114
^ ^ SOCIAL DARWINISM AND BRITISH IMPERIALISM, 1870-1900 by RAY HALL BYRD, B.A. A THESIS IN HISTORY Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Texas Tech University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for the Degree of MASTER OF ARTS Approved Accepted J D^ce/nbe^,/ 1971

Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

Embed Size (px)

Citation preview

Page 1: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

^ ^

SOCIAL DARWINISM AND BRITISH IMPERIALISM, 1870-1900

by

RAY HALL BYRD, B.A.

A THESIS

IN

HISTORY

Submitted to the Graduate Faculty of Texas Tech University in Partial Fulfillment of the Requirements for

the Degree of

MASTER OF ARTS

Approved

Accepted

J D^ce/nbe^,/ 1971

Page 2: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

T3 1971 No, 22 â CONTENTS

INTRODUCTION 1

I. THE BENTHAMITE INFLUENCE 3

II. HERBERT SPENCER 2 9

III. SOCIAL THEORY AND IMPERIALISM 65

CONCLUSION 102

BIBLIOGRAPHY 104

11

Page 3: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

INTRODUCTION

In discussing the ideological interrelationship between

Social Darwinism and British imperialistic thought during

the period 1870-1900, there is often presumed a close asso-

ciation based upon their common attribute, the "might is

right" principle. For example, after expounding on the domi-

nant "power politics" principle in late nineteenth century

Europe, C. J. H. Hayes writes in A Generation of Materi-

alism, "the timelessness of Darwinism . . . established

it . , . as the chief conditioning philosophy of Europe in

the 1870's." He expects the reader to see a logical asso-

ciation between Social Darwinism and the mainstream of

British imperialistic thought of the late nineteenth cen-

tury. This thesis seems to have some validity as one

studies the power politics of the two Conservative prime

ministers of the period, Disraeli and Salisbury. During

this period, England went to war to protect and strengthen

her Indian Empire. Furthermore England expanded into

Africa and subjected other people to her control. It would

indeed seem an easy matter to superimpose the prevalent

Darwinian theory as a justification of these actions. It

is this relationship that will be pursued in this study.

C. J. H. Hayes, A Generation of Materialism, 1871-1900 (New York, 1941), p. 12.

1

Page 4: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

and it will be surprisingly revealed that there existed an

animosity between the two doctrines, not the peaceful co-

existence that some writers would like to portray.

Darwinism arose in the mid-VictoriciJi age and was

quickly adapted to the prev.iiling social theory as expounded

by the Manchester School. The Manchester School supported

a laissez-faire philosophy in domestic and foreign affairs.

To the mid-Victorian mind struggle was associated with the

pseudo scientific and economic competition in England's in-

dustrial society. Thus Darwinism was interpreted as indi-

vidual Darwinism, that is, with the thesis that progress

was determined by the struggle between individuals in the

society. Obviously for the theory of Darwinism to evolve

from this framework to an imperialistic concept a gradual

change had to come about in the actual definition of Social

Darwinism. Collective Darwinism, the thesis that progress

was determined by the struggle between nations, took time

to develop in a mentality that had accepted individual

Darwinism. The process was complex, but interesting, and

deserving of more study than it has received.

Page 5: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

CHAPTER I

THE BENTHAMITE INFLUENCE

The antaqonism betwecn Social Darwinism and British

imperialistic dov^trine durinn the ninetcunth century can

be traced to their conflicting relationship with Benthamism.

Darwinism was greatly influenced by and was incorporated

into the Benthamite school, but it was the reaction against

Benthamite colonial theory that helped to create greater

interest in formal imperialism after 1870.

The founder of the Benthamite school was Jeremy Ben-

tham. Bentham propagandized the rationalism of the Enlighten-

ment and interwove the concepts of the classical economists

into this rationalistic framework. From rationalism he

postulated the individual as the ultimate reality. Man,

beginning only with himself, developed a unity of all knowl-

edge, and thus a verbal revelation from God was considered

nonsensical. For man's rationality to operate, the universe

was assumed to be a closed uniform system. Thus, the mir-

acles of Christianity were considered impossible because

they were not observable in the nineteenth century.

Politically Bentham's rationalism incorporated two

main axioms--"the greatest happiness of the greatest number"

Crane Brinton, English Political Thought in the Nineteenth Century (New York, 1962), pp. 15-24, originally published in 1933.

Page 6: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

2 principle and laissez-faire. Since each individual was the

best judge of his own happiness, his social responsibility

was to seek his egoistic interest. Because some individuals

wouid not seek happiness in a rational manner and thus di-

minish the happiness of the whole community, government

could intervene to protect society. The philosophical basis

for such intervention into individual rights was democracy;

government could identify with the interests of the commu-3

nity since the majority elected the representatives. This

"artificial identification" did not extend to the economic

sphere. Economically government was to adopt a policy of

laissez-faire; thus society could not assure to its members

"a just share in the product of the labor of society." Ac-

cording to the doctrines of the classical economists this

was "spontaneously provided for by the mechanism of competi-4

tion." The government's responsibility consisted only of

the removal of governmental restrictions that would inter-

. . 5 fere with economic competition.

2 D. C. Somervell, English Thought in the Nineteenth

Century (2nd ed.; London, 1929), pp. 42-45. Eli Halévy, The Growth of Philosophical Radicalism,

trans. by Mary Morris (London, 1928), p. 489; Frederick Copleston, A History of Philosophy (8 vols.; Westminister, Maryland, 1966) , VII, 13, 14.

Halévy, Philosophical Radicalism, p. 498.

Copleston, History of Philosophy, VII, 13.

Page 7: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

In the earlier Benthamite writings classical economics

was only part of a general philosophy, but in the process

of attacking the aristocratic structure of the eighteenth

century, Benthamite thought, although not the practice, v;as

set in the mold oí iaissez-faire. The formcr Westminister

School, which emphasized the artificial identification of

interests by the government, was replaced by the Manchester

School. The Manchester School emphasized the spontaneous

adjustment of interests and was very hostile to most legis-7

lation. In the minds of the ordinary mid-Victorian politi-

cians and the general public the works of the classical

economists became laws of nature that could not be broken

without disastrous repercussions.

It was one of these classical economists' works that

influenced Charles Darwin's development of the concept of

natural selection. This work was Thomas Robert Malthus'

Principle of Population (1798) which justified laissez-

faire with two postulates. First, population when unchecked

increased in a geometrical ratio, and second, the subsis-o

tence for man, food, increased in an arithmetical ratio.

Wilson H. Coates, "Benthamism, Laissez-Faire, and Collectivism," Journal of the History of Ideas, XI (1950), 358-363.

7 ' Halevy, Philosophical Radicalism, p. 514. o

Thomas Robert Malthus, An Essay on the Principle of Population, as it affects the future improvement of Society,

Page 8: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

If the population was not checked within the limits of the

food supply, then man would have to struggle against the

forces of nature and against those of the same species.

Concerning the latter struyyie Malthus revealed, "And when

they fell in with any tribes like their own, the contest

was a struggle for existence [italic mine]; [sic] and they

fought with a desperate courage, inspired by the reflection,

that death was the punishment of defeat, and life the prize

9 of victory." Politically he argued that laws attempting

to improve the general condition of the poor would only in-

crease their population without increasing their food sup-

ply; therefore legislation would only bring self-destruction

to the lower classes. Consequently, the best policy for the

government was laissez-faire and a minimum of social legis-

lation.

Darwin asserted that it was Malthus' thesis that influ-

enced him in his formulation of the doctrine of natural se-

lection:

In October 1838, that is, fifteen months after I had begun my systematic enquiry, I happened to read for amusement Malthus on Population, and be-ing well prepared to appreciate the struggle for existence which everywhere goes on from

with remarks on the speculations of Mr. Godwin, Mr. Cordorcet, and otJier writers (New York, 1965), p. 18.

^lbid., pp. 47-48.

•^^lbid., pp. 83-88.

Page 9: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

long-continued observation of the habits of ani-mals and plants, it at once struck me that under these circumstances favourable variations would tend to be preserved, and unfavourable ones to be destroyed. The result of this would be the formation of new species. Here, then, I had at last got a theory by which to work.H

Alfred Russel Wallace, Darwin's co-founder of natural selec-

tion, also claimed that he had been influenced by Malthus'

12 book. Both perhaps overrated the individual influence of

Malthus; it was perhaps more the intellectual and political

climate of the Benthamites, as manifested by Malthus, that

influenced their thoughts. Darwin was a Liberal, which was

the political expression of the Benthamite philosophy. He

professed great admiration for William Gladstone, the Lib-

eral leader in the late nineteenth century, and in The

Qrigin of Species (1859) he incorporated the utilitarian

philosophy of his time. He expressed the doctrine of ex-

treme laissez-faire in The Descent of Man (1871):

With savages, the weak in body or mind are soon eliminated; and those that survive commonly ex-hibit a vigorous state of health. We civilised

Charles Darwin, The Autobiography of Charles Darwin, 1809-1882, ed. by Nora Barlow (New York, 1959), p- 120; See Grant Allen, Charles Darwin; His Life and Work (New York, [n.d.]), pp. 29-30.

12 Alfred Russel Wallace, Alfred Russel Wallace; Letters

and Reminiscences, ed. by James Marchant (New York, 1916), ppT 91, 95, 260; Patrick Matthew in 1831 and Herbert Spencer in 1852 enunciated natural selection in the sphere of man. Both based their idea upon the Malthusian principle. Allen, Charles Darwin, pp. 36-37.

Page 10: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

8

men, on the other hand, do our utmost to check the process of elimination; we build asylums for the imbecile, the maimed, and the sick; we insti-tute poor-laws; and our medical men exert their utmost skill to save the life of every one to the last moment. There is reason to believe that vacination has preserved thousands, who from a weak constitution would formerly have succumbed to small-pox. Thus the weak members of civilised societies propagate their kind. No one who has attended to the breeding of domestic animals will doubt that this must be highly injurious to the race of man. It is surprising how soon a want of care, or care wrongly directed, leads to the de-generation of a domestic race; but excepting in the case of man himself, hardly anyone is so iq-norant as to allow his worst animals to breed.13

It must be pointed out that the Darwinian concept of laissez-

faire did not really represent the laissez-faire taught by

the Benthamites. For in the Darwinian system, as expressed

in The Origin of Species, competition was a constant strug-

gle for survival in which the fittest survived and the

weakest died, while in the Benthamite system the weakest

struggled, but he was not eliminated. The competition of

the ciassical economists and the Benthamites was an artifi-

cial competition, being hedged in by many legal restrictions.

In the Benthamite system there was always the assumption

that the government could intervene in the competition.

Besides identifying Darwinism with the economic strug-

gle for existence, Liberals also saw in Darwinism a

13 Charles Darwin, The Descent of Man and Selection in

Relation to Sex (New Yo Fk [1936] ) , p. 501, originally pub-lished in 1871, bound with The Origin of Species.

Page 11: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

verification of the doctrine of progress. Bentham assumed

the doctrine of progress, but he did not develop it. Evolu-

tionists seemed to have the philosophical basis for progress

in Darwin's system. Darwin expressed the doctrine of prog-

ress in The Origin of Species: "And as natural selection

works solely by and for the good of each being, all corporeal

and mental endowments will tend to progress towards perfec-

tion." Darwin also stated that the evolutionary process

was evolving toward the "greatest happiness" principle. It

has to be pointed out, though, that Darwin's writings con-

cerning the "greatest happiness" principle are very

nebulous.

Herbert Spencer, the evolutionary philosopher, made

progress in his system a necessity; the universe was a

machine, and thus progress was predetermined to be the des-

tiny of the universe.^'^ ^^^^ ^^ain, as with Darwin, Spencer

14 Walter E. Houghton, The Victorian Frame of Mind, 1830-

1870 (New Haven, 1957), pp. 36-38. 15 Charles Darwin, The Origin of Species, By Means of

Natural Selection or the Preservation of Favored Races in the Struggle for Life (6th ed.; New York [1936]), p. 373, originally published in 1859; See Darwin to Lyell, no date, in Beatrice Webb, My Apprenticeship (New York, 1926), p. 88.

Darwin, The Descent of Man, pp. 489-490; Jacques Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner; Critique of a Heritage (Garden City, 1958), p. 76, originally published in 1941.

17 J. B. Bury, The Idea of Progress, An nquiry into Its

Origin and Growth (London, 1920), p. 338. "

Page 12: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

10

postulated that the ultimate purpose of the evolutionary

process was the Benthamite doctrine of producing the great-

est amount of happiness for the greatest number of indi-

viduals.

Both Spencer and Darwin based progress primarily upon

intra-state struggle; thus both would be considered individ-

ual Darwinists. They developed Darwinism as a product of

the Manchester School, and as long as Darwinism was embedded

in this school, collective Darwinism, the doctrine that

progress was based upon inter-state struggle and the Dar^in-

ian theory that could have application to imperialistic

thought, could not be postulated. Darwin did, however, show

the potentiality for collective Darwinism by adopting some

of Walter Bagehot's concepts in The Descent of Man.

In Physics and Politics or Thoughts on the Application

of the Principles of "Natural Selection" and "Inheritance"

to Political Society (1867), Bagehot tried to incorporate

natural selection and Benthamite individualism into a two

step procedure for the formation of a nation. The first

step was the development of "a cake of custom." This gave

form to a nation by establishing its laws and morals, for

the "cake of custom" molded a group to believe basically in

the same concepts and revealed to each member his

18 Gertrude Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revo-

lution (Garden City, 1959), pp. 379-380.

Page 13: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

11 19 responsibility in the group. The group was emphasized;

obedience was demanded, because individuality would destroy

20 the group. This first stage of development unified the

group for the struggle of the survival of the fittest

against individuals and other groups. Thus military strength

was the criteria for progress, for it indicated intellectual

development and the degree of unification. The second

stage in the development of a nation was the evolving of a

democracy. In a democratic society individualism, which

was very important in Benthamite liberalism, could develop.^^

In The Descent of Man Darwin, in his effort to demon-

strate that there were no qualitative differences between

man and the animals, had to deal with the origin of morals.

In answering this question he adopted Bagehot's thesis,

2 3 thus creating the foundation of collective Darwinism.

19 Walter Bagehot, Physics and Politics or Thoughts on

the Application of the Principles of "Natural Selection" and "Inheritance" to Political Society (New York, 1 9 4 8 ) , p. 28, originally published in 1867.

^^ bid., pp. 29-30.

21 Ibid., pp. 52-86.

^^lbid., pp. 202-203.

^^Darwin, The Descent of Man, pp. 487-498, 500, 543; See Robert Clark, Darwin; Before and After, An Evangelical Assessment (Chicago, 1967) , pp. 102-103, originally pub-lished in 1966.

Page 14: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

12

Darwin speculated that the formation of morals and

laws, Bagehot's "cake of custom," resulted from the struggle

between nations. In the evolutionary process, there devel-

oped an instinct in the individual to transcend his per-

sonal interest and to be concerned with the general good of

24 the community. An mdividual who would submit his will

to the demands of the group would have a better chance of

survival than the total individualist. The nation that mani-

fested this social quality in the highest degree, that is,

the nation which subjected intra-state struggle to inter-

state struggle in the highest degree among the most members,

25 would be considered the strongest nation. By this state-

ment Darwin laid the foundation of collective Darwinism.

Together with Bagehot, Darwin seemed to believe, al-

though it is not clear, that collective Darwinism was appli-

cable primarily to uncivilized societies. This is speculated

from his doctrine of war. Darwin seriously considered war

as a natural process of progress, but Wallace convinced ? fi

him not to be dogmatic about this doctrine. Thus Darwin

stated only that a short war was beneficial, because it

^^C. Darwin to A. R. Wallace, May 28, 1864, in Wallace, Alfred Russel Wallace, p. 127; Arthur Keith, Darwin Re-valued (London, 1955), p. 260.

^^Darwin, The Descent of Man, p. 498.

^^A. R. Wallace to C. Darwin, May 24, 1865, and C. Darwin to A. R. Wallace, June 15, 1864, in Wallace, Alfred Russel Wallace, pp. 128-132.

Page 15: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

13

brought out the social and moral qualities of a nation,

while a long war would destroy the fittest in battle, and

27

the weakest, who remained at home, would survive. Thus

Darwin returned to inelividual Darwinism, where intra-state

struggle was more important thcin the inter-state struggle.

In The Descent of Man he stated, "With highly civilised

nations continued progress depends in a subordinate degree

on natural selection; for such nations do not supplant and 28 exterminate one another as do savage tribes." For within

these nations the state boundaries were recognized as super-

ficial, and in consequence the social instinct was extended

29

to all men and races. Thus there is a shallow representa-

tion of Benthamite cosmopolitanism. Natural selection

within highly civilized nations occurred primarily between

the individual members of the community and not between the 30 communities. But he also pointed out that there was

natural selection between civilized and uncivilized nations

and prophesied that the civilized nations would exterminate

31 and replace savage races.

27 Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner, p- 98.

2 8 Darwin, The Descent of Man, p. 509.

^^lbid., p. 492.

^°Ibid., p. 509.

^-^lbid. , p. 521.

Page 16: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

14

In The Descent of Man Darwin presented an equivocal

doctrine in which there were sections that defined the indi-

vidual Darwinian philosophy and sections that supported the

coliective Darwinian position, but the emphasis was on the

latter. In general, one would say that Darwin seemed to

devalue the individual by placing man's importance in a one

to one correspondence with his position in society. Francis

Galton, Darwin's cousin, pointed out, "The life of the indi-

vidual is treated as of absolutely no importance, while the

race is as everything; Nature being wholly careless of the

former except as a contributor to the maintenance and evolu-

32

tion or the latter." In order to maintain his own per-

sonal conviction in the primacy of intra-state struggle,

Darwin could only answer, "Nature does not more carefully

regard races than individuals, as . . . evidenced by the

multitude of races and species which have become extinct.

