4
International Journ Internati ISSN No: 24 @ IJTSRD | Available Online @ www.i Implications of D Different Cu Mansour Moklif Ala 1 Family and Geriatric Med 1 Director of Family Medicine i 2 Chief of Curriculum Developme Guard 2 Assistant Professor in King Saud b ABSTRACT Cultural relativism is based on a facil that what is considered to be morally rig and place (or in one culture) may or considered to be morally right in anoth no grounds for the assumption that morality is superior to another, leaving which the various moralities of cultures or compared. A major question that m when considering the use of cultural rel study of morality is, how widely do cu vary. This study showed that cultural r often be twisted in order to preclude m of acts that are clearly wrong, based on that these acts are traditional within th they are taking place in. This problem justification of immoral acts, but t assumption of superiority of one culture based on the assertion that some cu change. Key Words: cultural relativism, mor morality, norms INTRODUCTION The position that different cultures different moral standards, and that these incommensurate and not directly com position of cultural relativism (Gensle analytical position of cultural relativism social sciences such as anthropology and it allows for the researcher to understa norms and practices of other cult ethnocentrism (Ferraro and Andreatta 2 2012). nal of Trend in Scientific Research and De ional Open Access Journal | www.ijtsrd. 456 - 6470 | Volume - 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov ijtsrd.com | Volume – 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov-Dec 20 Differences in the Moral Stand ultures to the Nature of Morali anazi, MD 1 , Mohammed Ratoubi Alanazi, dicine, Pain Management Consultant, Riyadh, Sa in King Fahd Military Medical Complex, Riyadh ent in Military School of Allied Health Sciences d Health Affairs, Riyadh, Saudi Arabia bin Abdulaiz University for Health Sciences, Ri le observation ght at one time r may not be her. There are any culture’s g no basis on can be judged must be asked lativism in the ultures actually relativism can moral judgment n the assertion he culture that is not just the the continued e over another ultures cannot ral standards, have deeply e standards are mparable, is a er 2011). The m is useful in d sociology, as and the moral tures without 2009; Ferrante However, from a philosophica relativism is problematic bec standard by which certain Furthermore, those that trans may use cultural relativism attempt to justify these actio traditional culture. Thus, to ac uncritically is to create cond possible to question the mora the context of one’s own (na while erodes the fundamental ethics. Although cultural rela analytical assessment, it c preclude any possibility of et judgment. Cultural relativism is based that what is considered to be m and place (or in one culture considered to be morally rig 2008). For example, it is mora Arabia to have more than one and in Indian it is morally perm burned alive along with the funeral pyre; however, none Saudi Arabia and/or India) are Australia. Those that take relativism argue that no cultu superior to another (to ethnocentric) (Stevens 2008) argument, there are no groun that any culture’s morality leaving no basis on which th cultures can be judged or com evelopment (IJTSRD) .com v – Dec 2018 018 Page: 1108 dards of ity , PhD 2 audi Arabia h, Saudi Arabia in Saudi National iyadh, Saudi Arabia al point of view cultural cause it eliminates any acts may be judged. sgress moral boundaries m mendaciously in an ons as an expression of ccept cultural relativism ditions where it is not ality of an act except in arrowly defined) culture, l nature of morality and ativism has its place in cannot be allowed to thical analysis or moral on a facile observation morally right at one time e) may or may not be ght in another (Stevens ally permissible in Saudi e wife up to four wives, missible that wives to be eir dead husbands on a of these examples (in e morally permissible in a position of cultural ure can be deemed to be argue otherwise is ). Thus, based on this nds for the assumption is superior to another, he various moralities of mpared (Stevens 2008).

Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

  • Upload
    ijtsrd

  • View
    3

  • Download
    0

Embed Size (px)

DESCRIPTION

Cultural relativism is based on a facile observation that what is considered to be morally right at one time and place or in one culture may or may not be considered to be morally right in another. There are no grounds for the assumption that any cultures morality is superior to another, leaving no basis on which the various moralities of cultures can be judged or compared. A major question that must be asked when considering the use of cultural relativism in the study of morality is, how widely do cultures actually vary. This study showed that cultural relativism can often be twisted in order to preclude moral judgment of acts that are clearly wrong, based on the assertion that these acts are traditional within the culture that they are taking place in. This problem is not just the justification of immoral acts, but the continued assumption of superiority of one culture over another based on the assertion that some cultures cannot change. Mansour Moklif Alanazi, MD | Mohammed Ratoubi Alanazi, PhD "Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality" Published in International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (ijtsrd), ISSN: 2456-6470, Volume-3 | Issue-1 , December 2018, URL: https://www.ijtsrd.com/papers/ijtsrd20200.pdf Paper URL: http://www.ijtsrd.com/humanities-and-the-arts/social-science/20200/implications-of-differences-in-the-moral-standards-of-different-cultures-to-the-nature-of-morality/mansour-moklif-alanazi-md

