36
Telicity features of bare nominals Henriëtte de Swart Berlin, Dec 2010

Telicity features of bare nominals

  • Upload
    sydnee

  • View
    63

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Telicity features of bare nominals. Henri ëtte de Swart Berlin, Dec 2010. Bare plurals and telicity. Mary ate an/the apple in/*for an hour. [telic] Mary ate apples for/*in an hour. [atelic] Mary ate the apples in/*for an hour. It took Mary an hour to eat an apple/*apples. - PowerPoint PPT Presentation

Citation preview

Page 1: Telicity features of bare nominals

Telicity features of bare nominals

Henriëtte de Swart

Berlin, Dec 2010

Page 2: Telicity features of bare nominals

Bare plurals and telicity

Mary ate an/the apple in/*for an hour. [telic] Mary ate apples for/*in an hour. [atelic] Mary ate the apples in/*for an hour. It took Mary an hour to eat an apple/*apples. He continued to eat #an apple/#the apple/apples. English bare plurals lead to atelicity (unbounded

process), most other nominal arguments to telicity (event with inherent endpoint).

Page 3: Telicity features of bare nominals

Iterative durativity/bare habituality

John found #a flea/fleas on his dog for a week.

John repairs #a bicycle/bicycles. Every day, John repairs a bicycle/bicycles. Sg indefinite does not allow multiple event

reading, even if one object is involved per event; no bare habituality.

Sg indef OK under quantifier scope.

Page 4: Telicity features of bare nominals

Aspectual composition

Semantics of nominal argument determines aspectual nature of VP (S).

Verkuyl (1972/1993): [±SQA] feature on NPs Krifka (1989): quantized/non-quantized objects. Mapping objects events/path structure. Quantized object maps onto quantized event/

bounded path (Mary ate an apple) Cumulative object maps onto cumulative event/

unbounded path (Mary ate apples)

Page 5: Telicity features of bare nominals

Iterative durativity

With count noun interpretations, cumulative reference requires plurality (Scha 1984).

Van Geenhoven (2004, 2005): pluractionality explains combination of accomplishment/ achievement with for-adverbial: bare plural distributes internal argument over events.

De Swart (2006) on bare habituality: bare plural behaves like dependent plural on set of events.

Page 6: Telicity features of bare nominals

Inherent telicity

The dog ate up a/the cake that I baked for the party.

The dog ate up the cakes/ *cakes I baked for the party. He drank up (all) the water/*water in the tap.

Particle verb inherently telic: mapping from object to event requires object to be quantized incompatible with bare plural/mass noun.

Page 7: Telicity features of bare nominals

Cross-linguistic support (Italian)

Ha stirato molte camicie in due ore / *per due ore di seguito. He ironed many shirts in two hours/*for two hours.

Ha stirato camicie *in due ore / per due ore di seguito. He ironed shirts *in two hours/for two hours.

Dobrovie-Sorin & Laca (2003).

Page 8: Telicity features of bare nominals

Broadening our view

Do bare plurals in all languages lead to atelicity? If so, why? If not, why not?

What about bare singular (count) nominals (in languages in which they occur)? Predictions about telicity?

If we want to investigate the telicity features of bare nominals, where do we start?

Page 9: Telicity features of bare nominals

Bare nominal semantics

BN: nominal without a determiner ~ no info about quantity, discourse reference.

Intuition: bare nominals convey (covertly) what is not expressed (overtly) by determiners (cf. Chierchia 1998, blocking).

What features of the language come into play in determining the aspectual nature of configurations with bare nominals?

Page 10: Telicity features of bare nominals

A typology of bare nominals

Cross-linguistic variation in the semantics of bare nominals correlates with variation in number marking and article use.

Number: sg/pl distinction leads to BS/BPl distinction ~ investigate number neutrality.

Article use: definite/indefinite article blocks definite interpretation/discourse reference.

De Swart & Zwarts (2009, 2010): OT typology.

Page 11: Telicity features of bare nominals

OT typology of number/articles

*FunctN: Avoid functional structure in the nominal domain (markedness constraint).

FPl: Parse sum reference in the functional projection of the nominal (faithfulness constr.)

FDef: Parse dynamic uniqueness by means of a functional layer above NP.

Fdr: Parse a discourse referent by means of a functional layer above NP.

Page 12: Telicity features of bare nominals

No sg/pl, no articles: Mand. Chinese

*FunctN >> {faith constraints number, articles} Wò kànjiàn xióng le. [Mandarin

Chinese] I see bear Asp ‘I saw a bear/bears.’ Gou juezhong le. Dog extinct Asp. ‘Dogs are extinct.’ Gou hen jiling.

Dog very smart. ‘The dog/dogs are intelligent.’

Page 13: Telicity features of bare nominals

Induced telicity in Mandarin

Wo he-guan le tang. I drink-up asp soup ‘I drank up the soup/*soup.’

Wo mai-zhao le shu. I buy-get asp book I managed to buy the books/*books.’