Would it not be truer to say that Nature cares only for the

superior individuals and then makes her new and better

races?"

32 Editor's note in Charles Darwin, More Letters of

Charles Darwin, A Record of His Work in a Series of Hitlierto Unpublished Letters, ed. by Francis Darwin (2 vols.; New York, 1903), II, 44.

33 C. Darwin to F. Galton, January 14, 1873, in Ibid,

II, 43-44.

Page 17: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

15

Darwin in The Descent of Man modified natural selec-

tion making possible the formulation of a collective Darwin-

ian doctrine. In fact, Galton developed a movement, the

eugenic movcment, which advocated state centralization and

state control of the institutions of marriage and family.

He urged that a record should be kept of the superior fam-

ilies in Engiand so that these families could be encouraged

to breed while the inferior families would be discouraged

34 from breeding. This movement, which could be called the

Darwinian counterpart of socialism, became a serious rival

to individual Darwinism once the weaknesses of the Man-

chester School was revealed. Both individual Darwinism and

eugenic Darwinism were social theories that were not thought

of as policies for international relationships.

The British imperialistic movement of the late nine-

teenth century could have incorporated collective Darwinism

as an international policy. But it was also an anti-

Manchester movement, because this imperialism was national-

istic, while Benthamite liberalism, theoretically, was

individualistic and cosmopolitan. State boundaries to the

Benthamites were superficial and did not have any real value

This concept encouraged a policy of free trade and, theoret-

ically, a complacency concerning the breaking up of the

• »

"^"^Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, pp. 402-403.

Page 18: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

16

colonial empire. It was thought inevitable that the col-

onies would become independent as demonstrated by the Amer-

35 ican colonies. The Manchester School re-enforced this

doctrme with the writings of the classical economists, who

championed laisse::-faire in forcign affairs as well as in

domestic affairs. From these writings, the Benthamites

argued that the colonies cost money and were unsafe for

military reasons. The colonies had to depend for defense

on England, without which they would be totally defenseless

and an easy prey for England's enemies.^^

Richard Cobden and John Bright, the chief political

leaders of the Manchester School, and Goldwin Smith, its

most brilliant literary exponent, expressed the Manchester

School's attitude toward the colonies. Cobden wrote Goldwin

Smith in 1836, "The colonies, army, navy, and church are

with the Corn Laws, merely accessories to our aristocratic

government. John Bull has his work cut out for the next 50

37 years to purge his house of these impurities." In 1842

35 C. A. Bodelsen, Studies in Mid-Victorian mperialism

(London, 1960), pp. 13-16, 81, originally published in 1924; William L. Strauss, Joseph Chamberlain and the Theory of Imperialism (Washington, D.C., 1942), p. Ti

James Anthony Froude, Short Studies on Great Subjects (4 vols.; London, 1890), II, 187-191; A. P. Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies, A Study in British Power (New York, 1959), p. 11.

37 Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian mperialism, p. 33.

Page 19: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

17

he wrote, "The colonial system, with all its dazzling ap-

peals to the passions of the people, can never be got rid

of except by the indirect process of Free Trade, which will

gradually and impcrceptibly loosen the bands which unite

our colonies to us by a mistaken notion of self-interest. "" ^

John Bright stated in the House of Commons, "We are talking

folly when we say that the Government of this country would

send either ships or men to make an effectual defense of

Canada against the power of the United States, . . . I do

not object to separation in the least; I believe it would

3 9 be better for us and better for them." Smith proclaimed

most emphatically that the colonies were of no earthly good

to England:

The time was when the universal prevalence of commercial monopoly made it well worth our while to hold colonies in dependence for the sake of commanding their trade. But that time is gone. Trade is everywhere free; and this expensive and perilous connexion has entirely survived its sole legitimate cause. It is time that we should recognise the change that has come over the world.^^

The colonies, he argued, only weakened England's position

in Europe because she had to stretch her military force in

bid.

39 Great Britain, Parliament, Hansard's Parliamentary

Debates, Series 3, CXCIX, 211; See James L. Sturgis, John Bright and the Empire (London, 1969), pp. 101-117.

Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian mperialism, pp. 53-54.

Page 20: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

18

the effort to defend them. In addition, this defense of

the colonies by England would not be strong, could not

stand against powerful enemies, and was expensive for

England. Evcn as a source of emigration the colonies were

useless since most of the emigration went to the United

States and not to the colonies. Besides, in the process of

emigration, the strongest and the fittest went while the

weak and the old remained in England; thus emigration only

41 dramed the best men from England.

In most of the arguments of the Benthamites, it was not

concluded that the colonies should be immediately emanci-

pated. On June 25, 1862, George Lewis, the Secretary of

State for War, stated a typical Benthamite argument concern-

ing the emancipation of the colonies:

I, for one, can only say that I look forward without apprehension--and, I may add, without regret--to the time when Canada might become an independent State; but I think it behoves England not to cast Canada loose, or send her adrift be-fore she has acquired sufficient strength to assert her own independence.'^^

The Benthamites believed that it was the motherly duty of

England to see that the colonies were guided until they

were ready for independence, arguing that if they were

abandoned too soon they would flounder; the colonies were

- lbid.

" 3 Hansard, CLXVIII, 860.

Page 21: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

19

believed to be predestined to a state of independence, and

it was the duty of England to prepare them for that moment.

This line of reasoning expressed the colonial concepts

ot V /illiam Gladstone, who was regarded as a disciple of the

Manchester School. Gladstone compared colonies to organisms

which grew according to laws "stronger than the will of man."

As they grew their natures became essentially different, as

did a man when he grew out of the chiidhood stage. When a

colony reached its analogous maturity stage, history has

shown that "in every instance" separation from the mother

country was brought about "by war and bloodshed, involving

an inheritance of pain, hatred and shame." It was England's

responsibility to see that the separation from her colonies

would not follow the pattern of history, but would be the

result of a peaceful and friendly transaction, in the manner

43 as a man would leave the household of his parents. Glad-

stone argued that the colonies should be prepared for inde-

pendence by encouraging the growth of self-government and

self-defense. Liberalism should be taught to the colonies,

and when the colonies accepted and adopted liberalism, they

should then legally be given independence without any obli-

gation to the mother country.' ' He also believed that this

" 3 Hansard, CC, 1900-1901.

^^Paul Knaplund, Gladstone and Britain's Imperial Pol-icy (Hamden, Connecticut, 1966), pp. 65, 90, originally published in 1927.

Page 22: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

20

policy would provide for the strongest empire, an empire

bonded by sentiment and voluntary action, but in the his-

torical context of his period, his policy was looked upon

as anti-imoerialistic; an empire bonded by a "union in

heart and character" was viewed as existentialiy no empire

at all.

It was the reaction to the Gladstonian concept of

empire that helped to initiate the imperialistic movement

of 1870 to 1900. In 1868, Gladstone formed the first Lib-

eral, as distinct from Whig, government. It was the first

government that could apply the Manchester creed to foreign

policy as it contained in its cabinet Lord Granville,

Colonial Secretary, John Bright, President of the Board of

Trade (the department next to the Colonial Office which

most frequently had to deal with colonial problems), and

Robert Lowe, Chancellor of the Exchequer (a department that

was extremely concerned with the expenditures of the col-

45 onies). They were all exponents of the Manchester School.

In his first ministry, Gladstone tried to apply the

Liberal creed. For example, the Cape of Good Hope received

responsible government, and Australia gained more control

45 R. L. Schuyler, "The Climax of Anti-Imperialism in

England," Political Science Quarterly, XXXVI (1921), 538-549.

Page 23: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

21

of her tariff. Particular attention was paid to Glad-

stone's colonial policy when troops were recalled from such

responsibly governed colonies as Canada and New Zealand.^^

The withdrawal trom New Zealrind occurred at a time when New

Zealand was being afflicted by a dangerous Maoris uprising

in the North Island. The colonial government requested

that some Imperial troops be retained until the Maoris

could be suppressed. The tone of Granville's refusal

strained relations between the two governments as Granville

implied that New Zealand's native problem was brought upon

4 8 her because of her own foolishness. Granville undiplo-

matically reported:

The present distress of the Colony arises mainly from two circumstances: the discontent of the Natives, consequent on the confiscation of their land, and neglect of successive Governments to place on foot a force sufficiently formidable to overawe that discontent. [The real safety of the colonists lay in] deliberately measuring their own resources, and, at whatever immediate sacri-fice, adjuring their policy to them.^^

46 Knaplund, Gladstone and Britain's mperial Policy,

p. 95. 47

bid., p. 125. 4 8 Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialism, p. 89.

49 J. R. M. Butler, "Imperial Questions in British

Politics, 1868-1880," in E. A. Benians, James Butler, C. E. Carrington, eds., The Empire-Commonwealth, 1870-1919, Vol. III of The Cambridge History of the British Empire (9 vols. in 8; Cambridge, 1929-59), pp. 24-25.

Page 24: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

22

The refusal of Granville aroused the English public and

50 press to come to the support of New Zealand.

Gladstone's policy of withdrawal faced a great deal of

criticism. The colonists felt acj()rieved, because their

business had suffered on account of the withdrawal and be-

cause the outward visible connection with the mother coun-

51 try had been withdrawn. Sir Charles Adderley proclaimed

in the House of Commons that the "withdrawal of the Imperial

troops from the colonies appeared to be one main subject of

52 dissatisfaction."

It was rumored that the government's actions in the

colonies, particularly in New Zealand, were examples of a

Gladstonian anti-imperialistic policy. The Spectator for

July 24, 1869 stated:

It is clear that Mr. Goldwin Smith's colonial 'policy,' the policy, that is, of shaking off the colonies as too burdensome . . . has not only been accepted by the existing Government, but that they are acting on it. It is not only New Zealand which is going to be dismissed, but Australia, not only Australia, but the Canadian Dominion, all that ring of Anglo-Saxon States which, with a little trouble, a little patience

Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian mperialism, p. 91

"''Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies, p. 24; Knaplund, Gladstone and Britain's Imperial PolicyT pp. 125-126.

^^3 Hansard, CLXXXV, 1190.

Page 25: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

23

. . . might be converted into a chain of faith-ful and most powerful allies.^-^

The reaction to the belief that the Gladstonian govern-

ment was anti-imperialistic brought the empire into sight

as a public issue. The reaction was manifcsted in many

ways. In 1870, a petition to the Queen was presented by

104,000 working men in London urging that emigration be

encouraged and colonial ties strengthened. The petition

stated that the petitioners had "heard with alarm that Your

Majesty has been advised to give up the colonies, contain-

ing millions of acres which might be employed profitably

both to the colonies and to ourselves as fields of emigra-

tion." James Anthony Froude, a historian who was one of

the main propagandists of the imperialistic movement,

entered the ranks of the imperialists because he believed

55 that the government was going to set the colonies adrift.

On April 12, 1870, he wrote, "Gladstone and Company delib-

erately intend to shake off the Colonies. They are pri-

vately using their command of the situation to make the

separation inevitable."

^^Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialism, p. 89.

^"^Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies, p. 45.

^^Froude, Short Studies, II, 182-183, 215.

^^Waldo Hilary Dunn, James Anthony Froude, A Biography (2 vols.; Oxford, 1961-3), I, 353.

Page 26: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

24

It is quite certain that in the opinion of Mr. Gladstone's Administration the colonies are rather 'elements of weakness to us than of strength, that they belong to themselves rather than to us, and that any endeavour on our }virt to develop their iesources or trans-port the overflow of our peopLe there wili be wasted effort and money thrown away.^^

Reaction to Gladstone's policies was also expressed in Par-«

liament. On February 14, 1870, Lord Carnarvon, a former

Conservative Secretary of State for the Colonies, expressed

in the House of Lords that he had confirmation of the rumor

that Gladstone's Government was pursuing an anti-

imperialistic policy, and he "beg[ged] to enter [his] humble

and earnest protest against [this] course which [he] con-

ceive[d] to be ruinous to the honour and fatal to the best 5 8 interests of the Empire." He stated that the Government

was following this course of action because of her Man-

^ ^ - - 59 chester presuppositions.

The reaction against the Gladstone Government reached

its climax in the Conservative victory in the general elec-

tion of 1874. Benjamin Disraeli, the Conservative party

leader, believed that adding the popular plank of maintain-

ing the integrity of the Empire to the Conservative plat-

form was an important factor in the Conservative victory.

^^lbid., I, 354.

^^3 Hansard, CXCIX, 212-213.

59

^^Schuyler, "The Climax of Anti-Imperialism in England," p. 560.

Page 27: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

25

At a Conservative banquet at the Crystal Palace on June 24,

1872, Disraeli claimed that one of the main objectives of

the Conservative party was the preservation of the Empire.

He proclaimed that self-govornment could be conceded, but

it had to be "accompanied by an Imperiai tariff, by securi-

ties for the people of England for the enjoyment of the un-

appropriated lands which belonged to the Sovereign as their

trustee, and by a military code which should have precisely

defined the means and the responsibilities by which the

colonies should be defended, and by which, if necessary,

this country should call for aid from the colonies them-

6 1 selves." This statement contradicted the policy of Glad-

stone. Gladstone was working toward an empire bonded only

by sentiment and voluntary action, where cooperation would

be spontaneously provided.

In the period, 1870-1894, Gladstonian Liberals tried

to maintain this position, a position that helped to stereo-

type Darwinism as a doctrine of the Manchester School.

Herbert Spencer, a great admirer and follower of Gladstone,

especially made Darwinism a stronghold for the Manchester

School, a stronghold that did not come tumbling down until

the forceful criticisms of Thomas Huxley, Benjamin Kidd,

and Karl Pearson towards the end of the century. The

61 Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialism, p. 121.

Page 28: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

26

downfall of the Manchester School was required before col-

lective Darwinism could be used to justify an imperialistic

policy.

Imperialistic thought itsc lf: had to bc changed before

collective Darwinism could be applied to it. The early im-

perialistic movement was to stop the supposedly anti-

imperialistic policy of Gladstone. It was not associated

with any political party, and it had nothing to do with

6 2

military strength, jingoism, or an aggressive policy.

But the political and economic climate was changing so that

Darwinism could be applied to an imperialistic philosophy.

The spirit of the time was rolling against the Liberalism

of Gladstone. This development was especially emphasized

by the Franco-Prussian War and the serious economic compe-

tition from Germany and the United States. The Franco-

Prussian War, which was fully reported in the British press,

seemed to falsify the Benthamite concept that progress was

from a military society to an industrial society. In six

months Prussia as a military state defeated France, the

nation which was thought to represent liberalism in Europe.

Also, this war demonstrated what war as an instrument of

policy could accomplish.^ J. L. Wilkinson declared that

^^lbid., p. 127.

• R. C. K. Ensor, England, 1870-1914 (Oxford, 1936), pp. 3, 102.

Page 29: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

27

Liberalism was responsible for the prevalent and mistaken

concept in England that the use of force was always wrong.

He insisted that war was a legal "form of political

64 action." This idea seemed to have some validity since

the balance of power in Europc that England had hoped to

65 mamtam vanished because of the German victory. The

Franco-Prussian War also seemed to symbolize the retrogres-

sion of liberalism in Europe. As a broad generalization

it can be stated that between 1815 and 1850 there had been

the growth of liberal and democratic movements in Europe,

but between 1851 and 1874 most of these movements were

6 6 stopped and reversed to an anti-liberal nature.

In addition, the new economic competition of Germany

and the United States in the 1870's was destructive to the

Manchester doctrines. These doctrines were framed during

the mid-Victorian period when England had a near monopoly

of industrial production and could afford to propagandize

free trade and an anti-empire policy. Competition from

67 Germany and the United States undermined these doctrines.

^^R. B. McDowell, British Conservatism, 1832-1914 (London, 1959), p. 95.

^^Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies, pp. 26-27.

^^David Thomson, England in the Nineteenth Century, 1815-1914 (Baltimore, 1950) , p. 29. ~"

^^Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialism, pp. 82-83.

Page 30: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

28

Froude stated in 1870 that the prophecy that England would

be the emporium of the world's trade and the workshop of

mankind was being falsified by foreign competition and that

Enaland maintained herself in this competition only because

shc had cheapened the quality and workmanship of her prod-

. 68 ucts.

The years that followed Gladstone's first ministry were

characterized by the suppression of the Manchester doctrines

and by the advocation of an aggressive and interventionist

foreign policy. But the adaptation of the Darwinian sys-

tem to this political situation was a slow and almost

tedious process. This seemed to be primarily because of the

influence of the evolutionary philosopher, Herbert Spencer.

68 Froude, Short Studies, II, 192-197.

Page 31: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

CHAPTER II

HERBERT SPENCER

Karl Pearson, A collective Darwinist, stated in 1900:

The older evolutionists overlooked several of the factors of the struggle for existence. They emphasized, in a way which now appears almost absurd, the struggle of individual with individ-ual. . . . Like the other political economists, they thought all real progress depended on an all-around fight within the community.l

Thus the earliest evolutionists were individual Darwinists.

Charles Darwin was an individual Darwinist; Thomas Huxley

and Alfred Russel Wallace were individual Darwinists until

the 1880*3. Herbert Spencer was also an individual Darwin-

ist. It was Spencer, a Gladstonian, who worked out most

systematically the social implications of individual Darwin-

ism and embedded them in the doctrines of the Manchester

School. In Spencer, the conflict between Darwinism and

imperialism continued to exist on account of their Man-

chester relationship.

Spencer's political philosophy was a manifestation of

the Benthamite spirit. The high point of Benthamite liber-

alism was around 1850, and until about 1880 the general

2 tendency was toward mdividualism. The optimism of the

Karl Pearson, National Life From the Standpoint of Science (2nd ed.; London, 1905), p. 55.