Citation preview

Page 1: Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

International Journal of Trend in

International Open Access Journal

ISSN No: 2456

@ IJTSRD | Available Online @ www.ijtsrd.com

Implications of Differences Different Cultures

Mansour Moklif Alanazi, 1Family and Geriatric Medicine

1Director of Family Medicine i2Chief of Curriculum Development

Guard2Assistant Professor in King Saud bin Abdulaiz University for Health Sciences

ABSTRACT Cultural relativism is based on a facile observation that what is considered to be morally right at one time and place (or in one culture) may or may noconsidered to be morally right in another. There are no grounds for the assumption that any culture’s morality is superior to another, leaving no basis on which the various moralities of cultures can be judged or compared. A major question that must bwhen considering the use of cultural relativism in the study of morality is, how widely do cultures actually vary. This study showed that cultural relativism can often be twisted in order to preclude moral judgment of acts that are clearly wrong, based on the assertion that these acts are traditional within the culture that they are taking place in. This problem is not just the justification of immoral acts, but the continued assumption of superiority of one culture over another based on the assertion that some cultures cannot change. Key Words: cultural relativism, moral standards, morality, norms INTRODUCTION The position that different cultures have deeply different moral standards, and that these standards are incommensurate and not directly comparable, is a position of cultural relativism (Gensler 2011analytical position of cultural relativism is useful in social sciences such as anthropology and sociology, as it allows for the researcher to understand the moral norms and practices of other cultures without ethnocentrism (Ferraro and Andreatta 20092012).

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD)

International Open Access Journal | www.ijtsrd.com

ISSN No: 2456 - 6470 | Volume - 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov

www.ijtsrd.com | Volume – 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov-Dec 2018

f Differences in the Moral Standards Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

Mansour Moklif Alanazi, MD1, Mohammed Ratoubi Alanazi, PhGeriatric Medicine, Pain Management Consultant, Riyadh, Saudi Arabia

in King Fahd Military Medical Complex, Riyadhrriculum Development in Military School of Allied Health Sciences

Guard Health Affairs, Riyadh, Saudi Arabia Assistant Professor in King Saud bin Abdulaiz University for Health Sciences, Riyadh,

Cultural relativism is based on a facile observation that what is considered to be morally right at one time and place (or in one culture) may or may not be considered to be morally right in another. There are no grounds for the assumption that any culture’s morality is superior to another, leaving no basis on which the various moralities of cultures can be judged or compared. A major question that must be asked when considering the use of cultural relativism in the study of morality is, how widely do cultures actually vary. This study showed that cultural relativism can often be twisted in order to preclude moral judgment

ased on the assertion that these acts are traditional within the culture that they are taking place in. This problem is not just the justification of immoral acts, but the continued assumption of superiority of one culture over another

on that some cultures cannot

cultural relativism, moral standards,

t cultures have deeply different moral standards, and that these standards are incommensurate and not directly comparable, is a

Gensler 2011). The analytical position of cultural relativism is useful in social sciences such as anthropology and sociology, as it allows for the researcher to understand the moral norms and practices of other cultures without

Ferraro and Andreatta 2009; Ferrante

However, from a philosophical point of view cultural relativism is problematic becaustandard by which certain acts may be judged. Furthermore, those that transgress moral boundaries may use cultural relativism mendaciously in an attempt to justify these actions as an expression of traditional culture. Thus, to accept uncritically is to create conditions where it is not possible to question the morality of an act except in the context of one’s own (narrowly defined) culture, while erodes the fundamental nature of morality and ethics. Although cultural relativism has its place in analytical assessment, it cannot be allowed to preclude any possibility of ethical analysis or moral judgment. Cultural relativism is based on a facile observation that what is considered to be morally right at one tiand place (or in one cultureconsidered to be morally right in another2008). For example, it is morally permissible in Saudi Arabia to have more than one wife up to fouand in Indian it is morally permissible that wives to be burned alive along with their dead husbands on a funeral pyre; however, none of these examples (in Saudi Arabia and/or India) are morally permissible in Australia. Those that take a positionrelativism argue that no culture can be deemed to be superior to another (to argue otherwise is ethnocentric) (Stevens 2008)argument, there are no grounds for the assumption that any culture’s morality is superior to another, leaving no basis on which the various moralities of cultures can be judged or compared