Sybesma (1999): RV construction requires definite/specific interpretation of bare nominal.

Page 14: Telicity features of bare nominals

Telicity features of Mandarin BN

BNn: quantized (‘indef’, ‘specific’, ‘definite’),

cumulative (‘unbounded plurality’) No blocking of form/meaning combination:

telic/atelic interpretation for number neutral BN.

Page 15: Telicity features of bare nominals

Sg/pl distinction, no article: Slavic

FPl >> *FunctN >> {faithfulness constraints definiteness/discourse reference}

On ot-krylperf okno. [Russian] he open.past.perf window.acc ‘He opened (the/a) window.’

Petja čitalimp stat’i/literaturu Peter read-imp-past.sg. articles/literature-acc ‘Peter was reading articles/the articles/ literature/the literature/read articles/literature.’

Page 16: Telicity features of bare nominals

BS in Slavic semantically singular

BSs in Slavic languages have atomic reference: complement of BPl under bidirectional optimization (Farkas & de Swart 2010).

at sum

BS

BPl

Page 17: Telicity features of bare nominals

Bare habituality with BPl

Cumulativity of count noun depends on plurality (Scha 1984) ~ no cumulative interpretation for BSs.

Petja čitaet lekcii v universitete [Russian] Peter read-IMP-pres lectures in university ‘Peter gives lectures (is a lecturer) at the university

Petja zavtra čitaet lekciju v universitete Peter tomorrow read-IMP-pres.3sg lecture in university ‘Tomorrow, Peter is giving (will give) a lecture at the university’ Borik (2002: 140).

Page 18: Telicity features of bare nominals

BPl definite/indefinite in Slavic

Petja pro-čital stat’i/literaturu Peter perf-read-past.sg articles/literature-acc ‘Peter read the articles/the literature’

No definite article, no competition: BPl underspecified ~ adapts under contextual pressure to define inherent endpoint by taking up definite/specific interpretation: Filip (1999), Piñón (2001), Gehrke (2008),..

Page 19: Telicity features of bare nominals

Perfectivity induces telicity

Piñón (2001): Perfective prefix requires quantized (not cumulative) object.

Czytaći: Imp(Read) = yxe [Read(e,x,y)] Prze-czytaćp: Perf(Imp(Read)) =

PQe[Q(e,xe’[P(e’, xe” [Read(e”,s,y)])]) x[CUM(Q(xe’[Read(e’,x,y)]))] y[CUM(P(xe’[Read(e’,x,y)]))]]

PQ[CUM(Perf-Imp-Read(P )(Q))]

Page 20: Telicity features of bare nominals

Slavic BS/BPl and telicity

BSs: quantized (‘indef’, ‘specific’, ‘definite’)

cumulative BPl: quantized (‘specific’, ‘definite’)

cumulative (‘unbounded plural’)

Page 21: Telicity features of bare nominals

Definite article (Hebrew)

{FPl, Fdef} >> *FunctN >> Fdr ra’iti kelev. hu navax/ #hem navxu

I-saw dog. It barked/ #they barked ‘I saw a dog. It barked/ #they barked.’

novxim klavin. Bark dogs ‘Dogs are barking.’

Doron (2003). Strong contrast sg/pl ~ BS has atomic reference: BSs. Fully discourse referential. Restricted to indefinite interpretation under bidirectional optimization.

Page 22: Telicity features of bare nominals

BS in Hebrew semantically indefinite

Blocking by DefSg restricts BSs in Hebrew to indefinite interpretation.

Idem for BPl (non-definite only)

BS

DefSg

Page 23: Telicity features of bare nominals

Telicity features of Hebrew BS/BPl

hu kara sefer be-ša’a/ be-mešex ša’a he read book in-hour/ for hour ‘He read a book in an hour/for an hour.’ (weak telicity features, no cumulative reading)

hu nipeax balonim bemešex šaa he blew balloons for an hour

hu nipeax et ha-balonim tox 5 dakot. he blew acc the balloons in 5 minutes

Cabredo Hoffher (2009), Yitzhaki (2003)

Page 24: Telicity features of bare nominals

No iterative durativity for Hebrew BS

Lack of plurality blocks iterative durativity/bare habituality of Hebrew BSs

John me’ašen sigariya John smokes cigarette John is smoking a cigarette (episodic) John smokes cigarettes (habitual)

John me’ašen sigariyot John smokes cigarettes John smokes cigarettes (habitual)

Cabredo Hoffher (2009), Yoad Winter (p.c.)

Page 25: Telicity features of bare nominals

Telicity features of Hebrew BS/BPl

BSs: quantized (‘indefinite’)

cumulative BPl: quantized (‘specific’, ‘definite’)

cumulative (‘unbounded plural’)

Page 26: Telicity features of bare nominals

Def/indef article (Romance, Hungarian)

{Fpl, Fdef, Fdr} >> *FunctN Morphological sg/pl contrast, def/indef sg, and

bare/indef plural (depending on discourse role plural morphology, cf. Farkas & de Swart 2003).