2 Ernest Barker, Political Thought in England, 1848 to

1914 (2nd ed.; New York, 1928) , p. 12. '

29

Page 32: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

30

Benthamites was the dominant trend, and it was the Man-

chester School that dominated the thoughts of Spencer.

Spencer in writing his political philosophy advanced the

doctrines of the Manchester School by basing them on the

evolutionary theory.

In Social Statics (1850) Spencer laid the foundation

for his political thought. In this work Spencer elaborated

on the fundamental belief of the Manchester School in the

benevolence of nature and the harmony of personal interests.

Whereas the Benthamites spoke of this law abstractly, Spencer

defined this law as natural selection, or, as he called it,

adaptaiiion. This law guaranteed that progress was "not an 3

accident but a necessity." In "Theory of Population,

Deduced from General Law of Animal Fertility" (1852) Spencer

expounded on the nature of this law that governed the whole

creative progress of the universe:

For as those prematurely carried off must, in the - average of cases, be those in whom the power of

self-preservation is the least, it unavoidably follows, that those left behind to continue the race must be those in whom the power of self-preservation is the greatest--must be the select of their generation. So that, whether the dangers to existence be of the kind produced by excess of fertility, or of any other kind, it is clear, that by the ceaseless exercise of the faculties needed to contend with them, and by the death of all men who fail to contend with them successfully, there

Ibid., pp. 81-82; Herbert Spencer, An Autobiography (2 vols.; London, 1904), II, 7.

Page 33: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

31

is ensured a constant progress towards a higher degree of skill, intelligence, and self-regulation--a better co-ordination of actions— a more complete life.4

Spencer defined moral conduct as that which contributed to

man's better adaptation and to his highest evolution, human

freedom being the highest stage and the ultimate purpose of

evolution. Since personal happiness was also the result of

a satisfactory adaptation, morality and happiness were essen-

tially one; thus the evolutionary process was toward the

production of the greatest happiness of the greatest number, 5

toward a perfect utilitarianism.

The function of the state in the development of prog-

ress was limited; government was considered "a necessary

evil." Its only function was to protect the citizens from

criminals and from foreign invasions. This police func-

tion barred the government from regulating industries,

giving poor relief, providing state education, and coloniz-

7 ing. Man's natural rights, the concept of which was the

core of Spencer's thought, were the ultimate reality and

4 . . . Himmelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, p.

216. " Ibid., pp. 379-380; Herbert Spencer, Social Statics; .

or, The Conditions Essential to Human Happiness Specified, and the First of Them Developed (2nd ed.; New York, 1881), pp. 11-26.

Spencer, Social Statics, p. 25.

^lbid., pp. 325-334, 341-406.

Page 34: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

32 p

could not be interfered with by the government. Although

these concepts were the products of the Manchester School,

what embedded the evolutionary theory into the Benthamite 9

stronghold was Spencer's synthetic philosophy.

After The Origin of Species brought the doctrine of

evolution to a scientific standard, Spencer wrote a syn-

thetic philosophy by applying the basic principles of

laissez-faire to all the sciences and portraying the unifi-

cation of all knowledge by vindicating evolution as a uni-

versal principle of thought. This work included First

Principles (1862) , a volume that dealt with metaphysics;

Principles of Biology (1864-1867), two volumes; Principles

of Psychology (1855), one volume; Principles of Sociology

(1876-1896), three volumes; and Principles of Ethics (1879-

1893), two volumes. This work gained Spencer the reputa-

tion of being "widely recognized as the representative

^lbid., pp. 477-481. Q

John Morley, Recollections (2 vols.; New York, 1917), I, 111-112; Earnest Belfort Box, Reminiscences and Reflex-ions of a Mid and Late Victorian (New York, 1967), p. 277, originally published in 1918; David Thomson, "Social and Political Thought," in F. H. Hinsley, ed., Material Progress and World Wide Problems, 1870-189 8, vol. XI of The New Cambridge Modern History (Cambridge, 1962), p. 105.

•^^Herbert Spencer, Life and Letters of Herbert Spencer, ed. by David Duncan (2 vols.; New York, 1908), II, 366.

Page 35: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

33

English philosopher, and above all as the representative

scientific philosopher."

In order to carry out this gigantic scheme Spencer

came into contact with some of Britain's most influential

men. He adopted a plan of publication by installments

issued to subscribers, who numbered about 440 in England

12 plus about 200 in America. Some of those who helped

Spencer in this effort were John Stuart Mill, Charles

Darwin, Thomas Henry Huxley, George Eliot, Charles Kings-

ley, Sir Charles Lyell, John Tyndall, Henry T. Buckle,

13 Alexander Bain, and J. A. Froude. At one point in this

scheme, Spencer did not receive the financial support to

continue. He decided to discontinue the project, but

friends persuaded him from taking this course of action.

John Stuart Mill wrote:

On arriving here last week, I found the December livraison of your Biology, and I need hardly say how much I regretted the denouncement in the paper annexed to it. What the case calls for, however, is not only regret, but remedy; and I think it is right that you should be indemnified by the readers and purchasers of the series for the loss you have incurred by it. I should be glad to contribute my part, and should like to know at how much you estimate the loss, and whether you will allow me to speak to friends

"Death of Mr. Herbert Spencer," The Times, December 9, 1903, p. 12.

12 Spencer, An Autobiography, II, 52-54.

•'•• lbid., II, 484.

Page 36: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

34

and obtain subscriptions for the remainder. My own impression is that sum ought to be raised among the original subscribers.-^^

With the help of Huxley, John Tyndall, and Sir John Lubbock,

Mill initiated an action that drew attention to Spencer's

work. Mill expressed the optimism that was felt toward

Spencer's doctrine. He believed that the universe tended

imperfectly toward the production of good and thought that

the ultimate reality was the individual, although he would

disagree with Spencer upon the role of the state in the

15 process.

This confidence in Spencer was also expressed by Thomas

Huxley and Charles Darwin. In 1877 Huxley wrote a eulogy

to Spencer's work in the ninth edition of the Encyclopaedia

Britannica:

Mr. Darwin confines himself to the discussion of the causes which have brought about the present condition of living matter, assuming such matter to have once come into existence. On the other hand, Mr. Spencer and Professor Haeckel have dealt with the whole problem of evolution. The profound and vigorous writings of Mr. Spencer embody the spirit of Descartes in the knowledge of our day, and may be regarded as the "Principes des Philosophie" of the 19th century.l6

•'•'Mill to Spencer, Feb. 4, 1866, Ibid. , II, 134.

15 H. Hoffding, "The Influence of the Conception of

Evolution on Modern Philosophy," in A. E. Seward, ed., Darwin and Modern Science (Cambridge, 1909), p. 450; Brinton, English Political Thought, pp. 90, 101.

1 f: Thomas Huxley, "Evolution: Evolution in Biology,"

Encyclopaedia Britannica, 9th ed., VIII, 656.

Page 37: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

35

Darwin wrote, "After reading any of [Spencer's] books, I

generally feel enthusiastic admiration for his transcendent

talents, and have often wondered whether in the distant

future he would rank with such great men as Descartes,

17 Leibnitz, etc." Darwin, Huxley, and Tyndall often quoted

18 Spencer as an authority. Spencer combined the doctrine

that dominated their minds, evolution, with their religion,

agnosticism, and created a unified system.

It must be pointed out that Darwin, Huxley, and Tyndall

were more concerned with the acceptance of the doctrine of

evolution by the English society than with the social impli-

cations of Darwinism in the manner of Spencer's synthetic

philosophy. This was a gigantic work which few men could

have done, and in addition, Spencer had a genius for dis-

covering general principles; he was a builder, while a man

of Huxley's caliber found truths more satisfactorily by the

means of demolishing other systems, than by constructing a

19 personal system. Sir Joseph Dalton Hooker, a famous

English botanist, pointed out, "I have been deeply impressed

with your [Spencer's] accurate and extensive information.

17 Darwin, Autobiography, pp. 108-109.

18 See Darwin, The Descent of Man, pp. 419, 447, 468,

478-481; Spencer, Herbert Spencer, I, 200; Spencer, An Auto-biography, II, 283.

19 Webb, My Apprenticeship, pp. 27-38.

Page 38: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

36

your vast power of acquiring knowledge, and the sagacity

with which you analyse and generalise the facts and ideas

which lie at the foundation of both Natural and Physical

20 Sciences," Later, Huxley came into direct confrontation

with Spencer's doctrine of state education, the result of

which caused Huxley to deny the liberal doctrine that evo-

lution is equivalent to progress, a rejection which was

based upon the premises of the Spencerian philosophy.

Herbert Spencer used his reputation and Darwinism to

combat British imperialism during the years 1874-1900. His

basic anti-imperialistic concepts resulted primarily from

the action of the Disraeli administration of 1874-1880.

Some British expansion during this period resulted from the

pressure of events rather than from an imperialistic ide-

ology. For examples, Fiji asked to be annexed, and the

Gold Coast became a crown colony, following a war begun by

21 the Gladstone government of 1868-1874. But there was

also expansion because of the desire to strengthen the

Indian Empire. Imperialistic thought until Joseph Chamber-

lain was basically directed toward the Indian Empire, and

it was over this aspect of imperial policy that strife

20 Duncan, Herbert Spencer, I, 117.

Richard Faber, The Vision and the Need; Late Victo-rian Imperialist Aims (London, 1966) , p. 53*1

Page 39: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

37

arose between the Conservative position and the Gladstonian

position which Spencer advocated.

India was a valuable exporter and importer, taking

about 19 percent of all British exports in the 1880's.

In addition, India was central to British trade with other

parts of Asia. India also provided a power structure in

Asia, and the Indian army could be used as diplomatic per-

suasion, or, as a last resort, as a crushing force against

Asiatic rulers who threatened to eliminate British influ-

22 ence and trade.

It was thought in some British political circles that

Britain's strength depended upon the possession of India

and that England's position in the world depended foremost

upon safe communication between the two. This idea was

held most sacred by Disraeli. In the Crystal Palace speech

he had advocated a stronger organization among the colonies.

However, Disraeli was not very interested in purely colonial

23 questions; he was more interested in power politics. He

had realized that the colonies would be of supreme value

in the future as a demonstration of power, but more impor-

tant to the English power structure, he thought, was India:

22 John Gallagher, Ronald Robmson, and Alice Denny,

Africa and the Victorians: The Climax of Imperialism in the Dark Continent (New York, 1961), pp. 11-12.

^"^Butler, "Imperial Question in British Politics, 1868-1880," CHBE, III, 41-43.

Page 40: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

38

"Power and influence we should exercise in Asia; conse-

quently in Eastern Europe, consequently also in Western

..24 Europe.

The influence of the Indian Empire upon Disraeli's

25 foreign policy was great. Cyprus was occupied as "the

2 6 key of Western Asia." The purchase of shares in the

Suez Canal in 1875 was from the "desire to maintain a free

27 passage to the East." In 1877 England obtained dual con-

trol with France over Egypt's finances, for the Suez Canal

was a second lifeline to India in the Mediterranean Sea.

The Transvaal was annexed so that a master link of connec-

tion between England and India around Africa could be ob-

4. • ^ 2 8 tained.

This interest of Disraeli in the Indian Empire was not

held by Gladstone. He stated:

I hoid, firmly and unconditionally . . . that we have no interest in India, except the wellbe-ing of India itself, and what that wellbeing will bring with it in the way of consequence. If, in a certain sense and through indirect channels, India is politically tributary to England, the

^^lbid., p. 41.

2 5 . . F. J. C. Hearnshaw, "Benjamin Disraeli, Earl of

Beaconfield," in Fossey John Cobb Hearnshaw, ed., The Political Principles of Some Notable Prime Ministers of the Nineteenth Century (London, 1926), pp. 202-203.

3 Hansard, CCXXVII, 43.

'Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, p. 83.

27.

^^Gallagher, Africa and the Victoifians, p. 16.

Page 41: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

39

tribute is one utterly insignificant: it is probably not near a hundredth part of the sheer annual profits of the nation, nor near a fourth of the unforced gains of our commercial inter-course with that country. India does not add to, but takes from, our railitary strength. The root and pitch and substance of the material greatness of our nation lies within the compass of these islands; and is, except in trifling particulars, independent of all and every sort of political dominion beyond them.29

In addition, Gladstone thought that the main line of commu-

nication with India was the South African route, stating

that the route through the Mediterranean Sea was unimpor-

tant as it only shortened military communication by three

weeks. Gladstone proclaimed that he had no concern if the

Suez Canal was closed to Britain or if Russia exerted an

30 mfluence in Constantinople.

Russia was the nation which most directly threatened

British influence in India and Asia. Thus, one of Disraeli's

central foreign policies was to keep Russia out of Constan-

tinople and the communication link with India through the

Mediterranean Sea open. Maintaining the integrity of the

Turkish Empire made constant demands on Disraeli's ability,

especially during the years 1876-1878. It was during these

29 William Gladstone, "Aggression on Egypt and Freedom

in the East," Nineteenth Century, II (1877), 153.

^°Ibid., pp. 155-157.

Page 42: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

40

years that the tension between the attitudes of Disraeli

and Gladstone was dramatically expressed.

In 1876 the Christian population of Bosnia and

Herzegovina rebelled against the injustices of the Turkish

government. Russia, being regarded as the special protec-

tor of the Christians of the Balkans, in union with Germany

and Austria drew up in May, 1876, the Berlin Memorandum

demanding a series of reparations and reforms from the Turk-

ish government. If these reparations and reforms were not

carried out within two months, the memorandum provided for

joint military force to be applied. France and Italy agreed

to the memorandum, but England refused. Disraeli desired to

break with the Manchester School's policy of nonintervention

in the affairs of other countries. He also desired to have

a voice in the creation of any doctrine that was to dictate

terms to Turkey, and the British government had not been

31 consulted about the Berlin Memorandum. As a warning to

Russia, Disraeli ordered a squadron to Besika Bay near the

32 Dardanelles. In June the Berlm Memorandum was withdrawn.

31 D. C. Somervell, Disraeli and Gladstone: A Duo-

Biographical Sketch (New York, 1926), p. 193; Erick Eyck, Gladstone, trans. by Bernard Miall (London, 1966), p. 254, originally published in 1938.

32 R. T. Shannon, Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation

(London, 1963), pp. 20-31.

Page 43: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

41

In May, 1876, following Disraeli's rejection of the

Berlin Memorandum, some Bulgarian nationalists attempted an

insurrection against the Turks. Moslem irregulars were set

loose upon the defenseless Christian population, and about

fifteen thousand Bulgarians were massacred; over seventy

villages, two hundred schools, and ten monasteries were

destroyed. These atrocities aroused emotional responses

within the British public and ignited the wrath of Glad-

stone in the defense of the Christian Bulgarians. In Sep-

tember, 1876, Gladstone published the famous pamphlet The

Bulgarian Horrors and the Question of the East which sold

forty thousand copies in four days and by the end of the

33 . .

month 200,000 copies. Appealing to the British religious

conscience, the pamphlet was a violent attack upon the

Turkish administration and upon the pro-Turkish sentiment

of the Disraeli government. The Turkish atrocities were

referred to as the "basest and blackest outrages upon record

within the present century, if not within the memory of

man," and the Turkish race was referred to as "the one 34 great anti-human speciman of humanity." He also stated

3 3 Ibid., p. 22; Paul Knaplund, Gladstone's Foreign

Policy (Hamden, Connecticut, 1970), pp. 70-71, originally published in 1935.

John Morley, The Life of William Ewart Gladstone (3 vols.; London, 1903), II, 553.

Page 44: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

42

that Disraeli had condoned outrages so evil "that it passes

the power of heart to conceive or of tongue and pen ade-

quately to describe them." In conclusion, Gladstone ap-

pealed for a free and independent Bulgaria."^^

At first Disraeli tried to discount the Bulgarian hor-

rors, stating that "when we are thoroughly informed of what

has occurred it will be found that the [prevailing] state-

3 6 ments are scarcely warranted." When he had verification

of the Bulgarian incident, he continued to advocate a pro-

Turkish policy. In his last speech in the House of Commons

before he took his seat in the House of Lords as Earl of

Beaconsfield, Disraeli stated:

I am sure that as long as England is ruled by English Parties who understand the principles on which our Empire is founded, and who are re-solved to maintain that Empire, our influence in that part of the world [Turkeyj can never be looked upon with indifference. . . . There is nothing to justify us in talking in such a vein of Turkey, as has, and is being at this moment entertained. . . . What our duty is at this critical moment is to maintain the Empire of England.37

In other words, Disraeli was saying that the proper response

toward the Turkish atrocities should be based upon the ques-

tion, "What is the best way to protect the Indian Empire?"

35 Philip Magnus, Gladstone, A Biography (New York, 1954), p. 242.

36 3 Hansard, CCXXX, 1181.

^^lbid., CCXXXI, 1146.

Page 45: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

43

Gladstonian religious sentiment had its place but not in

international politics.

Disraeli's attitude provoked an outbreak of protest

meetings throughout Great Britain in 1876. Charles Darwin

and Herbert Spencer participated actively in these demon-

3 8 strations. In an open-air meeting held on September 9,

Gladstone called upon the Russians to drive the Turks out

of Bulgaria:

I, for one, for the purposes of justice, am ready as an individual to give the right hand of friendship to Russia when her objects are just and righteous, and to say, in the name of God, "Go on and prosper!"39

In April, 1877, Russia declared war on Turkey and

started an all-out drive on Constantinople. In August,

1877, Spencer became a member of a committee to organize a

40 Russian Sick and Wounded Fund. In May Gladstone intro-

duced in the House of Commons resolutions expressing strong

disapproval of the Turkish government and proposing that

41 Great Britain refuse to give Turkey any support. Although

Gladstone's resoiutions were defeated, they were one of the

3 8 Shannon, Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation, pp.