Research and Development (IJTSRD)

www.ijtsrd.com

1 | Nov – Dec 2018

Dec 2018 Page: 1108

he Moral Standards of f Morality

Mohammed Ratoubi Alanazi, PhD2 Riyadh, Saudi Arabia

Riyadh, Saudi Arabia Allied Health Sciences in Saudi National

Riyadh, Saudi Arabia

However, from a philosophical point of view cultural relativism is problematic because it eliminates any standard by which certain acts may be judged. Furthermore, those that transgress moral boundaries may use cultural relativism mendaciously in an attempt to justify these actions as an expression of traditional culture. Thus, to accept cultural relativism uncritically is to create conditions where it is not possible to question the morality of an act except in the context of one’s own (narrowly defined) culture, while erodes the fundamental nature of morality and

l relativism has its place in analytical assessment, it cannot be allowed to preclude any possibility of ethical analysis or moral

Cultural relativism is based on a facile observation that what is considered to be morally right at one time

lace (or in one culture) may or may not be considered to be morally right in another (Stevens

For example, it is morally permissible in Saudi Arabia to have more than one wife up to four wives, and in Indian it is morally permissible that wives to be burned alive along with their dead husbands on a funeral pyre; however, none of these examples (in Saudi Arabia and/or India) are morally permissible in

Those that take a position of cultural relativism argue that no culture can be deemed to be superior to another (to argue otherwise is

). Thus, based on this no grounds for the assumption

that any culture’s morality is superior to another, leaving no basis on which the various moralities of cultures can be judged or compared (Stevens 2008).

Page 2: Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

@ IJTSRD | Available Online @ www.ijtsrd.com

Instead, the only relation that is possible is between another culture and one’s personal morality; statements of X act is wrong must be reduced to I believe that X act is wrong (Stevens 2008eliminates much of the conflict in moral assertions and assumptions; however, it does not provide a basis for discerning a science or philosophy of ethics(Stevens 2008). It also does not prepare the individual for an increasingly globalized world, in which the moralities of different cultures, rather than being strictly contained within a geographical region are constantly in contact and in conflict (Stevens 2008Thus, one of the major perils of cultural relativism in regard to the nature of morality is that it reduces morality to a personal set of beliefs and constructs, rather than a meaningfully shared set of beliefs. A major question that must be asked when considering the use of cultural relativism in the study of morality is, how widely do cultures actually vary? Stevens (2008) argues that in actuality, the basic principles of morality do not vary significantly between cultures; instead, it is only the derived expressions of morality (the manners and norms) that vary greatly. Many universal basic principles, such as prohibitions against lying, killing members of one’s own society, and incest, derive from the dual nature of humans as social, yet selfish, creatures (Stevens 2008). These principles serve to hold societies together by prescribing limits to the expression of selfishness of the individual;furthermore, these principles are consistent because the basic rules by which human societies are organized are consistent (Stevens 2008). There are many cases, even in the extremeseemingly disparate set of norms and practices can be reduced to similar principles. One example is the practice of female infanticide among Eskimo groups(Rachels and Rachels 2010). On its face, this is a morally wrong practice to Western eyes, as infants are to be protected and not killed. However, in the Eskimo context of scarce food supplies, long nursing periods, and the dramatically greater risk to adult males than females, this makes sense; it is an act performed in recognition of the need to provide resources for the existing group (an expression of the social nature of humanity) and the limitations imposed by the environment (Rachels and Rachels 2010example shows that in order to understand cultural practices, it is necessary to look below the first level of norms and practices and examine the underlying

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

www.ijtsrd.com | Volume – 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov-Dec 2018

d, the only relation that is possible is between another culture and one’s personal morality; statements of X act is wrong must be reduced to I

Stevens 2008). This eliminates much of the conflict in moral assertions and assumptions; however, it does not provide a basis for discerning a science or philosophy of ethics

pare the individual for an increasingly globalized world, in which the moralities of different cultures, rather than being strictly contained within a geographical region are