Strong contrast BS everything else: BS does not satisfy Fdr ~ restricted to constructions with ‘weak’ discourse referentiality features: object position of ‘have’ verbs, bare predication, bare coordination, bare PPS..

Page 27: Telicity features of bare nominals

Number neutrality of BS

Busco pis. Un a Barcelona i un a Girona. [Catalan] look.for-1sg appartment. One in B. and one in G. ‘I’m looking for an apartment. One in Barcelona and one in Girona.’ Espinal & Mcnally (2010)

Mari belyeget gujt. [Hungarian] Mari stamp-acc collect ‘Mari collects stamps.’

BS in Romance/Hungarian number neutral: BSn. Farkas & de Swart (2003): number defined for

discourse referents, not for thematic arguments (DRT). Weak referentiality ~ number neutrality.

Page 28: Telicity features of bare nominals

Bare singulars with ‘have’ verbs

Spanish, Catalan, Romanian: fairly liberal use of bare singulars in object position of ‘have’ verbs, cf. Dobrovie-Sorin, Bleam & Espinal (2006), Espinal & McNally (2010).

Lleva sombrero. [Sp] / Porta barret. [Catalan] wears hat wears hat ‘(S)he wears a hat.’

Ion are casă [Romanian] Ion has house. ‘Ion has a house.’

But: mostly stative verbs no telicity effects.

Page 29: Telicity features of bare nominals

Accomplishment verbs: telicity

Encontraron aparcamento (en diez minutos) [Sp] Found parking (in ten minutes) ‘They found a parking place in ten minutes

Espinal (2009): there could be more than one parking place if more than one driver (NN).

Telic interpretation of bare nominal possible, at least with certain verbs. Espinal (p.c.): BSn must be aspectually inert (property interpretation).

Page 30: Telicity features of bare nominals

Collectivity vs. iteration in H.

Ma delutan szaraz levelet szedtem ossze a haz korul. This afternoon dry leaf gathered together the house around ‘This afternoon, I gathered dry leaves around the house.’

Ma delutan szaraz leveleket szedtem ossze egy-es-è-vel This afternoon dry leaves gathered together one-by-one a haz korul [Hungarian] the house around ‘This afternoon, I gathered dry leaves one by one around the house.’

Number neutrality in object position ‘collect’ verbs, but no iterative durativity. Dayal (2009).

Page 31: Telicity features of bare nominals

No iterative durativity in H

János (*egy hétig) bolhát talált a utyáján. John(*one week-till) flea.acc found the dog-3sg-on. John found some fleas on his dog (on one occasion). [Hungarian] Not: John found fleas on his dog for a week (iterative durative reading), Bende-Farkas (2001).

Number neutrality in Romance/Hungarian does not lead to atelicity via plurality (no cumulativity).

Page 32: Telicity features of bare nominals

Telicity features of BS/BPl in Romance/Hungarian

BSn: quantized (‘indefinite’, ‘definite’) cumulative (‘unbounded plurality’) BPl: quantized (‘specific’, ‘definite’) cumulative (‘unbounded plural’) Def/indef and sg/pl contrast do not apply to

non-referential arguments (require dr). Cumulative BSn requires (dr) plurality for event

distributivity: not available for BSn in Romance/ Hungarian.

Page 33: Telicity features of bare nominals

Recap: role of number in telicity

*FunctN >> FPl or FPl 0 *FunctN leads to number neutrality ~ BSn cumulative atelic, iterative durativity/bare habituality (Mandarin Chinese, Hindi, Braz. Portuguese)

FPl >> *FunctN leads to atomic reference for BSs ~ cumulative telic, no iterative durativity/bare habituality (Slavic, Hebrew).

Page 34: Telicity features of bare nominals

Recap: role of definite article

*FunctN >> Fdef makes definite/specific interpretations available for both BS and BPl ~ quantized telic interpretations available with BS and BPl (Mandarin Chinese, Hindi, Slavic).

Fdef >> *FunctN restricts BS/BPl to indefinite interpretation ~ BPl quantized atelic interpretation only for BPl (Hebrew, Brazilian Portuguese).

Page 35: Telicity features of bare nominals

Recap: role of indef. article

In Brazilian Portuguese, Papiamentu indefinite sg competes with BSn ~ BSn quantized atelic interpretation only, iterative durativity/ bare habituality OK. Why?

Fdr >> *FunctN: BS restricted to non-referential position, number and definiteness irrelevant, but no asserted plurality. BSn cumulative quasi telic interpretation verb driven, no iterative durativity/bare habituality (Romance, Hungarian).

Page 36: Telicity features of bare nominals

Project Info

Weak referentiality: bare nominals at the interface of lexicon, syntax and semantics (2008-2012).

http://www.hum.uu.nl/medewerkers/b.s.w.lebruyn/weakreferentiality/index.htm