174-175, 203, 204, 206, 212. 39 Magnus, Gladstone, p. 24 3. Shannon, Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation, pp.

174-175.

'•'•3 Hansard, CCXXXIV, 367, 404-439.

Page 46: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

44

factors which were responsible for the neutrality of England

42 during the Russo-Turkish War. On June 17, 1877 Spencer

wrote to Gladstone thanking him for saving England from a

"disastrous and disgraceful" condition which a war on behalf

of the Turkish government would have bestowed upon England.

Spencer stated that Gladstone had done this service to

43 England by his effort to arouse public opinion.

Russia won the war, and on March 3, 1878, a very pro-

Russian treaty was signed. The Treaty of San Stefano pro-

vided for a large independent Bulgaria. It also stipulated

that Russia would draw up a Bulgarian constitution and have

44 . . .

a temporary occupation of Bulgaria. The Disraeli admmis-

tration refused to accept the Treaty of San Stefano, since

it was believed that Russia would be influential in Bulgaria

and thus become a menace to British power in the Mediterra-

nean and become dangerous to the Indian Empire. At the end

of May, Disraeli sent 7,000 Indian troops to Malta, assert-

ing that since war with Russia might result in the effort to

defend India, it was the right and duty of India to support

Morley, Gladstone, II, 569.

^^Shannon, Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation, p. 212.

" F. H. Hinsley, "International Rivalry in the Colonial Sphere, 1869-1885," CHBE, III, 97-98.

Page 47: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

45

militarily this imperial policy. Russia submitted the

Treaty of San Stefano to the Congress of Berlin, which met

on June 13, 187 8. At the meeting Disraeli was one of the

central personalities. He succeeded in dividing Bulgaria

into two sections. The northern section was to have "polit-

ical autonomy"; the southern section was to remain Turkish.

Disraeli hoped that this separation would guard against a

Russianized Bulgaria capable of exerting major influence

m , 46 upon Turkey.

Gladstone was in basic agreement with the Congress of

Berlin because it resulted in approximately eleven million

people, formerly under Turkish rule, receiving self-

47 government. Although he thought that the Congress of

Berlin and the Russo-Turkish War could have been prevented

if the Conservative Government had accepted the Berlin Memo-

randum, his main criticism was directed against the secret

negotiation before the Congress of Berlin between Disraeli

and Turkey. By this convention England acquired Cyprus as

a base from which she promised to defend Turkish Asia

45 George Earle Buckle and W. F. Monypenny, The Life of

Benjamin Disraeli, Earl of Beaconsfield (6 vols.; New York, 1910-1920), VI, 287-288.

4 fi

Ibid., p. 362; Somervell, Disraeli and Gladstone, p. 204.

47 Morley, Gladstone, II, 576.

Page 48: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

46

48 against Russian aggression. Gladstone stated that no

"despotic power would have dared to do what Beaconsfield

had done." Disraeli had overly committed Britain to Turkey

without parliament's consent or knowledge. The agreement

was an "insane covenant" and its secret negotiation was an

"act of duplicity.""*^

In the Midlothian campaign of 1879, which Paul Knap-

iund called the "most famous political campaign in English

history," Gladstone made the Bulgarian atrocities an issue

in his crusade against "Beaconsfieldism." He attacked

the Indian policy of Disraeli and denounced Conservative

intervention in Cyprus, Egypt, the Transvaal, and

Afghanistan as "gratuitous, dangerous, ambiguous, imprac-

51 ticable and impossible." Gladstone stated that the Man-

chester policy of non-intervention should be adopted, not

the Conservative policy of centralized control and imperi-

52 alism. The appeal to Christianity and the moral

4 8 Magnus, Gladstone, p. 254.

Buckle, Disraeli, VI, 355.

^^Shannon, Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation, p. 272; Knaplund, Gladstone's Foreign Policy, p. 72.

^•^Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, p. 92.

^^Knaplund, Gladstone and Britain's Imperial Policy, p. 145.

Page 49: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

47

conscience contributed to the overwhelming Liberal victory

53 in the general election of 1880.

After Gladstone became prime minister, England with-

drew from the Transvaal and partly from Afghanistan. It

also considered returning Cyprus to the Turkish government.

Gladstone completely undermined Disraeli's influence and

54 power in Turkey. He demonstrated his belief that England

could not rule by the sword, but only by free partnership.

It was in this political atmosphere that Spencer wrote

his Principles of Sociology in which he contrasted the Con-

servative party, with its policy of militarism, and the

Liberal party, with its policy of industrialism and con-

55 tract. Motivated by dissatisfaction with Disraeli's

Indian policy, Spencer had already joined in 1881 an "Anti-

Aggression League," a group that he and Gladstone thought

56

coincided with the program of the Liberal party. The or-

ganization was a complete failure, but Spencer's writings

which were his main influence in anti-imperialistic propa-

ganda remained. In Principles of Sociology, Spencer stated

5 3 Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, p. 92.

^"^Buckle, Disraeli, VI, 366.

^ Herbert Spencer, The Man Versus the State (Garden City, 1940), p. 20, originally published in 1884.

^^Spencer, Herbert Spencer, I, 297-298.

Page 50: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

48

that progress evolved from the militant state to an indus-

trial state. The militant state was the condition where

centralization and militarism submerged the individual, and

the state was more important than the individual. All mem-

bers of the militant state had to be either warriors or

those that supplied the needs of warriors; all other occu-

pations were held in contempt. Since inter-state struggle

interfered with intra-state struggle, individuality was sup-

57 pressed. In the industrial state there was a condition

of semi-anarchy; the will of the citizen was supreme, and

the governing agency existed merely to carry out the citi-

5 8 zen's will. In the industrial state, the government was

bounded within the limits set forth by the classical econo-

mists: the defense of life and property against foreign

59 enemies and internal aggressors. In the ultimate stage

of the industrial state, the division of labor that charac-

terized industry would be completed; each person would have

a personal duty that would characterize him as an individu-

alist. All men, as ends in themselves, would be knit to-

gether by the rules of industry and laissez-faire. There

57 Herbert Spencer, The Principles of Sociology (2nd

ed.; 3 vols.; New York, 1898), II, 570-571; III, 367, 594-595.

^^lbid., II, 607.

^^lbid., II, 656.

Page 51: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

49

would be no war. There would be no state boundaries, for

there would be no governments. It would be the ultimate

stage of Benthamite cosmopolitanism. This ultimate stage

would come about by adaptation. As the stars, the sun, and

the earth evolved out of chaos to compose a unifying and

closely knit system, the members in the state would do the

same. Those that could not adapt to this system would be

eliminated, while those remaining would adapt to this per-

fection. As the stars, the sun, and the earth in the

rationalistic system have no central point of control, the

state would not have a need of a centralized government. "'

Thus this state would be a complete anarchy. The eternal

stage was the objective of the evolution of the state; thus

an imperialistic policy was very low in the evolutionary

scale.

Spencer continued to express anti-imperialistic con-

cepts in his last book, Facts and Comments, which was

stirred by the Boer War of 1899. Some time before the out-

break of hostilities in South Africa, he had denounced the

imperialistic policy of Salisbury's Government. When the

war broke out, it aroused a greater emotional response from

Spencer, An Autobiography, II, 329-330, 375-378; Barker, Political Thought in England, p. 100.

61 Robert MacKintosh, From Comte to Benjamin Kidd, The

Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Human Guidance (London, 1899), pp. 93-94.

Page 52: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

50

Spencer than any other political event; often he remorse-

62 fully said, "I am ashamed of my country." In a private

conversation he expressed a very deep pessimism toward

England:

Heading straight towards military despotism: the people will get what they deserve. I remem-ber being angry many years ago with an Irishman for saying that the English were a stupid race. I should not be angry now, I should only add that they are brutal as well as stupid.o3

In Facts and Comments, Spencer wrote, "The coincidence in

time between the South African war and the recent outburst

of Imperialism, illustrates the general truth that militancy

and Imperialism are closely allied—are, in fact, different

64 manifestations of the same local condition." This condi-

tion, argued Spencer, would cause individuals to be serfs

to the state, because they would work to pay the taxation

for the army and the navy. Paying these taxes would be the

primary function of the individuals in the state.

Spencer placed partial responsibility for the Boer War

on the Liberal party, for Rosebery's Government of 1894-

1895 had rejected the Manchester doctrines and had adopted

62 Duncan, Herbert Spencer, II, 190.

^"^Beatrice Webb, Our Partnership, ed. by Barbara Drake and Margaret I.Cole (New York, 1948), p. 197.

^^Herbert Spencer, Facts and Comments (New York, 1902), p. 159.

^^lbid., p. 169.

Page 53: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

51

the policy of imperialism. Thus the dominant thought in

both the Conservative and the Liberal parties from the end

of 1893 to 1900 was imperialism.^^ Archibald Philip Prim-

rose, 5th Earl of Rosebery, believing that the Empire was

a necessity of international power, was a radical imperi-6 7

alist. In 1893, he proclaimed that it was "part of

[England's] responsibility and heritage to take care that

the world as far as it can be moulded should receive the 6 8

Anglo-Saxon, and not another character." In 1895, Rose-

bery defined Liberal imperialism as "first, the maintenance

of the Empire; secondly, the opening of new spaces for our

surplus population; thirdly, the suppression of the slave

trade; fourthly, the development of our commerce, which so

69 often needs it." It was this development of Liberal ide-

ology that was greatly responsible for Gladstone's resigna-

70 tion as prime minister in 1894. Gladstone stated that the

foundation of the Liberal creed was being threatened and

that the last traces of the Manchester concepts iaid in his

^^Duncan, Herbert Spencer, II, 190-191.

^^Faber, The Vision and the Need, p. 69.

^^Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies, p. 82.

^^Faber, The Vision and the Need, p. 70.

•^^Knaplund, Gladstone's Foreign Policy, p. 12.

Page 54: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

52 71

very being. Indeed, the Manchester dogma had been sup-

pressed with Gladstone's resignation, a fact of which

Spencer was very rauch conscious.

Just as Spencer's popularity resulted from his support

of the liberal doctrine of individualism and progress at

the height of Benthamite influence, his rapid fall in popu-

larity in the 1890's and eariy 1900's was due in part be-

cause he would not conform to the emotional doctrine of

imperialism that had swept England. Barzun wrote, "When

Spencer . . . began to assail English railitarism and to

predict the degeneracy of the nation through the rise of a

new serfdom, he was scouted as a pacifist, a dotard, and a

dissenter. The London Times celebrated his death [1903]

with an article against him. English opinion was so violent

72 that protests came from the continent."

But Spencer's anti-iraperialistic propaganda should re-

ceive credit for hindering the use of collective Darwinism

as a justification for British imperialisra. His influence

was adequately expressed by H. G. Wells, an iraperialist,

though briefly, in the late nineteenth century.

I did not at first link the idea of science with the Socialist idea, the idea, that is, of a planned inter-co-ordinated society. The social-ist raoveraent in Engiand was the aesthetic

^•^Magnus, Gladstone, pp. 416-417; See D. A. Haraer, John Morley, Liberal Intellect in Politics (Oxford, 1968), p. 330

^^Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner, p. 103; See The Times, December 9, 19 03, p. 9.

Page 55: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

53

influence of Ruskin; it was being run by poets and decorators like Williara Morris . . . These leaders were generally ignorant of scientific philosophy and they had been misled by Herbert Spencer's Individualism into a belief that bio-logical science was anti-socialist.^3

Just as Darwinism was not thought of as a justification of

socialism in the years from 1874 to 1894, Darwinism was not

thought of as a justification of imperialisra. Darwinism

was absent from the political thoughts of Disraeli and

Salisbury and was lacking in the writings of the two raost

important imperialistic writers of this period, Jaraes

Anthony Froude and John Robert Seeley.

Disraeli, desiring England take an active part in the

settleraent of world affairs, tried to put an end to the Man-

chester School's principle of non-intervention. His iraperi-

alism was very much anti-Benthamite. Concerning Disraeli's

imperialisra Bodelsen wrote:

Two eleraents Disraeli did have a share in adding to Iraperialisra: the first beginnings of the as-sociation of Imperialisra with Jingoisra dates from his experiments in Indian and foreign pol-icy, and the particular brand of Iraperialisra which Seeley called the borabastic school, i.e. the school of Iraperialisra which dwells on the spectacular aspect of the possession of colonies.

73, H. G. Wells, Experiment in Autobiography, Discov-eries and Conclusions of a Very Ordinary Brain (Since 1866) (New York, 1934), p. 192. Wells also wrote that in 1912 "We do but eraerge from a period of deliberate happen-go-lucky and the influence of Herbert Spencer, who came near raising public shiftlessness to the dignity of a national philosophy" (p. 567).

Page 56: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

54

which is prone to consider mere extent of terri-tory an advantage in itself, and which glories in the possession of 'an Erapire on which the sun never sets,' may be said to have been first brought into fashion by Disraeli's Indian policy and his taste for the external symbols of Impe-rial rule as exemplified by the Royal Titles Act, by which the Queen assumed the title of Erapress of India.'4 ^

But Disraeli's power politics did not incorporate Darwinisra.

Disraeli first carae in contact with the evolutionary

theory through a pre-Darwinian book, Robert Charaber's

Vestiges of the Natural History of Creation (1844).

Disraeli was first "enchanted with it." But when he real-

ized the theological iraplications of it, realizing that

evolution underrained the historical account of Moses and

thus the whole Biblical systera, he, as an established novel-

ist, ridiculed Charaber's evolutionary theory in his novel

75 Tancred (1847). Tancred was the story of an idealist

concerned with restoring Biblical Christianity to the West.

Desiring to raake a pilgrimage to the Holy Sepulchre at

Jerusalem, he met a very beautiful young lady naraed Con-

stance Rawleigh. In the process of sharing his religious

feeling with her, he was disconcerted to find her reading

The Revelation of Chaos, Disraeli's raasquerade of Charaber's

74 Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialism, p. 124.

75 Leo J. Henkin, Darwinisra in the English Novel, 1860-

1910; The Irapact of Evolution on Victorian Fiction (New York, 1940) , p. 38.

Page 57: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

55

Vestiqes. Furthermore, Tancred's infatuation with her was

76 completely annihilated by her enthusiasm for the book.

The conversation between Tancred and Constance, as recorded

by Disraeli, is very arausing.

"You raust read the 'Revelations.'" Constance insists: "it is all explained. But what is most interesting, is the way in which man has been developed. You know, all is developraent. The principle is perpetually going on. First there was nothing, then there was something; then I forget the next, I think there were sheils, then fishes; then we came, let me see, did we corae next? Never mind that; we came at last. And the next change there will be some-thing very superior to us, something with wings. Ah! that's it: we were fishes, and I believe we shall be crows . . . ."

"I do not believe I ever was a fish," said Tancred.

"Oh, but it is all proved . . . . This is developraent. We had fins--we may have wings."

"I was a fish, and I shall be a crow," says Tancred to himself. Sadly he walks away. "What a spiritual raistressl" he exclaims, withal re-lieved at his escape. "And yesterday, for a moment, I alraost drearaed of kneeling with her at the Holy Sepulchre."77

In 1864 Samuel Wilberforce, Bishop of Oxford and one

of the main leaders in the Anglican church's struggle

against the theory of evolution, invited Disraeli to speak

against the Darwinian forces. In the Sheldonian Theatre

at Oxford on Noveraber 25, 1864, Disraeli stated:

What is the question now placed before society with a glib assurance the raost astounding?

" lbid. , pp. 38-39.

" " lbid. , p. 39.

Page 58: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

56

My question is this—Is raan an ape or an angel? My Lord, I am on the side of the angels.78

In 1870 Disraeli continued his attack against the evo-

lutionalists. First, he wrote in the general preface to

his republished novels that evolution was a "Teutonic rebel-

lion against the Divine truths entrusted to the Seraites"

and would raeet the sarae destiny as "the Celtic insurrection"

7Q of Voltaire and the Encyclopaedists. He asserted that

the ascendance of raaterialisra could be laid upon the offen-

sives of natural selection and Higher Criticism, for these

had propagandized a pseudo-science that postulated that

80 religion was anti-intellectual and anti-scientific. In

his last stateraent against the evolutionalists, Disraeli

portrayed in his Lothair (1870) a raan who fell consecutively

in love with three woraen who represented the Church of Rorae,

81 Liberal religion, and finally the Church of England.

Concerning Liberal religion, one of the characters in the

book proclaimed, "They have declared war against the Church,

the State, and the doraestic principle. All the great

78 Buckle, Disraeli, IV, 374.

^^lbid., IV, 375.

^^Henkin, Darwinisra in the English Novel, p. 78.

•'"Buckle, Disraeli, V, 151.

Page 59: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

57

truths on which the family reposes are denounced. Their

religion is the religion of science."®^

The writings of Disraeli demonstrated that the raan who

had identified the Conservative party with the policy of

imperialism would never consciously adopt evolution, much

less collective Darwinisra, as a justification of iraperial-

isra. Iraperialism, to Disraeli, was an emotional raoveraent

that transcended the small world of Darwinism.

Disraeli's anti-Darwinian views were also shared by

Salisbury, who became the Conservative leader in 1881.

From 1886 until 1900 British foreign policy was built upon

the political concepts of Salisbury. England began to rely

on Egypt rather than Constantinople as the pivot point to

83 protect the Indian Erapire. Gladstone's governraents of

1880-1886 had withdrawn British influence at Constantinople,

84 and Gerraany's influence had replaced it. Besides, by

1889 the decay of the Sultanate and the decline of the power

of the British fleet in the Mediterranean raade it irapossible

85 for Britain to hold its position there. To strengthen her

position in Egypt, England expanded into Africa,

^^lbid., V, 156.

83 Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, p. 255.

^^Buckle, Disraeli, VI, 367. oc

Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, p. 273.