Stevens 2008). Thus, one of the major perils of cultural relativism in regard to the nature of morality is that it reduces morality to a personal set of beliefs and constructs, rather than a meaningfully shared set of beliefs.

r question that must be asked when considering the use of cultural relativism in the study of morality is, how widely do cultures actually vary? Stevens (2008) argues that in actuality, the basic principles of morality do not vary significantly

tures; instead, it is only the derived expressions of morality (the manners and behavioural norms) that vary greatly. Many universal basic principles, such as prohibitions against lying, killing members of one’s own society, and incest, derive

l nature of humans as social, yet selfish, . These principles serve to

hold societies together by prescribing limits to the expression of selfishness of the individual; furthermore, these principles are consistent because the basic rules by which human societies are

.

There are many cases, even in the extreme, where a seemingly disparate set of norms and practices can be reduced to similar principles. One example is the practice of female infanticide among Eskimo groups

. On its face, this is a morally wrong practice to Western eyes, as infants are to be protected and not killed. However, in the

mo context of scarce food supplies, long nursing periods, and the dramatically greater risk to adult males than females, this makes sense; it is an act performed in recognition of the need to provide resources for the existing group (an expression of the ocial nature of humanity) and the limitations imposed

Rachels and Rachels 2010). This example shows that in order to understand cultural practices, it is necessary to look below the first level of norms and practices and examine the underlying

moral principles that are at work in generating these norms and practices before it is possible to understand how a practice comes about. Thus, the similarity of core values (even in the face of widely varying practices) requires not acceptance of cultural relativism as an analytical position, but instead a deepening of the analysis to get at these core values. The effects of applying cultural relativism to the nature of morality These arguments are not meant to indicate that cultural relativism should have no role in the study of ethics. As Bond (1996) points out, there are important uses for cultural relativism in ethics. In particular, cultural relativism is a means of overcoming psychological egoism, or the assumption that one’s own moral standards are the correct or right moral standards (or alternatively the only standards that are moral). Cultural relativism, by its removal of the assumption of universal morality and substitution of the understanding that moral standards vary widely by time and place, allows for the elimination of the self in the assessment of morality and critique1996). However, Bond also notes that this view freqreduces morality to mere standards of manners, which is not truly reflective of underlying norms regarding morality and its practice1996). Thus, even though cultural relativism has a use in Bond’s (1996), it must not be used to reduce ethical standards to simple behaviouralonce again reduces morality to individual rather than a shared society. In particular, while this removal of psychological egoism from a position of importance in analysis does mean that a particular injustice of Western academic research the assumption of Western socothers – is removed; it also removes the ability to critique practices that are by most standards immoral(Rachels and Rachels 2010)authoritarian practices of the Chinese state, which include brutal repression of political dissent, including armed military action against under a cultural relativism viewpoint, there is nothing to say about this practice, which must simply be accepted because it is accepted within Chinese culture(Rachels and Rachels 2010). In additionoverlooking the obvious problem (that if this behaviour were actually accepted within Chineseculture there would be no dissent to repress), it also reduces any critique of this regime to that of personal

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456-6470

Dec 2018 Page: 1109

moral principles that are at work in generating these and practices before it is possible to understand

how a practice comes about. Thus, the similarity of core values (even in the face of widely varying practices) requires not acceptance of cultural relativism as an analytical position, but instead a

ing of the analysis to get at these core values.

effects of applying cultural relativism to the

These arguments are not meant to indicate that cultural relativism should have no role in the study of

points out, there are important uses for cultural relativism in ethics. In particular, cultural relativism is a means of overcoming psychological egoism, or the assumption that one’s own moral standards are the correct or right moral

ively the only standards that are moral). Cultural relativism, by its removal of the assumption of universal morality and substitution of the understanding that moral standards vary widely by time and place, allows for the elimination of the self

sessment of morality and critique (Bond

also notes that this view frequently reduces morality to mere standards of behaviour or manners, which is not truly reflective of underlying norms regarding morality and its practice (Bond

. Thus, even though cultural relativism has a use in Bond’s (1996), it must not be used to reduce ethical

behavioural standards, since this once again reduces morality to the level of the individual rather than a shared society. In particular, while this removal of psychological egoism from a position of importance in analysis does mean that a particular injustice of Western academic research – the assumption of Western society’s superiority over

it also removes the ability to critique practices that are by most standards immoral

