 1920s developed

    Peirce's views on statistical reasoning and on inquiry in ways that provided fertileresearch programmes through much of the century, for example in the work of

    Isaac Levi at Columbia (Levi 1999). As Russell Goodman has documented

    (2002), Wittgenstein's later thought acquired a pragmatist flavour though his

    reading of James's Varieties of Religious Experience(1902). And there was

    always a relatively small but lively group of scholars who strove to maintain the

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    22/26

    values of what was championed as a distinctive American philosophical tradition

    even when this tradition was largely ignored by the philosophical establishment.

    In the last few decades of the twentieth century, scholarly work on pragmatist

    philosophy increased in both quantity and quality, making possible an

    appreciation of the sophistication of the pragmatist philosophers and enabling

    readers to escape from the of familiar caricatures of the position. Lacking the

    space to discuss all aspects of these developments, I shall comment on just two or

    three leading philosophers who have allowed their reading of the pragmatists to

    shape their conception of philosophy (Misak (ed) 1999 passim; Haack 1993).

    Richard Rorty has described his philosophy as pragmatist on a number of

    occasions. Where Peirce and Deweyand even perhaps Jameswere engaged

    in working out systematic philosophical visions, Rorty treated pragmatism as

    something more negative. What pragmatists teach us about truth, he tells us, is

    that there is nothing very systematic or constructive to say about truth at all. In

    particular, this concept does not capture any systematic or metaphysical relation

    between our beliefs and utterances, on the one hand, and reality on the other. We

    can describe what we do with the word true: we use it to express our

    endorsement of beliefs and sentences, and sometimes we might find it useful to

    express our fallibility by saying that some of our beliefs may not be true. But,

    beyond talking about the rather trivial formal properties of the concept, there is

    nothing more to be said. He also uses what he describes as a pragmatist

    principle to show that the truth cannot be our aim when we inquire. Thisprinciple holds that we can only adopt something as an aim when we are able to

    recognize that it has been achieved: it must thus make a practical difference

    whether a proposition is true or not. And since we are fallible, we are never in a

    position to recognize that one of our beliefs is actually trueall we can

    recognize is that it meets standards of acceptance that are endorsed, for the time

    being, in our community (Rorty 1991a: chapter one; 2000; Davidson 2005: 7;

    Hookway 2007). The consequentialist character of pragmatist ideas is also

    reflected in his account of how we can criticize and revise our view of the world.

    We should be free to propose new vocabulariessystems of classification anddescription. We do not test these vocabularies by seeing whether they enable us

    to discover truthsor by showing that they can be read off the nature of reality.

    Instead, we evaluate them by seeing how they enable us to achieve our goals and

    formulate better and more satisfying goals (Rorty 1995).

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    23/26

    Hilary Putnam denies that he is a pragmatist because he does not think that a

    pragmatist account of truth can be sustained. Indeed, he shows little sympathy for

    the pragmatist maxim. However he has written extensively on James, Peirce, and

    Deweyoften in collaboration with Ruth Anna Putnamand he has provided

    insightful accounts of what is distinctive about pragmatism and about what canbe learned from it (See Putnam 1994a). He has identified four characteristics of

    pragmatism: the rejection of skepticism; the willingness to embrace fallibilism;

    the rejection of sharp dichotomies such as those between fact and value, thought

    and experience, mind and body, analytic and synthetic etc; and what he calls the

    primacy of practice (1994c). He appears to count as a pragmatist in the wider

    sense but not as a pragmatist in the narrow sense that requires acceptance of the

    pragmatist maxim. With the turn of the twenty first century, he has made

    ambitious claims for the prospects of a pragmatist epistemology. After surveying

    the apparent failures of the original enlightenment project, and attributing them tothe fact that enlightenment philosophers were unable to overcome the

    fundamental dichotomies mentioned above, he expresses the hope that the future

    might contain a pragmatist enlightenment (Putnam 2004: 89108). The rich

    understanding of experience and science offered by pragmatists may show how

    to find an objective basis for the evaluation and criticism of institutions and

    practices. He is particularly struck by the suggestion that pragmatist

    epistemology, by emphasizing the communal character of inquiry and the need to

    take account of the experiences and contributions of other inquirers, provides a

    basis for a defence of democratic values (1993: 1180202). This may be related

    to Rorty's suggestion that pragmatists insist upon the priority of democracy over

    philosophy (Rorty 1991b).

    Another symptom of a pragmatist revival is found in the work of Robert

    Brandom, in books such asMaking it Explicit, andArticulating

    Reasons.Brandom's philosophical interests are rather different from those of the

    classical pragmatists. Indeed, the classical pragmatists, of whom he is quite

    critical, do not evidently influence his work. It owes more to philosophers such

    as Wilfrid Sellars and Quine and his teacher Richard Rorty. His concerns are

    mostly with semantics and the philosophy of language, developing a version of

    inferential role semantics in order to construct accounts of our use of words like

    true and refers to which are liberated from the representationalist idea that

    the function of thought and language is to provide a transcript of reality. The

    connection to pragmatism is that his approach to language is focused upon what

    we dowith language, with our practices of making assertions and of challenging

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    24/26

    or evaluating the assertions of others. He joins the pragmatists in denying

    that truthis a substantial metaphysical property that can be possessed by some

    propositions and not by others, and in focusing upon how this kind of discourse

    has a role in our practices, upon how truth or reference makes a difference in

    practice.