Page 60: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

58

particularly East Africa since this area was strategically

important to protect the Indian Empire.^^

The two chief corapetitors with Britain for control of

Egypt and East Africa were France and Germany. In 1879

England and France enjoyed dual control of Egypt, but the

British occupation of Egypt in 1882 terrainated France's

influence. This created friction between the two nations

since France desired corapensation. Salisbury encouraged

the expansion of France into West Africa as a means of di-

verting her from Egypt and reducing her antagonism toward

87 England. This left Germany as Salisbury's chief rival

in East Africa. This rivalry was settled on July 1, 1890.

Great Britain agreed to cede the island of Heligoland and

some territory in Southwest Africa to Germany in exchange

for British sovereignty over the territories in East Africa

88 which controlled the head waters of the Nile. During

the negotiations with Gerraany concerning East Africa,

Salisbury wrote:

I will say that, during these negotiations, it occurred to rae raore than once that it raight

^^lbid., pp. 462-463; J. A. S. Grenville, Lord Salis-bury and Foreign Policy (London, 1964), pp. 19, 97.

^^Gwendoien Ceci1, Life of Robert Marquis of Salisbury (4 vols.; London, 1922-1932), IV, 252-253; F. H. Hinsley, "International Rivalry, 1885-1895," CHBE, III, 263-264.

^^Hinsiey, "International Rivalry, 1885-1895," pp. 268-269.

Page 61: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

59

be wiser to break thera off altogether and to allow the years to pass over us until the natu-ral progress of civilization and the struggle for existence should have deterrained, in a far raore effective way than can be done by proto-cols and treaties, who are to be supreme, and in what parts of that vast continent each na-tion is to rule.S^

This statement by Salisbury seemed to have a Darwinian pre-

supposition, but an investigation of Salisbury's thoughts

reveals that he was an anti-Darwinist.

In Salisbury's presidential address to the British

Association in 1894, it appeared that the Conservative

party had accepted officially the doctrine of evolution.

Salisbury claimed that Darwin's real work was disposing "of

the doctrine of the irarautability of species" and proving

the evolutionary theory. As to the raechanism of the Darwin-

ian theory, natural selection, he implied that it was insig-

90 nificant to the evolutionary theory. Concerning Salis-

bury's presentation, Henry F. Osborn thought that Salisbury

was expressing the Conservative skepticism of Darwinisra and

was regarding Darwinisra as a disagreeable form of Liberal-

ism. Osborn observed, "It was only too evident that the

Marquis himself found no corafort in evolution, and even

^^Cecil, Salisbury, IV, 228.

^ Thoraas Huxley, Life and Letters of Thoraas Henry Huxley, ed. by Leonard Huxley (2 vols.; New York, 1901) II, 400-401.

Page 62: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

60

entertained a suspicion as to its probability. " - In 1894,

Salisbury, prirae minister during the Conservative govern-

ments of 1886-1892 and 1895-1902, was personally willing to

accept the doctrine of evolution, but he believed that to

apply any form of evolution to social and iraperialistic

thought transcended the limits of evolution. Salisbury

desired to keep evolution in the realm of biology and out

of the sphere of man.

Thus the framework was not Darwinian in which Salisbury

said, "struggle for existence should have deterrained, in a

far more effective way than can be done by protocols and

treaties, who are to be supreme." This apparent contradic-

tion resulted frora the lack of understanding of the rela-

tionship between power politics and Darwinisra. Darwinism

describes power politics biologically, but the acceptance

of power politics is not a sufficient condition for the

acceptance of Darwinism. Disraeli and Salisbury adopted

power politics, but they both disbelieved the Darwinian

theory. Power politics was a dorainant principle during

the late nineteenth century, but the Darwinian theory as a

92 justification of power politics was not vindicated.

^•^lbid., II, 399.

^^D. A. Hamer, John Morley, pp. 330-331; McDowell, British Conservatism, pp. 95-96, 105; Soraervell, English Thought, pp. 186-187.

Page 63: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

61

Another imperialist who taught the "might is right"

principle without invoking Darwinism was Jaraes Anthony

Froude. His concept of power was based upon the Carlylian

principle; thus Froude's force structure was a pre-Darwinian

concept. Froude and Carlyle both equated the physical and

social reign with the moral reign; that is, he equated the

most righteous with the strongest. In the long run, he

stated, the most righteous, who are the strongest, overcome

93 the weakest, who are least righteous. It was upon this

foundation that Froude wrote in The English in Ireland in

The Eighteenth Century, "the superior part has a natural

right to govern; the inferior part has a right to be gov-

94 erned." It was not upon the Darwinian foundation as

95 Carlton J. H. Hayes implies.

Froude's imperialism rested upon Carlyle's social the-

ory. Carlyle and Froude were very anti-Benthamite, hated

the political economists, and despised the doctrine of

9 6 utilitarianism. Because Froude was apparently very well

read in Spencer, he perhaps associated Darwinism with the

^"^Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Iraperialisra, p. 177.

^^Hayes, A Generation of Materialisra, p. 12.

^^lbid.

96 Bode l sen , M i d - V i c t o r i a n I r ape r i a l i sm, pp . 106, 107.

Page 64: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

62 97

Manchester School. This is perhaps the reason there is

not a word in his political writings concerning the Darwin-

ian theory. He advocated emigration as a solution to the

industrial system that the Manchester School had endorsed.

Thus the colonies played an important position in his im-

98 perialism. Gladstone's concept of erapire appeared to be

a separatist doctrine to hira, and thus he was one of the _ . QQ

first to attack Gladstonian policy.

John Robert Seeley also ignored Darwinism in his justi-

fication of British imperialism. Seeley wrote The Expansion

of England, a work which R. C. K. Ensor claimed was "the

single influence which did most to develop the iraperialist

idea" in the 1880's and 1890's. Seeley, in The Expansion

of England, presented war as a natural process, but it was

not survival of the fittest. In fact, he stated that

England's victories over France in the eighteenth and early

nineteenth centuries were not because England was superior,

for France was stronger, but because of England's geograph-

ical position. France located on the continent was enticed

^^Duncan, Herbert Spencer, I, 126; Spencer, An Auto-biography, II, 484.

^^Bodelsen, Mid-Victorian Imperialisra, p. 176.

^^lbid., p. 201.

•^^^Ensor, England, 1870-1914, p. 163.

Page 65: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

63

into European entangleraents which drained her strength. "

He also emphatically stated that England's conquest of

India had depended upon Indian troops comprising four-fifths

of the British array; thus India had conquered herself."^^^

Too many writers have desired to equate Seeley's doctrine

with collective Darwinism, but this is easily seen as

absurd in Seeley's own writings and in the knowledge that

the social implication of Darwinism was dominated by the

Spencerian interpretation.

The doraination of Spencer's interpretation of Darwinisra

was draraatically seen in Thoraas H. Huxley's Roraanes Lecture

of May 18, 1893. Huxley stated that Spencer's interpreta-

tion of the social implications of Darwinism was correct,

but Spencer was incorrect in equating evolution with prog-

ress. Huxley stated that Darwinisra was nothing but self-

ishness and death in which the weakest raust die. Morality

had to be established outside and against the Darwinian

systera, and social progress raeant the checking of the cosmic

progress at every step. The audience was very rauch sur-

prised, Thoraas Huxley's son wrote, for "Huxley was popularly

supposed to hold the sarae views as Mr. Spencer—for were

•'••'•J. R. Seeley, The Expansion of England, Two Courses of Lectures (Boston, 1901), pp. 126, 128.

-'• lbid. , pp. 200-202.

Page 66: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

64

103 they not both Evolutionists?" This lecture demonstrated

that individual Darwinism as a social theory in the late

1880's and 1890's was unsatisfactory. It raust be pointed

out that Darwinism was foremost a social theory, and only

as a by-product of a social theory was Darwinism applied

to international relations. It was only the pressure of

events that developed collective Darwinism into a theory

of international policy.

^^"^Huxley, Thomas Huxley, II, 374.

Page 67: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

CHAPTER III

SOCIAL THEORY AND IMPERIALISM

The evolution of Darwinism frora an individualistic

doctrine of the Manchester School to a collective doctrine

justifying British iraperialisra involved two basic steps.

First, Darwinisra had to be dislodged frora the Manchester

School. This process was accomplished by the writings of

Thomas Huxley, Alfred Russel Wallace, Benjamin Kidd, and

Karl Pearson. Second, the Liberal party had to reject

Gladstonian Liberalism and substitute a more imperialistic

policy, for Darwinism was a doctrine of the left. This

process was accomplished by Liberal reaction to Gladstone's

struggle for Irish Horae Rule and the ascendence of Rose-

bery to the leadership of the Liberal party in 1894.

The raan who first weakened Spencer's grip on Darwinis

was Darwin's bulldog, Thomas Huxley. At first Huxley

seemed content to follow the doctrines laid down by Spencer

I return your [Spencer's] proofs [of the First Principles] by this post. To my mind nothing can be better than their contents, whether in matter or in raanner. . . .

I rejoice that you have raade a beginning and such a beginning—for the more I think about it the more important it seeras to rae that soraebody

m

•'•See Alvar Ellegard, Darwin and the General Reader; The Reception of Darwin's Theory of Evolution in the British Periodical Press, 1859-1872 (Gbteborg, 1958), pp. 35-36.

65

Page 68: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

66

should think out into a connected systera the loose notions that are floating about raore or less distinctly in all the best minds.

It seems as if all the thoughts in what you have written were my own, and yet I am con-scious of the enormous difference your presenta-tion of them raakes in ray intellectual state. One is thought in the state of herap yarn, and the other in the state of rope. Work away, then, ex-cellent rope-raaker, and make us raore ropes to hold on against the devil and the parsons.2

In a personal letter, just after his son's death, he also

expressed Spencer's optimisra of the cosraic process, which

he was to attack in the Roraanes Lecture:

I am no optiraist, but I have the firraest belief that the Divine Governraent (if we raay use such a phrase to express the sum of the "customs of matter") is wholly just. The more I know inti-mately of the lives of other men (to say noth-ing of my own), the raore obvious it is to rae that the wicked does not flourish nor is the righteous punished. But for this to be clear we raust bear in mind what alraost all forget, that the rewards of life are contingent upon obedience to the whole law—physical as well as raoral--and that raoral obedience, will not atone for physical sin, or vice versa.3

As late as 1886, he continued to support this position. In

"Science and Morals," Huxley stated that he had "a real and

living belief in [the] fixed order of nature which sends

social disorganization upon the track of immorality, as

2 T. H. Huxley to H. Spencer, Septeraber 3, 1860, in

Huxley, Thoraas Huxley, I, 229. • T. H. Huxley to C. Kingsley, Septeraber 23, 1860,

Ibid., I, 233-236.

Page 69: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

67

surely as it sends physical disease after physical tres-4

passes."

Huxley's disagreeraent with Spencer arose out of the

inability of the Manchester School to handle the social

probleras of the late nineteenth century. New ideas were

needed for the new classes which had obtained the franchise:

the urban artisans in 1867, and the rural laborers in 1885-^

There was a deraand for social reforras. As long as the fac-

tory systera was in its infant and adolescent stages, the

factory was sraall, and an individual seeraed to have control

over his own destiny. An industrious individual could

clirab the social ladder and could even becorae the master of

his own factory. In this stage the Manchester School seemed

to have some validity with its gospel of individualisra. But

by 1886 the factory was no longer sraall but coraplex and

owned by thousands of shareholders. Thus the British indus-

trial society seemed to be a legalized system of slavery to

the workers, because they no longer had the opportunity for

social improveraent. In 1886 Charles Booth reported that

one-third of the London population lived "below the poverty

line." Collectivism became a popular deraand. Even

^Hiramelfarb, Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution, p. 382.

^Barker, Political Thought in England, pp. 183-184.

^Ensor, England, 1870-1914, p. 301.

Page 70: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

68

socialism invaded the political scene. In 1881, H. M.

Hyndmann founded the Democratic Federation, the first

modern English socialist body. In 1884, Williara Morris

broke away frora this organization and founded the Socialist

League. In January, 1884, the Fabian Society was also

founded. Huxley appreciated these new social conditions,

for he had worked araong the iower classes propagandizing

the evolutionary theory. His basic solution was public

education. Upon this presupposition he becarae an educa-

tional reforra leader. At a tirae when laissez-faire ex-

tremists were publicly belittling the provisions of

Forster's Education Act, Huxley wrote an article entitled

"Administrative Nihilism" (1871). In this article he

dealt with the Spencerian objections against state inter-

ference in education and criticized Spencer for limiting

the actions of the governraent to police functions.

Huxley stated that since a large proportion of the prole-

tariat were steeped in "misery and degradation," the sup-

pression of public education would disrupt the social peace

^lbid., p. 100.

^Huxley, Thoraas Huxley, I, 347; See Cyril Bibby, T. H. Huxley; Scientist, Huraanist, and Educator (New York, 1960), passim.

Q

Bibby, Huxley, p- 51.

Spencer, An Autobiography, II, 232.

Page 71: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

69

of the state, especially since the socialist raoveraent was

"stirring European society to its depths." He concluded

that if the governraent was to provide the greatest happi-

ness for the greatest number, government regulation was

inescapable.

The debate between Huxley and Spencer was not taken up

again until 1888 when Huxley in his article "The Struggle

for Existence in Society" first intimated that he had com-

pletely rejected the Spencerian system. In this article,

Huxley denied that Darwinism could be projected into society

as a standard for being and raorality, for nature was not

benevolent as Spencer had stated. It was evil and had

2 caused the destruction of thousands of species.

It is obvious in this article that Huxley interpreted

Darwinism as the Spencerian struggle, that is, as the strug-

13 gle among individuals. He advocated that society should

be organized to fight against this struggle. Progress in

the sphere of raan was the checking of natural selection;

raan progressed by a social evolution rather than a biologi-

14 cal evolution. Organization would involve state

William Irvine, Thomas Henry Huxley (London, 1960), p. 25; See Jay Runney, Herbert Spencer's Sociology (New York, 1965), pp. 47-49, originally published in 1937.

•'• Thoraas Huxley, "The Struggle for Existence: A Pro-grarame," Nineteenth Century, XXIII (1888), 161-165.

•'•- lbid. , p. 166.

-"• lbid., p. 165.

Page 72: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

70

intervention, especially in helping the condition of the

poor.

This article demonstrated the tension that Huxley felt

in the individual Darwinian doctrine. He had seen the ap-

plication of Louis Pasteur's ideas regarding the cause and

prevention of disease hindered partly because of Spencerian

doctrine. He stated, "the opposition which, as I see frora

the English papers, is threatened has really for the raost

part nothing to do either with M. Pasteur's merits or with

the efficacy of his method of treating hydrophobia. It

proceeds partly from the fanatics of laissez-faire, who

think it better to rot and die than to be kept whole and

lively by State interference." Upon the basis of the

doctrine of individual Darwinism Spencer opposed state-

education, poor laws, regulation of housing conditions,

and even the protection of the 'ignorant' from medicai

quacks. Huxley thought that individual Darwinism destroyed

the dignity of an individual. In a letter entitled "Rea-

soned Savagery," published in the Daily Telegraph, February

9, 1890, Huxley charged Spencer with propagandizing "brutal

individualism" and accused Spencer of having a "reasoned

«17 savagery.

^^lbid., p. 172.

• T. Huxley to Lord Major, June 25, 1889, in Huxley, Thomas Huxley, II, 254-256.

1 7 Spencer, Spencer, II, 34.

Page 73: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

71

By the time of his Roraanes Lecture in 1893, the case

against the Spencerian systera was occupying his whole imagi-

nation. The thesis of his Romanes Lecture, which was en-

titled "Evolution and Ethics," was evolution versus ethics.

Huxley stated that the raoveraent of nature by the Darwinian

process was an advanceraent by way of evil. Man was the

ultimate in the evolutionary process in that he excelled

over the ape and the tiger in those qualities that were

associated with the animals, which included "ruthless and

ferocious destructiveness when his anger is roused by oppo-

18 sition." Huxley continued:

Social progress raeans a checking of the cosmic process at every step and the substitution for it of another, which may be called the ethical process; the end of which is not the survival of those who raay happen to be the fittest . . . but of those who may happen to be the best. . . . [The] ethical progress of society depends, not on imitating the cosmic process, still less in running away frora it, but in corabating it.l^

Politically he declared that "fanatical individualism" was

absurd, because Spencer patterned moral progress upon the

doctrine of Darwinism and thus made the individual heedless

20 of his obligations to others.

•"" Thoraas Huxley, Evolution and Ethics, and other Essays (New York, 1894), pp. 51-52.

•'• lbid. , pp. 81, 83.

^^lbid., p. 82.

Page 74: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

72

After Huxley's death, papers were found in which he

seemed to equate collective Darwinism with the ethicai pro-

cess he had spoken of in the Romanes Lecture. He stated

that in civilized society intra-state struggle was largely

replaced by inter-state struggle. This latter struggle,

Huxley wrote, was usually won by the ethically superior. •'

Darwinism was again associated with progress, but progress

was determined by inter-state struggle, not the Spencerian

struggle.

Another eminent scientist who rejected Spencer's phi-

losophy because of its inadequacy in meeting the social

problems of the late nineteenth century was Alfred Russel

Wallace. Before 1881, Wallace was a devout Spencerian. In

fact he named his son, who was born in 1867, Herbert

22 Spencer. He also had a great desire to formulate social

reforras, but he was penned in by the do-nothing philosophy

of Spencer. Then in 1881 he read Henry George's Progress

and Poverty which, he said, refuted the conclusions of the

classical econoraists, thus knocking the very foundation out

from under Spencer's philosophical systera. In 1889 he pos-

tulated that the socialistic state could bring about the

^ Williara Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians; The Story of Darwin, Huxley, and Evolution (New York, 1955), p. 351.