). One example is the authoritarian practices of the Chinese state, which include brutal repression of political dissent, including armed military action against unarmed civilians; under a cultural relativism viewpoint, there is nothing to say about this practice, which must simply be accepted because it is accepted within Chinese culture

. In addition, of course overlooking the obvious problem (that if this

were actually accepted within Chinese culture there would be no dissent to repress), it also reduces any critique of this regime to that of personal

Page 3: Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

@ IJTSRD | Available Online @ www.ijtsrd.com

disagreement, not a meaningful statement regarding right and wrong. Thus, although cultural relativism is useful in a limited fashion, it must nsimply refute the notion of morality as a whole. There are many other examples that demonstrate the ways in which cultural relativism reduces the understanding and practice of morality. One example is the human rights practices of Iraexecutions, imprisonments, and the repression of women (Afshari, 2011). These practices are routineand justified by the Iranian government under the mantle of traditional cultural practice which is intended to have the effect of insulating them from outside critique (Afshari 2011). However, Iran is far from the only government that uses claims of tradition and culture to shield itself from critique regarding its actions. For example, the Israeli government makes many of the same claims, including a claim to traditional rights to the land, religious claims, and justice-seeking from prior persecution, to justify its treatment of Palestinians within its borders (Strong 1998). In fact, Strong (1998) identifies the same drivers of these positions of opposing states at work in these two cases. How cultural relativism in such this conflict to be resolved? The facile resolution offered by Stevens (2008) is of no use in this situation; even if the problem is reframed, as X believes Y is wrong and vice versa, there is still the potentially violent disagreement of large and well-armed states to contend with. Thus, cultural relativism has limited use in practical applications of morality and ethics, as it precludes any useful solution. This is a point reiterated by authors discussing NGovernmental Organizations (NGOs) participation in global civil society, who point out that societies no longer stop at international borders; instead, the position of judgment of a state’s actions is now international and global (Clark, Friedman et al. October 1998). Thus, the argument of a sovereign state that its actions are moral because they areappropriate under the norms of that society islonger valid. Furthermore, the position that some societies must retain norms because they are traditional implies an on-going oriental’sthat underhandedly continues to assert the unchanging and static nature of non-Western societies. Orientaliste thought is at the centre of the colonialist activity, and its core principle is that some (Western societies) are superior to others, among

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

www.ijtsrd.com | Volume – 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov-Dec 2018

disagreement, not a meaningful statement regarding right and wrong. Thus, although cultural relativism is useful in a limited fashion, it must not be used to simply refute the notion of morality as a whole.

There are many other examples that demonstrate the ways in which cultural relativism reduces the understanding and practice of morality. One example is the human rights practices of Iran, including executions, imprisonments, and the repression of

. These practices are routine and justified by the Iranian government under the

and religion, insulating them

. However, Iran is vernment that uses claims of

tradition and culture to shield itself from critique regarding its actions. For example, the Israeli government makes many of the same claims, including a claim to traditional rights to the land,

eeking from prior persecution, to justify its treatment of Palestinians

. In fact, Strong drivers of these positions of

t work in these two cases. How using this conflict to be resolved?

The facile resolution offered by Stevens (2008) is of no use in this situation; even if the problem is

as X believes Y is wrong and vice versa, there is still the potentially violent disagreement of

armed states to contend with. Thus, cultural relativism has limited use in practical applications of morality and ethics, as it precludes any

This is a point reiterated by authors discussing Non participation in

global civil society, who point out that societies no longer stop at international borders; instead, the position of judgment of a state’s actions is now

Clark, Friedman et al. argument of a sovereign

state that its actions are moral because they are appropriate under the norms of that society is no longer valid. Furthermore, the position that some societies must retain norms because they are

oriental’s viewpoint that underhandedly continues to assert the unchanging

Western societies. of the colonialist

activity, and its core principle is that some societies (Western societies) are superior to others, among