    6. Conclusion

    During the last quarter of the twentieth century, more philosophers became ready

    to describe themselves as pragmatists, leading to new ways of articulating

    pragmatism and original ways in which philosophy can be shaped by pragmatist

    ideas. These new pragmatists include Huw Price (2013), Robert Brandom and

    Philip Kitcher. Their understanding of pragmatism is not always the same, but

    we shall describe some of the most important developments. (See Bacon 2012,

    chapters 6, 7).

    First, what features do we look for in deciding whether a philosopher is a

    pragmatist? Most pragmatists embrace a form of naturalism, employing a

    methodology which uses the method of science and is open to exploring the

    different kinds of methods that are employed in different sciences. Although they

    are ready to move away from the views of the classical pragmatists, they will

    often be exploiting particular examples of pragmatic clarifications from Peirce,

    James, and Dewey. A good example of this is provided by Cheryl Misak's use of

    what she calls Peirce's naturalist account of truth (Misak 2007: 69f). She insiststhat Peirce did not want to define pragmatism. Rather it is the heart of

    pragmatism that Peirce does not offer a transcendental account of truth or a

    philosophical analysis'. Rather than trying to identify the essence of truth, she

    claims, pragmatists try to describe the role of the concept in our practices. Thus

    Peirce's account of truth examines the relations between the concept of truth and

    notions such as belief, assertion, and inquiry. Her approach is thus naturalistic

    because it is a sort of anthropological investigation; and the result of the

    investigation is neither a necessary truth nor something that is established a

    priori.

    This adoption of pragmatism is accompanied by a rejection of a priori

    metaphysics and of intellectualist accounts of thought. Peirce grounds this on his

    pragmatic maxim, a logical rule that shows the emptiness of concepts which

    have no practical consequences. This rejection of a a priori metaphysics is shared

    with Price, Brandom and other philosophers who embrace new forms of

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    25/26

    pragmatism. In similar vein, Kitcher's On the Role of Correspondence Truth

    (2012: chapter 4) provides a clarification of truth which builds on William

    James's view that true propositions are ones that enable us to function well, that

    function successfully as instruments.

    We have examined pragmatism in the narrow sense (the pragmatist maxim as a

    rule for clarifying concepts and hypotheses) and pragmatism in a wider sense.

    The latter involves a range of approaches to problems in epistemology,

    metaphysics and many other areas of philosophy that tend to display a broad

    common pattern. When pragmatism began, in the work of Peirce and James,

    pragmatism in the narrow sense was most important; while more recent

    manifestations of pragmatism have tended to give most weight to pragmatism in

    the wider sense. Many recent pragmatists are doubtful that a defensible form of

    the maxim can be found. However the connections between the two are clear.

    The pragmatist maxim was first developed in the context of a fallibilist, broadly

    empiricist approach to the study of inquiry, and it is this approach to inquiry that

    is central to pragmatism in the wider sense.

    Brandom's influential views introduce some different ideas. He focuses on the

    normative regulation of our practices, especially the practices involved in

    reasoning and cognitive activities. Rather than being influenced by the classical

    pragmatists, Brandom's work shows the influence of his teacher Wilfrid Sellars

    and also his reading of Kant and some of the writings of Hegel. Rationality

    involves possessing the ability to recognize the force of reasons. The requiredconnection with agency is manifested in the ways in which reasoning and

    deliberation are active activities ; and we can take responsibility for how well we

    deliberate and reason. In works likeMaking it Explicit(1994) he develops a

    systematic system of normative pragmatics which examines the rules that should

    guide the exercise of linguistic practices. His defence of naturalism resembles the

    anthropological approach of Misak: we understand our concepts by showing how

    they are used in our practices. Brandom also emphasises the importance of the

    fact that we can adopt different vocabularies, adopting different ways of

    describing and reasoning in different contexts (seeBetween Saying and Doing:Towards an Analytic Pragmatism, 2010). This is reflected in Brandom's distinct

    kind of naturalism. As well as forging a vocabulary for evaluating our reasons

    and participating in communal reasoning and discussion, he explores how one

    vocabulary can be understood as grounded in others, for example in the

    vocabulary of fundamental science. This does not conflict with our using other

    vocabularies,for different purposes. He follows Rorty in rejecting the aspiration

  • 8/12/2019 PRAGMATISM - SEP.docx

    26/26

    to provide accurate representations of our surroundings. Ways of talking are not

    to be evaluated in terms of whether they accurately describe our surroundings;

    rather, they are evaluated by the by the virtues of the practices that are involved

    in our use of them.