^^A. R. Wallace to C. Darwin, October 1, 1867, in Wallace, Wallace, p. 155.

Page 75: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

73

best selections, a coraplete reverse of the Spencerian sys-23

tera. Even after the rejection of Spencer's systera, he

did not support collective Darwinisra, but instead he advo-

cated another individual Darwinian systera. The difference

between Wallace's and Spencer's social theories was that in

the forraer the state controlled the struggle and guaranteed

each individual an equal opportunity. *

The developraent of Darwinisra in the writings of Huxley

and Wallace was priraarily a rejection of the Spencerian sys-

tera in favor of another social theory. Neither drearaed of

applying Darwinisra to his personal belief in British iraperi-

alisra. Huxley was a Liberal, but he hated Gladstone's Lib-

eralisra and had a strong iraperialistic bias, expressing a

pro-Disraeli sentiraent and giving approval to the policies

25 of Salisbury and Joseph Chamberlain. But he did not

justify his iraperialisra with Darwinian doctrine. Wallace

was an anti-imperialist and a strong supporter of

23 A. R. Wallace to C. Darwm, July 9, 1881, Ibid. , pp.

260-261; Wilraa George, Biologist Philosopher; A Study of the Life and Writings of Alfred Russel Wallace (New York, 1964) , pp. 220-225, 269.

24 Alfred Russel Wallace, Studies, Scientific and

Social (2 vols.; London, 1900), II, 513-516. 25 T. Huxley to his daughter, Deceraber 7, 1879, and

Huxley to his son, December, 1879, in Huxley, Thomas Huxley, I, 524-525; Irvine, Apes, Angels, and Victorians, p. 332.

Page 76: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

74 26

Gladstone. To Wallace iraperialism was a policy propa-

gandized "to distract attention from the starvation and

wretchedness and death-dealing trades at horae and thinly-

veiled slavery in raany of [England's] tropical or sub-

tropical colonies." However Wallace did not justify his

anti-imperialistic sentiment with Darwinism. The identifi-

cation of imperialisra with the Darwinian doctrine first

required the destruction of Gladstonian Liberalism. This

destruction found its roots in the split of the Liberal

party over Gladstone's struggle for Irish Horae Rule, 1886-

1894.

From the close of 1885 until the end of Gladstone's

official career in 1894, Irish Home Rule was the dominant

political issue. During this period Gladstone dedicated

his full power and energy in an effort to settle this issue.

The political and economic grievances of the Irish had re-

sulted in mob demonstrations and raurders which threatened

to destroy the peace and harraony of England. There were

cries frora the Irish to repeal the union with Great Britain

2 8 which had been established in 1800. To resolve the Irish

^^Alfred Russel Wallace, "Why I Voted for Mr. Glad-stone," Nineteenth Century, XXXII (1892), 182-185.

^ Alfred Russel Wallace, The Wonderful Century, The Age of New Ideas in Science and Invention (London, 1902), pT 466.

28 Strauss, Joseph Charaberlain, p. 37.

Page 77: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

75

problem Gladstone proposed in his Home Rule Bill of 1886

the creation of an Irish Parliament in Dublin which would

have complete control of doraestic affairs.^^ This bill was

based upon Gladstone's belief that the empire should be a

league of autonomous dominions. Gladstone's effort to get

this bill passed resulted in a split in the Liberal party.

An anti-Gladstone element in the Liberal party, the Liberal

Unionists, allied theraselves with the Conservatives to de-

feat the bill. This faction was led by Joseph Charaberlain,

a man known priraarily as a radical reforraer and an opponent

of the Manchester School. The denial of self-government to

Ireland became part of the larger issue of imperialism.

The Liberal Unionists, particularly Chamberlain, challenged

31 Gladstone's concept of the empire and imperialism.

On July 8, 1886, Charaberlain, lecturing on the Irish

Home Rule Bill, stated:

If to-morrow any one of the Legislative Assem-blies of the different provinces in Australia were to pass a resolution that they desired to be separate, do you suppose that we should

^^lbid., pp. 48-49.

^^R. E. Robinson, "Imperial Problems in British Poli-tics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 156-157; Haraer, John Morley, p. 322.

•'•Strauss, Joseph Chamberlain, pp. 48-49; Chamberlain's

Boyd ,_ in Bingley Hall, July 9, 1906, ibid., II, 361-362.

Page 78: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

76

send an army to compel them to remain as they are? Not a bit of it. The tie which binds us to Australia is a sentimental tie. That is very valuable, and I hope it may long continue to exist. But I hope raore than that. I hope we raay be able to strengthen it; I hope we raay be able sooner or later to federate, to bring together, all these great independencies of the British Erapire into one suprerae and Ira-perial Parliament, so that they shouid be units of one body. . . . That is what I hope, but there is very little hope for it if you weaken the ties which now bind the central portion of the Empire together.^^

Gladstone's Home Rule Bill had the effect of freeing

most Liberal iraperialists frora a frustrating association

with the Gladstonian Liberals. The bill itself was defeated

by thirty votes; ninety-three Liberal Unionists voted with

the Conservative party. Gladstone imraediately dissolved

Parliament, claiming that the Liberal Unionists had de-

serted the Liberal creed, that is, the creed of the Man-

33 chester School. By 1887 the Liberal Unionists formed

with the Conservatives an alliance which was to control

the government for the rest of the century except for a

34 brief Liberal interlude during the years 1892-1895.

32 Chamberlain's speech at Rawtenstall, July 8, 1886,

in Charaberlain, Mr. Charaberlain's Speeches, I, 276-278. "^^Eyck, Gladstone, pp. 402-403.

^^Robinson, "Iraperial Probleras in British Politics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 156-158.

Page 79: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

77

The Unionists were further coraraitted to an iraperialis-

tic policy, because its political strength was concentrated

in the metropolitan and urban constituencies. In these con-

stituencies, it was coraraonly believed that Gladstone's Horae

Rule Bill was dictated by the Irish raob. Instead of estab-

lishing law and order, by force if necessary, and protecting

the property and personal rights of the landed and business

interests, Gladstone seeraed to surrender to the "masses."

Gladstone's continued struggie for Irish Horae Rule during

the period 1886-1893 only further alienated the coraraercial

35 and business interests. This development had particular

3 6 influence upon British foreign policy.

British commercial and urban centers began to propa-

gandize an anti-Gladstonian doctrine of a strong unified

erapire and an expansionist policy. The conflict between

British free trade and colonial and foreign protectionisra

seeraed to place their interests in a chaotic condition.

During the last thirty years of the nineteenth century,

Gerraany and the United States becarae serious economic com-

petitors, and France was threatening to become one also.

These three countries passed high tariffs to exclude the

^^lbid., p. 158.

Eyck, Gladstone, p. 408; See Victor Berard, British Imperialisra and Coraraercial Supremacy, trans. by H. W. Foskett (New York, 1906), passi" T

Page 80: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

78

products of rivals: Germany in 1879 and particularly in

1885, France in 1882, and the United States in 1891 with the

McKinley tariff and in 1897 with the Dingley tariff. Other

European countries, such as Italy, Austria-Hungary, and

Russia, followed their protective policy. Thus British raan-

ufacturers were practically eliminated frora European and

American markets and had to compete seriously with her pro-

tected industrial rivals in her own free-trade market and

in the colonial markets. As the protectionist nations,

particularly France and Germany, expanded into Africa, there

were cries frora the coraraercial centers for Britain to safe-

guard this region. These cries were intensified when the

blame for the depression and uneraployraent of 1894-1895 was

placed on foreign corapetition and tariffs. Imperial expan-

sion was advocated as a raeans of securing British prosperity

38 and employment. In the 1890's the Presidents of the

London and Liverpool Chambers of Comraerce urged on Salisbury

"the absolute necessity, for the prosperity of [England]

that new avenues for coraraerce such as in East Equatorial

37 Bernard Serarael, Iraperialisra and Social Reform,

English Social-Imperial Thought, 1895-1915 (Carabridge, 1960) , pp. 86-89.

3fi

Robinson, "Iraperial Problems in British Politics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 158-159; "Great Britain's Policy in Africa," The Tiraes, August 22, 1888, p. 8.

Page 81: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

79

Africa should be opened up, in view of the hostile tariffs

with which British raanufacturers are being everywhere con-39

fronted." Manchester, Glasgow, Birraingham, Edinburgh,

and other coramercial centers followed with sirailar pleas.

On April 20, 1893, the London Charaber of Comraerce reported:

[There] is practicaily no raiddle course for this country, between a reversal of the free-trade policy to which it is pledged, on the one hand, and a prudent but continuous territorial exten-sion for the creation of new raarkets, on the other hand. This policy is not so rauch one of our own selection, . . . [but] as one forced upon us by the exclusive econoraic systems of other countries, including our own colonies.^^

By 1888, Chamberlain and Salisbury, the leaders of the

Unionists, were speaking the language of the comraercial

41 centers. In 1895, Salisbury declared in the House of

Lords:

It is [Governraent's] business in all these new [African] countries to raake smooth the paths for British coraraerce, British enterprise, the application of British capital, at a time when other paths, other outlets for the coraraercial energies of our race are being gradually closed by the coraraercial principles which are gaining raore and raore adhesion. Everywhere we see the advance of coraraerce checked by the enormous growth which the doctrines of Protection are ob-taining. We see it with our three great comraer-cial rivals, France, Germany, and America. The

39 F. D. Lugard, The Rise of Our East African Empire,

Early Efforts in Nyasaland and Uganda (2 vols.; London, 1893) , I, 379-380.

^^lbid., I, 380.

Robinson, "Imperiai Problems in British Politics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 160.

Page 82: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

80

doctrines of Protection are stronger and stronger, and operate to the exclusion of Brit-ish commerce wherever their power extends. We see even in our own colonies the same sinister influence at work.42

In 1892, Chamberlain proclairaed to a Birrainghara audience:

I should like to say . . . [that] all ques-tions which affect the extension of the Erapire, have a very pressing interest for working men. Those people who want you to have a little Empire raust raake up their mind that with a lit-tle Empire will go a little trade. This United Kingdom of ours is, after all, but a small place —it is but a raere speck upon the surface of the globe—and it would be absolutely impossible that from our resources alone we could find employraent for our crowded population of forty millions of souls. No; your hope of continuous employment depends upon our foreign comraerce, and now that other nations are ciosing their ports to us, and everywhere we see they are endeavouring to create a raonopoly for their own benefit—I say that the future of the working classes of this country de-pends upon our success in raaintaining the Empire as it at present stands, and in taking every wise and legitimate opportunity of extending it.^^

Chamberlain propagandized that the Erapire was "the greatest

44 business organization in the world." When the Liberal

Unionists joined the Conservative cabinet in 1895,

Chamberlain, receiving the Colonial Office, intensified the

^^4 Hansard, XXX, 698-699.

Lugard, The Rise of Our East African Empire, I, 381.

A. F. Madden, "Changing Attitudes and Widening Re-sponsibilities, 1895-1914," CHBE, III, 381; See J. L. Garvin, The Life of Joseph Chamberlain (3 vols.; London, 1932-1934), II, 466-467.

Page 83: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

81

drive for state-ordered development of the British colonial 45 estate.

The commercial and business interests had a strong in-

fluence upon the Unionists. Charaberlainite political

thought, or, as Chamberiain called it, the Birrainghara School,

exerted a gigantic influence in the late nineteenth century.

Beside advocating a strong empire, the Birmingham School

also supported social reforms. During the Conservative

adrainistration of 1886-1892, the Liberal Unionists were able

to persuade Salisbury to carry out raany radical pieces of

legislation which were anti-Gladstonian. Charaberlain's

concept of social reforra and a strong centralized govern-

raent coincided with the growing tendency in British society

. ^ T , . . . 48 to favor collectivism.

It was within this political framework of the Birming-

ham School that Benjamin Kidd wrote Social Evolution (1894).

Kidd was a Liberal who despised the dograa of the Manchester

^^4 Hansard, XXXVI, 640-642.

4 fi

Charaberlain's speech in Birmingham, May 28, 1888, in Chamberlain, Mr. Chamberlain's Speeches, I, 298-313; Chamber-lain's speech in Bingley Hall, July 9, 1906, Ibid., II, 361-372.

^^Garvin, Joseph Chamberlain, II, 423; McDowell, Brit-ish Conservatism, pp. 140-142, 147.

^^Paul Knaplund, The British Empire, 1815-1939 (New York, 1941), p. 326.

Page 84: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

82

School and was very violent in his anti-Gladstone proclama-49

tions. in 1910, he wrote, "For raore than a century Lib-

eralism of the Gladstonian type has contributed not a single

idea to the polical thought or action of the world."^^

Kidd favored the Chamberlainite political views. In fact,

when in 1903 Charaberlain proposed to destroy the free trade

favored by the Manchester School and to give the colonies a

preferential tariff as a step towards imperial union, Kidd

51 strongly supported him. In his book Social Evolution, he

synthesized the concepts of the Birrainghara School and the

ideas of the raan whora he considered had dorainated Darwinian

52 science after Darwin, Dr. August Weisraann. Kidd's thesis

in this book, which in four years went into nineteen edi-

tions, was that the quality which gave superiority to a so-

ciety or race was deterrained by the willingness of the

m.embers to subordinate personal interests to the interest

of society. Thus Kidd agreed with Huxley that progress in

Benjamin Kidd, "A National Policy," Fortnightly Re-view, XCIII (1910), 602-614; Brinton, English Political Thought, p. 287.

^^lbid., p. 603.

• Benjarain Kidd, "Imperial Policy and Free Trade," Nineteenth Century, LIV (1903), 33-54; Benjarain Kidd, "The Larger Basis of Colonial Preference," Nineteenth Century, LV (1904), 12-29.

^^Benjarain Kidd, "Darwin's Successor at Horae," Review of Reviews, II (1890), 647-650.

Page 85: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

83

the sphere of man was a social progress.^"^ But Kidd also

stated that social progress was determined by struggle.

Without struggle, there was no progress. Kidd deduced this

concept from the scientific studies of Weismann, who had

intensified the Darwinian doctrine of struggle. Darwin,

late in his life, had admitted other causes of progress

beside struggie, such as sexual selection and use-

inheritance, but Weismann recognized no other cause of

progress except the struggle for existence. When struggle

54 stopped, progress ceased and retrogression took its place.

Kidd wrote, "When there is progress there must inevitably

be selection, and selection in its turn involves corapeti-

tion of some kind." Kidd agreed with Spencer that intra-

state struggle was a necessity for progress. It was this

intra-state competition that falsified the socialistic doc-

trine, for sociaiism desired to eliminate competition,

which consequently eliminated progress. Kidd also pointed

out, however, that the Spencerian doctrine of laissez-faire

57 was useless and nonsensical. The state had to provide a

^^Benjamin Kidd, Social Evolution (2nd ed.; New York, 1894) , pp. 306-307; Eli Halévy, Imperialisra and the Rise of Labour (New York, 1951), p. 19.

^^MacKintosh, From Comte to Benjarain Kidd, pp. 234-257.

^^Kidd, Social Evolution, pp. 36-39.

^^lbid., pp. 254-255.

^^lbid., pp. 214-215.

Page 86: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

84

society in which all would have equal opportunities for cora-.... 58

petition. Spencerian struggle, continued Kidd, was sanc-

tified by reason as it grew out of the Bentharaite philosophy

in which reason was a pagan god to be worshipped. Reason

taught that the individual should be selfish, should be con-

cerned with his egotistial welfare, and should think of the

Darwinian struggle as hiraself against the whole world.^^

If that was the nature of progress, the Spencerian corapeti-

tion, as pointed out by Huxley, could never have created

society and a coraplete adherence to this doctrine would

ultimately destroy society. But instead society was an

organic growth sanctified not by reason, but by religion.

Religion transcended the individual frora personal self-

centeredness to a concern for society and a concern for

other individuals.

A religion is a forra of belief, providing an ultra-rational sanction for that large class of conduct in the individual where his inter-ests and the interests of the social organisra are antagonistic, and by which the former are rendered subordinate to the latter in the gen-eral interests of the evolution which the race is undergoing.61

Inter-state struggle, which was as iraportant as intra-

state struggle, was won by the nations that had the highest

^^lbid., p. 152.

^^lbid., pp. 66-67.

^^lbid., p. 110.

^•^lbid., p. 111.

Page 87: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

85

levels of religion. More specifically Kidd stated that

collective Darwinian struggles were being won by the Teu-

tonic peoples, because they had the highest level of reli-

gion—the religion of the Reforraation. ^ This was

illustrated by the struggles between England and France in

the eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries and, between

Gerraany and France in 1870. Although France had the higher

intellectual capacity, she could not win the collective

Darwinian struggle with England or Gerraany because of her

Roman Catholic religion.

Kidd's religious ideas seem to be another concept he

adopted from Weisraann. In a personal interview with

Weismann in 1890, Kidd reported:

With regard to the part which, from the point of view of the Darwinian, religion had played in the evolution of modern society, Professor Weis-raann was very decided in his views. "I certainly think," he said, "that religion has been a most iraportant factor on the side of human evolution."

"You say 'has been.' Do you consider that it will continue to be a necessity of society?" The reply, after a short pause, was a decided affirmative.

"There will," he said, "always reraain behind soraething which there is no hope that science will ever explain, and this will continue to forra the basis of religion. . . . "

^^lbid., p. 264.

^^lbid., pp. 303-304

" lbid. , pp. 298-303.