other reasons because they have the ability to grow and change (Said 2003). Thus, to assert in the face of international disapprobation of a given cultural practice that it must not be criticizecultural practice, as both Iran and Israel insist upon, is to remove the power of cultural relativism to eliminate hierarchies of cultures. This use of cultural relativism actually reinstates the position of moral superiority, when its rejection is one of the main uses of the principle in the first place. This leaves the question of morality and biology.strict position of moral universalism would imply that morality was in some sense encoded in our genes, and that it was an innate physical or cognitive characteristic of humans. A studymorality and ethics are an expression of culture, not of nature, and that this means that there is no universal nature of morality; thus, we must accept the position of cultural relativism, reducing ethical standards differences to simple disagreementsNitecki 1993). However, there are other arguments that suggest that morality does have an evolutionary purpose, and that it evolved alongside the evolution of Homo sapiens as a social mammal as a means of improving fitness (Campbell 1998morality plays an important role in ensuring the survival of the group, which is the main aim of sociality among humans (Campbell 1998 The evolutionary role of morality does not imply that all human cultures will have the same expression of morality, as humans are among the most elastic (or individually adaptable) of all species and various genetic traits are expressed difenvironment (Bogin 1999). There is also evidence that the basic structures of human society ddevelopment of core principles and practices (i.e. morals) even when the environment generates pressures for the evolution of different norms and practice (i.e. manners) (Rachels and Rachels 2010Thus, it is simplistic to say that cultural relativism must simply be accepted because morality is not biologically determined; in fact, the biological determination of morality is not clearly understood, and it cannot be presumed that the basic principles of morality as an enabler of social organization are not biologically determined. Conclusion This article has elaborated on a number of points regarding cultural relativism. First, it is fundamentally

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456-6470

Dec 2018 Page: 1110

other reasons because they have the ability to grow . Thus, to assert in the face of

international disapprobation of a given cultural practice that it must not be criticized because it is a cultural practice, as both Iran and Israel insist upon, is to remove the power of cultural relativism to

hierarchies of cultures. This use of cultural relativism actually reinstates the position of moral

jection is one of the main uses of the principle in the first place.

This leaves the question of morality and biology. A strict position of moral universalism would imply that morality was in some sense encoded in our genes, and

ate physical or cognitive A study suggests that

morality and ethics are an expression of culture, not of nature, and that this means that there is no universal nature of morality; thus, we must accept the position

tivism, reducing ethical standards differences to simple disagreements (Nitecki and

. However, there are other arguments that suggest that morality does have an evolutionary purpose, and that it evolved alongside the evolution of Homo sapiens as a social mammal as a means of

Campbell 1998). Under this view, morality plays an important role in ensuring the

the group, which is the main aim of Campbell 1998).

The evolutionary role of morality does not imply that all human cultures will have the same expression of morality, as humans are among the most elastic (or

of all species and various genetic traits are expressed differently depending on

There is also evidence that the basic structures of human society demand the development of core principles and practices (i.e. morals) even when the environment generates pressures for the evolution of different norms and

Rachels and Rachels 2010). Thus, it is simplistic to say that cultural relativism must simply be accepted because morality is not

determined; in fact, the biological lity is not clearly understood,

and it cannot be presumed that the basic principles of morality as an enabler of social organization are not

has elaborated on a number of points regarding cultural relativism. First, it is fundamentally

Page 4: Implications of Differences in the Moral Standards of Different Cultures to the Nature of Morality

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

@ IJTSRD | Available Online @ www.ijtsrd.com

destructive to the idea of shared morality because the only determination that can be made from a culturally relativist standpoint is that an act is persimmoral, rather than a statement of comparison of wider culture. Furthermore, it demonstrated that the basis of cultural relativism – that the moral norms and values of cultures vary widely – is often overstated and thus that the use of moral relatianalysis of morality is not actually as useful as it may be. Then, this article demonstrated thecultural relativist arguments that morality is strictly cultural, there are in fact evolutionary reasons for the development of morality and as such it is not possible to strictly exclude the study of morality as a biological trait of humans. Finally, it showed that cultural relativism can often be twisted in order to preclude moral judgment of acts that are clearly wrong, based on the assertion that these acts are traditional within the culture that they are taking place in. This problem is not just the justification of immoral acts, but the continued assumption of superiority of one culture over another based on the assertion that some cultures cannot change. Although there are some analytical uses of cultural relativism, such as reducing the tendency to psychological egoism, ultimately cultural relativism, if accepted uncritically, precludes the study of morality entirely and reduces this study to an assertion of personal opinions about acts. This substantially reduces, if not eliminates, the strength of morality as a basis of judgment. REFERENCES 1. Afshari, R. (2011). Human rights in Iran: The

abuse of cultural relativism. Philadelphia, University of Pennsylvania Press.

2. Bogin, B. (1999). Patterns of human growth. Cambridge Cambridge University Press.

3. Bond, E. J. (1996). Ethics and human wellAn introduction to moral philosophy. Oxford, Blackwell Publishers Ltd.

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456

www.ijtsrd.com | Volume – 3 | Issue – 1 | Nov-Dec 2018

destructive to the idea of shared morality because the only determination that can be made from a culturally relativist standpoint is that an act is personally immoral, rather than a statement of comparison of wider culture. Furthermore, it demonstrated that the

that the moral norms and is often overstated

and thus that the use of moral relativism in the analysis of morality is not actually as useful as it may

demonstrated the contrary to cultural relativist arguments that morality is strictly cultural, there are in fact evolutionary reasons for the

y and as such it is not possible to strictly exclude the study of morality as a biological

Finally, it showed that cultural relativism can often be twisted in order to preclude moral judgment of acts

n the assertion that these acts are traditional within the culture that they are taking place in. This problem is not just the justification of immoral acts, but the continued assumption of superiority of one culture over another

t some cultures cannot change. Although there are some analytical uses of cultural relativism, such as reducing the tendency to psychological egoism, ultimately cultural relativism, if accepted uncritically, precludes the study of

uces this study to an assertion of personal opinions about acts. This substantially reduces, if not eliminates, the strength of morality as a

Afshari, R. (2011). Human rights in Iran: The al relativism. Philadelphia,

Bogin, B. (1999). Patterns of human growth. Cambridge Cambridge University Press.

Bond, E. J. (1996). Ethics and human well-being: An introduction to moral philosophy. Oxford,

4. Campbell, B. (1998). Human evolution: An introduction to man's adaptation. New Jersey, Transaction Publishing.

5. Clark, A. M., E. J. Friedman, et al. (October 1998). "The sovereign limits of global civil society: A comparison of NGO participation inUN World Conferences on the Environment, Human Rights, and Women." World Politics 51: 1-35.

6. Ferrante, J. (2012). Sociology: A global perspective. Belmont, WADSWORTH: Cengage Learning.

7. Ferraro, G. and S. Andreatta (2009). Cultural anthropology: An applied WADSWORTH: Cengage Learning.

8. Gensler, H. J. (2011). Ethics: A contemporary introduction. New York, Taylor & Francis Group.

9. Nitecki, M. H. and D. V. Nitecki, Eds. (1993). Evolutionary ethics. Albany, University of New York Press.

10. Rachels, J. and S. Rachels (2010). The elements of moral philosophy New York, McGraw

11. Said, E. W. (2003). Orientalism. New York, Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.

12. Stevens, D. (2008). "Cultural Relativism and the Nature of Morality." Retrieved 23 March 2012from http://www.bioethicseducation.com/attachments/027_Cultural%20Relativism%20and%20the%20Implication%20for%20the%20Nature%20of%20Morality.pdf.

13. Strong, S. I. (1998). "Law and Religion in Israel and Iran: How the Integration of Secular and Spiritual Laws Affects Human Rights and the Potential for Violence." Michigan Journal of International Law 19: 109-

International Journal of Trend in Scientific Research and Development (IJTSRD) ISSN: 2456-6470

Dec 2018 Page: 1111

Campbell, B. (1998). Human evolution: An introduction to man's adaptation. New Jersey,

Clark, A. M., E. J. Friedman, et al. (October 1998). "The sovereign limits of global civil society: A comparison of NGO participation in UN World Conferences on the Environment, Human Rights, and Women." World Politics 51:

Ferrante, J. (2012). Sociology: A global perspective. Belmont, WADSWORTH: Cengage

Ferraro, G. and S. Andreatta (2009). Cultural anthropology: An applied perspective. Belmont, WADSWORTH: Cengage Learning.

Gensler, H. J. (2011). Ethics: A contemporary introduction. New York, Taylor & Francis Group.

Nitecki, M. H. and D. V. Nitecki, Eds. (1993). Evolutionary ethics. Albany, University of New

ls, J. and S. Rachels (2010). The elements of moral philosophy New York, McGraw-Hill.

Said, E. W. (2003). Orientalism. New York, Knopf Doubleday Publishing Group.

Stevens, D. (2008). "Cultural Relativism and the Nature of Morality." Retrieved 23 March 2012,

http://www.bioethicseducation.com/attachments/027_Cultural%20Relativism%20and%20the%20Implication%20for%20the%20Nature%20of%20Mor

Strong, S. I. (1998). "Law and Religion in Israel and Iran: How the Integration of Secular and

s Human Rights and the Potential for Violence." Michigan Journal of

-115.