Page 88: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

86

Looking at the history of Europe frora the point of view of the Darwinian, Professor Weisraann was inclined to rank the Reforraation amongst the greatest of the social evolution-ary forces of modern tiraes. The raoral idea necessary to society had been preserved, and more room for expansion had been obtained for the human raind, As a sociologist he said he considered the new churches of Gerraany and England as constituting a higher order of social force than that contributed by Roraan Catholicisra.^^

It was because of England's religion that Kidd justi-

fied British iraperialistic policy, not because collective

6 6 Darwinism justified aggressive foreign policy. Because

of England's religion she could bring qualities such as

humanity, strength, righteousness, and devotion, without

having the concept of exploitation, into those nations that

were underdeveloped, because they were low in the religious

evolutionary scale. This religious view of Kidd was not

esoteric. From 1883 to 1890 there was an extraordinary

revival of religious and humanitarian interest in Africa.

Ever since the 1870's the philanthropists and anti-slavers

had besieged the government to civilize Africa, but when

the protectionists expanded into Africa they intensified

^ . • ^ - - 67 their iraportunities.

^^Kidd, "Darwin's Successor at Horae," pp. 648-649.

^^Kidd, Social Evolution, pp. 339-350.

^^Robinson, "Imperial Problems in Politics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 158-159.

Page 89: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

87

The popularity of Social Evolution was basically be-

cause of its religious element, not its iraperialistic

1 ..68 element. A writer of the Critics recoramended "Social

Evolution to the earnest attention of [the] religious teach-

ers of the people, for [it is] wise and inspiring."^^ The

Darwinian philosophy had shaken or destroyed the faith of

many religious individuals, who were not prepared to stand

against the overwhelraing arguraents of the scientists. Many

of these people, observed John A. Hobson, were "willing to

grasp eagerly at a theory which [would] save their religious

systera in a manner which seeras consistent with the mainte-

70 nance of modern culture." Kidd's Social Evolution seemed

to many to be that systera.

Kidd's priraary objective in writing Social Evolution

was to set up a social theory that fit the political atraos-

phere of the 1890's, not to justify British iraperialisra.

To a Daily Chronicle interviewer he stated, "If you ask me

to describe 'Social Evolution' in a word, I should say that

it is an endeavor to give a biological basis to our social

6 8 "The Forgotten Fact of Social Evolution," Spectator,

LXXII (1894), 292-293; "Is Pure Selfishness Natural," Spectator, LXXII (1894), 154; "Social Evolution," Critics, XXI (1894) , 231; "Social Evolution," Popular Science Monthly, XLV (1894) , 557-558; W. D. Le Suer, "Kidd on 'Social Evolu-tion,'" Popular Science Monthly, XLVIII (1895), 38-48.

69 "Social Evolution," Critics, p. 231.

70 . . . Richard Hofstader, Social Darwinism in American

Thought (2nd ed.; New York, 1959), p. 101.

Page 90: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

88 71

science." As a social theory, the imperialistic eleraents

were suppressed, which in the first place only encorapassed

a comparitively few pages. Karl Pearson and Francis Galton,

both collective Darwinists, considered Kidd in his Social

Evolution as the leading exponent of individual Darwinism

72 in the 1890's. Even Robert MacKintosh's book Frora Comte

to Benjamin Kidd, The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for

Human Guidance (1899), which gave a good account of Kidd's

system, did not study Kidd's collective Darwinism or Kidd's

justification of British imperialisra; the book only gave

the arguments for intra-state struggle and the arguments

73 against the socialistic state. In Imperialism, A Study

(1902) J. A. Hobson, who wrote a chapter analyzing British

collective Darwinisra, did not identify Kidd as a collective

Darwinist, arguing that Kidd's contribution to the imperi-

alistic moveraent of the late nineteenth century was only in

74 his book The Control of the Tropics (1898).

• Karl Pearson, "Socialisra and Natural Selection," Fortnightly Review, LVI (1894), 2.

^^C. P. Blacker, Eugenics: Galton and After (Cam-bridge, Massachusetts, 1952), p. 90; Pearson, "Socialism and Natural Selection," p. 8.

^^MacKintosh, Frora Comte to Benjarain Kidd, pp. 258-277; See "The Forgotten Fact of Social Evolution, Spectator, LXXII (1894), 292-293; "Kidd's Social Evolution, Nation, LVIII (1894) , 294-295.

^^J. A. Hobson, Iraperialism, A Study (3rd ed.; London, 1938) , pp. 226-227.

Page 91: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

89

The Control of the Tropics, which contained articles

that Kidd had forraerly published in The Tiraes, depicted the

mentality of the Birraingham School raore clearly than Social

Evolution, for it propagandized its comraercial interests

and the leadership's responsibility in Africa.^^ Kidd wrote

that the overpopulation of the world had created a serious

international rivalry for the trade and coramercial interests 76

in the tropics. The trade in this area was very important

for Britain. If defeated, she would be excluded frora the

tropics because of protective tariffs, and this barrier

7 7

would have repercussions on the British econoray.

Besides these very iraportant comraercial and business

interests, England had a raoral responsibility to civilize

these regions. Kidd pointed to the undeveloped possibil-

ities of Haiti, the West Indies, and Central and South Amer-

ica to deraonstrate that the tropical races could not

administer themselves; thus it was necessary that England 7 8 and America govern them out of humanitarian reasons. In

75 Strauss, Joseph Charaberlain, p. 132. "Mr. Kidd on

the Control of the Tropics," Spectator, LXXXI (1899), 235-236; "The Control of the Tropics," Spectator, LXXXII (1899), 460.

Benjarain Kidd, The Control of the Tropics (London, 1898) , pp. 2-17.

Ibid., p. 32.

^^lbid., pp. 53-57.

Page 92: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

90

this book Kidd's justification of colonies was not based on

collective Darwinism, but on raaterial and coraraercial neces-

sity and because England was the most efficient governing

country as proven by her adrainistration in Egypt and 79

India.'^

Kidd's "trustee for civilization" principle was a very

common arguraent during the late nineteenth century, and was

especially used araong the exponents of the Birrainghara

80 School. Charaberlain declared in 1898 that England was

"the greatest of governing races the world has ever seen"

and "predestined by [her] defects as well as [her] virtues

81 to spread over the habitable globe." England had proven

herself administratively, Charaberlain stated, by her rule

in Egypt and Uganda. Since she was the best administrator,

he continued, she had a responsibility to "civilize the

82 backward people of the globe."

Through Benjarain Kidd's writings, the Darwinian philos-

ophy was adapted to the dominant political thought of the

1890's, the Birminghara School. The political climate was

anti-Gladstonian, and the Manchester School was looked upon

Ibid.

80 Madden, "Changing Attitudes and Widening Responsi-

bilities, 1895-1914," CHBE, III, 347. Ibid.

Joseph Chamberlain, "A Bill for the Weakening of the Empire," Nineteenth Century, XXXIII (1893), 546; Faber, Th£ Vision and the Need, pp. 76-77.

Page 93: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

91

with contempt. The defection of the Liberal Unionists had

greatly diminished the power of the Gladstonians, and this

power was further dirainished by Rosebery and the Liberal

imperialists, who followed the Conservative policy of the

Birraingham School and who gained the ieadership of the Lib-

83 eral party in 1894. The raost proraising new leaders of

the Liberal party, H. H. Asquith, R. B. Haldane, and Edward

84 Grey confessed theraselves to be imperialists. Gladstonian

Liberalisra was for the raoraent suppressed. Gladstone wrote

on February 9, 1894:

Whether it be true that everyone of ray best friends is against rae I do not know. I admit I ara without support. But the world of today is not the world in which I was bred and trained and have principally lived. It is a world which I have had rauch difficulty in keeping on terras with and those difficulties increase. . . . I will not draw coraparisons. I take the worst at the worst and say that if the whole generation be against rae, even that is far better than that I should with ray eyes open (to say nothing of this country) do anything . . . to accelerate, exasperate, widen or preraaturely take or verge towards taking a part in the controversies of blood which we all fear and seem to see are hanging over Europe.85

Man had grown sceptical toward the idealisra of Gladstone and

the Manchester School. Most politicians would have agreed

83 Haraer, John Morley, p. 330.

^^Robinson, "Imperial Problems in British Politics, 1880-1895," CHBE, III, 157; Knaplund, The British Empire, 1815-1939, p. 325.

^^Knaplund, Gladstone's Foreign Policy, pp. 266-267.

Page 94: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

92

with Otto von Bisraarck's son when he stated, "To discuss

the external policy of a great nation with Mr. Gladstone is

pointless, because his raind simply wanders from the sub-

ject."^^

It was only a raatter of time before Darwinisra would be

used to justify British iraperialisra. Kidd had taken a sraall

step in that direction, but it was a socialist, Karl Pearson,

who first completely associated Darwinisra and iraperialism.

Most socialists suspected imperialisra of being a forra

of capitalism in "its raost predatory and militant point"

and as a great obstacle to social reforms. But there were

some socialists who supported the principles of the Birraing-

hcim School, especially when the Liberal imperialists ex-

87 pounded them. The Fabians were a few of these. Pearson

was also one. In "Socialisra in Theory and Practice" (1884) ,

Pearson in an address to London workers proclaimed, "Some

of you may be indifferent to the great erapire of England,

but let me assure you that small as in sorae cases is the

corafort of the English working classes, it is on the average

8 8 large corapared with that of an inferior race."

^^Eyck, Gladstone, p. 270.

^^Madden, "Changing A t t i t u d e s and Widening Respons i -b i l i t i e s , 1894-1914 ," CHBE, I I I , 348-349; Serarael, I raper i -a l i s m and S o c i a l Reforra, pp . 64-72 .

88 Semmel, I raper ia l i s ra and S o c i a l Reform, p . 42.

Page 95: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

93

Pearson was also a collective Darwinist who followed

the lead of Francis Galton as the latter propagandized

eugenic concepts. The eugenic movement, which was the first

to teach collective Darwinism, was very unpopular in the

nineteenth century. The idea of state-intervention in raar-

riage and family institutions to set up huraan breeding

farras was very distasteful to the Victorians. Because of

this attitude, Galton did not become completely dedicated

to his doctrine until the last decade of his life, 1901-

89 1911. Thus the eugenic moveraent did not raake a contribu-

tion to English nineteenth century thought, except through

Pearson.

Around 1894 Pearson began contributing many articles

propagandizing collective Darwinism. The articles savagely

criticized the individual Darwinism of the Manchester School

and Kidd's Social Evolution. In "Socialism and Natural

Selection," Pearson, being also a well known mathematician,

attacked individual Darwinism by a very simple mathematical

process. He presented a mortality chart to determine the

percentage of those elirainated by intra-state struggle.

The chart showed 1000 English males born in the sarae year

90 and the age they died.

^^Blacker, Eugenics, p. 110.

^^Karl Pearson, "Socialisra and Natural Selection," p. 13

Page 96: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

94

Mortality of old age centering about 67 484 deaths Mortality of middle age 41 173 deaths Mortality of youth 22 51 deaths Mortality of children 6 46 deaths Mortaiity of infancy — 246 deaths

Pearson demonstrated that this table showed that only 27

percent of the deaths could possibly be attributed to intra-

state competition since the infants died before struggle and

the old and most of the middle aged had already reproduced.

Thus natural selection, continued Pearson, was not a main

factor within the state, because group selection was more

92 important than internal selection. Consequently the state

should be established according to the socialistic fraraework,

which would eliminate intra-state struggle and be best

fitted for inter-state struggle. Pearson justified collec-

tive Darwinisra by quoting many passages from The Descent of

Man in which Darwin showed the state to be greater than the

individual. It raust be pointed out, however, that before

1900 Pearson's collective Darwinisra was siraply a justifica-

tion of socialisra. He was not concerned with the inter-

national implications of collective Darwinism. When he

spoke of them, it was only superficiaily and abstractly and

only as a justification of socialism. It was the Boer War

that awakened Pearson to the harsh reality of what collec-

tive Darwinism iraplied.

•'•Ibid. , p. 14.

^^lbid., p. 16.

Page 97: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

95

The Boer War had its roots in the large number of

British people or Uitlanders, as they came to be called,

who entered the Transvaal after 1885 to work in the raines

of the Rand. The Transvaal governraent, seeing their state

overwhelraed by these Uitlanders, denied the raajority of

thera full citizenship in order to raaintain political con-

trol. This situation created agitation between the Boers

and the Uitlanders. The Uitlanders forraed the Transvaal

National Union for the purpose of obtaining citizenship and

a "redress of all grievance." This organization made con-

stant deraands that the British governraent use its suzerainty

over the Transvaai to settle the grievances of the

Uitlanders. These iraportunities fell upon deaf ears during

the Gladstone adrainistration of 1892-1894. But when the

Conservative party carae to power in 1895, the league inten-

sified its supplications. On March 24, 1899, a petition was

presented to the Queen which stated, "your Majesty's humble

petitioners beseech . . . measures which will secure the

speedy reforra of the abuses complained of and to obtain sub-

stantial guarantees frora the Government of the State for a

93 recognition of their rights as British subjects."

These appeals did affect the British government, pri-

marily because the Transvaal was strategically vital as a

^"^Grenville, Lord Salisbury and Foreign Policy, pp. 100, 242; Strauss, Joseph Charaberlain, p. 70.

Page 98: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

96

communication link with the Indian Empire. The Gladstone

government of 1880-1885 had given the Transvaal self-

governraent, although Britain retained suzerainty. This

policy seemed to undermine the British iraperial position

throughout southern Africa.^^ The Transvaal had grown to

be politically and coraraercially the raost powerful state in

South Africa. The wealth and power of the Transvaal were

seen as luring agents in forraulating a "United States of

South Africa" in which the colonies of South Africa would

be independent of British power and influence, a policy

which could have had political repercussion upon the Indian

95 Erapire. These iraperial thoughts were running through the

minds of the Conservatives as the Uitlanders sought British

9 6 aid in their struggle for political rights.

The Transvaal governraent, in an effort to elirainate

British influence, agreed to give a five-year franchise if

England agreed to surrender her suzerainty. Britain refused

to yield her last political rights in the Transvaal and put

pressure on that country to accept the terms stipulated in

a dispatch of Septeraber 8, 1899. The dispatch proposed

that a five-year franchise be guaranteed, that one-quarter

94 Gallagher, Africa and the Victorians, pp. 71-72.

^^lbid., pp. 418, 431, 461.

^^John Gallagher and Ronald Robinson, "The Imperialisra of Free Trade," Economic History Review, VI (1953), 3.

Page 99: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

97

of the seats in the Volksraad be guaranteed to the

Uitlanders, that an equal vote in the election of President

and Commandant be given to the Uitlanders, and that a legal

board of enquiry investigate to raake sure that these terras

were carried out. Because the dispatch stipuiated terras

that would increase the influence of Britain, it was ac-

cepted by the Boers as a declaration of war. On October 9,

1899, Stephanus Johannes Paulus Kruger, the President of

Q 7

the Transvaal, declared war on Great Britain. For the

first few raonths of the war, the sraall British forces were

repeatedly defeated. It was in the pessiraisra of this polit-

ical atraosphere that Pearson gave in November, 1900, the

lecture National Life From the Standpoint of Science, which

was published as a book in 1901. This work was an expres-

sion of the demoralizing effect that the Boer War had upon

the British raentality. Concerning National Life, Karl Pearson's son wrote:

There is a strain of pessiraisra now, in his discussion of national and social probleras, which was undoubtedly associated with eraotions roused by the South African War. That realiza-tion of failure of national shortcoraing and muddle-headedness which was brought home to the country in 1900 was certainly shared fully [by] Pearson. This roused in him a national self-consciousness, a feeling of patriotisra, with an outlook on erapire and the use of colonies which

^"^Grenville, Lord Salisbury and Foreign Policy, pp 252-253, 259-260, 263-264.

Page 100: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

98

we should perhans not expect from a study of his early writings.98

Iri National Life Frora the Standpoint of Science,

Pearson patriotically defended British action in South

Africa by justifying the application of war in international

politics.

History shows rae one way, and one way only, in which a high state of civilization has been pro-duced, naraely, the struggle of race with race, and the survival of the physically and mentality fitter race. If you want to know whether the lower races can evolve a higher type, I fear the only course is to leave thera to fight it out among themselves. . . .

[If there is no struggle] mankind will no longer progress; there will be nothing to check the fer-tility of inferior stocks; the relentless law of heredity will not be controlled and guided by natural selection.^^

Pearson understood the national and international iraplica-

tions of collective Darwinisra, because of the Boer War, but

he did not create a new school of thought in England. J. A.

Hobson in his Iraperialisra, A Study and L. T. Hobhouse in

his Deraocracy and Reaction (1905) each dedicated a chapter

to the refutation of collective Darwinisra and naraed only

one expounder of this doctrine, Karl Pearson. This raay

^^E. S. Pearson, Karl Pearson, An Appreciation of Some Aspects of His Life and Work (Carabridge, 1938), p. 45.

^^Karl Pearson, National Life Frora the Standpoint of Science (2nd ed.; London, 1905), pp. 21-22, 26-27.

^^^Hobson, Iraperialism, A Study, pp. 154, 157, 159, 161, 164, 173, 190; L. T. Hobhouse, Deraocracy and Reaction (New York, 1905) , pp. 114-115.

Page 101: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

99

be because Pearson's Darwinisra not only advocated the unpopu-

lar eugenic doctrine, but even opposed the principle of the

Birmingham School. it seems more likely, however, that

it was because the hurailiating defeats of the British

forces in the early period of the war and then the long-

drawn-out war caused English imperial enthusiasra to wilt,

especially since the European nations were condemning

British policy as despotic.

In this light, Williara L. Strauss' thesis that collec-

tive Darwinism becarae a popular theory seems invaiid.

Strauss based this thesis on the supposition that Chamber-

lain adopted Social Darwinism in his imperial arguments

102 during his visit to South Africa after the Boer War.

Strauss made this assuraption on the basis of one, and only

one, lecture given by Charaberlain in which he stated:

Between [the British and the Boer people] there raust be a struggle, a rivalry. As long as human nature is what it is, it was inevitable that in the clash of interests there should be this struggle for supremacy, and it had to be fought out. We are neither of us nations to surrender without a fight, and in ray opinion, this terri-ble war, which we all deplore, was in the nature of things inevitable, and no statesmanship could have perraanently prevented it. Neither would yield but to a trial of strength.103

•'••'"See Karl Pearson, National Life, p. 50.

•'• Strauss, Joseph Charaberlain, p. 93.

•^^•^Chamberiain's speech at Durban, December 27, 1902, in Chamberlain, Mr. Chamberlain's Speeches, II, 76-81

Page 102: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

100

While Chamberlain seemed to be speaking in the Darwinian

framework, a closer investigation reveals a different con-

clusion. First, Charaberlain stated that he had reached

this conclusion because the British and the Boers had inde-

pendent histories which spoke of the love of freedom, endur-

ance, independence, and seif reliance. It was these

qualities that made the war inevitable, not natural selec-

104 tion. Second, Chamberlain in his early political career

was foremost a radical social reformer. He knew and de-

spised the Spencerian philosophy, and he likely associated

Social Darwinism with this philosophy.

The Boer War was the decadence of the iraperialisra of

the late nineteenth century, not the fraraework for an ag-

gressive Darwinian doctrine. Britain won the war, but her

international prestige suffered and her army was discredited,

The repercussions of the war on the British public were cli-

maxed in the Liberal victory in the General Election of

1906. The raain reason was that the Conservative governraent

had justified the war on the grounds that the Uitlanders

deserved the franchise, a natural right as British

104iMd.

105 Webb, My Apprenticeship, p. 120.

Page 103: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

101

subjects. After the war, no one in the Transvaal had

the franchise. Also, Chamberlain promised that eraployraent

would be provided in the raines of the Transvaal. Instead,

Chinese labor was imported after the war to work in the

gold mines. During the General Election of 1906 Liberal

posters of "a hideous yellow Chinese face" were circu-

107 lated. The sweeping Liberal-Labour Representation Com-

mittee's victory was the victory of the anti-imperialistic

concepts of the Manchester School and was the conclusion

10 8 to England's nineteenth century iraperialisra.

•'•^^Chamberlain's speech to the House of Coraraons, October 19, 1899, in Charaberlain, Mr. Chamberlain's Speeches, II, 12-22.

lO'^Thorton, The mperial dea and Its Eneraies, p. 108; Somerville, English Thought, p. 190.

-"•^^Oliver MacDonagh, "The Anti-Imperialism of Free Trade," Econoraic History Review, XIV (1962), 500.

Page 104: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

CONCLUSION

Victor Berard wrote in 1906:

[Darwinisra] is [the] doctrine which has reaily created the Iraperialist fraraework of raind in the nation; it is, at any rate, this pseudo-doctrine which has brought about the acceptance of aggres-sive Jingoisra as a vital necessity.l

Although Berard raade a very bold stateraent, it is evident

that Darwinism did not affect British imperialisra during

the period 1870-1900. The Manchester School had an effect

on the political thoughts of Darwin and Spencer, not vice

versa. The Birrainghara School had an effect upon the polit-

ical thoughts of Benjamin Kidd, not vice versa. The Boer

War had an effect on the political thoughts of Karl Pearson,

not vice versa. Instead, during the years 1870-1900

British iraperialisra had a raolding effect upon the social

and political iraplications of Social Darwinisra. As a social

and political theory, Darwinisra itself had no substance or

content, but was adapted to already preconceived ideas.

What Berard, as raany other authors, raust evidently be

referring to is the pragraatic philosophy of the nineteenth

century. Pragraatisra deraanded a relative interpretation of

the universe--to do what was expedient for the raoment not

according to an absolute standard. For the late nineteenth

Berard, British Imperialisra and Comraercial Supreraacy, p. 279.

102

Page 105: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

103

century had surrendered to materialisra and Realpolitik.^

Barzun wrote, "Divine right had descended to 'the people'

and in the forra of nationalisra was legitiraizing the asser-

tion of competitive wants and the virtue of cynicisra."^

Since pragraatism and Darwinism had coraraon roots in rational-

ism, and since Darwinisra described pragmatism biologically,

the confusion concerning Darwinism's effect upon British

imperialistic thought is perhaps understandable. During

the period 1870-1900 Darwinism had very little, if any,

effect on the development of British imperialism.

2 Barzun, Darwin, Marx, Wagner, pp. 131, 133; Hayes, A

Generation of Materialism, passira. ~ 3 Barzun, Darwm, Marx, Wagner, p. 131.

Page 106: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

BIBLIOGRAPHY

Priraary Sources

"The Control of the Tropics." Spectator. LXXXII (1899), 460. -^

"The Forgotten Fact of Social Evolution." Spectator. LXXII (1894), 292-293.

"Is Pure Selfishness Natural." Spectator. LXXII (1894), 77-78. -^

"Kidd's Social Evolution." Nation. LVII (1894), 294-295.

"Mr. Kidd on the Control of the Tropics." Spectator. LXXXI (1898), 235-236.

"Social Evolution." Critics. XXI (1894), 231.

"Social Evolution." Popular Science Monthly. XLV (1894), 557-558.

Bagehot, Walter. Physics and Politics or Thoughts on the Application of the Principles of "Natural Selection"" and "Inheritance" to Political Society. New York, 1948, originally published in 1867.

Berard, Victor. British Iraperialism and Coraraercial Suprera-acy. Translated by H. W. Foskett. New York, 1906.

Box, Earnest Belfort. Reminiscences and Reflexions of a Mid and Late Victorian. New York, 1967, originally published in 1918.

Charaberlain, Joseph. "A Bill for the Weakening of Great Britain." Nineteenth Century. XXXIII (1893), 545-558.

Mr. Charaberlain's Speeches. Edited by Charles wT~Boy3"^ 2 vols. New York, 1914.

Darwin, Charles. The Autobiography of Charles Darwin, 1809-1882. Edited by Nora Barlow. New York, 1959.

104

Page 107: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

105

. The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex. New York [1936], originally published in 1871, bound with The Origin of Species.

^ . The Origin of Spccies by Means of Natural Selec-tion or the Proservation of Favored Races in the Strug-gle of Life. Gtli ed. New York [1936], originally published in 1859, bound with The Descent of Man.

More Letters of Charles Darwin, A Reccrd of His Work in A Series of llitherto Unpublished Letters. Edited by Francis Darwin. 2 vols. New York, 1903.

Froude, James Anthcny. Slicrt Studies on Great Subjects. 4 vols. London, 189 0.

Gladstone, William. "Aggression on Egypt and Freedoin in the East." Nineteenth Century. II (187""), 149-166.

Great Britain. Parliament. Hansard's Parliamentary Debates. 3rd and 4th series.

Hobhouse, L. T. Democracy and Reaction. New York, 1905.

Hobson, J. A. Imperialism, A Study. 3rd ed. Londcn, 1938.

Huxley, Thomas. Evolution and Ethics, and Other Essays. New York, IQTTÍ

Life and Letters of Thomas Henry Huxley. Edited b7~Leonard Huxley. 2 vcls. New York, 1901.

"The Struggle for Existence; A Frogramrie." Nmeteenth Century. XXIII (1S88) , 161-180.

Huxley, Thomas and Sully, James. "Evolution." Encyclopeûia Britannica. 9th ed. Vol. vill.

Kidd, Benjamin. The Control of the Tropics. Lonãon, 1S?S:.

"Darwm's Successor 3t Home." Reviev rf F.e-T:Í (:89U) , 1-47-650.

-'-,-•;-r\â'. j\-".-. .-;; and Free Trade." Nineteenth ' ].Vv {l^::-) r 32-54.

\..r.r:roY 1- ?.? c: Colonial Preference." I ineteenf.'-:V (:904), 12-2 9.

views.

Centur;;'. II

Century.

Page 108: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

106

_^, "A National Policy." Fortnightly Review. XCIII TT^IO), 602-614. ^

. Social Evolution. New York, 1894.

Malthus, Thoraas Robert. An Essay on the Principle of Popu-lation, as it affect¥ the future iraprovement of Society, with reraarks on the speculations of Mr. Godwin, Mr. Condorcet, and other writers. New York, 1965, origi-nally published in 1798.

Morley, John. Recollections. 2 vols. New York, 1917.

Pearson, Karl. National Life Frora the Standpoint of Science. 2nd ed. London, 1905. ""

"Socialism and National Selection." Fortnightly Review. LVI (1894), 1-20.

Seeley, J. R. The Expansion of England, Two Courses of Lectures. Boston, 1901.

Spencer, Herbert. An Autobiography. 2 vols. London, 1904.

. Facts and Comraents. New York, 1902.

. Life and Letters of Herbert Spencer. Edited by David Duncan. 2 vols. New York, 1908.

. The Man Versus the State. Garden City, 1940, originally published in 1884.

The Principles of Sociology. 2nd ed. 3 vois. New York, 1898.

Social Statics; or, The Conditions Essential to H râan Happiness Specified, and The First of Them De-veloped^ 2nd ed. New York, 18 81.

Suer, W. D. Le. "Kidd on 'Social Evolution.'" Popular Science Monthly. XLVIII (1895), 38-48.

The Tiraes (London).

Wallace, Alfred Russel. Alfred Russel Wallace; Letters and Rerainiscences. Edited by Jaraes Marchant. New York, 1916.

Page 109: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

1900.

107

Studies, Scientific and Social. 2 vols. London,

"Why I Voted for Mr. Gladstone." Nineteenth Century. XXXII (1892), 182-185.

^' The Wonderful Century, The Age of New Ideas in

Science and Invention. London, 1902.

Webb, Beatrice. My Apprenticeship. New York, 1926.

Our Partnership. Edited by Barbara Drake and Margaret I. Cole. Nêw York, 1948.

Wells, H. G. Experiraent in Autobiography, Discoveries and Conclusions of a Very Ordinary Brain (Since 1866). New York, 1934. —

Secondary Sources

Allen, Grant. Charles Darwin; His Life and Work. New York, [n.d.].

Barker, Ernest. Political Thought in England, 1848 to 1914. 2nd ed. New York, 1928.

Barzun, Jacques. Darwin, Marx, Wagner; Critique of a Heri-tage. Garden City, 1958, originally published in 1941.

Bibby, Cyril. T. H. Huxley; Scientist, Huraanist, and Educa-tor. New York, 1960.

Blacker, C. P. Eugenics: Galton and After. Carabridge, Massachusetts, 1952.

Brinton, Crane. English Political Thought in the Nineteenth Century. New York, 1962, originally published in 1933.

Bodelsen, C. A. Studies in Mid-Victorian Imperialism. London, 1960, originally published in 1924.

Buckle, George Earle, and Monypenny, W. F. The Life of Benjamin Disraeli, Earl of Beaconsfield. 6 vols. New York, 1910-1920.

Bury, J. B. The Idea of Progress, An Inquiry into Its Origin and Growth. London, 1920.

Page 110: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

108

Butler, J. R. M. "Imperial Questions in British Politics, 1868-1880." E. A. Benians, James Butler, C. E. Carrington, eds. The Erapire-Commonwealth, 1870-1919. Vol. III of The CarâFridge History of the British Erapire, 8 vols. in 9 Carabridge, 1Ô29-59.

Cecil, Gwendolen. Life of Robert Marquis of Salisbury. 4 vols. London, 1922-1532".

Clark, Robert. Darwin: Before and After, An Evangelical Assessraent. Chicago, 1967, originally published in 1966.

Coates, Wilson H. "Benthamisra, Laissez Faire and Collec-tivisra." Journal of the History of Ideas. XI (1950), 357-363. •

Copleston, Frederick. A History of Philosophy. 8 vols. Westrainister, Maryland, 1966.

Dunn, Waldo Hilary. Jaraes Anthony Froude, A Biography. 2 vols. Oxford, 1961-3.

Ellegard, Alvar. Darwin and the General Reader; The Recep-tion of Darwin's Theory of Evolution in the British Periodical Press, 1859-1872. Goteborg, 1958.

Ensor, R. C. K. England, 1870-1914. Oxford, 1936.

Eyck, Erich. Gladstone. Translated by Bernard Miall. London, 1966, originally published in 1938.

Faber, Richard. The Vision and the Need; Late Victorian Imperialist Airas. London, 1966.

Gallagher, John and Robinson, Ronald. "The Imperialism of Free Trade." Econoraic History Review. VI (1953), 1-15.

Gallagher, John; Robinson, Ronald; and Denny, Alice. Africa and the Victorians; The Cliraax of Iraperialism in the Dark Continent^ New York, 1961.

Garvin, J. L. The Life of Joseph Chamberlain. 3 vols. London, 1932-1934.

Page 111: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

FT

109

George, Wilraa. Biologist Philosopher; A Study of the Life and Writings of Alfred Russel Wallace. New York, 1964.

Grenville, J. A. S. Lord Salisbury and Foreign Policy. London, 1964. "

Halévy, Eli. The Growth of Philosophical Radicalism. Translated by Mary Morris. London, 1928.

Imperialism and the Rise of Labour. New York, T9S1.

Haraer, D. A. John Morley, Liberal Intellect in Politics. Oxford, 1968.

Hayes, Carlton J. H. A Generation of Materialism, 1871-1900. New York, 1941.

Hearnshaw, Fossey John Cobb, ed. The Political Principles of Sorae Notable Prime Ministers of the Nineteenth Cen-tury. London, 1926.

Henkin, Leo J. Darwinism in the English Novel, 1860-1910; The Impact 5 Evolution on Victorian Fiction. New York, 1940.

Hiramelfarb, Gertrude. Darwin and the Darwinian Revolution. Garden City, 1959.

Hinsley, R. H. "International Rivalry, 1885-1895." E. A. Benians, James Butler, C. E. Carrington, eds. The Empire-Commonwealth, 1870-1919. Vol. III of The Cambridge History of the Brit sh Empire. 8 vols. in T. Cambridge, 1929-59.

"Internationai Rivalry in the Colonial Sphere, r86"9-1885." E. A. Benians, James Butler, C. E. Carrington, eds. The Empire-Commonwealth, 1870-1919. Vol. III of The Cambridge History of the British Empire. 8 vols. in 9. Cambridge, 1929-59.

Hofstadter, Richard. Sccial Darwinism in American Thought. 2nd ed. :iew York, 19 59.

Houghton, Walter £. The \^ictorian Frame of Mind, 1830-1870 New Haven, 19 57.

Page 112: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

110

Irvine, William. of Darwin

- Apes, Angels, and Victorians; The Story , Huxley, and Evolution. New York, 1955.

• Thoraas Henry Huxley. London, 1960.

Keith, Arthur. Darwin Revalued. London, 1955.

Knaplund, Paul. The British Empire, 1815-1939. New York, 1941. — ~

Gladstone and Britain's Iraperial Policy. Hamden, Connecticut, 1966, originally published in 1927.

Gladstone's Foreign Policy. Haraden, Connecticut, 1970, originally published in 1935.

Lugard, F. D. The Rise of Our East African Empire; Early Efforts in Nyasaland and Uganda. 2 vols. London, 1893. ^

MacDonagh, Oliver. "The Anti-Imperialism of Free Trade." Econoraic History Review. XIV (1962), 489-501.

McDowell, R. B. British Conservatism, 1832-1914. London, 1959.

MacKintosh, Robert. From Corate to Benjarain Kidd, The Appeal to Biology or Evolution for Huraan Guidance. London, 1899.

Madden, A. F. "Changing Attitudes and Widening Responsi-bilities, 1895-1914." E. A. Benians, James Butler, C. A. Carrington, eds. The Erapire-Coramonwealth, 1870-1919. Vol. III of The Carabridge History of the British Erapire. 8 vols. in"~9"! Carabridge, 1929-1959.

Magnus, Philip. Gladstone, A Biography. New York, 1954.

Morley, John. The Life of Williara Ewart Gladstone. 3 vols. London, 1903.

Pearson, E. S. Karl Pearson, An Appreciation of Some Aspects of His Life and Work. Cambridge, 1938. ~

Robinson, R. E. "Imperial Probleras in British Politics, 1880-1895." E. A. Benians, Jaraes Butler, C. E. Carring-ton, eds. The Erapire-Coraraonwealth, 1870-1919. Vol. III of The Cambridge History of the British 1'mpire. 8 vols. in 9. Carabridge, 1929-59.

Page 113: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism

111

Runney, Jay. Herbert Spencer's Sociology. New York, 1965, originally published in Í937.

Schuyler, R. L. "The Cliraax of Anti-Iraperialisra in England." Political Science Quarterly, XXXVI (1921), 537-560.

Seramel, Bernard. Imperialism and Social Reform; English Social-Imperiai Thought, 1895-1915. Cambridge, 1960.

Seward, A. C., ed. Darwin and Modern Science; Essays in Coraraeraorate of the Centenary of the Birth of Charles Dãrwin and of the Fiftieth Anniversary of the Publica-tion of The Origin of Species. Cambridge, 1909.

Shannon, R. T. Gladstone and the Bulgarian Agitation. London, 1963.

Somervell, D. C. Disraeii and Gladstone: A Duo-Biographical Sketch. New York, 1926.

English Thought in the Nineteenth Century. 2nd ed, London, 1929.

Strauss, Williara L. Joseph Charaberlain and the Theory of Iraperialisra. Washington, D.C., 1942.

Sturgis, Jaraes L. John Bright and the Empire. London, 1969

Thomson, David. England in the Nineteenth Century, 1815-1914. Baltiraore, 1950.

"Social and Political Thought." T. H. Hinsley, ed. Material Progress and World Wide Problems, 1870-1898. Vol. XI of The New Cambridge Modern History. Carabridge, 1962, pp. 101-120.

Thornton, A. P. The Iraperial Idea and Its Eneraies, A Study in British Power. New York, 1959.

Page 114: Social Darwinism and British Imperialism